Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-12-03 Thread Bart Ingles


JanetRAnderson wrote:
 
 I'm still grasping for a counting method which is easily explained to the
 public.  Let me try this out with you. Using IRV, eliminate all but the two
 top candidates, in order from least to most.  A look at the real life
 current returns in Florida shows, better than most mathematical formulas,
 how critical the order of transfer becomes in a close election.  Would this
 be an improvement over the current definition of IRV?
 Janet


Is this any different from IRV as currently defined?

I think the general consensus, even among those on this list who don't
agree on much else, is that the root of most of IRV's problems is the
fact that it uses transfers at all.

Bart




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-12-03 Thread Bart Ingles


Markus Schulze wrote:
 Suppose that this given voter would have approved Nader and disapproved
 Gore and Bush if he had no information about the voting behaviour of
 the other voters. Then I am saying that this voter votes insincerely
 when he approves Nader and Gore and disapproves only Bush after he
 has got additional information about the voting behaviour of the
 other voters. You seem to consider it to be an advantage of Approval
 Voting that he can't express both preferences. I consider it to be a
 disadvantage of Approval Voting that he can't express both preferences.

From my own perspective as a voter, I consider it an advantage NOT to be
able to express all preferences.  Here's why:

If I can express all preferences, then I must assume that other voters
can do likewise.  Now typically, I will consider some preferences to be
more important than others.  By being able to express all preferences,
all I am really gaining is the right to express preferences I consider
unimportant, in addition to the important ones.  In exchange for this
slight gain, I must accept that other voters' slight preferences can
cancel out my important ones.

By restricting the ability to express preferences, you encourage voters
to focus on the distinctions they consider important, leaving less
important ones for other voters to decide (who may be more interested in
these).  This closely mirrors the social contract we call common
courtesy, where individuals willingly accept a slight inconvenience when
it provides a greater benefit to another -- such as holding a door open
for someone carrying an armload of packages.  The expectation is that
we, or someone we care about, will benefit from this social contract at
some time or another.  Immediate reciprocity is not nessary or expected.

 
 The fact that he can't express both preferences means that he can
 influence the election result only when he has very exact information
 about the voting behaviour of the other voters. When his information

I think you know better than this.  The behavior of approval voting in
the complete absence of polling information is well known.  Its
average-case performance w/resp. to individual expectations is nearly as
good as the Condorcet methods, and certainly better than IRV. 
Approval's worst-case behavior is actually better than Condorcet's, at
least where excluding extremely unpopular candidates is concerned.


 isn't exact enough then he will probably approve all potential winners
 resp. disapprove all potential winners so that his vote has no influence
 on the election result.

I don't know what you mean by this statement, but your conclusion makes
no sense.

Bart



 
 Is this really what you want?
 That a person who doesn't have exact information about the voting
 behaviour of the other voters should not be able to influence the
 result of the elections?
 
 Markus Schulze




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-12-02 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF





you wrote (2 Dec 2000):
  This, along with small party members' tendency to vote for a lesser-
  evil in 1st place, and the parties reluctance to run more than 1
  candidate, should be mentioned whenever someone talks about IRV's
  "track record".

However, I would like to know whether you would consider a change
from Alternative Voting to Plurality in Australia to be a step forward
or a step backward.

Come on, Markus, that's like asking someone which they like, Bush or
Gore. Changing from IRV to Plurality would be a step sideways.


You wrote (2 Dec 2000):
  As you suggested, a version of IIAC could be written about sincere
  ratings. In fact, we often hear IIAC spoken of as if it is about
  sincere ratings, and 2 ballotings, one of which has a candidate who
  isn't in the other balloting. When people refer to that "version",
  they never define it. It would obviously be much wordier and more
  complicated than the version that I quote, and which is almost surely
  Arrow's version: Deleting a loser from the ballots and then recounting
  those ballots should never change who wins.

Arrow presumes that every voter always casts his complete opinion of
the candidates on the ballot. He calls this presumption "Unrestricted
Domain Criterion." This criterion says that the election method must
not restrict the opinion that a given voter can cast.

That's odd, because in the versions that I've heard of, Arrow
stipulates rank balloting, not ratings balloting.

Therefore, to
your opinion, Arrow is one of the "head-up-the-ass academics"

One thing Arrow is, is a mystery man about whose impossibility theorem
many many legends and rumors and tales have been woven.

If you want to say that Arrow is one of those academics who are
accurately described by my characterization, I'll take your word for
that.

who
doesn't use your "universally accepted" theory.

It isn't a theory. And it isn't mine. But you're 1/3 right, because
it's universally accepted by everyone but you and your you-know-whats
that what voters vote is ballots of the type that are called for by
the voting system in use. They don't vote ratings in rank balloting
elections, for instance.


You wrote (2 Dec 2000):
  But what are you saying?
  That the person who doesn't vote Gore over Bush because he wants to
  vote Nader over Gore is voting insincerely?. He can't express both
  preferences. As I said, not doing the impossible can't be counted as
  an act, and so it also isn't an insincere act.

Suppose that this given voter would have approved Nader and disapproved
Gore and Bush if he had no information about the voting behaviour of
the other voters. Then I am saying that this voter votes insincerely
when he approves Nader and Gore and disapproves only Bush after he
has got additional information about the voting behaviour of the
other voters.

And I'm saying that that isn't relevant to sincerity, which is about
voting a false preference or avoidably declining to vote a sincere
one (as described in my definition).

Look, if I was going to vote for Gore in the election, believing that
I needed him as a lesser-evil, and then I heard that Nader actually
could have a win, and that information induces me to change my vote
from Gore to Nader, do you claim that I'm voting insincerely when I
vote for my favorite because I've found out that I might be able to
help him win?

Maybe, according to you, sincere voting is possible only in a 0-info
election, or by someone who votes according to principle and couldn't
care less about optimizing his outcome.

You seem to consider it to be an advantage of Approval
Voting that he can't express both preferences.

Excuse me, Markus; would you post the date of the archived posting
in which I said that?

I consider it to be a
disadvantage of Approval Voting that he can't express both preferences.

Yes, according to popular belief, you improve the situation when you
let people express more preferences. You've just re-stated that
very common popular belief. Actually, however, rank balloting only
makes things worse when it forces people to rank someone else over
their favorite. When rank balloting is counted by any but the few
best ways, it creates a strategic mess, and yes: It's not as good
as Approval. Does that answer your question?


The fact that he can't express both preferences means that he can
influence the election result only when he has very exact information
about the voting behaviour of the other voters.

Wrong. Vote for all the candidates whose merit is above the average,
and you maximize your utility expectation when there's zero information
about other people's preferences.

Also, many, probably including you, have an exaggerated notion of
how much, on the average, people's expression of preferences will be
shored in Approval. Actually, since typically a voter will vote for
about half of the candidates, it turns out that he'll be expressing
about half of his pairwise preferences. If he voted for exactly half
of 

Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-12-02 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF




Markus's definition of sincere Approval voting says that reversing or
falsifying preferences among candidates other than the incumbant is
sincere. Nonsense.

Besides, it seems real funky to have different sincerity definitions
for different methods.
To my opinion, "sincerity" must be defined in such a manner that there is
a unique (but not necessarily deterministic) way of voting "sincerely" for
a voter with a given opinion.

Though everyone has a right to their opinion, you'd have a difficult
time convincing others to share that one.

Likewise, sincere means that you're not misrepresenting your
preferences, but it certainly doesn't say anything about whether
or not your voting is influences by strategic considerations. As
was pointed out, a sincere ranking can be a strategic vote, if it's
done after a strategic calculation when other ways of voting were
considered.


Mike wrote (24 Nov 2000):
  A voter votes sincerely if he doesn't vote a preference
  that isn't a sincere preference or leave unvoted a sincere
  preference that the balloting system would have allowed him
  to vote in addition to the preferences that he actually did
  vote.

To my opinion, this is only a necessary but not a sufficient condition
for "sincerity." To my opinion, it is also necessary that the voting
behaviour of a "sincere" voter does not depend on his information
about the voting behaviour of the other voters.

I answered this mistaken claim earlier in this message. Say I
sincerely believe that candidate X is corrupt. So I spread the word
everywhere that he's corrupt, so that he won't win. I'm doing it
for a strategic purpose, with an intent to change the outcome of the
election. But I also sincerely believe that it's true. Am I acting
insincerely?


Mike wrote (1 Dec 2000):
  Markus wrote (30 Nov 2000):
   I doubt that those who don't promote Approval Voting
   will agree to your definition of "sincerity."
 
  I'm reasonably sure that Brams  Fishburn have said, in their book
  _Approval Voting_, that, for Approval, they define sincere voting
  as voting without reversing a preferences, without falsifying a
  preference.

Brams and Fishburn are well known supporters of Approval Voting.

I'd misunderstood that sentence, and thought that you'd said
"promote" instead of "don't promote".

But what are you saying?
That the person who doesn't vote Gore over Bush because he wants to
vote Nader over Gore is voting insincerely?. He can't express both
preferences. As I said, not doing the impossible can't be counted as
an act, and so it also isn't an insincere act.


Mike wrote (1 Dec 2000):
  Their definition means the same thing that my definition means when
  it's applied to Approval. My definition agrees with how Brams 
  Fishburn would define sincere voting for Approval, and it also
  agrees with how we'd all define sincere voting with rank balloting
  and Plurality.

When Approval Voting is used then the optimal strategy looks as
follows:

1. Approve all those candidate you prefer to the expected winner.
2. Disapprove all those candidate to which you prefer the expected
winner.
3. Approve the expected winner when rather a less preferred than
a more preferred candidate is elected. Otherwise disapprove him.

#3 isn't clear. It should say "Vote for the expected winner when
the other of the 2 frontrunners is someone whom you like less."

This is a better way of saying what you said:

Vote for whichever of the likely 2 frontrunners you prefer to the other,
and vote for everyone whom you like better than him.


That's one way of saying that you should vote for the candidate you'd
vote for in Plurality, and for everyone whom you like more.

But the person who likes mathematics might want to be more
elaborate, and take into account estimates of frontrunner probabilities
for the various pairs of candidates, to calculate strategy for
Plurality or Approval. I emphasize that that isn't necessary, and
that one can do fine in Approval by voting for the candidate he'd
vote for in Plurality and for everyone whom he likes better--for
his favorite of the 2 expected frontrunners and for everyone whom
he likes better.

Due to Mike's definition of "sincerity," a voter who uses this
strategy votes "sincerely." To my opinion, this voter votes
"insincerely" at least in those cases where he would have voted
in a different manner when he had no information about the voting
behaviour of the oher voters.

Did you say that with the purpose of convincing anyone or influencing
anyone? Then you didn't say it sincerely. It was an insincere
statement :-)

Mike


_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-12-02 Thread JanetRAnderson

I'm still grasping for a counting method which is easily explained to the
public.  Let me try this out with you. Using IRV, eliminate all but the two
top candidates, in order from least to most.  A look at the real life
current returns in Florida shows, better than most mathematical formulas,
how critical the order of transfer becomes in a close election.  Would this
be an improvement over the current definition of IRV?
Janet
- Original Message -
From: "MIKE OSSIPOFF" [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Saturday, December 02, 2000 10:11 AM
Subject: Re: [EM] Majority winner set





 Markus's definition of sincere Approval voting says that reversing or
 falsifying preferences among candidates other than the incumbant is
 sincere. Nonsense.

 Besides, it seems real funky to have different sincerity definitions
 for different methods.
 To my opinion, "sincerity" must be defined in such a manner that there is
 a unique (but not necessarily deterministic) way of voting "sincerely"
for
 a voter with a given opinion.

 Though everyone has a right to their opinion, you'd have a difficult
 time convincing others to share that one.

 Likewise, sincere means that you're not misrepresenting your
 preferences, but it certainly doesn't say anything about whether
 or not your voting is influences by strategic considerations. As
 was pointed out, a sincere ranking can be a strategic vote, if it's
 done after a strategic calculation when other ways of voting were
 considered.


 Mike wrote (24 Nov 2000):
   A voter votes sincerely if he doesn't vote a preference
   that isn't a sincere preference or leave unvoted a sincere
   preference that the balloting system would have allowed him
   to vote in addition to the preferences that he actually did
   vote.
 
 To my opinion, this is only a necessary but not a sufficient condition
 for "sincerity." To my opinion, it is also necessary that the voting
 behaviour of a "sincere" voter does not depend on his information
 about the voting behaviour of the other voters.

 I answered this mistaken claim earlier in this message. Say I
 sincerely believe that candidate X is corrupt. So I spread the word
 everywhere that he's corrupt, so that he won't win. I'm doing it
 for a strategic purpose, with an intent to change the outcome of the
 election. But I also sincerely believe that it's true. Am I acting
 insincerely?

 
 Mike wrote (1 Dec 2000):
   Markus wrote (30 Nov 2000):
I doubt that those who don't promote Approval Voting
will agree to your definition of "sincerity."
  
   I'm reasonably sure that Brams  Fishburn have said, in their book
   _Approval Voting_, that, for Approval, they define sincere voting
   as voting without reversing a preferences, without falsifying a
   preference.
 
 Brams and Fishburn are well known supporters of Approval Voting.

 I'd misunderstood that sentence, and thought that you'd said
 "promote" instead of "don't promote".

 But what are you saying?
 That the person who doesn't vote Gore over Bush because he wants to
 vote Nader over Gore is voting insincerely?. He can't express both
 preferences. As I said, not doing the impossible can't be counted as
 an act, and so it also isn't an insincere act.

 
 Mike wrote (1 Dec 2000):
   Their definition means the same thing that my definition means when
   it's applied to Approval. My definition agrees with how Brams 
   Fishburn would define sincere voting for Approval, and it also
   agrees with how we'd all define sincere voting with rank balloting
   and Plurality.
 
 When Approval Voting is used then the optimal strategy looks as
 follows:
 
 1. Approve all those candidate you prefer to the expected winner.
 2. Disapprove all those candidate to which you prefer the expected
 winner.
 3. Approve the expected winner when rather a less preferred than
 a more preferred candidate is elected. Otherwise disapprove him.

 #3 isn't clear. It should say "Vote for the expected winner when
 the other of the 2 frontrunners is someone whom you like less."

 This is a better way of saying what you said:

 Vote for whichever of the likely 2 frontrunners you prefer to the other,
 and vote for everyone whom you like better than him.


 That's one way of saying that you should vote for the candidate you'd
 vote for in Plurality, and for everyone whom you like more.

 But the person who likes mathematics might want to be more
 elaborate, and take into account estimates of frontrunner probabilities
 for the various pairs of candidates, to calculate strategy for
 Plurality or Approval. I emphasize that that isn't necessary, and
 that one can do fine in Approval by voting for the candidate he'd
 vote for in Plurality and for everyone whom he likes better--for
 his favorite of the 2 expected frontrunners and for everyone whom
 he likes better.

 Due to Mike's definition of "sincerity,&qu

Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-12-01 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Craig, dear Martin, dear Mike,

Craig wrote (1 Dec 2000):
 Markus wrote (30 Nov 2000):
  I suggest the following definition of sincere voting in Approval Voting:
 
A voter votes "sincerely" when he approves all those candidates
he prefers to the incumbent and disapproves all those candidates
to which he prefers the incumbent.

 Ahh.  I was halfway into writing a message against this when I realised that
 it's actually quite a good definition.  The incumbent represents a perceived
 utility value of zero (no change) while the other candidates are above or
 below that value.  I'm assuming that whether or not he votes for the
 incumbent does not effect the sincerity of the vote (?).

I agree.

Craig wrote (1 Dec 2000):
 Does this mean, however, that if the incumbent is no longer running, and
 the incumbent is more liked by a voter than any of the candidates (00 pres
 election?), then that voter cannot cast a sincere vote?

Even when the incumbent doesn't run for re-election the vNM utility of the
incumbent is a good guess for what a given voter can expect from the new
winner. When the incumbent doesn't run for re-election and a given voter
strictly prefers the incumbent to every running candidate, then -to my
opinion- this voter disapproves all candidates when he votes sincerely.

Martin wrote (1 Dec 2000):
 Is there not a difference between voting insincerely and voting
 strategically? For example, if I like Alice and Bob equally in a
 plurality system, then a cross-mark for Alice, and a cross-mark for
 Bob are both sincere votes. Suppose I use a dice to initially decide,
 and pick Alice. then I get info from polls and discover that the race
 is between Bob and Charlie, and change my vote. This, by Mr. Schulze's
 requirement, is insincere.

 But if in the same case the dice happens to pick Bob, then presumably
 this would be a sincere vote? But to have the sincerity of my vote
 effectively decided by a dice seems, well... odd at least. Don't like it.

To my opinion, "sincerity" must be defined in such a manner that there is
a unique (but not necessarily deterministic) way of voting "sincerely" for
a voter with a given opinion.

Example:

   When FPP is used then the unique way of voting sincerely is to
   make a cross-mark for that candidate who is the favorite candidate
   due to this voter's sincere opinion.

   Of course it is possible that a given voter has no unique favorite
   candidate. In this case he will randomly or arbitrarily decide which
   of his favorite candidates gets his cross-mark. But who gets his
   cross-mark must not change when this given voter gets additional
   information about the voting behaviour of the other voters.

Mike wrote (24 Nov 2000):
 A voter votes sincerely if he doesn't vote a preference
 that isn't a sincere preference or leave unvoted a sincere
 preference that the balloting system would have allowed him
 to vote in addition to the preferences that he actually did
 vote.

To my opinion, this is only a necessary but not a sufficient condition
for "sincerity." To my opinion, it is also necessary that the voting
behaviour of a "sincere" voter does not depend on his information
about the voting behaviour of the other voters.

Mike wrote (1 Dec 2000):
 Markus wrote (30 Nov 2000):
  I doubt that those who don't promote Approval Voting
  will agree to your definition of "sincerity."

 I'm reasonably sure that Brams  Fishburn have said, in their book
 _Approval Voting_, that, for Approval, they define sincere voting
 as voting without reversing a preferences, without falsifying a
 preference.

Brams and Fishburn are well known supporters of Approval Voting.

Mike wrote (1 Dec 2000):
 Their definition means the same thing that my definition means when
 it's applied to Approval. My definition agrees with how Brams 
 Fishburn would define sincere voting for Approval, and it also
 agrees with how we'd all define sincere voting with rank balloting
 and Plurality.

When Approval Voting is used then the optimal strategy looks as
follows:

1. Approve all those candidate you prefer to the expected winner.
2. Disapprove all those candidate to which you prefer the expected
   winner.
3. Approve the expected winner when rather a less preferred than
   a more preferred candidate is elected. Otherwise disapprove him.

Due to Mike's definition of "sincerity," a voter who uses this
strategy votes "sincerely." To my opinion, this voter votes
"insincerely" at least in those cases where he would have voted
in a different manner when he had no information about the voting
behaviour of the oher voters.

Markus Schulze




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-30 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF


Markus said:

I assume that the voters vote vNM utilities and that the election
method takes from the reported vNM utilities the information it
needs to calculate the winner because I define the criteria in
terms of reported vNM utilities.

Yes, you define the criteria in terms of a form input that the
voting system doesn't actually receive. That's why you can't apply
your system to Approval or single-winner Cumulative.

Mike Ossipoff

_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




RE: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-30 Thread LAYTON Craig

Markus wrote (in part):

I suggest the following definition of sincere voting in Approval Voting:

   A voter votes "sincerely" when he approves all those candidates
   he prefers to the incumbent and disapproves all those candidates
   to which he prefers the incumbent.

Ahh.  I was halfway into writing a message against this when I realised that
it's actually quite a good definition.  The incumbent represents a perceived
utility value of zero (no change) while the other candidates are above or
below that value.  I'm assuming that whether or not he votes for the
incumbent does not effect the sincerity of the vote (?).

Does this mean, however, that if the incumbent is no longer running, and the
incumbent is more liked by a voter than any of the candidates (00 pres
election?), then that voter cannot cast a sincere vote?




RE: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-30 Thread LAYTON Craig

Mike wrote (in part):

Take another look at my definition of sincere voting. It doesn't
say that sincere voting must be nonstrategic. With a rank method
the only sincere ballot is a sincere ranking of all the candidates.

Why do you have to rank all the candidates in order for it to be a sincere
ballot?  In fact, I think that the opposite could be true (see below).

In Plurality, the only sincere ballot is one that votes for one's
sincere favorite. But in Approval, I'm not sure what you'd want to call
a sincere ballot.

I think that a sensible definition of sincere voting, encompassing all
voting methods, is as follows;

A voter votes sincerely where no candidate x is voted below another
candidate y, if the voter actually prefers x to y.  In situations where a
voter does not prefer one candidate to another, and is allowed by the method
to express the equality of those candidates on the ballot without
compromising the validity of that vote or preventing the voter for
expressing other sincere preferences, then the vote must show those
candidates as equal on the ballot.

This definition would mean that in a rank ballot with three candidates
A,B,C, and the voter preferring A to B and C, but not having a preference
between B and C, then voting A first, and not numbering the others, is the
only sincere vote possible.  If you add candidate D, whom the voter likes
less than all the other candidates, then there are five (or seven) sincere
ways of voting;
A1
A1,B2
A1,C2
A1,B2,C3 (with or without D4)
A1,C2,B3 (with or without D4)

In a cumulative voting situation, it would allow a voter to give two
candidates the same number of votes, even if that voter prefers one
candidate to another, but doesn't allow a voter to give a different number
of votes to two candidates liked the same.  I could extrapolate to the other
methods, but I won't bother at the moment.

The definition is broad enough to define a wide range of voting choices as
sincere, and also allows for a distinction between sincere strategic voting
and insincere strategic voting.  Whether this is a good thing or not, I
don't know, but I think the definition is intuitively correct, as well as
applicable to all methods  situations.




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-30 Thread Bart Ingles


Dear Markus:

You wrote:
 
 Of course, it is possible that a given voter makes strategical considerations
 and gets to the conclusion that voting _sincerely_ is the best _strategy_.
 But nevertheless it makes sense to differ between sincere voters and
 insincere voters. When a given voter makes strategical considerations and
 gets to the conclusion that he cannot get any advantage by voting insincerely,
 then this is a desirable situation. When a given voter makes strategical
 considerations and gets to the conclusion that it is advantageous to vote
 insincerely, then this is not a desirable situation.

To me there are degrees of undesirability, depending on the type of
strategy used and on the effects of that strategy:

1)  I consider it worse if voters actually reverse preferences, than to
either express a preference where there is none or abstain where there
is a preference.

2)  I consider it worse if the insincere strategy worsens the outcome. 
It is still undesirable if insincere strategy tends to improve the
outcome, but less so -- this just means that strategy provides a means
to compensate for a system's shortcomings.  It's perhaps undesirable
that this is necessary, but it's better than not compensating for the
shortcomings.

3)  I consider it worse if the needed strategy is overly obscure or
complex, or misleading in the sense that some voters are fooled into
using it incorrectly or lulled into falsely thinking it unnecessary

Depending on the above, insincere strategy can be more important or less
important than other concerns -- do you agree?  If not, it seems to me
that the only option is the raffle method, where each voter chooses a
single name, and one of these ballots is selected randomly (which does
this violate -- non-dictatorship, or non-imposition?)


 In other words: It is not a problem that a given voter makes strategical
 considerations after he has got additional information about the voting
 behaviour of the other voters. But it is a problem when this given
 voter changes his own voting behaviour because of these strategical
 considerations.

But if there weren't a chance of this happening, there would be no
strategical consideration.


 I suggest the following definition of sincere voting in Approval Voting:
 
A voter votes "sincerely" when he approves all those candidates
he prefers to the incumbent and disapproves all those candidates
to which he prefers the incumbent.

It might work where the incumbent is the obvious front-runner -- at
least it gives the voter the flexibility of whether or not to vote for
the incumbent -- but there are situations where it wouldn't make sense:

1) There is no incumbent, or
2) The incumbent has no particular advantage over one or more other
candidates.




RE: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-30 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF



 Take another look at my definition of sincere voting. It doesn't
 say that sincere voting must be nonstrategic. With a rank method
 the only sincere ballot is a sincere ranking of all the candidates.

Why do you have to rank all the candidates in order for it to be a sincere
ballot?  In fact, I think that the opposite could be true (see below).

Maybe. Then my definition could be greatly shortened. I'd felt that
not expressing a sincere preference when there voting system gives no
reason not to is an insincere nonvoting of that preference, an insincere
statement that the candidates are equally good. But yes, there's a
case for saying the only insincere ballot is one which votes an
unfelt pairwise preference. That's because not voting either over the
other could be interpreted as not saying anything about their relative
merit, rather than saying that they're equally good. That sounds just
as valid, and would simplify my definition.

Anyway, I claim that in Approval, when it's impossible to vote
2 preferences on the same ballot, it isn't insincere to not combine
them, because not doing the impossible doesn't count as an
act of any kind, and so it isn't an insincere act. Hence the way I
worded my definition. But if we agree that the only insincere vote
is one which votes an unfelt preference, then my definition can be
much shortened.

 In Plurality, the only sincere ballot is one that votes for one's
 sincere favorite. But in Approval, I'm not sure what you'd want to call
 a sincere ballot.

I think that a sensible definition of sincere voting, encompassing all
voting methods, is as follows;

A voter votes sincerely where no candidate x is voted below another
candidate y, if the voter actually prefers x to y.  In situations where a
voter does not prefer one candidate to another, and is allowed by the 
method
to express the equality of those candidates on the ballot without
compromising the validity of that vote or preventing the voter for
expressing other sincere preferences, then the vote must show those
candidates as equal on the ballot.


Ok, you've removed the insincere label from not voting a felt
preference, and, as I said, there seems to be a perfectly valid case
for regarding it that way.

Where I simply referred to voting a preference that isn't a sincere
preference, you allow the voter to do that under conditions where
he rates the candidates equal, but voting them so would interfere with
voting other preferences. I've got to check out how that will act
differently from my wording. If you already know, tell me. Maybe when
I study your example, that will answer my question.

Of course anytime two or more different definitions are reasonable, but
only some of them act with all criteria  all methods in keeping with
how the criteria are intended, then there's a case for using one of
those definitions. I don't know yet how these different definitions
would act differently. So far I don't know if there are situations
where voting 2 candidates equal would interfere with the voting of
some preference. Again, a study of your example might show a situation
like that.

Mike Ossipoff



This definition would mean that in a rank ballot with three candidates
A,B,C, and the voter preferring A to B and C, but not having a preference
between B and C, then voting A first, and not numbering the others, is the
only sincere vote possible.  If you add candidate D, whom the voter likes
less than all the other candidates, then there are five (or seven) sincere
ways of voting;
A1
A1,B2
A1,C2
A1,B2,C3 (with or without D4)
A1,C2,B3 (with or without D4)

In a cumulative voting situation, it would allow a voter to give two
candidates the same number of votes, even if that voter prefers one
candidate to another, but doesn't allow a voter to give a different number
of votes to two candidates liked the same.  I could extrapolate to the 
other
methods, but I won't bother at the moment.

The definition is broad enough to define a wide range of voting choices as
sincere, and also allows for a distinction between sincere strategic voting
and insincere strategic voting.  Whether this is a good thing or not, I
don't know, but I think the definition is intuitively correct, as well as
applicable to all methods  situations.




_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-30 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF



Dear Markus--


You said:

you say that the well known and widely used concept that
criteria and election methods are defined on the reported
von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters is
"inadequate," "vague," "sloppy," "dishonest," "absurd,"
"faulty," "incorrect," "poor," "silly," "contradictory,"
"incoherent," "useless," "garbage" and "mumbojumbo." But
on the other side, your concept has similar ingredients.

First:

Your definitions of SFC, GSFC, WDSC, SDSC, FBC,
SARC and defensive strategies use "sincere preferences."

Of course they do, because those criteria are about people being able
to vote sincerely without a penalty, to whaterver degree that can
be guaranteed. Since unpenallized sincere voting is the goal, it's
odd that you think I shouldn't talk about sincere voting.



Second:

Your definition of "sincerity" is implausible. You wrote
(24 Nov 2000):
  A voter votes sincrely if he doesn't vote a preference
  that isn't a sincere preference or leave unvoted a sincere
  preference that the balloting system would have allowed him
  to vote in addition to the preferences that he actually did
  vote.

Example:

   Suppose that Approval Voting is used. Suppose that the
   sincere opinion of a given voter is A  B  C  D  E and
   that this voter decides to approve A, B, C and D.

   The day before election day, this voter hears that candidate
   E has no chances to win and that only candidate B and
   candidate C have realistic chances to win. Therefore, this
   given voter decides to approve only candidate A and
   candidate B.

   Due to your definition of "sincerity," this given voter votes
   "sincerely." But (1) in so far as this voter changes his
   voting behaviour after he has got additional information
   about the voting behaviour of the other voters and (2) in so
   far as this given voter changes his voting behaviour because
   of strategical considerations, it is clear that this given
   voter votes strategically. Therefore your definition of
   "sincerity" isn't suitable to differ between sincere voters
   and strategical voters.

Take another look at my definition of sincere voting. It doesn't
say that sincere voting must be nonstrategic. With a rank method
the only sincere ballot is a sincere ranking of all the candidates.
In Plurality, the only sincere ballot is one that votes for one's
sincere favorite. But in Approval, I'm not sure what you'd want to call
a sincere ballot. Obviously the 2 kinds of insincerity are voting
a false preference, and not voting a sincere preference when there's no 
reason why you couldn't have voted it. Hence my definition. With rank 
balloting and Plurality, the only sincere vote is one that doesn't 
strategize. Though you'd like it to, that statement would have no meaning 
with Approval. Maybe that doesn't sound like what "sincere" means to you, 
but that's how I define it.

My definition complies with your expectations with rank balloting 
Plurality, and it's general enough that it applies to Approval
too, even though sincerity in Approval isn't as easy to discuss as you'd 
like it to be.


Again: When you really think that the well known and widely
used concept that criteria and election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters
is "inadequate," "vague," "sloppy," "dishonest," "absurd,"
"faulty," "incorrect," "poor," "silly," "contradictory,"
"incoherent," "useless," "garbage" and "mumbojumbo" then
please explain why you think that your "universally accepted"
concept that criteria should be defined on sincere opinions
and election methods should be defined on casted ballots

Wrong. I never said that all criteria should be defined in terms of
sincere ballots. I said that some work only if defined that way. And
I never said that even that is universally accepted. And yes I
did and do say that election methods defined on cast ballots is
universally accepted by everyone but you  your head-up-the-ass
academics. Most would agree with me that it's preposterous and silly to add 
your contrafactual assumption about balloting.



might
be better. Actually the fact that you define criteria and
election methods on different inputs

Wrong, voting systems have the same input in my voting system
definitions and my criterion definitions: Actual ballots.

But there's no reason why a criterion can't speak of voters' sincere
preferences as well as their votes. That isn't a voting system
input, but it's part of the overall configuration that makes up an
example. Remember, Markus, that my criteria are about allowing
penalty-free sincere voting to the extent possible. Therefore it's
odd that you don't think I should mention sincere voting in criteria.
The Condorcet Criterion too can be stated in terms of your not having
to do other than vote sincerely as long as there's a SCW and everyone
else votes sincerely.

Have we cleared that up? Sincere preferences aren't part of a voting
system's input, in any of my definitions of 

Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-29 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Mike,

you say that the well known and widely used concept that
criteria and election methods are defined on the reported
von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters is
"inadequate," "vague," "sloppy," "dishonest," "absurd,"
"faulty," "incorrect," "poor," "silly," "contradictory,"
"incoherent," "useless," "garbage" and "mumbojumbo." But
on the other side, your concept has similar ingredients.

First:

Your definitions of SFC, GSFC, WDSC, SDSC, FBC,
SARC and defensive strategies use "sincere preferences."

Second:

Your definition of "sincerity" is implausible. You wrote
(24 Nov 2000):
 A voter votes sincrely if he doesn't vote a preference
 that isn't a sincere preference or leave unvoted a sincere
 preference that the balloting system would have allowed him
 to vote in addition to the preferences that he actually did
 vote.

Example:

  Suppose that Approval Voting is used. Suppose that the
  sincere opinion of a given voter is A  B  C  D  E and
  that this voter decides to approve A, B, C and D.

  The day before election day, this voter hears that candidate
  E has no chances to win and that only candidate B and
  candidate C have realistic chances to win. Therefore, this
  given voter decides to approve only candidate A and
  candidate B.

  Due to your definition of "sincerity," this given voter votes
  "sincerely." But (1) in so far as this voter changes his
  voting behaviour after he has got additional information
  about the voting behaviour of the other voters and (2) in so
  far as this given voter changes his voting behaviour because
  of strategical considerations, it is clear that this given
  voter votes strategically. Therefore your definition of
  "sincerity" isn't suitable to differ between sincere voters
  and strategical voters.

Again: When you really think that the well known and widely
used concept that criteria and election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters
is "inadequate," "vague," "sloppy," "dishonest," "absurd,"
"faulty," "incorrect," "poor," "silly," "contradictory,"
"incoherent," "useless," "garbage" and "mumbojumbo" then
please explain why you think that your "universally accepted"
concept that criteria should be defined on sincere opinions
and election methods should be defined on casted ballots might
be better. Actually the fact that you define criteria and
election methods on different inputs makes it significantly
more difficult to check whether a given election method meets
a given criterion. Example: It hasn't yet been demonstrated
whether PC resp. Smith//PC meets SDSC.

You claim that I "endlessly repeated" the same questions.
You claim that you are "real tired of that repetition." But
you apparently neglect that you have never answered any of my
questions. Although I have invited you several times to explain
why you think that your concept might be better, you have never
answered.

However, I doubt that those who don't promote Approval Voting
will agree to your definition of "sincerity."

However, I don't have the impression that your statements have
anything to do with majority winner sets or beat path GMC.

Markus Schulze




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-29 Thread Bart Ingles



Markus Schulze wrote:
 
 Dear Mike,
 
 you wrote (29 Nov 2000):
  I'm sorry! Because Markus had been repeating things, I must have
  not thoroughly read one of the paragraphs in his most recent posting.
  I thought that I did, but I must have missed that sentence, where
  he stated that the assumption is that the voters report vN-M
  utilities, sincere or not, and then the voting system takes from
  those that information that it needs, and would normally get from
  its own balloting procedure.
 
  So I take back the statement that Markus didn't explain it.
 
  But my criticisms of those assumptions mostly still remain valid.
 
  My answers to some of Markus's statements are different based on
  what I've just noticed, though.
 
  I still say that it's a contrafactual assumption. Why assume that
  people vote ratings, and that the voting system takes from them
  the information that it needs, when we could instead just say that
  the voting system collects the kind of input that it actually does
  collect when in actual use??
 
 I assume that the voters vote vNM utilities and that the election
 method takes from the reported vNM utilities the information it
 needs to calculate the winner because I define the criteria in
 terms of reported vNM utilities.
 
 Markus Schulze


I don't see any problem with this, so long as you don't assume that this
is the final word in the behavior of the voting system in question. 
Many voting system analyses start with sincere vNM utilities, and then
try to determine the likely effects of strategy.

Actually, "sincere vNM utilities" is redundant.  I'm not sure what
"insincere vNM utilities" could even mean.  Anything reported by a voter
would be a rating, not a utility, whether sincere or not.  I think
utilities are mainly useful in thought exercises and computer models,
where you can simply generate the numbers and assume they represent
utilities.  The voters don't "report" these -- the modeler "just knows
them", without necessarily even assuming that the hypothetical voters
are able to report them accurately.  Maybe you mean "report" in a
different way -- that the simulator generating the utilities reports
them, for example.


As to criteria, it seems to me that criteria based on utilities, and
criteria based on votes as cast are both useful, but there needs to be
an understanding of which is which.  Maybe some criteria are more
applicable to utilities, and others to votes-as-cast.  For example,
monotonicity by its definition seems to apply to votes-as-cast.  There
is probably a sincere analog using utilities, but I don't know how it
would be useful.

Something like IIA could apply to either, but would have different
meanings in either case (and probably should have different names in
either case).  One might comment on the stability of the system itself
-- for example, would additional absentee ballots for Gore cause Bush to
win -- while the other might comment on the type or degree of strategy
needed to vote most effectively.




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-28 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF


Markus said:

The concept that criteria and election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
voters presumes that every voter casts (not necessarily
sincerely) his von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities and that the
used election method takes from the reported von Neumann-
Morgenstern utilities that information that this election
method needs to calculate the winner.

That presumption is incorrect. What each voter casts depends on
the balloting used by the particular method in use. If the method
is Cardinal Ratings, then you can call someone's ratings his
sincere or insincere vN-M utilities. And then maybe you can bend the
meanings a lot and say that when, in Plurality, someone votes for
Gore, then he's voting a set of insincere vN-M utilities, when he gives
Gore 1 and everyone else zero. But there's no way that you can call
a ranking a set of sincere or insincere vN-M utilities.


You claim that this
concept was "faulty" because some election methods depend on
LESS than the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities.
But when you re-think your statement then you will observe
that this concept is problematic only when the used election
method depends on MORE than just the reported von Neumann-
Morgenstern utilities.

No, it's problematic anyway. You didn't say that the voter casts
something that could be derived from his sincere or insincere vN-M
utilities. You said that he casts his sincere or insincere vN-M
utilities. With rank methods he in no way can be said to do that.
This isn't complicated.

You say it isn't problematic because, if we know the vN-M utilities
that the voter would like to represent, then from that we can
determine how he would vote a ranking, or any other type of balloting.
But that's got nothing to do with your earlier claim that the voter
votes his sincere or insincere vN-M utilities. He doesn't necessarily.
You claim is obviously incorrect.


Again: When you really think that the well known and widely
used concept that criteria and election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
voters is "inadequate," "vague," "sloppy," "dishonest,"
"absurd," "faulty," "poor," "silly," "contradictory,"
"useless," "garbage" and "mumbojumbo"

...don't forget "crap".

then you are invited
to introduce your own concept

I'm not going to claim credit for a concept that isn't mine, for
specifying balloting in method definitions. However, I'm going to
introduce you to the universally accepted concept for that:
When defining a method, we tell how voters can indicate preferences
or ratings, by marking their ballot, and we specify a count rule
for determining the winner from those ballots. That's what you
yourself did when you specified that your method uses rank-ballots.

and to explain why you think
that your own concept might be better.

Now I'm going to explain to you why that's better: It applies to
more diverse methods, with their different balloting systems, than
does your suggestion to define methods as receiving a set of
sincere or insincere vN-M utilities from each voter, a suggestion
that is quite inapplicable to rank methods.

This isn't rocket science, Markus: The fact that you can make a ranking
by ordering the candidates according to someone's vN-M utilities for
them does not mean that the voter who votes a ranking is casting his
vN-M utilities, sincere or otherwise.


Nobody hinders you
from introducing your own concept.

You're too kind, but I'm willing to use the same balloting concept
for method definitions that everyone else uses when defining methods.


However, I don't have the impression that your statements have
anything to do with majority winner sets or beat path GMC.

Actually, at this point, you're right. When I said that Plurality meets 
BPGMC, as
you define it, you at first claimed that it doesn't, because of
your claim that methods (or just Plurality?) should be evaluated
according to what their count rule would do if it were applied
to rank ballots. You abandoned that when I asked you to apply
it to some well-known methods. Then you started repeating that
methods are defined in terms of an input of vN-M utilities. You
say you don't have the impression that that has anything to do with
my claim that Plurality passes BPGMC? Neither do I :-)

I agree that what you've been saying has nothing to do with my
claim that Plurality meets BPGMC, and that it doesn't in any way
answer that claim.

You know what, Markus? I would expect that people are real tired of
that repetition. I'm not going to be a party to continuing to send
them that repetition. When I reply to those endlessly repeated
statements, then I'm partly at fault for their being posted, and
I prefer to not be part of the cause of that repetition being
posted. Repeat the statements again if you want to, but for me to
keep replying to them would be inconsiderate of the other people on
this list.

Mike Ossipoff


And so let me summarize and conclude it in 

Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-28 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF




Markus said:

I have already said in a different context (23 Sep 2000)
that I use the concept that election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
voters.

Excuse me, but I didn't notice anything about von Neumann-Morgenstern
utilities in your definition of "Schulze's method", for example.

But in your reply (23 Sep 2000) you wrote that
this concept was "funny," "incomplete," "undefined,"
"vague" and "not precise." Now you write that this
concept was also "sloppy" and "dishonest."

Maybe the reason why I said "undefined" and "vague" was because
you referred to those purported definitions in the same vague way
as you do now, and because you haven't given us a definition of
the type to which you vaguely refer.


If you didn't refuse to read scientific literature

When did I say I was unwilling to read scientific literature?


then you
would observe that the concept that election methods are
defined on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities
of the voters is widely used and that e.g. Gibbard and
Hylland use this concept for their impossibility theorems.

You say that someone else defines methods in that way, but you
don't define your own method in that way. I have to admit that
it isn't clear to me how someone else's way of defining some other
method is relevant to the issues we've been discussing. For instance,
how does it save your BPGMC criterion from its faults that I
described? I've asked you twice to show that Approval, Cardinal Ratings,
Plurality, and single-winner Cumulative pass or fail the Condorcet
Criterion , if we assume that each voter votes a
ranking and we have to apply those methods' count rules to rankings.
I've explained that your failure to do that shows that the limited
applicability of our approach makes it a poor approach of limited
 questionable usefulness. I've pointed out the silliness of judging
a method by what its count rule does with some other method's balloting,
when the method we're judging doesn't use that balloting.


When you think that this concept is "vague," "sloppy" and
"dishonest"

I'm not saying that the concept to which you refer so vaguely is
vague or sloppy or dishonest. Your reference to it is certainly
vague, and your attempt to save BPGMC by requiring the tested method's
count rule to be used with a different method's balloting system,
with which it may not be usable--that was sloppy. Or, if it wasn't
pure sloppiness, maybe it was bias in favor of the way you want to
define BPGMC--that's what I meant by "a little bit less than honest
with us."


then you are invited to introduce your own
concept and to explain why you think that your own concept
might be better.
But unless you have done this,

The concept to which you refer is a way of defining a method. All of
us here and elsewhere who have defined methods have defined them in
some way. I daresay that most of us have defined them in terms
of a way in which voters are allowed to express their preferences or
ratings of the candidates, and a count rule for counting those
expressed preferences or ratings.

Explain why that's better than what you've vaguely referred to?
Look, if you want to introduce here a way of defining methods that's
new here, then you first must define it much better than you have.

Then you must show why it's better. It isn't on me to show that it
isn't better--least of all now, when it hasn't been defined, but has
only been vaguely referred to.

For instance, after you define your idea much more clearly than you'
have defined it, then you should write definitions for Plurality,
Approval, IRV, Tideman(wv) and BeatpathWinner, using the form that
you propose for method definitions.

But I am NOT asking you to do that, because it doesn't sound like
something that would be useful. I'm saying that if you want to
discuss the issue of whether your way is better, then you must do as
I suggested in the 3 preceding paragraphs.

you have to
live with the fact that the concept that election methods
are defined on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities
of the voters is widely used.

Fine, I'll take your word for that, that someone else, somewhere else,
defines voting systems in a different way that you refer to vaguely.
But I'm not asking you for a more precise specification about that.
I doubt that it would be useful. I merely state that you've referred
to it vaguely, and I'm willing to leave it at that and take your
word for it that someone defines methods in that sort of a way.


However, I don't have the impression that your statements have
anything to do with majority winner sets or beat path GMC.

This has been about a problem of BPGMC.






Markus Schulze


_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-28 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF




Markus said:

you wrote (28 Nov 2000):
  Excuse me, but I didn't notice anything about von Neumann-
  Morgenstern utilities in your definition of "Schulze's
  method", for example.

In my definition of the Schulze method, I talk about the
number of voters who strictly prefer candidate X to candidate
Y. When you know the von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
voters, then you also know how many voters strictly prefer
candidate X to candidate Y. Therefore the Schulze method
can also be defined in terms of von Neumann-Morgenstern
utilities.

Look, I don't care how you find out people's sincere preferences,
but what you're saying is that you define "Schulze's method" in terms
of sincere preferences. It makes no sense to define a method that
way, since the method's actual input consists of votes, not preferences,
and those votes are what the method must act on.

You've contradicted yourself about whether you define BPGMC in terms
of preferences or votes. And now you say you define "Schulze's method"
in terms of sincere preferences, which is entirely absurd, because
a method can only act on votes. By all means define your criterion
in terms of sincere preferences, with a stipulation of sincere voting,
but a voting system must be defined in terms of votes rather than
preferences.



You wrote (28 Nov 2000):
  How does it save your BPGMC criterion from its faults that
  I described?

In my definition of beat path GMC, I talk about the number of
voters who strictly prefer candidate X to candidate Y.

No, a voting systek must be defined in terms of how it acts on
people's actual votes, not on their preferences.


When
you know the von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters,
then you also know how many voters strictly prefer candidate X
to candidate Y. Therefore beat path GMC can also be defined in
terms of von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities.

No. For the reasons I stated above.



Again: When you think that the well known and widely used
concept that criteria and election methods are defined on the
reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters is
"vague," "sloppy," "dishonest," "faulty," "poor," "silly"
and "useless" then you are invited to introduce your own
concept and to explain why you think that your own concept
might be better. Nobody hinders you from introducing your
own concept.

Again: I didn't say that the concept that you hinted about is
any of those things. I didn't criticize it at all. But, from your
demonstration of its use so far, I must say that it's an entirely
inadequate way to define a voting system, if it's used as you
describe. That's because you speak of using the utilities to determine
people's sincere preferences, and defining the method in terms of
those sincere preferences. What you forgot to explain was: How does
the voting system find out the voters' von Neumann-Morgenstern
utilities? The only input available to the voting system is the
voters' actual votes.

There's no need for me to introduce a new concept for what input to
refer to when defining voting systems. All of us define them in
terms of people's votes. The voting system specifies a way that
voters may express their preferences in the balloting, and a count
rule for choosing a winner based on those ballots. That's how
voting systems are defined, by everyone who defines a voting system.

As I said, I don't have any argument with your claim that someone
else does it differently. That's their business, and it's fine with
me. I have no idea how it would be done, but I'm not asking you
to explain it. However what you've said so far about how it's done
wouldn't work: You said that we define a voting system in terms
of sincere preferences rather than in terms of votes. That's absurd.
You said that the vN-M utilities are used to determine people's
sincere preferences, but you didn't explain how the voting system
determines those utilities.

Mike Ossipoff


_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-28 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Mike,

you wrote (28 Nov 2000):
 Markus wrote (28 Nov 2000)
  Mike wrote (28 Nov 2000):
   Excuse me, but I didn't notice anything about von Neumann-
   Morgenstern utilities in your definition of "Schulze's
   method", for example.
 
  In my definition of the Schulze method, I talk about the
  number of voters who strictly prefer candidate X to candidate
  Y. When you know the von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
  voters, then you also know how many voters strictly prefer
  candidate X to candidate Y. Therefore the Schulze method
  can also be defined in terms of von Neumann-Morgenstern
  utilities.

 Look, I don't care how you find out people's sincere preferences,
 but what you're saying is that you define "Schulze's method" in terms
 of sincere preferences. It makes no sense to define a method that
 way, since the method's actual input consists of votes, not preferences,
 and those votes are what the method must act on.

 You've contradicted yourself about whether you define BPGMC in terms
 of preferences or votes. And now you say you define "Schulze's method"
 in terms of sincere preferences, which is entirely absurd, because
 a method can only act on votes. By all means define your criterion
 in terms of sincere preferences, with a stipulation of sincere voting,
 but a voting system must be defined in terms of votes rather than
 preferences.

It isn't clear to me why you believe that the Schulze method and
beat path GMC were defined in terms of SINCERE preferences. In so
far as I wrote that I use "the concept that criteria and election
methods are defined on the REPORTED von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities
of the voters" it is clear that I am talking about the REPORTED
von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters and not about the
SINCERE von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters.

You wrote (28 Nov 2000):
 From your demonstration of its use so far, I must say that it's an
 entirely inadequate way to define a voting system, if it's used as
 you describe. That's because you speak of using the utilities to
 determine people's sincere preferences, and defining the method in
 terms of those sincere preferences.

Again: It isn't clear to me why you believe that the Schulze method
and beat path GMC were defined in terms of SINCERE preferences.

You wrote (28 Nov 2000):
 You said that we define a voting system in terms of sincere
 preferences rather than in terms of votes. That's absurd.
 You said that the vN-M utilities are used to determine people's
 sincere preferences, but you didn't explain how the voting system
 determines those utilities.

Again: It isn't clear to me why you believe that the Schulze method
and beat path GMC were defined in terms of SINCERE preferences.

Again: When you think that the well known and widely used
concept that criteria and election methods are defined on the
reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters is
"vague," "sloppy," "dishonest," "faulty," "poor," "silly,"
"useless" and "contradictory" then you are invited to introduce
your own concept and to explain why you think that your own
concept might be better. Nobody hinders you from introducing
your own concept.

You wrote (28 Nov 2000):
 There's no need for me to introduce a new concept.

Then you have to live with the fact that the concept that
criteria and election methods are defined on the reported von
Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the voters is widely used.

Markus Schulze





Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-28 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Mike,

you wrote (28 Nov 2000):
 Ok. So now you're saying that, when Schulze's method is used, voters
 report their vN-M utilities. You'd previously given the impression
 that the voters report pairwise preferences, via a ranking. Which
 is it?

 Yes, you'll say that someone could rank the candidates in order of
 their vN-M utilities for that voter. Fine, but the voter reports
 pairwise preferences, via a ranking, with your method, yes? You can
 call that reporting the order of his vN-M utilities, or we could just
 as well call it reporting pairwise preferences that may or may not
 be sincere.

 So now, unless you're really changing that, we're back to you saying
 that, actually, with your method, voters report pairwise preferences,
 via a ranking. You call it reporting pairwise preferences which may
 be insincere, and I'd say it would make more sense to say that people
 are simply casting pairwise votes with their ranking, but now that
 I know what you mean, it doesn't matter which way we say it.

 Good, because that's what I thought--people report pairwise preferences
 in your method, which means they cast pairwise votes.

 Now that we know what you mean, it's evident that it doesn't do
 anything to save BPGMC. All this mumbojumbo about vN-M utilities,
 and what it still amounts to is that your method, like all rank
 methods, is defined in terms of the rankings that people vote.

 Sometimes you say that your BPGMC is defined in terms of preferences
 and sometimes you say it's defined in terms of votes. Now I realize
 that when you say "preferences" you mean preferences that may be
 insincere, and so we can assume that by pairwise prefereces you mean
 pairwise votes.

 Fine. We're now back to this: Plurality meets your BPGMC. You
 say it doesn't, because you say that Plurality should be tested by
 applying its count rule to rankk balloting, which Plurality doesn't
 use, by calling top-rankedness a Plurality vote. You never answered
 about how you'd apply that notion to Approval, Cardinal Ratings,
 and single-winner Cumulative, and it's evident now that you aren't
 going to, because of course you know that it can't be applied to them.

 And all that garbage about vN-M utilities was just an attempt to
 use big words to try to cover up the fact that you can't defend your
 faulty definition of BPGMC.

The concept that criteria and election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
voters presumes that every voter casts (not necessarily
sincerely) his von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities and that the
used election method takes from the reported von Neumann-
Morgenstern utilities that information that this election
method needs to calculate the winner. You claim that this
concept was "faulty" because some election methods depend on
LESS than the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities.
But when you re-think your statement then you will observe
that this concept is problematic only when the used election
method depends on MORE than just the reported von Neumann-
Morgenstern utilities.

Again: When you really think that the well known and widely
used concept that criteria and election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
voters is "inadequate," "vague," "sloppy," "dishonest," 
"absurd," "faulty," "poor," "silly," "contradictory,"
"useless," "garbage" and "mumbojumbo" then you are invited
to introduce your own concept and to explain why you think
that your own concept might be better. Nobody hinders you
from introducing your own concept.

However, I don't have the impression that your statements have
anything to do with majority winner sets or beat path GMC.

Markus Schulze





Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-27 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Mike,

I have already said in a different context (23 Sep 2000)
that I use the concept that election methods are defined
on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities of the
voters. But in your reply (23 Sep 2000) you wrote that
this concept was "funny," "incomplete," "undefined,"
"vague" and "not precise." Now you write that this
concept was also "sloppy" and "dishonest."

If you didn't refuse to read scientific literature then you
would observe that the concept that election methods are
defined on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities
of the voters is widely used and that e.g. Gibbard and
Hylland use this concept for their impossibility theorems.

When you think that this concept is "vague," "sloppy" and
"dishonest" then you are invited to introduce your own
concept and to explain why you think that your own concept
might be better. But unless you have done this, you have to
live with the fact that the concept that election methods
are defined on the reported von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities
of the voters is widely used.

However, I don't have the impression that your statements have
anything to do with majority winner sets or beat path GMC.

Markus Schulze




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-26 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Mike,

you wrote (21 Nov 2000):
 Plurality doesn't have rank balloting. Plurality isn't just a
 count rule to be applied to rank-ballots. Plurality, like any
 voting system, is a combination of a balloting system and a
 count rule.

I don't agree with you that the ballot design is a part of the
election method. To my opinion, the ballot design --especially
questions like (1) how the candidates have to be sorted on the
ballot, (2) whether there should be party affiliations, (3)
whether there should be write-in options, (4) whether there
should be a NOTA option, (5) what should be done when NOTA is
chosen or (6) whether the ballots should be counted by hand or
by computer-- is a part of the electoral law but not of the
election method itself.

However, I don't have the impression that your statements have
anything to do with majority winner sets or beat path GMC.

Markus Schulze





Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-26 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF



Markus said:

you wrote (21 Nov 2000):
  Plurality doesn't have rank balloting. Plurality isn't just a
  count rule to be applied to rank-ballots. Plurality, like any
  voting system, is a combination of a balloting system and a
  count rule.

I don't agree with you that the ballot design is a part of the
election method. To my opinion, the ballot design --especially
questions like (1) how the candidates have to be sorted on the
ballot, (2) whether there should be party affiliations, (3)
whether there should be write-in options, (4) whether there
should be a NOTA option, (5) what should be done when NOTA is
chosen or (6) whether the ballots should be counted by hand or
by computer-- is a part of the electoral law but not of the
election method itself.

I reply:

I didn't say that the shape, size  color of the ballot, and the
order of the candidates on the ballot, and whether there should be
party affiliations, and whether there should be write-in options,
and whether the ballots should be counted by hand or by computer--
is part of the voting system. Also, adding NOTA to the alternatives isn't 
part of the voting system either, as you said.

Those things are details of balloting, but they aren't part of the
intrinsic balloting system any more than they're part of the voting
system.

Now I'll tell you something that _is_ the intrinsic balloting system:

The basic rules for how voters may express preferences for candidates,
disregarding size  shape of ballot, which candidates are allowed on
the ballot, in what order the candidates are listed, etc.

Either you're real sloppy today, or you're being a little less than
honest with us
, if you're claiming that the basic rules governing
how voters may express preferences for candidates isn't part of the
voting system. Has it occurred to you why they call it a _voting_
system? "Doo...oing" :-)

Markus continues:

However, I don't have the impression that your statements have
anything to do with majority winner sets or beat path GMC.

I reply:

Wrong. My initial comment was that your definition of Beatpath GMC
was worded in such a way that no method can pass it. Then you changed
your definition from being about preferences to being about votes.
Then I told you that, by your new definition, Plurality meets
Beatpath GMC.

Then, wanting to be nice, I said that it isn't just Beatpath GMC,
but also Condorcet needs the fix that I described. Then I began
using Condorcet's Criterion as an example, because it's a simpler
criterion, and a much more widely-used one than Beatpath GMC.
But the discussion was still about Beatpath GMC, and whether or
not it's met by Plurality, and whether your newest statements about
BPGMC make any sense.

By the way, you never did say whether Condorcet's Criterion, according
to your way of looking at it, as met by Approval. While you're at
it, you can tell me whether it's met by Cardinal Ratings and
single-winner Cumulative.

As I said, the fact that you can't answer that shows that your
definitions of CC  BPGMC don't work.

Look, it just fortuitously happens that a ranking reveals a 1st
choice, and so you can call that 1st choice the Plurality vote.
But it isn't always the case that a balloting system for one type
of voting system can be counted by another voting system's count
rule. To base a criterion's definition on an attempt to do that
is silly.

If you wanted CC  BPGMC to mean what you're saying they mean, then
you ought to say what you mean when you write the definition.
You should say, for example: "If we have the voters rank the
candidates, and then we count those rank ballots according to
a certain voting system's count rule, then..." If you don't say what
you mean when you write the definition, then people have no way of knowing 
what you man. Anyway, don't bother rewriting your BPGMC definition in that 
way, because it wouldn't make any sense, as I've
already explained.

Mike Ossipoff





Markus Schulze



_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-25 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Mike,

you wrote (24 Nov 2000):
 Ok, that was what I'd thought, but the other day you posted a
 definiton in terms of people preferring one candidate to another,
 and the natural interpretation of that is felt preferences,
 sincere preferences. But I recognize that BPGMC is in terms of
 voted preferences, and therefore I agree that BeatpathWinner
 meets BPGMC. And so does Plurality. I'm not just picking on
 BPGMC. The usual definitions of the Condorcet Criterion have the
 same problem. When CC is defined in terms of sincere preferences,
 as it often is, then no method meets it. When it's defined in
 terms of voted preferences, then Plurality meets it.

FPP violates Condorcet and beat path GMC.

Example:

   40 voters vote A  B  C.
   35 voters vote B  C  A.
   25 voters vote C  B  A.

   Due to the Condorcet criterion, candidate B must be
   elected. Due to beat path GMC, candidate B must be
   elected. But the FPP winner is candidate A.

   In the example above, I didn't make any presumptions
   about whether the voters vote sincerely or strategically.
   In the example above, I didn't make any presumptions
   about the sincere opinions of the voters. Did I?

Markus Schulze




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-25 Thread Bart Ingles



Bart Ingles wrote:
 
 Markus Schulze wrote:
 
  FPP violates Condorcet and beat path GMC.
 
  Example:
 
 40 voters vote A  B  C.
 35 voters vote B  C  A.
 25 voters vote C  B  A.
 
 Due to the Condorcet criterion, candidate B must be
 elected. Due to beat path GMC, candidate B must be
 elected. But the FPP winner is candidate A.
 
 In the example above, I didn't make any presumptions
 about whether the voters vote sincerely or strategically.
 In the example above, I didn't make any presumptions
 about the sincere opinions of the voters. Did I?
 
 Uh, yes, you presume the voters will vote sincerely in FPP, in order for
 A to win.

My mistake, I can't say that you presume sincere voting for FPP, since
you don't specify whether the rankings are sincere.  On the other hand,
the example is not sufficient to show A as the FPP winner.




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-25 Thread Bart Ingles



Markus Schulze wrote:

 FPP violates Condorcet and beat path GMC.
 
 Example:
 
40 voters vote A  B  C.
35 voters vote B  C  A.
25 voters vote C  B  A.
 
Due to the Condorcet criterion, candidate B must be
elected. Due to beat path GMC, candidate B must be
elected. But the FPP winner is candidate A.
 
In the example above, I didn't make any presumptions
about whether the voters vote sincerely or strategically.
In the example above, I didn't make any presumptions
about the sincere opinions of the voters. Did I?


Uh, yes, you presume the voters will vote sincerely in FPP, in order for
A to win.




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-24 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF



Markus wrote:

Beat path GMC is defined in terms of voted preferences.
Beat path GMC is met e.g. by Schulze(wv)

I reply:

Ok, that was what I'd thought, but the other day you posted a
definiton in terms of people preferring one candidate to another,
and the natural interpretation of that is felt preferences,
sincere preferences. But I recognize that BPGMC is in terms of
voted preferences, and therefore I agree that BeatpathWinner meets
BPGMC.

And so does Plurality.

I'm not just picking on BPGMC. The usual definitions of the
Condorcet Criterion have the same problem. When CC is defined in
terms of sincere preferences, as it often is, then no method meets it.
When it's defined in terms of voted preferences, then Plurality meets
it.

So here's how I define the Condorcet Criterion:

If there's a sincere CW, and if everyone votes sincerely, then
the sincere CW should win.

Sincere Voting:

A voter votes sincrely if he doesn't vote a preference that isn't
a sincere preference or leave unvoted a sincere preference that the
balloting system would have allowed him to vote in addition to the
preferences that he actually did vote.

(By "preference", I mean "pairwise preference")

[end of definition]

A similar fix could fix BPGMC, as well as Condorcet Loser,
Mutual Majority Criterion, etc., which share that problem.

Mike Ossipoff





_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-22 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Mike,

you wrote (21 Nov 2000):
 It seems to me that no method can meet that criterion. Say, for
 instance, that the method is BeatpathWinner, defined in terms
 of actual voted preferences. Maybe the voter believe that they
 have a situation where they need defensives truncation, and so
 they don't vote all of the preferences that they feel. (It's
 also possible that some voters merely might not have time to
 rank all of the candidates, or don't feel like expressing
 preferences for disliked candidates over more disliked ones--
 there are some voters who might feel that way).

 Then those people's preferences won't translate into actual
 voted preferences on the BeatpathWinner ballots. BeatpathWinner
 is defined in terms of voted preferences rather than felt
 preferences, and your criterion is defined in terms of felt
 preferences. You told me that a criterion shouldn't be defined
 in that way. Of course you could specify that if some voters
 have certain sincere preferences and vote sincerely, then a
 certain result must happen. In that way your criterion would
 be meetable, without being met by Plurality, as it would be
 if you merely defined it in terms of voted preferences.

Beat path GMC is defined in terms of voted preferences.
Beat path GMC is met e.g. by Schulze(wv):
http://www.fortunecity.com/meltingpot/harrow/124/methods.html

Markus Schulze




Re: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-21 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF



Markus defined Beatpath GMC as follows:


"X  Y" means that an absolute majority of the voters
strictly prefers candidate X to candidate Y.
"There is a majority beat path from X to Y" means that
(1) X  Y or
(2) there is a set of candidates C[1],...,C[n] with
X  C[1]  ...  C[n]  Y.

If there is a majority beat path from candidate A to
candidate B and no majority beat path from candidate B
to candidate A, then candidate B must not be elected.

I reply:

It seems to me that no method can meet that criterion. Say, for instance,
that the method is BeatpathWinner, defined in terms of actual voted
preferences. Maybe the voter believe that they have a situation where
they need defensives truncation, and so they don't vote all of the
preferences that they feel. (It's also possible that some voters
merely might not have time to rank all of the candidates, or don't
feel like expressing preferences for disliked candidates over more
disliked ones--there are some voters who might feel that way).

Then those people's preferences won't translate into actual voted
preferences on the BeatpathWinner ballots. BeatpathWinner is defined
in terms of voted preferences rather than felt preferences, and
your criterion is defined in terms of felt preferences. You told me
that a criterion shouldn't be defined in that way. Of course you
could specify that if some voters have certain sincere preferences and
vote sincerely, then a certain result must happen. In that way your
criterion would be meetable, without being met by Plurality, as it
would be if you merely defined it in terms of voted preferences.


Mike Ossipoff


_
Get more from the Web.  FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com




[EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-19 Thread LAYTON Craig

I'm proposing a majority winner set method.  It could go with a new criteria
(which would be failed by margin systems, and either passed or failed by
winning votes systems depending on the specific wording).

Definition of majority winner set:
The set of candidates who pairwise beat all candidates outside the Smith
set, and pairwise beat at least one candidate inside the Smith set by an
absolute majority

Where this set contains at least one candidate, and is smaller than the
Smith set, all candidates not in the majority winner set are eliminated.
The majority winner set becomes the new Smith set, and the test is
reapplied.

eg Smith Set

AB   55 - 45
BC   47 - 35
CA   51 - 35

-Majority Winner Set consists of A  C
-A is eliminated
-Majority Winner Set consists of C

Also handy for resolving draws.  Consider the same as above, but with CA
50-50.  Majority winner set consists of A.

Comments?




RE: [EM] Majority winner set

2000-11-19 Thread LAYTON Craig

Martin wrote:

Isn't there another majority winner set consisting of A  B? And another
for B 
C?
Or do I misunderstand your 'absolute majority'?

Yes, I think so.  Absolute majority means majority of all votes cast (ie
over 50%).  B is not included in the majority winner set.  However, I should
clarify that the majority winner set is those candidates who are in the
Smith set, and pairwise beat another member of the Smith set by an absolute
majority.  This removes the contradiction in my original message.  If B
defeated C by 52 - 48, then the majority winner set would consist of all
three candidates A,B,C, and another method is needed to decide between them
- probably Minmax(wv) for want of a better alternative.

LAYTON Craig wrote:

 I'm proposing a majority winner set method.  It could go with a new
criteria
 (which would be failed by margin systems, and either passed or failed by
 winning votes systems depending on the specific wording).

 Definition of majority winner set:
 The set of candidates who pairwise beat all candidates outside the Smith
 set, and pairwise beat at least one candidate inside the Smith set by an
 absolute majority

 Where this set contains at least one candidate, and is smaller than the
 Smith set, all candidates not in the majority winner set are eliminated.
 The majority winner set becomes the new Smith set, and the test is
 reapplied.

 eg Smith Set

 AB   55 - 45
 BC   47 - 35
 CA   51 - 35

 -Majority Winner Set consists of A  C

 -A is eliminated
 -Majority Winner Set consists of C

 Also handy for resolving draws.  Consider the same as above, but with CA
 50-50.  Majority winner set consists of A.

 Comments?