Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-14 Thread Dave Ketchum
If you object to plurality as I used it below, then WHAT label would  
you use for this major (often used) election method?


I did go to Robert's 10th which is not into our level of detail on  
this topic (I see neither approval nor Condorcet mentioned).


I went to Wikipedia, which I see as agreeing with what I wrote as to  
all three categories.


On Feb 13, 2010, at 4:33 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

At 11:55 PM 2/11/2010, Dave Ketchum wrote:

We all get careless and stumble, sooner or later!

But I choke on two details here:

You misuse the label plurality - having only the ability to vote  
for

1 even though, for many races most intelligent voters will find there
is only one candidate deserving approval.
Even Approval has more power, letting voters vote for more than
one, though unable to differentiate.
Condorcet is another important step up, letting voters vote for
more than one while indicating which they like best.

Forcing voters to act as if they wanted to vote for more than they
wish to is a step backward, and should not pretend to be an asset for
a method.


I'm not following Mr. Ketchum's arguments here. But plurality was  
used in a very ordinary sense. Any method which elects without a  
vote of a majority of those who cast non-blank ballots in an  
election is an election by plurality, using the definitions of  
Robert's Rules (and of most parliamentary procedure manuals, I  
believe, if not all). There is room for interpretation on whether or  
not a non-blank ballot that does not contain a legal vote should be  
included in the basis for majority, but no room for excluding from  
the basis those who do cast a valid vote, but for a candidate that  
is, say, later eliminated due to low vote count.


Hence almost all voting systems that have been considered, absent  
vote coercion (as with mandatory full ranking or penalization of  
partial ranking, as happens with some versions of Borda Count), are  
plurality methods, including Approval and Range and, the point  
here, Condorcet methods.


I did incorrectly state the case at first, by showing lower rankings  
that did add additional votes for other candidates by A. The example  
was clearer with all bullet votes. What this points out is that a  
ranking of, say, ABCDDFGH is, from this point of view, a vote  
for G over H. Should this be considered an approval of G? The  
voter has expressed that, in an election between G and H, the voter  
would prefer H, though, in fact, in a deep ranking like that, this  
is probably noise for the most part. (Robson Rotation is, in fact,  
used to eliminate some of this noise by averaging it out so that, at  
least, it is not produced by ballot position.)



Majority is a word whose merits need more serious thought - see an
earlier post from today.

Ditto runoffs.


Your words below seem intended as response - but I see little if  
anything as to merits.


Dave Ketchum



Indeed. Voting systems theory, early on, focused on attempts to find  
the ideal single-ballot system, from various perspectives. While  
this is a theoretically interesting question, it essentially misled  
the entire field when applied to real election reform, ignoring the  
most widely used voting reform, top two runoff, as if it were merely  
a more expensive and cumbersome version of Sri Lankan Contingent  
vote. Or batch-elimination IRV, same thing. It isn't. It produces  
different results than IRV, in about one-third of runoffs in  
nonpartisan elections. (Probably in partisan elections, it produces  
roughly the same results.)


In addition, this approach ignored the *universally used* direct  
democratic method, repeated balloting, with no decision being made  
without a majority of those voting supporting it. None. No exceptions.


Ignoring explicit voter approval, then, is one of the widespread  
systemic errors. Another one, arising early on, was the assumption  
that pure preference profiles were adequate to understand how voting  
systems would amalgamate votes and produce a useful social ordering,  
when, in fact, any sane method of studying how voting systems work  
would realize that a strong preference is different from a weak or  
barely detectable one, not to mention an indistiguishable one that  
is forced by a voting system to be crammed into one of AB or BA,  
with no allowance for A=B. And real, human, social decision-making  
systems, outside of voting, do consider preference strength, very  
much.


And any system that attempts to maximize benefit to a society based  
on preference profiles would have to take preference strength into  
account. That it may be difficult to do this, that it may be  
difficult to determine commensurability, does not change this. What  
we can see through the device of assuming absolute utilities for  
voters in simulated elections is that the Condorcet Criterion and  
the Majority Criterion, for similar reasons, can require  
preposterous results, in situations 

Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-11 Thread Jameson Quinn
2010/2/10 Abd ul-Rahman Lomax a...@lomaxdesign.com

 At 02:16 PM 2/10/2010, Jameson Quinn wrote:

  What if the bribe is payable only after the vote, and only for effective
 votes? (And don't say that the bribegiver can't be trusted. Since corruption
 is often a very cheap investment for the bribegiver, they would not be
 particularly motivated to fail to pay the bribe after the fact. Even if
 trust was lacking, human ingenuity can easily come up with ways of securing
 the deal.)


 The real issue is whether or not it would be easier to corrupt a delegable
 proxy system than others.


Although you make a number of other, speculative arguments for why DP should
be objectively difficult to corrupt, this is by far your strongest point.
Even if DP is corruptible - an idea which, despite your arguments, I still
find plausible - I see no reason why it should be more corruptible than any
present-day system, or than any other proposed system. Any anti-corruption
safeguards could be made to work as well or, in some cases, better under DP
than with other systems. Thus, corruptibility is not really a valid argument
against DP.

(In other words... quit while you're ahead. If you have one good argument,
you don't need 3.)

Jameson Quinn

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-11 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 01:08 PM 2/10/2010, Dave Ketchum wrote:

Condorcet does an N*N matrix showing for EACH pair of candidates which
is better liked - used in counting and usable by others to help plan
their future.  Often there is a CW which wins for winning in all of
its pairs; else a cycle in which each would be CW if other cycle
members were not candidates.
 How best to resolve a cycle is debatable, but a simple method
could be used unless others are demonstrated to be much better:
Delete weakest pair used to define the cycle; repeat until remainder
defines a CW.
 Note that N*Ns show progress, or lack of such, among non-winners.


Often overlooked is that Condorcet methods, if truncation is allowed 
(and voting without truncation being allowed tends to input a lot of 
noise), is that it they are plurality methods, unless used with 
special rules, which I've never seen anyone buy myself propose.


Consider the following votes:

34 A
33 BC
33 CB.

The Condorcet winner is A, because in the two pairwise elections 
involving A, A wins


AB, 34:33
AC, 34:33.

However, A certainly does not have a majority. This is a problem 
entirely apart from the issue of cycles. Note that a majority winner 
is always a Condorcet winner.


In the election above, almost two-thirds of the voters are actually 
voting against A. A could be a *lousy* result. Or not. Can't tell.


I just noticed that while Wikipedia has many articles on voting 
systems, it doesn't list as a voting system what is commonly used by 
democratic organizations, probably most commonly! Repeated ballot 
until a majority is found for the winner. No eliminations, the 
election process is repeated, with new nominations allowed -- and, of 
course, withdrawals are also allowed.


Basically, seeking a majority and not insisting on finding a winner 
in a single ballot, can make Condorcet almost irrelevant.


(But I find it quite relevant in determining featured candidates in 
runoff elections; in my view, a Condorcet winner should *always* be, 
if not the winner, at least featured in a runoff election, for 
optimal overall results. But some algorithms may make a runoff 
unnecessary, i.e., the possible improvement in social utility from 
holding a runoff *might* be so small as to make it unnecessary. And 
I'd vastly prefer much more collection of data on real elections that 
do collect much more information than is on a plurality ballot, 
than coming to some fixed conclusion about that, snatched out of thin air.)



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-11 Thread Jameson Quinn
 Consider the following votes:

 34 A
 33 BC
 33 CB.

 The Condorcet winner is A, because in the two pairwise elections involving
 A, A wins

 AB, 34:33
 AC, 34:33.


Huh? I count 66 voters who prefer either B or C over A.

Change it up:

49 A
26 BC
25 CB

Now the CW is B. In the C vs. B competition, 26 pro-B voters beat 25 anti
and 49 indifferent voters. This is arguably problematic, but not nearly as
pathological as the original example would have been if true. The pro-(BC)
coalition has decided the relative worth of B and C, while the A voters have
abstained on that question.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-11 Thread Rob LeGrand
Abd wrote:
 34 A
 33 BC
 33 CB.

 The Condorcet winner is A, because in the two pairwise
 elections involving A, A wins

 AB, 34:33
 AC, 34:33.

Assuming that by the above votes you mean

34:AB=C
33:BCA
33:CBA,

A is not the Condorcet winner and is in fact the Condorcet loser, losing
both A:B and A:C by 34:66.  Perhaps you had in mind an example like

35:A
32:BC
33:C,

by which I mean

35:AB=C
32:BCA
33:CA=B.

In this example, C is the Condorcet winner even though C does not have a
majority over B.  I can see how this example could be seen as an
embarrassment to the Condorcet criterion, in that a good method might not
choose C as the winner.

--
Rob LeGrand
r...@approvalvoting.org
Citizens for Approval Voting
http://www.approvalvoting.org/


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-11 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 01:45 PM 2/11/2010, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

34 A
33 BC
33 CB.

The Condorcet winner is A, because in the two pairwise elections 
involving A, A wins


AB, 34:33
AC, 34:33.


Oops. Of course, A is the Condorcet loser. I added the second 
preferences as an afterthought. I meant


34 A
33 B
33 C

But more examples could be constructed where there is deeper ranking. 
Why bother, though?


Condorcet methods, like any deterministic single-ballot method, is a 
plurality method, unless voters are coerced into voting for 
candidates they do not wish to be responsible for supporting, as with 
mandatory full ranking. 



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-11 Thread Dave Ketchum

We all get careless and stumble, sooner or later!

But I choke on two details here:

You misuse the label plurality - having only the ability to vote for  
1 even though, for many races most intelligent voters will find there  
is only one candidate deserving approval.
 Even Approval has more power, letting voters vote for more than  
one, though unable to differentiate.
 Condorcet is another important step up, letting voters vote for  
more than one while indicating which they like best.


Forcing voters to act as if they wanted to vote for more than they  
wish to is a step backward, and should not pretend to be an asset for  
a method.


Majority is a word whose merits need more serious thought - see an  
earlier post from today.


Ditto runoffs.

Dave Ketchum

On Feb 11, 2010, at 9:02 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:


At 01:45 PM 2/11/2010, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

34 A
33 BC
33 CB.

The Condorcet winner is A, because in the two pairwise elections  
involving A, A wins


AB, 34:33
AC, 34:33.


Oops. Of course, A is the Condorcet loser. I added the second  
preferences as an afterthought. I meant


34 A
33 B
33 C

But more examples could be constructed where there is deeper  
ranking. Why bother, though?


Condorcet methods, like any deterministic single-ballot method, is a  
plurality method, unless voters are coerced into voting for  
candidates they do not wish to be responsible for supporting, as  
with mandatory full ranking.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-10 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 05:33 AM 2/10/2010, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

Who says organization, says oligarchy. One has to be careful not 
to have the organization become undemocratic, because the default 
tendency is for it to turn so, since it is (initially) more effective that way.


That's right. The Iron Law of Oligarchy. Nice Wikipedia article on 
it, last time I looked. Oligarchy is inevitable and necessary, but 
the trick is to contain it and keep it responsible, to members who 
have means to be informed, information that is generally trustworthy, 
and who retain as much individual power as possible.



Yes, it's quite likely that they will stay this course right into 
the ground. Hitching proportional representation (a very good idea) 
on to single-winner STV (a quite bad idea) may have seemed like a 
good idea at the time, perhaps because of the brilliant invention 
of the name, instant runoff voting, which itself suggested a 
strategy to spread the idea by attacking a vulnerable institution, 
but it was, in fact, not sustainable.
Some of the reasons why it is not sustainable were not necessarily 
known then. Who would have expected that IRV would closely imitate 
Plurality in nonpartisan elections? Lots of people seem to be 
surprised that IRV doesn't produce real majorities, but that one was known.


I think there's somewhat of an improvement no matter how small 
aspect to it, as well. IRV handles the spoiler problem with minor 
third parties, woo hoo! and then they stop there. But how much of 
that is after-the-fact justification (means for the ends that is 
STV) and how much of that is truly believed is hard to tell.


The original goal still exists for FairVote, but has largely been 
eaten by the IRV monster. That the preceding organizations to 
FairVote co-opted the PR movement was noticed early on, by the 
original PR proponents. If Richie realizes the problems, he doesn't 
let on. He's a dedicated, bulldog political activist, and, in 
general, I consider his office to be part of the problem. It's 
necessary in an adversarial system, far less so in systems that 
attempt to find social consensus.



And the prior history of IRV in the U.S. should have been a clue. 
What was it replaced with? Often -- not always -- with top two 
runoff. Because of the desire for majorities


For multiwinner STV, you could argue that the reason it was replaced 
was not because it did so badly, but because it did too well. 
Consider New York. After STV, there were many parties, not just the 
Democratic stranglehold. What did the Democrats do, seeing their 
power being diluted? Since they didn't want to share, they started 
employing red-scare tactics, with such rational appeals as calling 
the method Stalin Frankenstein.


Yes. The same is true, by the way, with Bucklin. It worked; when it 
failed' it had simply reverted closer to Plurality due to bullet voting.


As for IRV, the single-winner method, you're probably right. In some 
situations, the reason is that it seems to provide no different 
results than Plurality. In others, there's complexity (which is made 
no better by that IRV isn't summable).


FairVote has sold IRV most successfully in jurisdictions that were 
using top-two runoff with nonpartisan elections, and in that 
environment, it's clear that dropping TTR for IRV is quite 
equivalent, in practice, to simply running Plurality, which is a lot 
cheaper. I have seen one fairly clear exception, the Ed Jew District 
4 Supervisor race in San Francisco in 2006, and in that race, we had 
visible markers (the names of the candidates) that identified ethnic 
affiliation, apparently quite similar to partisan affiliations in 
partisan elections. It stands out like a sore thumb in the vote 
transfers, and apparently Jew actually only campaigned to Asians and 
advised them to rank all the Asian candidates. Since the district has 
a high Asian population So this exception actually proves the 
rule. Nominally non-partisan, but, in fact, highly partisan.


Top Two Runoff is an improvement over Plurality, and is the 
most-established election reform in the U.S. And FairVote has been 
shooting it down with its efforts. It's tragic, in fact.


In the long run, though, it will probably prove to have been 
suicidal, as results from all these trials accumulate and are 
analyzed by people who aren't nailed to the FairVote agenda.


Well, Asset bypasses the whole shebang, by making what we think of 
as elections irrelevant. At least in theory. Everyone wins in an 
Asset election, or, if not, then there is someone very specific for 
the voter to blame: the candidate the voter voted for in first 
preference. (Asset may be STV with the Asset tweak for exhausted 
ballots, or it could just be vote-for-one. I, personally, would see 
no need or desirability to rank more candidates, provided my choice 
has a backup (a proxy should be allowed in case of incapacity), but 
some people seem to think otherwise. 

Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-10 Thread Jameson Quinn
 I've elsewhere detailed how an attempt to corrupt a proxy in a DP system
 could easily lead to a mouthful of hair for the would-be corrupter. They pay
 the money, they get the open support of the proxy, the proxy ends up looking
 very good to the constituents, who, on this issue, vote directly, bypassing
 the proxy's vote. I've recommended in DP systems that proxies *not accept*
 votes from large numbers of constituents, or, at least, that they understand
 the problems created if they do. If I got large numbers of requests to
 serve, I would instead recommend that they choose someone who has chosen me.
 And then I can communicate with all of them through direct (and private)
 communication with a handful of individuals. So I've been offered some huge
 sum to exercise my influence. Publicly, I promote the idea, using the best
 arguments provided to me, and perhaps I shut up about the reasons why it's a
 Bad Idea. But I'm in direct communication with my set of direct clients, and
 we discuss everything, routinely. And it would be very easy to make sure
 that they are aware of the counterarguments and that I'm voting as I vote
 because of, shall we say, special considerations. So I vote and argue as I'm
 paid to do, and my clients decide that they just don't like my opinion on
 this particular issue, so they vote directly.


What if the bribe is payable only after the vote, and only for effective
votes? (And don't say that the bribegiver can't be trusted. Since corruption
is often a very cheap investment for the bribegiver, they would not be
particularly motivated to fail to pay the bribe after the fact. Even if
trust was lacking, human ingenuity can easily come up with ways of securing
the deal.)

Consider the common types of corruption at the moment. The two most common
are non-quid-pro-quo support for the candidate who, of themselves, are more
amenable to one's position, unless both are on one's side (this is corrupt
if the issue is under the radar for most voters, as it tends to winnow
opposition down to nothing over time, even if the majority of the electorate
opposes you); and allowing lobbyists essentially free hand in writing the
fine print of laws (again, the point is that the average voter will not
know or care enough about the effects of this to make a difference). If the
majority - even an overwhelming majority - does not care enough to vote
directly, then it can be perfectly effective to corrupt the judgement of a
key representative.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-10 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 02:16 PM 2/10/2010, Jameson Quinn wrote:

What if the bribe is payable only after the vote, and only for 
effective votes? (And don't say that the bribegiver can't be 
trusted. Since corruption is often a very cheap investment for the 
bribegiver, they would not be particularly motivated to fail to pay 
the bribe after the fact. Even if trust was lacking, human ingenuity 
can easily come up with ways of securing the deal.)


The real issue is whether or not it would be easier to corrupt a 
delegable proxy system than others.


Question about a payment for effective votes? Do you mean an actual 
decision that favors the bribegiver, or merely that the bribegiver 
does his best, as far as the bribegiver sees? Now, if I were doing 
something illegal, like accepting a bribe, I'd have no trust in being 
able to enforce an agreement. I've never heard of a bribe being 
payment on results; in addition, I might corrupt myself, place all my 
relationships at risk, and then, because the arguments for this 
proposal were bad, it doesn't pass. That my own clients might also 
betray my vote and open argument is only part of this.


If I don't tell my clients and I argue stupid arguments to them, then 
I risk my entire relationship with them. It better be a lot of money!


Remember, I'm not suggesting DP for government, per se. The political 
applications would be for organizations that advise voters. So what a 
bribe would be accomplishing is that I'd give bad advice to voters. 
In a DP system, this really means to my friends.


That's sociopathic. Now, how many sociopaths are going to be highly 
trusted, in a system that depends on frequent personal contact (not 
the abstract persona and image that play in present politics)? And 
the trust runs in both directions.


If a proxy has weak connections with clients, say, lots of clients, 
they will not be as solidly advised, they may take it or leave it. 
They won't donate money to a suggested cause, they won't necessarily 
bother to vote.


Consider the common types of corruption at the moment. The two most 
common are non-quid-pro-quo support for the candidate who, of 
themselves, are more amenable to one's position, unless both are on 
one's side (this is corrupt if the issue is under the radar for 
most voters, as it tends to winnow opposition down to nothing over 
time, even if the majority of the electorate opposes you); and 
allowing lobbyists essentially free hand in writing the fine print 
of laws (again, the point is that the average voter will not know or 
care enough about the effects of this to make a difference). If the 
majority - even an overwhelming majority - does not care enough to 
vote directly, then it can be perfectly effective to corrupt the 
judgement of a key representative.


That's right. That's how corruption works. Rather than spend money to 
serve the public more effectively to win contracts, spend money to 
influence a corrupt award. It only makes sense if there is some 
fulcrum, some point of serious excess power.


You are incorrect about one thing. It's not necessary for the 
majority to vote on most things. In an Asset system, most people, the 
vast majority, would vote once every election cycle, for a 
representative. It's possible that there may be different reps: to 
neighborhood, to city, to county, to state. Those who are more 
interested will offer to serve as electors and register as 
candidates. These become public voters and will be far more motivated 
than your average citizen, and probably substantially more 
knowledgeable, on average. Anyone can do it, in the systems I 
envision, but getting other people, enough to make it worth the 
continued effort, isn't so easy. Still, none of it is lost, the votes 
aren't wasted. You just pass it on, and, in a direct/Asset rep 
system, you can either forget about it -- which then makes your rep 
like a present rep -- or you can watch -- or you can watch closely 
only when there is an issue you have some particular interest in.


And when you have something to say about it, you know exactly whom 
you can go to, *your representative*. The one you gave your votes to. 
You will be recieved, I expect, with more genuine cordiality than we 
are accustomed to from our representatives. Remember, you freely 
picked this person as the one you most trust to pass on your votes 
to. (If this person also passed your vote on, that merely gives you 
*two* people to go to.)


To me, Asset Voting is not merely an election method, it is a device 
for increasing involvement in government, for making the connection 
between the people and government very real, tangible, visible, as 
well as fair.


We are so far from this that it's hard for most of us to imagine. 
*OUR government.*


I've been in a small town where it was like that. Town Meeting 
government, in fact. Sure, there were elected officials, but the town 
was actually run by the people, and it felt like that. Positions were 
volunteer except for 

Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-09 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 12:20 PM 2/8/2010, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

Given that much better methods exist, have been tried and worked, 
and are much easier to canvass, WTF?


If I were to guess: in part a desire to produce a stepping stone to 
STV, and in part organizational inertia. FairVote bet on IRV and now 
will stay the course.


That's right. One of my first observations on this, when I became 
aware of the election methods list and the Approval voting list, and 
discovered the Center for Voting and Democracy, which had started as 
the Center for Proportional Representation, and which became 
FairVote, was that people trying to reform democracy didn't trust 
democracy, they would always gravitate toward nondemocratic 
institutions which are easily co-opted to become self-preserving and 
inflexible. Typical co-opt is by staff!


Yes, it's quite likely that they will stay this course right into the 
ground. Hitching proportional representation (a very good idea) on to 
single-winner STV (a quite bad idea) may have seemed like a good idea 
at the time, perhaps because of the brilliant invention of the 
name, instant runoff voting, which itself suggested a strategy to 
spread the idea by attacking a vulnerable institution, but it was, in 
fact, not sustainable.


Some of the reasons why it is not sustainable were not necessarily 
known then. Who would have expected that IRV would closely imitate 
Plurality in nonpartisan elections? Lots of people seem to be 
surprised that IRV doesn't produce real majorities, but that one was known.


And the prior history of IRV in the U.S. should have been a clue. 
What was it replaced with? Often -- not always -- with top two 
runoff. Because of the desire for majorities


To address the former: the grail here would be a polytime monotone 
summable multiwinner method that reduces to a good Condorcet variant 
(or Bucklin/Range/etc) in the single-winner case. A multiwinner 
method can be summable in two ways: summable with the number of 
seats held fixed, or summable no matter what.


Well, Asset bypasses the whole shebang, by making what we think of as 
elections irrelevant. At least in theory. Everyone wins in an Asset 
election, or, if not, then there is someone very specific for the 
voter to blame: the candidate the voter voted for in first 
preference. (Asset may be STV with the Asset tweak for exhausted 
ballots, or it could just be vote-for-one. I, personally, would see 
no need or desirability to rank more candidates, provided my choice 
has a backup (a proxy should be allowed in case of incapacity), but 
some people seem to think otherwise. I'd rather not yank my vote away 
from my most-trusted candidate to put it in the hands of this 
less-trusted candidate, but then to return it to the most trusted if 
the less-trusted drops out somehow.  rules in STV/Asset have not 
much been delineated.)


What's important is that we don't know of such a method; but also 
that the stepping stone strategy itself might be dangerous - if the 
base method is bad, then it may fail to dislodge those whose 
interest is in less democracy, and so the objective of moving to 
multiwinner never gains any additional strength by the so-called 
stepping stone.


My own decision about all this is that it's best to begin with NGOs, 
voluntary organizations that demonstrate how advanced methods work. 
The Election Science Foundation held an Asset election for its 
steering committee. It was quite interesting




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-06 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Feb 6, 2010, at 12:27 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 For all practical purposes, except when there are only a few candidates, the 
 first format (1) would be much more compact than the second - which is the 
 point you're making. The data is probably quite compressible as well.

Well, yes. So why bother with opaque binary formats? Choose a natural text 
representation of the ballots, add a digital signature, and compress the 
result. For linear ballots, each ballot is just a list of candidates, or 
candidate keys (A,B,etc) with a key-to-name table added.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-05 Thread James Gilmour
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax   Sent: Friday, February 05, 2010 4:50 PM
CUT
 Practically speaking, I'd assume, the precincts would be provided 
 with a spreadsheet showing the possible combinations, and they would 
 report the combinations using the spreadsheet, transmitting it. So 
 some cells would be blank or zero. With 5 candidates on the ballot, 
 the spreadsheet has gotten large, but it's still doable. What happens 
 if preferential voting encourages more candidates to file, as it 
 tends to do? 23 candidates in San Francisco? Even with three-rank 
 RCV, it gets hairy.

Respectfully, I would suggest this would NOT be a wise way to collect the data. 
 As I pointed out in my e-mail that correctly listed
the maximum possible number of preference profiles for various numbers of 
candidates, the actual number of preference profiles in
any election (or any one precinct) with a significant number of candidates, 
will be limited by the number of voters.  Further,
because some (many) voters will choose the same profiles of preferences, the 
actual number of preference profiles will likely be
even lower  -  as in the Dáil Éireann election I quoted.

Thus a spreadsheet containing all possible preference profiles would be 
unnecessarily large and the probability of making mistakes
in data entry would likely be greater than if each precinct recorded only the 
numbers for each profile actually found in that
precinct.

CUT

 There is a way to avoid such massive reporting, which is to report 
 interactively, which is what is done in Australia. Only one set of 
 totals is reported from a precinct at a time, the totals for the 
 current round. (which can be just uncovered votes due to eliminations 
 that have been reported to the precinct from central tabulation.)
 
 However, the problem with this is that a single error in a precinct 
 can require, then, all precincts to have to retabulate. 

Yes, this distributed counting would work.  But there is an even simpler 
solution  -  take all the ballots to one counting centre
and then sort and count only the ballots that are necessary to determine the 
winner (or winners in an STV-PR election).  That what
has been done for public elections in Ireland and the UK for many decades and 
it works well without problems.  But I do appreciate
that is far too simple and practical a solution and it suffers from NMH.

James Gilmour

No virus found in this outgoing message.
Checked by AVG - www.avg.com 
Version: 9.0.733 / Virus Database: 271.1.1/2669 - Release Date: 02/05/10 
07:35:00



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-05 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 01:12 PM 2/5/2010, James Gilmour wrote:

Abd ul-Rahman Lomax   Sent: Friday, February 05, 2010 4:50 PM
CUT
 Practically speaking, I'd assume, the precincts would be provided
 with a spreadsheet showing the possible combinations, and they would
 report the combinations using the spreadsheet, transmitting it. So
 some cells would be blank or zero. With 5 candidates on the ballot,
 the spreadsheet has gotten large, but it's still doable. What happens
 if preferential voting encourages more candidates to file, as it
 tends to do? 23 candidates in San Francisco? Even with three-rank
 RCV, it gets hairy.

Respectfully, I would suggest this would NOT be 
a wise way to collect the data.  As I pointed 
out in my e-mail that correctly listed
the maximum possible number of preference 
profiles for various numbers of candidates, the 
actual number of preference profiles in
any election (or any one precinct) with a 
significant number of candidates, will be 
limited by the number of voters.  Further,
because some (many) voters will choose the same 
profiles of preferences, the actual number of 
preference profiles will likely be

even lower  -  as in the Dáil Éireann election I quoted.


That's correct; however, there is no practical 
way to predict which profiles are needed. Sorting 
the ballots into piles and subpiles until there 
is a separate pile for every profile strikes me 
as how it would be done. (or they could be sorted 
in sequence, according to the physical position 
of the marks, which would be faster, probably). 
Then the data from each pattern would be entered 
into the matching position on the spreadsheet.


Thus a spreadsheet containing all possible 
preference profiles would be unnecessarily large 
and the probability of making mistakes
in data entry would likely be greater than if 
each precinct recorded only the numbers for each profile actually found in that

precinct.


The probability of making mistakes is not as 
stated, because there is a check on the 
spreadsheet data, there can be several checks. 
First of all, I'd first sort the ballots by first 
preference and transmit that data. This is merely 
preliminary, but those totals might decide the 
election. The sums should equal the number of ballots found.


Then the piles would be sequenced and the totals 
for each particular pattern found. It may be more 
efficient to keep A.B separate from AB, 
because there is less interpretation required. 
I.e., Blank simply becomes another candidate. 
That adds to the possibilities, for sure, but 
simplifies the actual sorting. Blank intermediary 
votes should be pretty rare with IRV, so this 
will not materially add to the data that must be transmitted.


The spreadsheet could be transmitted raw, or it 
could be edited to remove empty rows (i.e, 
patterns with no ballots found matching). That 
reduces transmitted data but increases local 
processing and possibility for error. However, in 
either case, the check by summing remains. The 
check for subpatterns of each first choice is an 
additional error check. The first data 
transmitted could actually be used to shorten the 
process, i.e., there would be two reports from 
precincts: the first report with only first rank 
votes, a wait for central tabulation to have 
collected enough precincts to be able to advise 
on batch elimination, and then an additional 
transmission with all remaining relevant patterns


There is no doibt but that IRV can be counted, 
but the point is that it can get really complex 
and take a lot of time, when an election is close 
with many candidates. With more than a small 
handful of candidates, experience has shown that 
it can be a time-consuming and expensive process, 
done by hand. And very difficult to audit, even 
if done by computer. That's why the election 
security people here in the U.S., in general, don't like it.


What is done, in practice, is to collect and 
analyze ballot images. This has been done with 
preprocessing to collapse votes like A,B, but 
that's actually only a minor improvement and 
reduces transparency. If I'm correct, the 
collection of the data has been done centrally, 
the equipment not being present at the voting 
precincts, so, in short, they truck the ballots 
to central tabulation. This creates other risks.



 However, the problem with this is that a single error in a precinct
 can require, then, all precincts to have to retabulate.

Yes, this distributed counting would 
work.  But there is an even simpler 
solution  -  take all the ballots to one counting centre
and then sort and count only the ballots that 
are necessary to determine the winner (or winners in an STV-PR election).


That's what's being done. What experience here 
shows is that, even centrally counted, errors 
happen in earlier rounds that then require 
recounting all later rounds. The possibility of 
this rises with the number of candidates and the closeness of the election.



  That what
has been done for public 

Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-04 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Feb 4, 2010, at 7:51 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:


The general formula for the number of possible rankings (for strict
ordering, without allowing equal rankings) for N candidates when
partial rankings are allowed and voters may rank up to R candidates
(N=R if voters are allowed to rank all candidates) on a ballot is
given on p. 6 of this doc:

http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/ 
InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf


the only issue, Kathy, is whether the lower limit is i=0 or i=1.  you  
have to defend your use of i=0 for the case illustrated below (using  
the rules in Burlington VT and Cambridge MA).



In the US, R=3 in most IRV elections.



in Burlington it was 5 in both 2006 and 2009.  N was also 5 (not  
counting any write-in).


but Kathy, suppose N=R=3 and it's the regular-old IRV rules that do  
not require any minimum number of candidates ranked and do not allow  
ties.  to be clear, i need to also point out that only *relative*  
ranking is salient (at least in Burlington).  if a voter only ranks  
two candidates and mistakenly marks the ballot 1 and 3, the IRV  
tabulation software will close up the gaps and treat that precisely  
as if it was marked 1 and 2.


now, given those parameters, are you telling us that the 9 tallies  
shown on Warren's page:
 http://rangevoting.org/Burlington.html (i have very similar  
numbers, no more different than 4), are not sufficient to apply the  
IRV rules and resolve the election?


1332  MKW
 767  MWK
 455  M
2043  KMW
 371  KWM
 568  K
1513  WMK
 495  WKM
1289  W

is there any reason those 9 tallies could not have been summed from  
subtotals coming from all 7 wards of Burlington?


please tell us why those 9 piles are not enough, given the parameters  
stated above?



--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-04 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Feb 4, 2010, at 8:29 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:


On Thu, Feb 4, 2010 at 8:18 PM, robert bristow-johnson
r...@audioimagination.com wrote:


On Feb 4, 2010, at 7:51 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:


The general formula for the number of possible rankings (for strict
ordering, without allowing equal rankings) for N candidates when
partial rankings are allowed and voters may rank up to R candidates
(N=R if voters are allowed to rank all candidates) on a ballot is
given on p. 6 of this doc:


http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/ 
InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf


the only issue, Kathy, is whether the lower limit is i=0 or i=1.   
you have
to defend your use of i=0 for the case illustrated below (using  
the rules in

Burlington VT and Cambridge MA).


False Robert. Starting the index at 0 or 1 is completely irrelevant.


so you're saying that

N-1  N-1
SUM{ N!/i! }  =  SUM{ N!/i! }  ?
i=0  i=1

that the N!/0! term is equal to zero?



Any formula is easily adjusted to either initial index.


i ain't talking about any substitution of dummy variable, i, and  
changing the limits.



You are obviously not a mathematician.


i guess not.  just a Neanderthal electrical engineer who does signal  
processing algs for a living.



in Burlington it was 5 in both 2006 and 2009.  N was also 5 (not  
counting

any write-in).


My formula gives the general case for R equals anything, as I said.



but Kathy, suppose N=R=3 and it's the regular-old IRV rules that  
do not
require any minimum number of candidates ranked and do not allow  
ties.  to
be clear, i need to also point out that only *relative* ranking is  
salient

(at least in Burlington).  if a voter only ranks two candidates and
mistakenly marks the ballot 1 and 3, the IRV tabulation software  
will close

up the gaps and treat that precisely as if it was marked 1 and 2.


So?  What's your point?


the point is that a ballot marked with 1 and 3 goes on the same pile  
as a properly marked ballot marked with the same two candidates as  
1 and 2.




now, given those parameters, are you telling us that the 9 tallies  
shown on

Warren's page:
 http://rangevoting.org/Burlington.html (i have very similar  
numbers, no

more different than 4), are not sufficient to apply the IRV rules and
resolve the election?


Obviously you did not read my email. I'll read and respond to yours
after you've tried to read and understand my points. Otherwise I am
not wasting my time responding to you.


no need to, but...



   1332  MKW
767  MWK
455  M
   2043  KMW
371  KWM
568  K
   1513  WMK
495  WKM
   1289  W

is there any reason those 9 tallies could not have been summed from
subtotals coming from all 7 wards of Burlington?

please tell us why those 9 piles are not enough, given the  
parameters stated

above?



... you're running away from the salient question.  are those 9 piles  
good enough to resolve the IRV election with 3 candidates or not?   
was salient information lost when the MK pile was combined with the  
MKW pile, enough that could cause the IRV election (with the rules  
above) to be decided differently?


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-04 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Kathy Dopp wrote:

People on this list seem to still be sending around their incorrect or
incomplete formulas for the number of possible rank orders for rank
order ballots.  This number BTW does *not* correspond to the number of
piles needed to count IRV which is a lesser number but does correspond
to the only method of making IRV precinct-summable.


For precinct summability, whether or not you include both AB and 
ABC votes as distinct (in a three-candidate election) doesn't really 
matter because the factorial term dominates and so one can broadly say:


- When one formula says it's practical to send raw ballot counts around, 
it's practical to do it by any of the other formulas


- When not practical for one, it's not practical for the others either.

Of course, when verifying the outcomes, you'd want to have the exact 
number right, but it seems to me that the question of whether the method 
can be feasibly summed in precincts by transmitting raw counts (how 
many voted this order, how many voted that order) does not depend on 
the exact nature of the formula, because they all grow so quickly.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-03 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

robert bristow-johnson wrote:


On Feb 2, 2010, at 2:28 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:



Warren tells me that

C-1
SUM{ C!/n! }
n=1

has a closed form, but didn't tell me what it is.  does someone have 
the closed form for it?  i fiddled with it a little, and i can 
certainly see an asymptotic limit of


(e-1)(C!)

as C gets large, but i don't see an exact closed form for it.  if 
someone has such a closed form, would you mind sharing it?


Okay, I spent a little time working on this and figgered it out.  The 
fact that the number of distinct piles needed to represent all possible 
manners of *relatively* ranking C candidates (no ties except unranked 
candidates are tied for lowest rank) is


C-1
SUM{ C!/n! }  =  floor( (e-1) C! ) - 1
n=1


Now I wonder if there's a closed form for the number of orders with both 
equality and truncation permitted. Since I don't quite get the proof, I 
can't answer, though!


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-02 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Feb 2, 2010, at 2:28 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:



Warren tells me that

C-1
SUM{ C!/n! }
n=1

has a closed form, but didn't tell me what it is.  does someone  
have the closed form for it?  i fiddled with it a little, and i can  
certainly see an asymptotic limit of


(e-1)(C!)

as C gets large, but i don't see an exact closed form for it.  if  
someone has such a closed form, would you mind sharing it?


Okay, I spent a little time working on this and figgered it out.  The  
fact that the number of distinct piles needed to represent all  
possible manners of *relatively* ranking C candidates (no ties except  
unranked candidates are tied for lowest rank) is


C-1
SUM{ C!/n! }  =  floor( (e-1) C! ) - 1
n=1

I was at first unconvinced that the right hand side is an exact  
closed form for the left, but now accept that it is.


The proof requires as given:

inf
SUM{ 1/n! }  =  e  ~=  2.718281828...
n=0


The floor(a) function which returns the only integer such that

a-1floor(a)  =  a

and, if n is an integer, then

   floor(a + n) = floor(a) + n  for any a.


It also requires knowledge that if C and n are integers and C = n, then

   C!/n!  = C(C-1)(C-2)(C-3)...(n+1) = integer

From that

 inf C-1inf
C! e  =  SUM{ C!/n! }  =  C!  +  SUM{ C!/n! }  +  C!/C!  +  SUM 
{ C!/n! }

 n=0 n=1   n=C+1

or

C-1inf
C! e  =  C!  +  SUM{ C!/n! }  +  1  +  SUM{ C!/n! }
n=1   n=C+1


The first three terms on the RH are integers.  The last term

inf
SUM{ C!/n! }  =  1/(C+1) + 1/[(C+1)(C+2)] + 1/[(C+1)(C+2)(C+3)]  
+ ...

   n=C+1

is less than

inf
SUM{ C!/n! }1/C + 1/C^2 + 1/C^3 + ...
   n=C+1

which is

infinf
SUM{ C!/n! }(1/C) SUM{ (1/C)^j }   =  (1/C)/[1 - (1/C)]  =   
1/(C-1)

   n=C+1   j=0

which is less than 1 for any C  2.  So we know that the last term in


C-1inf
C! e  =  C!  +  SUM{ C!/n! }  +  1  +  SUM{ C!/n! }
n=1   n=C+1

is less than 1.


Then applying the floor() function to both sides yields

  C-1inf
floor(C! e)  =  floor( C!  +  SUM{ C!/n! }  +  1  +  SUM{ C!/n! } )
  n=1   n=C+1

which is

   C-1   inf
floor(C! e)  =  C!  +  SUM{ C!/n! }  +  1  +  floor( SUM{ C!/n! } )
   n=1  n=C+1


Since the argument of the floor() function on the right is less than  
1, the returned value of the floor() function is known to be zero.



   C-1
floor(C! e)  =  C!  +  SUM{ C!/n! }  +  1
   n=1

Resulting in


C-1
SUM{ C!/n! }  =  floor( (e-1) C! ) - 1
n=1

at least for any integer C greater than 2.



I do this kinda thing all the time at comp.dsp or the music-dsp  
mailing list, but haven't done this before outside of those two  
technical contexts.It was kinda fun.


Thanks Warren, for the hint.

--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info