Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-10-01 Thread John Collier


At 03:24 PM 2014-09-30, Howard Pattee wrote:
At 08:58 PM 9/29/2014, Clark
Goble wrote:

HP: To get a fairer picture of
how physicists think, please peruse
this
survey.
CG: I'd seen that before. While it's a great guide to interpretations of
quantum mechanics it really doesn't address the nominalism issue.

HP: I'm curious how you would state the nominalism issue? In my view, in
at least half the questions the answers imply a pro- or anti-nominalistic
stance (Questions 1, 2, 3, 4, 9, 10, 12, 15).
The realism-nominalism issue is a complex one with both a traditional
form (pre-logicism) and a more contemporary form, championed by Goodman
and Quine, originally, in this century. On the traditional view concepts
are constructions of our minds, and everything that exists is a
particular, and all that is real is what exists (I add the last to
accommodate Peirce). It is typically associated with some form of
materialism or physicalism, but Peirce also applies the notion to some
idealists, arguing that their generals are not real in his sense. I will
leave that aside. Proponents are Locke, Hume, Reid and the British
Empiricists in general.
The more contemporary nominalism is based in a view of language and
thought (which is understood on a linguistic model), and pays special
attention to what we can sense. Quine, for example, calls himself a
physicalist because he believes that our knowledge comes from the senses,
which are physical (as a pragmatist, he shares this with Peirce, except
Peirce regards them as external, not physical, but that might be only a
difference in terminology). Quine and Goodman believe that there are no
propositions, only instances of sentences or statements, and these are
related not by identity of some sort (being of the identical kind) but
just by being similar. From this and the grounding of knowledge in the
senses Quine argues that meaning must be limited to what he calls the
ersatz version such that dispositions to assent alone
determine meaning, and that translation is multiply ambiguous, even for
our own language onto itself. The only meaning that remains is what
withstands this transformation, but he agrees that this is not what we
usually call meaning. Followers have argued that this makes truth either
trivial (Paul Horwich, Huw Price), or dispensable, with assent being all
that matters (Richard Rorty). This differs from the traditional view,
since it accepts the existence of external objects in a well-defined way,
and even having an individual essence that is real (Locke, though he
thought that language usually followed the nominal essence -- for Quine
this is the only way possible). For Goodman the big issue is what sort of
similarity matters. He points out that all evidence that we have of
emeralds is compatible both with the projection that emeralds are blue
until the are observed and green afterwards (I am simplifying), so both
ways of projecting all emeralds are green and all
emeralds are blue until observed and then they are green are
equally compatible with all evidence, so we have no evidence basis for
choosing one or the other generalization. Note that this may seem odd,
but it is a consequence of assuming t5hat we o0nly observe particulars
and any generals are ones we freely make up. The big issue for the
contemporary nominalist, as Russell pointed out, is whether similarity is
sufficient first of all, and second, whether it works. He argued that
similarity, to work, must be a universal, so the nominalist project,
clever though it is, falls apart from the get go. He then argues that
once you accept this argument, that it is obvious that similarity is not
sufficient, since it raise the question, similarity of what? Everything
is similar to everything else in some respect, so we need respects. (I
read this argument in a mimeographed paper of Russell's at UCLA, and I am
not sure that it was ever published.)
The reason why I go into this is that it has some bearing on how to
evaluate all of the questions. I think that it is a given that for any
realist position there is a nominalist position in the contemporary sense
that can fit the same assent structure. Typically one is realist about
some things, but not others (for example one can be a realist about
physical laws but not numbers, or vice versa). So contemporary
nominalism, if it works at all, will work for all claims of reality
involving a specific external existence.
This isn't so for traditional nominalism, since they assume the existence
external conditions that make claims about particulars, at least, true.
Similarity is likewise and external condition. 
I think that many of the questions can be seen as about objective
projections by induction that would be acceptable to the traditional
nominalist who believes that everything that exists is a particular. This
view can be called (and is) scientific realism about the entities science
proposes. So I think the answers to many of the questions fits realism of
the 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-30 Thread Howard Pattee

At 08:58 PM 9/29/2014, Clark Goble wrote:
HP: To get a fairer picture of how physicists think, please peruse 
http://arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069v1.pdfthis survey.


CG: I'd seen that before. While it's a great guide to 
interpretations of quantum mechanics it really doesn't address the 
nominalism issue.


HP: I'm curious how you would state the nominalism issue? In my view, 
in at least half the questions the answers imply a pro- or 
anti-nominalistic stance (Questions 1, 2, 3, 4, 9, 10, 12, 15).


Howard


-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-30 Thread Benjamin Udell

Clark, list,

You wrote,

[CG] The line of thinking I was following was that generals, as
   used by Peirce, simply has much narrower application possible than
   universals like colors. It’s true that the universal yellow can be
   instantiated by a limited number of objects but is treated as an
   universal. However it seems like “some flowers are yellow” are
   different from “some men wear hats.” The distinction I was getting
   at, relative to Newton’s laws, was that distinction. The predicate
   “is wearing a hat” simply seems a different sort of thing from “is
   yellow.” Traditional universals within science accept the latter but
   tend not to apply it to the former.
   [End quote]

Peirce makes the distinction between mechanical qualities and qualities 
of feeling, see CP 1.422-426, circa 1896. Particularly interesting is 
that here he calls qualities generals - but qualities only as reflected 
on. http://www.textlog.de/4282.html .


I'd think that laws of physics are more general than a sensible quality 
like 'yellow', which is less widely applicable than the laws of physics 
in our known physical universe, even if one does think that sensible 
qualities are real.


Except when discussing 'universal' as understood in physics, it might be 
better to stick to 'more general' and 'less general', rather than trying 
for a distinction between 'universal' and 'general' that (A) merely 
involves different degrees of generality and (B) gets tangled up in 
terminological history. I've avoided (A) but tripped over (B).  At one 
time, I defined 'universal' and 'general' in the monadic case as 
follows: given a term H true of something, H is _/universal/_ if there 
is not also something of which H is false, otherwise H is _/special/_. 
Given a term H true of something, H is _/general/_ if there is something 
else of which H is true, otherwise H is _/singular/_. But that is more 
in keeping with everyday English than with logical and philosophical 
terminology, so if I need to discuss my notion of 'universal' you'll see 
me using an invented word for it.


 [CG] [...] I think realism in physics is also partially about
   that hope. I think when one is a realist about a particular claim
   that one also has a hope that a particular entity is just such a
   mind independent entity. So one can be a realist broadly about
   something we don’t know (say whether there are fundamental
   structures) but I take realism in practice to be claims about
   particular entities.

 If one is a realist only about things one doesn’t know, then do
   you think that makes one an instrumentalist about the other entities
   if one views such entities as simplified models and not the ultimate
   constituents?
   [End quote]

Realism about particular laws etc. is just realism adjoined to the claim 
to have found certain entities. 'Realism about GR' or 'Realism about 
natural selection', etc. But philosophical realism is not the sum or 
generality of such realisms. Instead _/realism about particular laws 
etc./_ is the sum or generality of such realisms.


If one is a realist _/only/_ about things that one doesn't know, then 
one implies that the real is not cognizable. I suppose that one could 
say in a loose sense that one is partly an instrumentalist about 
simplified models, but one may regard such models as still being close 
to the truth, and thus as reflecting something nearly real, and in that 
sense one is not an instrumentalist.  In On the Logic of Drawing 
Ancient History from Documents, EP 2, somewhere in pages 107–9 Peirce 
speaks of _/incomplexity/_, that of a hypothesis that seems too simple 
but whose trial may give a good 'leave,' as the billiard-players say, 
and be instructive for the pursuit of various and conflicting hypotheses 
that are less simple. One could loosely call that instrumentalism, but 
to regard the incomplex hypothesis as offering some degree of promise of 
leading to a true theory about something real, is not instrumentalism.


Regarding A-time and B-time, I thought that those were questions in 
philosophy of physics, not in physics. Do you think that they have 
something to do with the unification of space and time in the sense in 
which that unification is understood in physics - such as to modify the 
idea of the signal speed limit as a common yardstick of space and time?


Best, Ben

On 9/29/2014 2:36 PM, Clark Goble wrote:


On Sep 29, 2014, at 10:38 AM, Benjamin Udell wrote:

By the way, I think that we should remind or inform readers that many 
physicists, when they speak of 'realism', mean ideas such as that a 
particle has an objective, determinate state, even when unmeasured. 
Peirce's realism does not imply that, so far as I can see, and his 
realism about absolute chance doesn't clash with the denial of of 
such unmeasured objective determinate states either.


Yes. Great point. I really should have clarified the issues of realism 
in physics from more broad realism vs. 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-30 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 30, 2014, at 7:24 AM, Howard Pattee hpat...@roadrunner.com wrote:
 
 At 08:58 PM 9/29/2014, Clark Goble wrote:
 HP: To get a fairer picture of how physicists think, please peruse this 
 survey http://arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069v1.pdf.
 
 CG: I'd seen that before. While it's a great guide to interpretations of 
 quantum mechanics it really doesn't address the nominalism issue.
 
 HP: I'm curious how you would state the nominalism issue? In my view, in at 
 least half the questions the answers imply a pro- or anti-nominalistic stance 
 (Questions 1, 2, 3, 4, 9, 10, 12, 15).

To me nominalism is whether there are just particular things and not real 
generals. I don’t quite see how whether there’s really randomness (a property 
of the fundamental things), whether there are hidden variables, whether one 
should take a more epistemic view of QM, the role or the observer or so forth 
apply. Even with regards to interpretations of QM I’m not sure those get at the 
issue, although they are closer.

For instance, within the Everett MWI what are the ultimate constituents? 
Likewise with information-theoretical interpretations is the information the 
fundamental things? If so then if that’s all there is, isn’t that nominalism?

So I confess I’m a bit confused. Admittedly with regards to quantum mechanics 
things are odd enough that one has to unpack a lot. Further the authors note 
that a lot of the terms are intentionally left unpacked. So it’s not even clear 
how we are to take the terms. (Which I think is a bad thing in a poll like this 
where there may be ignorance or equivocation with regards to the terms)

Since you appear to think those question imply many physicists aren’t 
nominalists, could you perhaps clarify why? Maybe I’m just thinking about this 
all wrong.


-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-30 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 30, 2014, at 9:21 AM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com 
 mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:
 
 If one is a realist _only_ about things that one doesn't know, then one 
 implies that the real is not cognizable. I suppose that one could say in a 
 loose sense that one is partly an instrumentalist about simplified models, 
 but one may regard such models as still being close to the truth, and thus as 
 reflecting something nearly real, and in that sense one is not an 
 instrumentalist.  In On the Logic of Drawing Ancient History from 
 Documents, EP 2, somewhere in pages 107–9 Peirce speaks of _incomplexity_, 
 that of a hypothesis that seems too simple but whose trial may give a good 
 'leave,' as the billiard-players say, and be instructive for the pursuit of 
 various and conflicting hypotheses that are less simple. One could loosely 
 call that instrumentalism, but to regard the incomplex hypothesis as offering 
 some degree of promise of leading to a true theory about something real, is 
 not instrumentalism.
 
 

The way this is often dealt with is via convergence - traditional scientific 
realism being one example. I’m not sure this implies the real is not 
cognizable, although that’s definitely been a position. (Wasn’t Dummett’s views 
on realism tied to that? A set with one uncognizable element - it’s been too 
long since I read him)

There are other solutions of course - Heisenberg actually wrote a little book 
discussing objects like tables and then fundamental objects. It’s been years 
since I read it so I don’t want to say too much about it. I vaguely recall it 
being a kind of realism that allows macro-objects to be real. But I may be 
misrecalling that.

Whether the “nearly real” is good enough is a reasonable question. Like you, I 
see it as good enough, but I think there are important caveats one has to make 
which is why I mentioned that on practical grounds for many entities they act 
like instrumentalists.

 Peirce makes the distinction between mechanical qualities and qualities of 
 feeling, see CP 1.422-426, circa 1896. Particularly interesting is that here 
 he calls qualities generals - but qualities only as reflected on. 
 http://www.textlog.de/4282.html http://www.textlog.de/4282.html . 

Thanks. I thought he’d said something like that but I couldn’t find it. That’s 
closer to the distinction I was poorly making.

 I'd think that laws of physics are more general than a sensible quality like 
 'yellow', which is less widely applicable than the laws of physics in our 
 known physical universe, even if one does think that sensible qualities are 
 real.
 
 Except when discussing 'universal' as understood in physics, it might be 
 better to stick to 'more general' and 'less general', rather than trying for 
 a distinction between 'universal' and 'general' that (A) merely involves 
 different degrees of generality and (B) gets tangled up in terminological 
 history. 

It’s a subtle issue that’s hard to get terminology for. (Probably one should do 
a literature search and see how others have solved it - but I don’t have time 
for that unfortunately) I’m not sure I like more or less general either since 
the more or less is in different areas.

 Regarding A-time and B-time, I thought that those were questions in 
 philosophy of physics, not in physics. Do you think that they have something 
 to do with the unification of space and time in the sense in which that 
 unification is understood in physics - such as to modify the idea of the 
 signal speed limit as a common yardstick of space and time?

I think the distinction between physics and philosophy of physics is blurry 
despite many physicists having a negative view of philosophy. Lee Smolin argues 
that it should be even blurrier and that physicists should pay more attention 
to philosophy. And it seems often that when physicists do philosophical 
thinking they often tend to jump in ignorant of what’s been done in philosophy. 
(I can think of a few major recent works where a little more research in 
philosophy would have benefited the book significantly)

With regards to the A/B debate, I think if there is an absolute time 
ontologically and measurements just behave akin to time distortion then that 
implies a lot about time/space relations. I’m very skeptical about such views. 
I was actually surprised when I first encountered it that there was such a 
large philosophical literature arguing against a more literal view of GR. I do 
think these issues end up being pertinent for searching for a grand unified 
theory. I don’t think most physicists have paid much attention to such things. 
But then I do notice more and more are appearing at arXiv.org 
http://arxiv.org/ so perhaps they are having a bit of an effect. I’m not sure 
I’m really qualified to say how influential all this is since I’ve been out of 
physics for quite a few years now.
-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-30 Thread Benjamin Udell

Clark, list,

You wrote,

 [CG] It’s a subtle issue that’s hard to get terminology for.
   (Probably one should do a literature search and see how others have
   solved it - but I don’t have time for that unfortunately) I’m not
   sure I like more or less general either since the more or less is in
   different areas.
   [End quote]

Another problem with 'general' is that 'general among' very nearly means 
'universal among'. If something is general among horses or general to 
horses, one might mean that there could be exceptions, but the 
exceptions would be special cases that don't really invalidate the 
general rule; but the general rule might not be by definition of the 
class or by the essential nature of the elements of the class. That 
nuance is involved in 'generic', which sometimes now replaces 'general' 
- something generic to horses is something that they have by essential 
nature or as implied by (sufficiently detailed) definition, e.g., four 
legs, but definition and nature allow of accidental exceptions.


A problem that would arise again even with an invented word to replace 
'universal' in the sense of 'true in one case and exceptionless 
elsewhere' is that something universal to elements of a set or class is 
a general in the larger universe but not necessarily universal to 
everything in that universe. That creates a risk of confusion rooted not 
merely in conventional language but in logic. So the conflict of senses 
will recur. I think that the word translated as 'universal' in Aristotle 
is _/catholikon/_. Greek _/catholikon/_ , as far as I can tell, usually 
means 'universal' in pretty much the everyday English sense. So the use 
of 'a universal' without qualification to mean something true of as few 
as two things seems an unfortunate turn in the history of terms; such 
universality is relative to those as-few-as-two things. To avoid the 
semantic influence of cases of relative universality, one would need a 
special set of terms or phrases for the non-relative cases.


You wrote,

 [CG] Whether the “nearly real” is good enough is a reasonable
   question. Like you, I see it as good enough, but I think there are
   important caveats one has to make which is why I mentioned that on
   practical grounds for many entities they act like instrumentalists.
   [End quote]

I'd say that they're acting as fallibilists. They may also hold that a 
theory should be evaluated not for the plausibility of its assumptions 
but the only for the success of its predictions, and it's more tempting 
to call that approach instrumentalism. Some have even held that it's 
okay and even necessary for the assumptions to be 'descriptively false'. 
Now, that could mean merely seemingly false by omission of factors that 
one would have thought to be pertinent, and I do think that is part of 
it. However, sometimes the assumptions clash with things that we think 
that we know, and the theory's success is telling us that some of our 
supposed knowledge is false. So, in expectation of unknown unknowns, we 
shouldn't rule a theory out automatically solely because its assumptions 
conflict with at least one of our beliefs. Still, I'd call that 
fallibilism, not instrumentalism, although it reflects the spirit of 
some who call themselves instrumentalists. Such considerations may also 
be involved in reconciling the idea of plausibility above and Peirce's 
idea of plausibility, which I think is something a bit different. But 
even Peirce's idea of plausibility is more about developing a theory 
than about evaluating its success. Most scientific hypotheses, including 
quite a few highly plausible ones, get disconfirmed, and I don't think 
that Peirce held that hypotheses that stand up to testing generally turn 
out to have been the most plausible in advance.


Best, Ben

On 9/30/2014 12:26 PM, Clark Goble wrote:


On Sep 30, 2014, at 9:21 AM, Benjamin Udell wrote:

If one is a realist _/only/_ about things that one doesn't know, then 
one implies that the real is not cognizable. I suppose that one could 
say in a loose sense that one is partly an instrumentalist about 
simplified models, but one may regard such models as still being 
close to the truth, and thus as reflecting something nearly real, and 
in that sense one is not an instrumentalist.  In On the Logic of 
Drawing Ancient History from Documents, EP 2, somewhere in pages 
107–9, Peirce speaks of _/incomplexity/_, that of a hypothesis that 
seems too simple but whose trial may give a good 'leave,' as the 
billiard-players say, and be instructive for the pursuit of various 
and conflicting hypotheses that are less simple. One could loosely 
call that instrumentalism, but to regard the incomplex hypothesis as 
offering some degree of promise of leading to a true theory about 
something real, is not instrumentalism.


The way this is often dealt with is via convergence - traditional 
scientific realism being one example. I’m not sure this implies the 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-30 Thread Benjamin Udell

Clark, list, sorry, a few corrections/additions in *bold red*. - Best, Ben

On 9/30/2014 1:58 PM, Benjamin Udell wrote:

Clark, list,

You wrote,

 [CG] It’s a subtle issue that’s hard to get terminology for.
   (Probably one should do a literature search and see how others have
   solved it - but I don’t have time for that unfortunately) I’m not
   sure I like more or less general either since the more or less is in
   different areas.
   [End quote]

Another problem with 'general' is that 'general among' very nearly means 
'universal among'. If something is general among horses or general to 
horses, one might mean that there could be exceptions, but the 
exceptions would be special cases that don't really invalidate the 
general rule; but the general rule might not be by definition of the 
class or by the essential nature of the elements of the class. That 
nuance is involved in 'generic', which sometimes now replaces 'general' 
- something generic to horses is something that they have by essential 
nature or as implied by (sufficiently detailed) definition, e.g., four 
legs, but definition and nature allow of accidental exceptions.


A problem that would arise again even with an invented word to replace 
'universal' in the sense of 'true in one case and exceptionless 
elsewhere' is that something universal to elements of a set or class is 
a general in the larger universe but not necessarily universal to 
everything in that universe. That creates a risk of confusion rooted not 
merely in conventional language but in logic. So the conflict of senses 
will recur. I think that the word translated as 'universal' in Aristotle 
is _/catholikon/_. Greek _/catholikon/_ , as far as I can tell, usually 
means 'universal' in pretty much the everyday English sense. So the use 
of 'a universal' without qualification to mean something true of as few 
as two things *among many* seems an unfortunate turn in the history of 
terms; such universality is relative to *as few as two things among 
many*. To avoid the semantic influence of cases of relative 
universality, one would need a special set of terms or phrases for the 
non-relative cases.


You wrote,

 [CG] Whether the “nearly real” is good enough is a reasonable
   question. Like you, I see it as good enough, but I think there are
   important caveats one has to make which is why I mentioned that on
   practical grounds for many entities they act like instrumentalists.
   [End quote]

I'd say that they're acting as fallibilists. They may also hold that a 
theory should be evaluated not for the plausibility of its assumptions 
but the only for the success of its predictions, and it's more tempting 
to call that approach instrumentalism. Some have even held that it's 
okay and even necessary for the assumptions to be 'descriptively false'. 
Now, that could mean merely seemingly false by omission of factors that 
one would have thought to be pertinent, and I do think that is part of 
it. However, sometimes the assumptions clash with things that we think 
that we know, and the theory's success is telling us that some of our 
supposed knowledge is false. So, in expectation of unknown unknowns, we 
shouldn't rule a theory out automatically solely because its assumptions 
conflict with at least one of our beliefs. Still, I'd call that 
fallibilism, not instrumentalism, although it reflects the spirit of 
some who call themselves instrumentalists. Such considerations may also 
be involved in reconciling the idea of plausibility above and Peirce's 
idea of plausibility, which I think is something a bit different. But 
even Peirce's idea of plausibility is more about developing a theory 
than about evaluating its success. Most scientific hypotheses, including 
quite a few highly plausible ones, get disconfirmed, and I don't think 
that Peirce held that hypotheses that stand up to testing generally turn 
out to have been the most plausible in advance.


*The case of the incomplex hypothesis which one really doesn't expect to 
be true is the closest, I think, to instrumentalism, but it's a case of 
treating a hypothesis instrumentally without embracing the view called 
'instrumentalism', which holds (or originally held, according to what we 
find in Peirce's account of it) that theories don't affirm objective 
laws or norms but merely predict particular results.

*

*Still, insofar as fallibilism applies to our beliefs, and incomplex 
hypotheses aside for the moment, how does one characterize other than as 
'instrumental' one's attitude _/toward/_ the tentative or experimental 
hypothesis or theory that conflicts with a belief that one holds? I 
would call it 'successiblism', the attitude that said hypothesis or 
theory is 'successible', i.e., it could be true, and that one could find 
the real through it. Even the incomplex hypothesis has to be granted 
some provisional credibility, as a kind of possible approximation to the 
truth. Of course one needs both 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-29 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 29, 2014, at 10:38 AM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:
 
 By the way, I think that we should remind or inform readers that many 
 physicists, when they speak of 'realism', mean ideas such as that a particle 
 has an objective, determinate state, even when unmeasured. Peirce's realism 
 does not imply that, so far as I can see, and his realism about absolute 
 chance doesn't clash with the denial of of such unmeasured objective 
 determinate states either.

Yes. Great point. I really should have clarified the issues of realism in 
physics from more broad realism vs. idealism debates such as those Dewey was 
involved in.

 On 9/28/2014 11:57 PM, Clark Goble wrote:
 
 On Sep 27, 2014, at 8:11 PM, Benjamin Udell wrote:
 
  [BU] A realist can and often enough ought to be skeptical about 
  particular models and diagrams as representative of reality. A realist 
  believes not that all generals are real but instead that some generals 
  are real and some generals are figmentitious.
 
 [CG] Yes, I think this is key. I think Peirceans have more tools at our 
 disposal because generals are broader than mere universals. (Broader in the 
 sense of encompassing more structures)
 
 [BU] I didn't know that Peirce or Peirceans made such a distinction.  Do you 
 remember where you've found that?  One finds Aristotle translated as using 
 the noun 'universal' to mean a character that belongs, or at least could 
 belong, to more than one thing, and even recent philosophers (E.J. Lowe, for 
 example) call 'universals and particulars' the things that Peirce called 
 'generals and singulars'. (The ambiguity of 'particular' as referring the 
 indefinite _something_ and the determinate _Socrates_ is another issue.)  
 Peirce's usage is more congenial to everyday English, wherein the noun 
 'universal' instead parallels the adjective, and, unqualified, evokes 
 unlimited generality, and the word 'general', unqualified, evokes a 
 generality that is not necessarily universal and uninterrupted. In logic, 
 examples of universal propositions are 'all G is H' and 'all is H'. That's 
 where I've noticed Peirce speaking of the universal, while a general term is, 
 roughly speaking, a non-singular term (leave plurals and polyads out of it 
 for the moment), and thus correlates to the Aristotelian idea of a universal. 
 Anyway, given the way that English works, I'd advise against a terminology in 
 which the general is said to be broader than the universal. Or maybe that was 
 a typo and you meant to say that the universal is broader than the general. I 
 think so, given I what I re-read now in your remarks below.
 

Hmm. That was really a bad way of expressing that on my part. I now regret I 
wrote that. Clearly I’m wrong in what I wrote. 

The line of thinking I was following was that generals, as used by Peirce, 
simply has much narrower application possible than universals like colors. It’s 
true that the universal yellow can be instantiated by a limited number of 
objects but is treated as an universal. However it seems like “some flowers are 
yellow” are different from “some men wear hats.” The distinction I was getting 
at, relative to Newton’s laws, was that distinction. The predicate “is wearing 
a hat” simply seems a different sort of thing from “is yellow.” Traditional 
universals within science accept the latter but tend not to apply it to the 
former.

Probably what I should have written was more about what universals/generals one 
was a realist about. Especially as it relates to the reductionist issue.

As you note Peirce typically uses general as non-singular. The reason I had 
said it was broader was more about Peirce allowing realism towards many 
generals that a physicist wouldn’t. So many people are open to mathematical 
entities being universals for instance. (Think Quine for example) However they 
tend not to be a realist towards statements like “is wearing a hat.” That’s 
fundamentally an emergent phenomena and wrapped up with individual minds, the 
way most nominalists think of it.

But I might just simply be wrong in all this. I think I was thinking in terms 
of passages like the following:

A particular proposition asserts the existence of something of a given 
description. A universal proposition merely asserts the non-existence of 
anything of a given description. 

Had I, therefore, asserted that a perceptual judgment could be a universal 
proposition I should have fallen into rank absurdity. For reaction is existence 
and the perceptual judgment is the cognitive product of a reaction. 

But as from the particular proposition that “There is some woman whom any 
Catholic you can find will adore,” we can with certainty infer the universal 
proposition that “Any Catholic you can find will adore some woman or other,” so 
if a perceptual judgment involves any general elements, as it certainly does, 
the presumption is that a universal proposition can be necessarily deduced from 
it. (EP 2:210)
 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-29 Thread Howard Pattee



On Sep 29, 2014, at 10:38 AM, Benjamin wrote:
By the way, I think that we should remind or 
inform readers that many physicists, when they 
speak of 'realism', mean ideas such as that a 
particle has an objective, determinate state, even when unmeasured.


Goble: I think the ultimately problem is that 
most physicists (like most scientists) are 
nominalists and thus to make a realist claim 
requires knowing what the singulars are. Yet 
most physicists don’t think they know the 
singulars. This leads to problems for a 
nominalist that a scholastic realist like Peirce doesn’t face.


Now I think physicists would do well to jettison nominalism.


HP: To get a fairer picture of how physicists 
think, please peruse http://arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069v1.pdfthis survey.


Howard

-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-29 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 29, 2014, at 6:28 PM, Howard Pattee hpat...@roadrunner.com wrote:
 
 Goble: I think the ultimately problem is that most physicists (like most 
 scientists) are nominalists and thus to make a realist claim requires 
 knowing what the singulars are. Yet most physicists don’t think they know 
 the singulars. This leads to problems for a nominalist that a scholastic 
 realist like Peirce doesn’t face.
 
 Now I think physicists would do well to jettison nominalism.
 
 HP: To get a fairer picture of how physicists think, please peruse this 
 survey http://arxiv.org/pdf/1301.1069v1.pdf.

I’d seen that before. While it’s a great guide to interpretations of quantum 
mechanics it really doesn’t address the nominalism issue. There were some 
surprises when I first read it - mainly that Bohmian mechanics have completely 
fallen out of favor. Back when I was in school it was still a notable theory, 
albeit one few followed. I expected far more people to pick the Everett 
interpretation as well. 

It did touch briefly on the idealist vs realist question with question 9. 
However that really didn’t get at the issue of nominalism. Although as the 
authors noted the options weren’t well defined here. I wonder how many 
physicists are familiar with terms like ontic or epistemic enough to understand 
how they are applied.

Still that’s a great link to share. I do wish there was one on nominalism.




-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-28 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 28, 2014, at 2:29 PM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:
 
 On 9/28/2014 11:22 AM, Jerry LR Chandler wrote:
 
  [JC] List, Ben, Clark:
 
  I am surprised by the search for such a fine -scale parsing of the concept 
  of formal causality (telos).
 
 [BU] I'd regard formal causation generally as entelechiac causation, rather 
 than as telic causation when _telos_ has the sense of culminal end, a working 
 or functioning (once, sometimes, or habitually) as an end or goal. In 
 Peirce's view, entelechy is merely more perfect realization or completion of 
 the activity, the _energeia_ (which is a _telos_) (_Century Dictionary_ 1889 
 and the definition's draft from 1886 in W 5:404 
 https://sites.google.com/site/cspmem/terms 
 https://sites.google.com/site/cspmem/terms), but I haven't thought so. 
 Anyway there's parsing because there are various ways to apply the ideas.
 
I think that’s an important point you brought up Ben. This confused me to no 
end when first studying Peirce as I kept thinking of teleology in Peirce more 
akin to how Aquinas and the medievals took it. However for Peirce it’s very 
much wrapped up in the discussion of entelenchy 

The discussion of Aristotle’s famous four causes is interesting. I’d posted 
this last month but I’ll repost it because I think it rather pertinent.

It may be added that a part of a cause, if a part in that respect in which the 
cause is a cause, is also called a cause. In other respects, too, the scope of 
the word will be somewhat widened in the sequel. If the cause so defined is a 
part of the causatum, in the sense that the causatum could not logically be 
without the cause, it is called an internal cause; otherwise, it is called an 
external cause. If the cause is of the nature of an individual thing or fact, 
and the other factor requisite to the necessitation of the causatum is a 
general principle, I would call the cause a minor, or individuating, or perhaps 
a physical cause. If, on the other hand, it is the general principle which is 
regarded as the cause and the individual fact to which it is applied is taken 
as the understood factor, I would call the cause a major, or defining, or 
perhaps a psychical cause. The individuating internal cause is called the 
material cause. Thus the integrant parts of a subject or fact form its matter, 
or material cause. The individuating external cause is called the efficient, or 
efficient cause; and the causatum is called the effect. The defining internal 
cause is called the formal cause, or form. All these facts which constitute the 
definition of a subject or fact make up its form. The defining external cause 
is called the final cause, or end. It is hoped that these statements will be 
found to hit a little more squarely than did those of Aristotle and the 
scholastics the same bull’s eye at which they aimed. From scholasticism and the 
medieval universities, these conceptions passed in vaguer form into the common 
mind and vernacular of Western Europe, and especially so in England. 
Consequently, by the aid of these definitions I think I can make out what it is 
that the writer mentioned has in mind in saying that it is not the law which 
influences, or is the final cause of, the facts, but the facts that make up the 
cause of the law. (EP 315-316)

He distinguishes internal from external causes. Although with regards to the 
entelechy there’s some connection since the ideal sign signified the very 
matter denoted by it united by the very form signified by it. As I understand 
him this gets at both the internal and external.

Every sign that is sufficiently complete refers to sundry real objects. All 
these objects, even if we are talking of Hamlet's madness, are parts of one and 
the same Universe of being, the “Truth.” But so far as the “Truth” is merely 
the object of a sign, it is merely the Aristotelian Matter of it that is so. In 
addition however to denoting objects, every sign sufficiently complete 
signifies characters, or qualities. We have a direct knowledge of real objects 
in every experiential reaction, whether of Perception or of Exertion (the one 
theoretical, the other practical). These are directly hic et nunc. But we 
extend the category, and speak of numberless real objects with which we are not 
in direct reaction. We have also direct knowledge of qualities in feeling, 
peripheral and visceral. But we extend this category to numberless characters 
of which we have no immediate consciousness. All these characters are elements 
of the “Truth.” Every sign signifies the “Truth.” But it is only the 
Aristotelian Form of the universe that it signifies. The logician is not 
concerned with any metaphysical theory; still less, if possible, is the 
mathematician. But it is highly convenient to express ourselves in terms of a 
metaphysical theory; and we no more bind ourselves to an acceptance of it than 
we do when we use substantives such as “humanity,” “variety,” etc. and speak of 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-28 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 27, 2014, at 6:05 PM, Stephen C. Rose stever...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 Have you read The God Problem by Harold Bloom. I have no science but it seems 
 he is out to contradict every theory out there. He has one of his own about 
 origins. Best, S

I confess I’ve not read that one, although I’ve read some of Bloom’s other 
works on religion.


 On Sep 27, 2014, at 8:11 PM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:
 
 [BU] A realist can and often enough ought to be skeptical about particular 
 models and diagrams as representative of reality. A realist believes not that 
 all generals are real but instead that some generals are real and some 
 generals are figmentitious.

Yes, I think this is key. I think Peirceans have more tools at our disposal 
because generals are broader than mere universals. (Broader in the sense of 
encompassing more structures)

  [CG] If that’s true, even if a realist appears to be appealing to 
  Aristotle’s four causes in practice what they really think is going on is 
  probably something different. That is on a practical basis for most 
  physical theories even realists behave as an instrumentalist. If true, 
  then in what way can Aristotle’s categories really be seen ontologically?
 
 So it’s really a subtle point about realism, foundational ontology and 
 Aristotle I'm making. 
 
 [BU] I'm not sure that I get you. Skepticism toward particular models, the 
 desire that they 'do the job' (i.e., stand up to evidence) doesn't by itself 
 seem to amount to choosing instrumentalism over realism.
 
I’ll give it an other shot. It’s a subtle point, and one that perhaps isn’t a 
problem to Peirceans due to our distinctions between generals and universals.

Skepticism towards model’s reality is a problem simply because most physicists 
are reducitonist but also don’t think they know what a final theory is like. 
That means any model has to be reduced to foundational laws/objects to discern 
what things really are. However since we don’t know what to reduce them to, 
we’re left not knowing how to conceive of the physics we know in terms of what 
they actually are.

Now Peirce has a solution to this with generals. So we could say that Newton’s 
Laws are true generals but are not universals. They have a limited area of 
application. But within that application they are true. Now we can quibble 
about how we’re dealing with errors due to the difference between the general 
and what a more general law, like general relativity might give. There are 
obviously some complexities there we can debate. But fundamentally how Peirce 
approaches common sense as phenomena heavily tested in a limited area is how we 
approach physics.

But note that this isn’t really how realists among physicists conceive of it. 
When they talk about realism they aren’t merely talking about structures that 
are mind independent but also the grounds of those structures. And those 
grounds just aren’t known. (Clearly a realist will accept that Newton’s laws 
describe mind independent structures for most phenomena though, even if they 
don’t quite put it into the form of generals the way Peirce might)

Hope that helps. The issue is really that realism within a reductionist system 
is what is fundamentally real. So it’s not that the realists are the same as 
the instrumentalists. Simply that because they don’t know the assumed 
foundational laws in certain practical ways they act like an instrumentalist.


  [CG] The closest I could find was the more typical (even today) physicts 
  view that we haven’t a clue what energy is beyond it’s place in an 
  equation.
 
 We should hardly find today a man of Kirchhoff’s rank in science saying that 
 we know exactly what energy does but what energy is we do not know in the 
 least. For the answer would be that energy being a term in a dynamical 
 equation, if we know how to apply that equation, we thereby know what energy 
 is, although we may suspect that there is some more fundamental law 
 underlying the laws of motion. (EP 2:239)
 
 Peirce here was using energy and its meaning as an analogy for relations. 
 
 [BU] I like to think that Peirce would think that the equations tell us a 
 little more now. Energy, in nearly the sense that he understood it, is a 
 time-minus-proper-time quantity in the sense that momentum is a distance (or 
 displacement) quantity. Energy, momementum, mass, can all be expressed in the 
 same units, in a sense they're the same thing in terms of different 
 reference-frame structures. I should add at some point that Peirce didn't 
 think that energy was an cenoscopically philosophical subject, since the 
 conservation of energy requires special experiments to establish.

I won’t even try to guess what Peirce would think. I don’t feel I know his 
thought enough for that. I suspect you’re right in regards to energy being 
cenoscopic or idioscopic. It seems an experimental reduction rather something 
worked out philosophically. Whether they are the same 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-27 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 26, 2014, at 12:41 PM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:
 
 Clark, list,
 
 
 I've also noticed a difficulty of finding usefulness for the formal cause in 
 physics, though I came at it from other directions, simpler ones for me since 
 I'm not a physicist, but also I'd like to add a clarification of the idea of 
 formal causation.
 
 

I think there are things like formal causes in physics. For instance if you are 
discussing symmetries how different really is that from discussing forms? 

However I think there’s a huge gap within physics simply because of how physics 
views foundational theories. Right now there’s near universal consensus we 
don’t have a foundational theory and (except for the string proponents) most 
don’t think we have any idea what one would look like. (I’ve no idea how far 
string theory has fallen in favor the last few years. There’s definitely been a 
backlash, but how widespread it is at the moment I couldn’t say)

Given that acknowledged ignorance of foundations there’s a strong sense even 
among realists that most of what we do in physics is model making with the 
models highly idealized from what’s really going on. So a realist might be a 
realist towards certain structures and behaviors about GR or QM but a bit of a 
skeptic regarding particular models.

If that’s true, even if a realist appears to be appealing to Aristotle’s four 
causes in practice what they really think is going on is probably something 
different. That is on a practical basis for most physical theories even 
realists behave as an instrumentalist. If true, then in what way can 
Aristotle’s categories really be seen ontologically? 

So it’s really a subtle point about realism, foundational ontology and 
Aristotle I'm making. 

 If I remember Peirce correctly, the ideas of force, impulse, momentum were 
 ideas of ways to quantify (efficient) 'causativeness' or capacity to cause, 
 impart motion, etc., while power (wattage), work, energy, were ways to 
 quantify effect (_telos_, end, in a sense) or capacity for effect. The matter 
 obviously was quantified as mass, and related mechanical quantities would be 
 change of mass and the rate of it, which I guess one could call 'affluence' 
 :-), but nowadays I guess one would say that internal work, internal power, 
 are also mechanical counterparts to rest mass (i.e., to rest energy).

It’s true that Peirce adopts telos in terms of capacity. So he says idea in the 
Platonic sense is “anything whose Being consists in its mere capacity for 
getting fully represented.”

I only have the EP to search through but I couldn’t find a passage like that. 
I’d be interested if you know it. The closest I could find was the more typical 
(even today) physicts view that we haven’t a clue what energy is beyond it’s 
place in an equation.

We should hardly find today a man of Kirchhoff’s rank in science saying that we 
know exactly what energy does but what energy is we do not know in the least. 
For the answer would be that energy being a term in a dynamical equation, if we 
know how to apply that equation, we thereby know what energy is, although we 
may suspect that there is some more fundamental law underlying the laws of 
motion. (EP 2:239)

Peirce here was using energy and its meaning as an analogy for relations. 

I do think Peirce is influenced by Aristotle’s two grades of being as actuality 
and potentiality. But I’m not sure he put things in quite the form you suggest. 
I may be completely wrong here I should add - this is just coming from me 
scanning EP. If you have a reference I’d be very interested as I’ve honestly 
not even looked to see what Peirce’s theory of physics was. Partially because 
he wrote before the great revolutions of the early 20th century.



-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-27 Thread Benjamin Udell

Clark, list,

Responses interleaved.

On 9/27/2014 7:41 PM, Clark Goble wrote:


 On Sep 26, 2014, at 12:41 PM, Benjamin Udell wrote:/p

 Clark, list,

I've also noticed a difficulty of finding usefulness for the formal 
cause in physics, though I came at it from other directions, simpler 
ones for me since I'm not a physicist, but also I'd like to add a 
clarification of the idea of formal causation.


 [CG] I think there are things /like / formal causes in physics. For 
instance if you are discussing symmetries how different really is that 
from discussing forms?


[BU] Yes, I should have sad a difficulty of finding usefulness for 
formal _/causation/_ in physics, and of finding a useful kinetic 
quantity in the manner of momentum, mass, energy. Insofar as a thing's 
form is its formal cause, physics obviously has use for forms.


 [CG] However I think there’s a huge gap within physics simply 
because of how physics views foundational theories. Right now there’s 
near universal consensus we don’t have a foundational theory and 
(except for the string proponents) most don’t think we have any idea 
what one would look like. (I’ve no idea how far string theory has 
fallen in favor the last few years. There’s definitely been a 
backlash, but how widespread it is at the moment I couldn’t say)


[BU] On _The Big Bang Theory_, Sheldon has given up on string theory. 
Clearly the walls have been breached.


 [CG] Given that acknowledged ignorance of foundations there’s a 
strong sense even among realists that most of what we do in physics is 
model making with the models highly idealized from what’s really going 
on. So a realist might be a realist towards certain structures and 
behaviors about GR or QM but a bit of a skeptic regarding particular 
models.


[BU] A realist can and often enough ought to be skeptical about 
particular models and diagrams as representative of reality. A realist 
believes not that all generals are real but instead that some generals 
are real and some generals are figmentitious.


 [CG] If that’s true, even if a realist /appears/ to be appealing to 
Aristotle’s four causes in practice what they /really/ think is going 
on is probably something different. That is on a practical basis for 
most physical theories even realists behave as an instrumentalist. If 
true, then in what way can Aristotle’s categories really be seen 
ontologically?


So it’s really a subtle point about realism, foundational ontology and 
Aristotle I'm making.


[BU] I'm not sure that I get you. Skepticism toward particular models, 
the desire that they 'do the job' (i.e., stand up to evidence) doesn't 
by itself seem to amount to choosing instrumentalism over realism.


 [BU] If I remember Peirce correctly, the ideas of force, impulse, 
momentum were ideas of ways to quantify (efficient) 'causativeness' 
or capacity to cause, impart motion, etc., while power (wattage), 
work, energy, were ways to quantify effect (_telos_, end, in a sense) 
or capacity for effect. The matter obviously was quantified as mass, 
and related mechanical quantities would be change of mass and the 
rate of it, which I guess one could call 'affluence' :-), but 
nowadays I guess one would say that internal work, internal power, 
are also mechanical counterparts to rest mass (i.e., to rest energy).


 [CG] It’s true that Peirce adopts telos in terms of capacity. So he 
says idea in the Platonic sense is “anything whose Being consists in 
its mere capacity for getting fully represented.”


[BU] I was talking about capacity in all cases. Momentum isn't 
'casativeness' in the sense that impulse and force seem, but it is a 
kind of 'causative' capacity. Work is a kind of effect, energy is 
capacity for work, capacity for effect.


 [CG] I only have the EP to search through but I couldn’t find a 
passage like that. I’d be interested if you know it.


[BU] It was a brief passage, it'd be hard to find again. Peirce was 
merely mentioning the history of the idea, not his philosophy of it.


 [CG] The closest I could find was the more typical (even today) 
physicts view that we haven’t a clue what energy is beyond it’s place 
in an equation.


We should hardly find today a man of Kirchhoff’s rank in science
saying that we know exactly what energy does but what energy is we
do not know in the least. For the answer would be that energy
being a term in a dynamical equation, if we know how to apply that
equation, we thereby know what energy is, although we may suspect
that there is some more fundamental law underlying the laws of
motion. (EP 2:239)

Peirce here was using energy and its meaning as an analogy for relations.

[BU] I like to think that Peirce would think that the equations tell us 
a little more now. Energy, in nearly the sense that he understood it, is 
a time-minus-proper-time quantity in the sense that momentum is a 
distance (or displacement) quantity. Energy, momementum, mass, can all 
be expressed in the 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-26 Thread Benjamin Udell

Clark, list,

I've also noticed a difficulty of finding usefulness for the formal 
cause in physics, though I came at it from other directions, simpler 
ones for me since I'm not a physicist, but also I'd like to add a 
clarification of the idea of formal causation. A thing's form is its 
formal cause, and the form (in the sense of structure) obviously gets 
involved in mechanics, where angles and directions are important from 
the start. So the formal cause gets involved there but not in the usual 
sense of formal _/causation/_, of which the old typical example was the 
'beautiful idea' that guides a painter to actualize it in the painting. 
A structure dynamically causing into the future is traditionally 
regarded as an efficient cause.


The Aristotelian four causes (efficient cause, matter, end, form) enter 
into physics in at least two ways that I can see. One is in the kinetic 
and mechanical quantities developed that reflect them. The other is in 
in the idea of stages of a process.


If I remember Peirce correctly, the ideas of force, impulse, momentum 
were ideas of ways to quantify (efficient) 'causativeness' or capacity 
to cause, impart motion, etc., while power (wattage), work, energy, were 
ways to quantify effect (_/telos/_, end, in a sense) or capacity for 
effect. The matter obviously was quantified as mass, and related 
mechanical quantities would be change of mass and the rate of it, which 
I guess one could call 'affluence' :-), but nowadays I guess one would 
say that internal work, internal power, are also mechanical counterparts 
to rest mass (i.e., to rest energy).


Anyway, there seems to have been no idea of quantifying of form in some 
kinetic or mechanical (dynamic or static) sense; it's not clear how it 
would have seemed useful, or how it would be useful now. Anyway, I've 
tried it and it doesn't seem useful for physics. If you picture the form 
or structure as being a kind of balancing, or more-or-less stable 
balance, of momenta or forces in a system, then in special relativity 
one can assign a related kinetic quantity to the system by considering 
the internal 'potential' momenta or potential impulses stored in the 
system's material parts and the internal kinetic momenta (that are 
netted out, canceled out, in the system's net momentum) all the way down 
through the fundamental particles. I can't imagine how to directly 
measure it, only how to calculate it, and it (call it 'f') is 
proportional to (E/c) - p, which seems useless in physical theory - 
sorry, Aristotle. (Basically f differs from momentum in the way that 
slowness differs from speed, such that f is an idea of how much 
potential and actual motion is tied up in the system as its arrangement 
or structure.) Moreover, at conventional velocities, f is proportional 
to rest mass (and to total mass), rendering form (structure) and matter 
hard to distinguish in that perspective. Given the mathematics, I don't 
think that there will be another candidate than f for a structure 
quantity directly akin to momentum 'p', rest mass 'm', and kinetic 
energy 'e', such that reflections of the ideas of the Four Causes are 
picturable neatly in a square around a central E (total relativistic 
mass-energy)


p e
E
mf

where, if we set lightspeed at 1, then p+f = m+e = E;  p-e = m-f = 
sqrt(2fe); and p-m = e-f (or m-p = f-e).


Another way in which the formal cause enters idioscopy including physics 
is as a final form, or a form that is final in the sense of being stable.


The idea of a form or structure acting mechanically, dynamically, etc., 
into the future is traditionally regarded not as formal causation, but 
as efficient (a.k.a. agent) causation.


An idea commonly given of formal causation was that of the 'beautiful 
idea' that guides a painter and is actualized in the completed painting. 
I recently discussed at peirce-l the idea of an entelechy as a bigger 
picture whereby one balances impetuses, means, and culminal ends - 
taking into account possible further risks and opportunities, clashes 
and consistencies of values, and so on. A biological-evolutionary idea 
of this would be a form toward which a species evolves and which, as a 
result of natural selection, organizes and balances the functions of the 
organism, taking account of significantly probable and feasible 
contingencies which may be encountered by organisms of the given 
species. At lower levels, I don't clearly see final forms, likewise of 
ends, acting or quasi-acting through mind or quasi-mind to shape and 
guide processes to lead to them. At the level of matter and multitudes 
of particles, the common end of a closed system, a population 'total' in 
that sense, seems to be decay in the sense of increasing entropy, and a 
final form (final at least for the time being) a stable higher-entropy 
state, and this is a matter of probabilities. At the level of mechanics, 
the end seems to be conservation of certain quantities (at least when 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-25 Thread Frederik Stjernfelt
Dear Clark, lists  -

But aren't formal and material causes just re-baptized in physics as constants 
(of laws), as types of forces or particles, or as boundary conditions?

Best
F



Den 22/09/2014 kl. 15.59 skrev Clark Goble 
cl...@lextek.commailto:cl...@lextek.com
:


On Sep 21, 2014, at 9:13 PM, Clark Goble 
cl...@libertypages.commailto:cl...@libertypages.com wrote:


On Sep 18, 2014, at 8:49 AM, Gary Fuhrman 
g...@gnusystems.camailto:g...@gnusystems.ca wrote:

Clark, in reference to the Peirce passage you quoted about the “community of 
quasi-minds”, you said that “While we could obviously and perhaps should 
discuss this purely as efficient causation, I love how Peirce discusses it 
instead in terms of signs.” But it’s not at all obvious to me how or why we 
could or should discuss this purely as efficient causation. To me, the material 
and formal (if not final) causes of the fact determined by this process appear 
much more prominent than the efficient causes.


Typically physicists and most physical scientists avoid material and formal 
causes in the Aristotilean sense. They become more the properties or 
information that changes. Since the focus is on those changes of state the 
focus is really on efficient causation with little focus on material or formal 
changes - they are simply bracketed and left uninvestigated usually.

When they are investigated by truly theoretical physicists and occasionally 
philosophers things get tricky. One could well argue, for instance, that most 
of string theory is really a theory about material and formal causes for 
instance. While I honestly don’t think most physicists are instrumentalists 
like Feynman, I do think they adhere to a certain instrumentalist ethos that 
says one should leap into the abyss of worrying about ultimate stuff beyond 
what we can empirically talk about clearly. (Which is why string theory has 
long been so controversial, IMO)

The reason this is important is of course how physics conceives of formal and 
material causes tends to view them as somewhat illusionary. That is they are 
emergent phenomena but there’s always the assumption of a true reduction to 
basic physics is in theory possible. (This is different from the reductionism 
of description that I take Frederik was addressing a few weeks ago) So to a 
physicist to only real form and material are the ultimate constituents of the 
universe, whether they be strings, quantum fields or whatever they turn out to 
be. And the reason talk of formal or material causes is pointless is because we 
don’t know the ultimate constituents (or if people think they do, it’s merely 
talk about strings)

I’m not saying this is the only way one could talk about this sort of thing. 
But I do think this is, in practice, the way physicists and to only a slightly 
lesser extent chemists think about all this. Biologists are a different beast 
of course.


-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to 
peirce-L@list.iupui.edumailto:peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send 
a message not to PEIRCE-L but to 
l...@list.iupui.edumailto:l...@list.iupui.edu with the line UNSubscribe 
PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-22 Thread Clark Goble

On Sep 21, 2014, at 9:13 PM, Clark Goble cl...@libertypages.com wrote:


 On Sep 18, 2014, at 8:49 AM, Gary Fuhrman g...@gnusystems.ca 
 mailto:g...@gnusystems.ca wrote:
 
 Clark, in reference to the Peirce passage you quoted about the “community of 
 quasi-minds”, you said that “While we could obviously and perhaps should 
 discuss this purely as efficient causation, I love how Peirce discusses it 
 instead in terms of signs.” But it’s not at all obvious to me how or why we 
 could or should discuss this purely as efficient causation. To me, the 
 material and formal (if not final) causes of the fact determined by this 
 process appear much more prominent than the efficient causes.
 

Typically physicists and most physical scientists avoid material and formal 
causes in the Aristotilean sense. They become more the properties or 
information that changes. Since the focus is on those changes of state the 
focus is really on efficient causation with little focus on material or formal 
changes - they are simply bracketed and left uninvestigated usually.

When they are investigated by truly theoretical physicists and occasionally 
philosophers things get tricky. One could well argue, for instance, that most 
of string theory is really a theory about material and formal causes for 
instance. While I honestly don’t think most physicists are instrumentalists 
like Feynman, I do think they adhere to a certain instrumentalist ethos that 
says one should leap into the abyss of worrying about ultimate stuff beyond 
what we can empirically talk about clearly. (Which is why string theory has 
long been so controversial, IMO)

The reason this is important is of course how physics conceives of formal and 
material causes tends to view them as somewhat illusionary. That is they are 
emergent phenomena but there’s always the assumption of a true reduction to 
basic physics is in theory possible. (This is different from the reductionism 
of description that I take Frederik was addressing a few weeks ago) So to a 
physicist to only real form and material are the ultimate constituents of the 
universe, whether they be strings, quantum fields or whatever they turn out to 
be. And the reason talk of formal or material causes is pointless is because we 
don’t know the ultimate constituents (or if people think they do, it’s merely 
talk about strings)

I’m not saying this is the only way one could talk about this sort of thing. 
But I do think this is, in practice, the way physicists and to only a slightly 
lesser extent chemists think about all this. Biologists are a different beast 
of course.


-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-19 Thread Frederik Stjernfelt
Dear Ben, lists,
I think you are right in proposing that quasi-inferences are inferences with 
less than full self-control.
But self-control comes in many degrees ( I address this a bit in ch. 6 I 
think). A very low degree of self-control may be the slow change over 
evolutionary adaption -  with the lineage as the self-controlling entity able 
to learn, rather than the single organism.
You're right about the vague sense of Peirce's different quasis - maybe an 
intended vagueness. But I think it is right that, as a tendency, P would regard 
learning (ever so slowly) as essential for his mind concept (of course the 
famous crystals-and-bees quote may be marshaled as a counter-quote).
Best
F

Den 16/09/2014 kl. 20.09 skrev Benjamin Udell 
bud...@nyc.rr.commailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com
:


Clark, list,

In regard to the Peirce quote from 1907 that you provided, it's also pertinent 
to the discussion of biosemiosis, physiosemiosis, etc., taking place lately 
here. It was in the 1906 Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism that he 
discusses quasi-mind, quasi-utterer, 
quasi-interpreterhttp://www.commens.org/dictionary/term/quasi-mind . In the 
1907 passage that you quote, mentioning the Jacquard loom, he doesn't mention 
the quasi-s although they seem pertinent. But in another 1907 from the same 
MS 318, published in CP 5.473 (the famous semeiosy passage), he says that a 
Jacquard loom should be regarded as a quasi-sign, because the action is that 
of automatic regulation, which he distinguishes from semeiosy (semiosis).

[Quote]
In these cases, however, a mental representation of the index is produced, 
which mental representation is called the _immediate object_ of the sign; and 
this object does triadically produce the intended, or proper, effect of the 
sign strictly by means of another mental sign; and that this triadic character 
of the action is regarded as essential is shown by the fact that if the 
thermometer is dynamically connected with the heating and cooling apparatus, so 
as to check either effect, we do not, in ordinary parlance speak of there being 
any _semeiosy_, or action of a sign, but, on the contrary, say that there is an 
automatic regulation, an idea opposed, in our minds, to that of _semeiosy_. 
For the proper significate outcome of a sign, I propose the name, the 
interpretant of the sign. The example of the imperative command shows that it 
need not be of a mental mode of being. Whether the interpretant be necessarily 
a triadic result is a question of words, that is, of how we limit the extension 
of the term sign; but it seems to me convenient to make the triadic 
production of the interpretant essential to a sign, calling the wider concept 
like a Jacquard loom, for example, a quasi-sign.
[End quote]

I tend to see this distinction as allied a distinction that he makes in an 
unpublished MS which the Robin Catalogue describes as follows:

831. [Reasoning and Instinct]
A. MS., n.p., n.d., pp. 2-29, incomplete.
The fine gradations between subconscious or instinctive mind and conscious, 
controlled reason. Logical machines are not strictly reasoning machines because 
they lack the ability of self-criticism and the ability to correct defects 
which may crop up. Three kinds of reasoning: inductive, deductive, 
hypothetical. Quasi-inferences.

Well, I don't know what to make of quasi-inferences - I'd have thought that 
he would regard instinctive or automatic inferences as quasi-reasonings. I'll 
be very interested to read MS 831 if it ever becomes available.

Anyway I've tended to think of genuine semiosis as involving the capacity to 
learn, capacity for self-correction etc. (and I've heard that this is De 
Tienne's view) - I mean not merely self-correction to maintain homeostasis or 
balance while walking etc. (which could be done by automatic regulation), but 
'design-level' self-correction, correction of one's own methods, correction of 
one's own semiosic habits, etc.

But one finds inferences embodied in vegetable-level and physical phenomena, 
are they not semioses? Are they quasi-semioses? The prefix quasi- starts to 
seem too vague to capture the possible senses. I also don't have too firm an 
idea of all the things that Peirce means by mind. Does mind, in Peirce's 
sense, always involve the capacity to learn? If I call something a quasi-mind, 
should that mean like a mind but not learning? Or could it mean learning like a 
mind without being a mind capable of consciousness (I've thought of biological 
evolution as having a 'quasi-mind'). Vegetable-level (quasi-)semiosis seems 
like we ought to strongly distinguish it from whatever strictly dynamic or 
material/chemical (quasi-) semiosis we think there is, because at the vegetable 
level, signs or signals are 'interpreted' in terms of highly specific kinds of 
pertinence to the organism for the end of the thriving of the species. It 
indeed _seems_ rather like semiosis as we ordinarily think of it because, 
although 

RE: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-18 Thread Gary Fuhrman
Clark, in reference to the Peirce passage you quoted about the “community of 
quasi-minds”, you said that “While we could obviously and perhaps should 
discuss this purely as efficient causation, I love how Peirce discusses it 
instead in terms of signs.” But it’s not at all obvious to me how or why we 
could or should discuss this purely as efficient causation. To me, the material 
and formal (if not final) causes of the fact determined by this process appear 
much more prominent than the efficient causes.

 

gary f.

 

From: Clark Goble [mailto:cl...@lextek.com] 
Sent: 16-Sep-14 9:01 PM
To: Peirce List
Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

 

 

On Sep 16, 2014, at 12:09 PM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:

 

In regard to the Peirce quote from 1907 that you provided, it's also pertinent 
to the discussion of biosemiosis, physiosemiosis, etc., taking place lately 
here. It was in the 1906 Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism that he 
discusses quasi-mind, quasi-utterer, quasi-interpreter 
http://www.commens.org/dictionary/term/quasi-mind . 

 

Yes, when I came upon it I noticed that connection. (Thank heavens for Kindle 
and having at least EP2 available -  if only a cheap CP collection was around 
that worked on Macs  iPads)

 

And the 1906 Prolegomena definitely is one of my favorite of Peirce’s texts - 
second probably only to some of the Lady Welby texts.

 

It seems to me that quasi-mind, quasi-utterer, quasi-interpreter and even 
quasi-signs are very important for the discussion. That’s not to say that I 
disagree with Frederik once caveats are made. Just that I think Peirce sees 
this very much as a continuum in complexity. While I’m dubious the continuum 
works quite as broadly as Peirce sometimes suggests, the notion as a regulatory 
concept is amazingly productive.

 

That quote you gave gets very much at the issue I initially brought up. As 
Peirce says, we don’t ordinarily call this a sign but clearly there are some 
resemblances.

 

 

831. [Reasoning and Instinct] 

A. MS., n.p., n.d., pp. 2-29, incomplete. 

The fine gradations between subconscious or instinctive mind and conscious, 
controlled reason. Logical machines are not strictly reasoning machines because 
they lack the ability of self-criticism and the ability to correct defects 
which may crop up. Three kinds of reasoning: inductive, deductive, 
hypothetical. Quasi-inferences.

 

That’s a fantastic little quote I’d not seen before. It also points to levels 
of complexity. Obviously some complex phenomena do self-correct. The recent 
advent of self-healing materials are but one example. This suggests that the 
continuum is one of complexity in many ways.

 

My favorite discussion of these “quasi” aspects of the sign. (BTW one of my 
favorite Peircean uses of “quasi” was in quasi-self when talking about 
secondness and how we attribute the causes of secondness to objects despite the 
same thing never happening twice in secondness. (This was in “Sundry Logical 
Conceptions”)

 

While I may be overly generalizing I’ve long seen Peirce’s use of “quasi” as 
tied to his notion of continuity but also recognizing where we sense 
differences from the ideal definition but for which there is a strong 
resemblance.

 

Since any sign function can itself be typically broken down into parts, the 
role of quasi-mind becomes more clear. Peirce uses quasi-mind to deal with 
these sub-parts of the sign but must also recognize there is something more 
fundamental than what we call mind. Today we’d recognize this as a notion of 
complexity and emergence. However it also avoids some of the messiness that 
Continental philosophy took when it recognized mind, as conceived of by 
Descartes, just wouldn’t work. There had to be something lower level going on. 
This led to all number of excesses of metaphor and performance while Peirce had 
a much more fruitful approach to describing all this. 

 

I like to think that had people embraced Peirce’s later mature thought more 
seriously a lot of the problems of philosophy in the second half of the 20th 
century could have been avoided.

 

I should note also, getting back to the Prolegomena, the following passage that 
I should have quoted in my response to Sungchul.

 

Let a community of quasi-minds consist of the liquid in a number of bottles 
which are in intricate connexion by tubes filled with the liquid. This liquid 
is of complex and somewhat unstable mixed chemical composition. It also has so 
strong a cohesion and consequent surface-tension that the contents of each 
bottle take on a self-determined form. Accident may cause one or another kind 
of decomposition to start at a point of one bottle producing a molecule of 
peculiar form, and this action may spread through a tube to another bottle. 
This new molecule will be a determination of the contents of the first bottle 
which will thus act upon the contents of the second bottle

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-17 Thread Benjamin Udell

Clark, list,

You wrote,


831. [Reasoning and Instinct]
A. MS., n.p., n.d., pp. 2-29, incomplete.
The fine gradations between subconscious or instinctive mind
and conscious, controlled reason. Logical machines are not
strictly reasoning machines because they lack the ability of
self-criticism and the ability to correct defects which may
crop up. Three kinds of reasoning: inductive, deductive,
hypothetical. Quasi-infIerences.


 [CG] That’s a fantastic little quote I’d not seen before.

To be sure, that's not a direct quote of Peirce, instead it's a quote of 
Richard Robin's summary of MS 831 
http://www.iupui.edu/~peirce/robin/robin_fm/toc_frm.htm 
http://www.iupui.edu/%7Epeirce/robin/robin_fm/toc_frm.htm .


I'm still wondering how to sort out these quasi's.

Semiosis dependent on learning or on the capacity to learn:

Learning in a concentrated mind. *Mathetic* semiosis?
Learning in a dispersed commind. *Symmathetic* semiosis?
Quasi-learning by, e.g., large-scale social (without individuals 
commentally aware) or biological evolution, a quasi-mind or 
quasi-commind. *Mathoidic* semiosis?


Any and all of them: *Mathinic* semiosis?

Maybe somebody has already sorted out these or similar distinctions and 
suggested terms for them.


Then I'd make similar distinctions at the level of (quasi-)semiosis for 
systems that don't learn but still regulate themselves automatically. It 
involves ideas of communication and control, and the idea that the 
system arose from a mathinic process even though the system (e.g., a 
vegetable organism) is not itself mathinic. A Jacquard loom seems 
actually a weak example of this, although a mathinic process is required 
for the Jacquard loom to be set up. A pheromone is very like an 
indexical instance of a symbol. Something has to know the 'lingo' or the 
code in order to 'understand' it. It has its 'meaning' because of how it 
_/will/_ be interpreted by certain organisms, and the whole thing 
depends on its purpose, to which congenial underlying material and 
dynamic processes were adapted. I'd make a distinction between life and 
quasi-life (e.g., quasi-life would include the hypothetical Gaia, 
self-regulative climate systems, etc.). I suppose the idea of quasi-life 
could be extended like that of quasi-mind to even lower phenomena, the 
liquids that Peirce mentions in your quote of him. These start to seem 
like quasi-quasi-life and quasi-quasi-mind to me. I'm used to thinking 
of mind as both capable of learning _/and/_, in Peirce's excellent 
phrase, theater of consciousness. I'm thinking that Peirce sees both 
as essential to genuine mind, if we take 'learning' as 'habit-taking'. 
But I'm not sure of this.


Then there are also stochastic processes (material or quasi-material 
causation, large numbers of particles; or behaving probabilistically as 
if randomly selected from swarm of particles, or something like that, my 
background is very limited here) and more-or-less deterministic 
physical/dynamic processes (efficient causation), some of which will be 
complex decision processes in some sense, following and affecting rules 
and constraints. It gets pretty murky for me here. A 'quasi-dynamic' 
actual process won't be a lower form if there's nothing lower 
physically, it could only be a higher form.


Best, Ben

On 9/16/2014 9:00 PM, Clark Goble wrote:



On Sep 16, 2014, at 12:09 PM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com 
mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:


In regard to the Peirce quote from 1907 that you provided, it's also 
pertinent to the discussion of biosemiosis, physiosemiosis, etc., 
taking place lately here. It was in the 1906 Prolegomena to an 
Apology for Pragmaticism that he discusses quasi-mind, 
quasi-utterer, quasi-interpreter 
http://www.commens.org/dictionary/term/quasi-mind .


Yes, when I came upon it I noticed that connection. (Thank heavens for 
Kindle and having at least EP2 available -  if only a cheap CP 
collection was around that worked on Macs  iPads)


And the 1906 Prolegomena definitely is one of my favorite of Peirce’s 
texts - second probably only to some of the Lady Welby texts.


It seems to me that quasi-mind, quasi-utterer, quasi-interpreter and 
even quasi-signs are very important for the discussion. That’s not to 
say that I disagree with Frederik once caveats are made. Just that I 
think Peirce sees this very much as a continuum in complexity. While 
I’m dubious the continuum works quite as broadly as Peirce sometimes 
suggests, the notion as a regulatory concept is amazingly productive.


That quote you gave gets very much at the issue I initially brought 
up. As Peirce says, we don’t ordinarily call this a sign but clearly 
there are some resemblances.




831. [Reasoning and Instinct]
A. MS., n.p., n.d., pp. 2-29, incomplete.
The fine gradations between subconscious or instinctive mind and
conscious, controlled reason. Logical machines are not 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-16 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 15, 2014, at 9:23 AM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com 
 mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:
 
 (He came to regard philosophy as consisting of so-called logical analysis 
 (intellectual autobiography, 1904, Ketner editor), and to regarding such 
 logical analysis as really being phaneroscopic analysis (Peirce to James, 
 1909, CP 8.305); obviously by logical analysis in that context Peirce did 
 not mean the study of logic _per se_.)

What do you think he meant by that term broadly speaking? (“so called logical 
analysis”)  I ask, not because I don’t have some vague sense of the term, but 
because that seems to be my limit. Earlier on he seemed to speak of three 
degrees of clarity with the second degree logical analysis and the third degree 
to be the pragmatic maxim. However later on he seems to accord “logical 
analysis” as much more finding accurate definitions for concepts. (He suggests 
this for instance in the letters to Lady Welby but also the Neglected Argument)

It’s tempting to see it as somewhat akin to what happened to analytic 
philosophy. However I’ve long found many elements of analytic philosophy rather 
tepid relative to what I find in Peirce. I think his logic of vagueness and 
generals is rather key to a difference with how analytic philosophy developed 
in the 20th century.

In particular his MS 318 is a great example of how he uses this term (I’m not 
sure I could easily define it)

Everybody recognizes that it is no inconsiderable art, this business of 
“phaneroscopic” analysis by which one frames a scientific definition. As I 
practice it, in those cases, like the present, in which I am debarred from a 
direct appeal to the principle of pragmatism, I begin by seizing upon that 
predicate which appears to be most characteristic of the definitum, even if it 
does not quite apply to the entire extension of the definitum. If the predicate 
be too narrow, I afterward seek for some ingredient of it which shall be broad 
enough for an amended definitum and, at the same time, be still more 
scientifically characteristic of it. 

Proceeding in that way with our definitum, “sign,” we note, as highly 
characteristic, that signs mostly function each between two minds, or theatres 
of consciousness, of which the one is the agent that utters the sign (whether 
acoustically, optically, or otherwise), while the other is the patient mind 
that interprets the sign. Going on with my account of what is characteristic of 
a sign, without taking the least account of exceptional cases, for the present, 
I remark that, before the sign was uttered, it already was virtually present to 
the consciousness of the utterer, in the form of a thought. But, as already 
remarked, a thought is itself a sign, and should itself have an utterer (namely 
, the ego of a previous moment), to whose consciousness it must have been 
already virtually present, and so back. Likewise, after a sign has been 
interpreted, it will virtually remain in the consciousness of its interpreter, 
where it will be a sign,— perhaps, a resolution to apply the burden of the 
communicated sign,— and, as a sign should, in its turn have an interpreter, and 
so on forward. Now it is undeniably conceivable that a beginningless series of 
successive utterers should all do their work in a brief interval of time, and 
that so should an endless series of interpreters. Still, it is not likely to be 
denied that , in some cases, neither the series of utterers nor that of 
interpreters forms an infinite collection. When this is the case, there must be 
a sign without an utterer and a sign without an interpreter. Indeed, there are 
two pretty conclusive arguments on these points that are likely to occur to the 
reader. But why argue, when signs without utterers are often employed? I mean 
such signs as symptoms of disease, signs of the weather, groups of experiences 
serving as premisses, etc . Signs without interpreters less manifestly, but 
perhaps not less certainly, exist. Let the cards for a Jacquard loom be 
prepared and inserted, so that the loom shall weave a picture. Are not those 
cards signs? They convey intelligence,— intelligence that, considering its 
spirit and pictorial effect, cannot otherwise be conveyed. Yet the woven 
pictures may take fire and be consumed before anybody sees them. A set of those 
models that the designers of vessels drag through the water may have been 
prepared; and with the set a complete series of experiments may have been made; 
and their conditions and results may have been automatically recorded. There, 
then, is a perfect representation of the behavior of a certain range of forms. 
Yet if nobody takes the trouble to study the record, there will be no 
interpreter. So the books of a bank may furnish a complete account of the state 
of the bank. It remains only to draw up a balance sheet. But if this be not 
done, while the sign is complete, the human interpreter is wanting.

Rather different from what we 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-16 Thread Stephen C. Rose
Maybe there is a mental Higgs Boson that no one can quite describe.

*@stephencrose https://twitter.com/stephencrose*

On Tue, Sep 16, 2014 at 2:27 AM, Clark Goble cl...@lextek.com wrote:


 On Sep 15, 2014, at 9:23 AM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:

 (He came to regard philosophy as consisting of so-called logical
 analysis (intellectual autobiography, 1904, Ketner editor), and to
 regarding such logical analysis as really being phaneroscopic analysis
 (Peirce to James, 1909, CP 8.305); obviously by logical analysis in that
 context Peirce did not mean the study of logic _*per se*_.)


 What do you think he meant by that term broadly speaking? (so called
 logical analysis)  I ask, not because I don't have some vague sense of the
 term, but because that seems to be my limit. Earlier on he seemed to speak
 of three degrees of clarity with the second degree logical analysis and the
 third degree to be the pragmatic maxim. However later on he seems to accord
 logical analysis as much more finding accurate definitions for concepts.
 (He suggests this for instance in the letters to Lady Welby but also the
 Neglected Argument)

 It's tempting to see it as somewhat akin to what happened to analytic
 philosophy. However I've long found many elements of analytic philosophy
 rather tepid relative to what I find in Peirce. I think his logic of
 vagueness and generals is rather key to a difference with how analytic
 philosophy developed in the 20th century.

 In particular his MS 318 is a great example of how he uses this term (I'm
 not sure I could easily define it)

 Everybody recognizes that it is no inconsiderable art, this business of
 phaneroscopic analysis by which one frames a scientific definition. As I
 practice it, in those cases, like the present, in which I am debarred from
 a direct appeal to the principle of pragmatism, I begin by seizing upon
 that predicate which appears to be most characteristic of the definitum,
 even if it does not quite apply to the entire extension of the definitum.
 If the predicate be too narrow, I afterward seek for some ingredient of it
 which shall be broad enough for an amended definitum and, at the same time,
 be still more scientifically characteristic of it.

 Proceeding in that way with our definitum, sign, we note, as highly
 characteristic, that signs mostly function each between two minds, or
 theatres of consciousness, of which the one is the agent that utters the
 sign (whether acoustically, optically, or otherwise), while the other is
 the patient mind that interprets the sign. Going on with my account of what
 is characteristic of a sign, without taking the least account of
 exceptional cases, for the present, I remark that, before the sign was
 uttered, it already was virtually present to the consciousness of the
 utterer, in the form of a thought. But, as already remarked, a thought is
 itself a sign, and should itself have an utterer (namely , the ego of a
 previous moment), to whose consciousness it must have been already
 virtually present, and so back. Likewise, after a sign has been
 interpreted, it will virtually remain in the consciousness of its
 interpreter, where it will be a sign,-- perhaps, a resolution to apply the
 burden of the communicated sign,-- and, as a sign should, in its turn have
 an interpreter, and so on forward. Now it is undeniably conceivable that a
 beginningless series of successive utterers should all do their work in a
 brief interval of time, and that so should an endless series of
 interpreters. Still, it is not likely to be denied that , in some cases,
 neither the series of utterers nor that of interpreters forms an infinite
 collection. When this is the case, there must be a sign without an utterer
 and a sign without an interpreter. Indeed, there are two pretty conclusive
 arguments on these points that are likely to occur to the reader. But why
 argue, when signs without utterers are often employed? I mean such signs as
 symptoms of disease, signs of the weather, groups of experiences serving as
 premisses, etc . Signs without interpreters less manifestly, but perhaps
 not less certainly, exist. Let the cards for a Jacquard loom be prepared
 and inserted, so that the loom shall weave a picture. Are not those cards
 signs? They convey intelligence,-- intelligence that, considering its spirit
 and pictorial effect, cannot otherwise be conveyed. Yet the woven pictures
 may take fire and be consumed before anybody sees them. A set of those
 models that the designers of vessels drag through the water may have been
 prepared; and with the set a complete series of experiments may have been
 made; and their conditions and results may have been automatically
 recorded. There, then, is a perfect representation of the behavior of a
 certain range of forms. Yet if nobody takes the trouble to study the
 record, there will be no interpreter. So the books of a bank may furnish a
 complete account of the state of the bank. It 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-16 Thread Benjamin Udell

Clark, list,

In regard to the Peirce quote from 1907 that you provided, it's also 
pertinent to the discussion of biosemiosis, physiosemiosis, etc., taking 
place lately here. It was in the 1906 Prolegomena to an Apology for 
Pragmaticism that he discusses quasi-mind, quasi-utterer, 
quasi-interpreter http://www.commens.org/dictionary/term/quasi-mind . In 
the 1907 passage that you quote, mentioning the Jacquard loom, he 
doesn't mention the quasi-s although they seem pertinent. But in 
another 1907 from the same MS 318, published in CP 5.473 (the famous 
semeiosy passage), he says that a Jacquard loom should be regarded as 
a quasi-sign, because the action is that of automatic regulation, 
which he distinguishes from semeiosy (semiosis).


   [Quote]
   In these cases, however, a mental representation of the index is
   produced, which mental representation is called the _immediate
   object_ of the sign; and this object does triadically produce the
   intended, or proper, effect of the sign strictly by means of another
   mental sign; and that this triadic character of the action is
   regarded as essential is shown by the fact that if the thermometer
   is dynamically connected with the heating and cooling apparatus, so
   as to check either effect, we do not, in ordinary parlance speak of
   there being any _semeiosy_, or action of a sign, but, on the
   contrary, say that there is an automatic regulation, an idea
   opposed, in our minds, to that of _semeiosy_. For the proper
   significate outcome of a sign, I propose the name, the interpretant
   of the sign. The example of the imperative command shows that it
   need not be of a mental mode of being. Whether the interpretant be
   necessarily a triadic result is a question of words, that is, of how
   we limit the extension of the term sign; but it seems to me
   convenient to make the triadic production of the interpretant
   essential to a sign, calling the wider concept like a Jacquard
   loom, for example, a quasi-sign.
   [End quote]

I tend to see this distinction as allied a distinction that he makes in 
an unpublished MS which the Robin Catalogue describes as follows:


   831. [Reasoning and Instinct]
   A. MS., n.p., n.d., pp. 2-29, incomplete.
   The fine gradations between subconscious or instinctive mind and
   conscious, controlled reason. Logical machines are not strictly
   reasoning machines because they lack the ability of self-criticism
   and the ability to correct defects which may crop up. Three kinds of
   reasoning: inductive, deductive, hypothetical. Quasi-inferences.

Well, I don't know what to make of quasi-inferences - I'd have thought 
that he would regard instinctive or automatic inferences as 
quasi-reasonings. I'll be very interested to read MS 831 if it ever 
becomes available.


Anyway I've tended to think of genuine semiosis as involving the 
capacity to learn, capacity for self-correction etc. (and I've heard 
that this is De Tienne's view) - I mean not merely self-correction to 
maintain homeostasis or balance while walking etc. (which could be done 
by automatic regulation), but 'design-level' self-correction, correction 
of one's own methods, correction of one's own semiosic habits, etc.


But one finds inferences embodied in vegetable-level and physical 
phenomena, are they not semioses? Are they quasi-semioses? The prefix 
quasi- starts to seem too vague to capture the possible senses. I also 
don't have too firm an idea of all the things that Peirce means by 
mind. Does mind, in Peirce's sense, always involve the capacity to 
learn? If I call something a quasi-mind, should that mean like a mind 
but not learning? Or could it mean learning like a mind without being a 
mind capable of consciousness (I've thought of biological evolution as 
having a 'quasi-mind'). Vegetable-level (quasi-)semiosis seems like we 
ought to strongly distinguish it from whatever strictly dynamic or 
material/chemical (quasi-) semiosis we think there is, because at the 
vegetable level, signs or signals are 'interpreted' in terms of highly 
specific kinds of pertinence to the organism for the end of the thriving 
of the species. It indeed _/seems/_ rather like semiosis as we 
ordinarily think of it because, although vegetable-level organisms don't 
learn (at least last that I heard of), they behave by seemingly 
specific-purposeful interpretants, thanks to the trial-and-error 
(quasi-)learning by evolution that made them that way.  People set up 
the Jacquard loom, put its cards in place, etc., evolution sets up 
(vastly more complex) vegetable organisms. The hypothetical Gaia seems 
like another case. One might say that it is 'quasi-alive'. I guess it 
also has a 'quasi-mind'. Evolving over time, it has 'quasi-mind' in the 
(quasi-)learning sense. We need more prefixes, this is turning into mush.


Best, Ben

On 9/16/2014 12:32 PM, Benjamin Udell wrote:


Clark, list

I thought that Cornelis de Waal had found another passage 

Re: [PEIRCE-L] [biosemiotics:6834] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 2

2014-09-16 Thread Clark Goble

 On Sep 16, 2014, at 10:32 AM, Benjamin Udell bud...@nyc.rr.com wrote:
 
 Yes, analytic philosophy seems tepid next to Peirce. I hardly know what 
 analytic philosophers mean by 'analysis' or, more importantly, by 
 'philosophy'. Decades ago I got a similar vagueness from continental 
 philosophy. 

I think the roll of intuitions are key here. However as you might recall this 
is also the place I have most of my trouble with logical analysis within 
analytic philosophy. It seems too tied to intuitions (i.e. conclusions to 
thought experiments) attempting to create clearly defined definitions. The 
problem is that often the intuitions of philosophers differ greatly from other 
groups. Experimental philosophy attempts to reconcile this but I think it still 
rests on the idea that it’s somehow clear judgments that get a definitions and 
thus analysis. (This gets at Frederik’s comments on Peirce and Husserl too) The 
key problem is that it misses the logic of absence. Peirce’s conception of the 
sign and the difference between object and interpretant avoids that error.

Continental philosophy, especially the brief period of Heideggarian inspired 
post-structuralism, seems to recognize the importance of that absence but 
instead of going to a clear logic of absences the way Peirce’s signs allow 
instead went to an overly metaphoric language where the words were 
intentionally exemplifying the gaps but which in the process lost clarity. 
(Nothing was more frustrating to me than philosophers who I know could write 
clearly, concisely and insightfully aping Derrida’s demonstrative period)

The problem is that both get at part of the problem, and both recognize the 
other misses something important. But neither seem able to reconcile. (Although 
to be fair that’s been changing a lot the past 10 years or so - but it has a 
long ways to go)

 In the preface to his _Phenomenology of Perception_, Merleau-Ponty mentioned 
 that his own kind of philosophy cannot define its own scope, at least not 
 yet, insofar as it has existed as a movement before arriving at complete 
 awareness of itself as a philosophy”. 

To be fair, when one considers how broad Peirce’s approach to signs is and (my 
own belief) that the post-Husserlian phenomenologists were touching on this, it 
makes sense that they recognized the problem. They were working from the much 
more restrictive approach of Husserl but recognizing there was much more. (This 
is made explicit in Derrida’s approach to Husserl where he explicitly says 
Peirce comes closest to what he sees as beyond) While I think there was a 
method in the madness of Derrida’s demonstrative period, I confess as I get 
older I prefer his older works best. Every thing after seems the same idea 
expressed different ways via an immanent critique that seems designed to annoy 
people. To me Derrida’s play is very much Peirce’s musement but perhaps done in 
a less than ultimately fashion. (Of course I think that of most of the 
“revolutions” of the 60’s - it seemed like people could revolt only through a 
process of excess)

Anyways, I raise this due to your quote from Baldwin Dictionary.

Analysis (in logic): Ger. logische Analyse; Fr. analyse logique; Ital. analisi 
logica. Literally a resolution, an unloosening of that which has been combined. 
(Emphasis mine)

That is explicitly the meaning of deconstruction too so that as we deconstruct 
what is combined we can start to see it. This is a kind of backwards working 
through a genealogy. For Peirce, especially in that quote from MS 318 I gave, 
is doing that very kind of analysis. Now thankfully he avoids the excesses of 
Derrida as well as usually the aporias that characterize many Socratic dialogs 
and even at times Aristotle. (The place of aporias in Derrida is interesting 
but tangental here) Still he approaches that at times, such as when he says,

When this is the case, there must be a sign without an utterer and a sign 
without an interpreter. Indeed, there are two pretty conclusive arguments on 
these points that are likely to occur to the reader. But why argue, when signs 
without utterers are often employed? I mean such signs as symptoms of disease, 
signs of the weather, groups of experiences serving as premisses, etc . 

To my ears, this is very much a productive use of aporia. In Peirce’s case (as 
I’d argue in Derrida, although it’s more confusing there) this leads to all 
interesting expansions of the notion of the sign into the various “quasi” 
elements we’ve discussed.

Sorry for the tangent, but I think the path of the post-Husserlian philosophers 
is interesting relative to Frederik’s book.







-
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on Reply List or Reply All to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L in the BODY of the message. More at