Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2013-02-19 Thread Angela C Carmella
Yes iust left roselle pk

Sent from my iPhone

On Oct 4, 2012, at 11:26 AM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

Marci:  As this thread has demonstrated, I certainly have concerns about the 
nature of the cooperation with evil theory of substantial burden being 
asserted here.  But the theory is anything but new.  It is also not based on 
the notion that others' use of contraception would violate the employers' 
religious liberty--indeed, I think most of these employers likely assume that 
their employees will continue to use contraception regularly in any event, 
albeit at a greater cost to the employees.

The claim here is that the employer's involvement in allegedly facilitating the 
employees' conduct implicates the employers themselves in wrongdoing.  As I've 
explained, I think this theory raises serious, difficult questions.  But it's 
hardly novel.  It was the theory in Thomas (he wasn't the one using the tanks 
to shot enemy soldiers).  It's the theory we discussed on this list back in 
1999-2000, when confronted by cases of landlords who didn't want to rent to 
unmarrieds.  It's the theory raised in the Posner and related cases about 
police protection of abortion facilities.  And it's the theory underlying the 
current disputes about proprietors -- BBs, florists, photographers, caterers, 
etc. -- who wish to discriminate against gay couples.

Indeed, what makes it interesting and important is precisely that, post-Thomas, 
so many different religious liberty claims take this form.

On Thu, Oct 4, 2012 at 11:08 AM, 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
Actually, this free exercise theory is new.  It is the first time that a 
religious believer has made a free exercise claim because they
don't want others (with different beliefs) to potentially violate the 
believer's religious rules for conduct.  The company owner and family won't use 
the plan for women's health benefits involving contraception or sterilization, 
and are not required to.  The owner will not even know if the plan ever covers 
these services because
of the doctor-patient privilege.  It is a potential event, over which the owner 
has no control or right to control and will have no knowledge, and the conduct 
is the employee's conduct, not the employer's.  The purported violation is that 
a for-profit company, which is not permitted to discriminate on the basis of 
religion, must pay health insurance that includes coverage for independent acts 
obtained solely for health reasons that differ from the employer's religious 
beliefs.

The approach taken in the HHS regs also is not new.  States have routinely 
required insurance companies to include in their plans various services, e.g., 
Pap smears, and physicals, etc.  That means that the employer buying a plan can 
only buy plans that include the mandatory coverage.  The HHS regs follow this 
model of including the health protection that reduces health costs and 
increases health -- particularly for women, whose health issues historically 
have seemed to be easier to exclude than men's.  So the approach taken in the 
regs is actually not a new approach to keeping health care costs down and 
achieving the greatest health for the largest number.

What is new is this attempt to avoid cost and health-driven decisions about 
coverage by interposing personal religious requirements on others.  It is a 
weaker
claim than any yet brought against government regulations on free exercise 
grounds.



Marci




Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215tel:%28212%29%20790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com


-Original Message-
From: Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org
To: religionlaw religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 2:47 pm
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-05 Thread hamilton02
Actually, Doug, you might want to reread Thomas. He worked in the roll foundry, 
which closed.
So he then asked to work in any other department.  All of those departments 
involved parts for weapons.  He could not do that he said,
But he said that he would have been willing to create materials that then later 
were built into weapons.


In the opinion's  words:


He testified that he could, in good conscience, engage indirectly in the 
production of materials that might be used ultimately to fabricate arms -- for 
example, as an employee of a raw material supplier or of a roll foundry.


So it is not nearly the complicity-with-evil case others have said it is.  
Thomas was objecting to having to work directly on weapons parts, not doing 
something that might ultimately produce something he disagrees with.  I think 
Thomas could have sent his money into a fungible stream...  The HHS regs 
situation is different.  The employer has no belief against paying for health 
care.  What he objects to is sterilization and contraception.  He says he can't 
give money so that someone else might use it to do something he disagrees with. 
 Yet, any use of the fungible funds is made completely independently of the 
employer -- under patient-doctor confidentiality and by a woman.   On her side 
is Griswold, Title VII on gender discrimination, and doctor-patient 
confidentiality.




Marci



 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; 
hamilton02 hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Thu, Oct 4, 2012 12:09 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA  
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


Marci, you are arbitarily singling out different steps in a parallel sequence 
of 
events. 

Thomas was asked to help assemble tank turrets. Others would put the turrets 
into tanks. Still others, maybe, would use the tanks to kill people. Or maybe 
not. 

The bishops' view is that they are being asked to contract for and pay for 
policies that cover contraception and very early abortifacients. That is what 
they object to, whether or not anything happens thereafter. Other people will 
use those policies to pay for medical care. Maybe some of them will pay for 
contraception or emergency contraception. Or maybe not, although here the odds 
seem higher than with the tanks. But it doesn't matter. The objection is to 
contracting for and paying for the coverage.


On Thu, 4 Oct 2012 11:44:49 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
First, let me applaud Marty's memory.  I am certain I could not tell you what 
was discussed on this list in 1999!  I'm not sure I was even reading it then.


In any event, this is not the Thomas case.  In Thomas, the objection was based 
on the believer avoiding taking action that he would find in conflict with his 
faith.
He could not, consistent with his faith, participate in the manufacture of 
materials used in arms.  In this case, the alleged violation is in the 
financial 
support of a system
in which others engage in acts that conflict with his religion.  That is a 
step 
farther.  That is what makes me most uncomfortable about this (along with the 
fact it singles out women's health).


I understand that the argument is that the payment into the fund itself is a 
burden, but that cannot be a winning argument after Lee, or after Zelman or the 
4-person plurality in Mitchell v. Helms, either.  Under the Religion Clauses, 
money is fungible, and the entity/person sending money into a stream no longer 
has power/say/responsibility for how the money is used by independent actors 
who 
pluck it from that stream.   So we are back to the question whether there is a 
free exercise right for a for-profit company to deter employees from engaging 
in 
acts that conflict with the employer's religion.  


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com





Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-04 Thread hamilton02
Actually, this free exercise theory is new.  It is the first time that a 
religious believer has made a free exercise claim because they
don't want others (with different beliefs) to potentially violate the 
believer's religious rules for conduct.  The company owner and family won't use 
the plan for women's health benefits involving contraception or sterilization, 
and are not required to.  The owner will not even know if the plan ever covers 
these services because
of the doctor-patient privilege.  It is a potential event, over which the owner 
has no control or right to control and will have no knowledge, and the conduct 
is the employee's conduct, not the employer's.  The purported violation is that 
a for-profit company, which is not permitted to discriminate on the basis of 
religion, must pay health insurance that includes coverage for independent acts 
obtained solely for health reasons that differ from the employer's religious 
beliefs.  


The approach taken in the HHS regs also is not new.  States have routinely 
required insurance companies to include in their plans various services, e.g., 
Pap smears, and physicals, etc.  That means that the employer buying a plan can 
only buy plans that include the mandatory coverage.  The HHS regs follow this 
model of including the health protection that reduces health costs and 
increases health -- particularly for women, whose health issues historically 
have seemed to be easier to exclude than men's.  So the approach taken in the 
regs is actually not a new approach to keeping health care costs down and 
achieving the greatest health for the largest number.


What is new is this attempt to avoid cost and health-driven decisions about 
coverage by interposing personal religious requirements on others.  It is a 
weaker
claim than any yet brought against government regulations on free exercise 
grounds.  






Marci






 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org
To: religionlaw religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 2:47 pm
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Dear Marci,
 
The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.  
 
I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.
 
Blessings,
Derek
 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 
The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system 

so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-04 Thread Marty Lederman
Marci:  As this thread has demonstrated, I certainly have concerns about
the nature of the cooperation with evil theory of substantial burden
being asserted here.  But the theory is anything but new.  It is also not
based on the notion that others' use of contraception would violate the
employers' religious liberty--indeed, I think most of these employers
likely assume that their employees will continue to use contraception
regularly in any event, albeit at a greater cost to the employees.

The claim here is that the employer's involvement in allegedly facilitating
the employees' conduct implicates *the employers themselves* in
wrongdoing.  As I've explained, I think this theory raises serious,
difficult questions.  But it's hardly novel.  It was the theory in *Thomas *(he
wasn't the one using the tanks to shot enemy soldiers).  It's the theory we
discussed on this list back in 1999-2000, when confronted by cases of
landlords who didn't want to rent to unmarrieds.  It's the theory raised in
the Posner and related cases about police protection of abortion
facilities.  And it's the theory underlying the current disputes about
proprietors -- BBs, florists, photographers, caterers, etc. -- who wish to
discriminate against gay couples.

Indeed, what makes it interesting and important is precisely that, post-*
Thomas*, so many different religious liberty claims take this form.

On Thu, Oct 4, 2012 at 11:08 AM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

 Actually, this free exercise theory is new.  It is the first time that a
 religious believer has made a free exercise claim because they
 don't want others (with different beliefs) to potentially violate the
 believer's religious rules for conduct.  The company owner and family won't
 use the plan for women's health benefits involving contraception or
 sterilization, and are not required to.  The owner will not even know if
 the plan ever covers these services because
 of the doctor-patient privilege.  It is a potential event, over which the
 owner has no control or right to control and will have no knowledge, and
 the conduct is the employee's conduct, not the employer's.  The purported
 violation is that a for-profit company, which is not permitted to
 discriminate on the basis of religion, must pay health insurance that
 includes coverage for independent acts obtained solely for health reasons
 that differ from the employer's religious beliefs.

  The approach taken in the HHS regs also is not new.  States have
 routinely required insurance companies to include in their plans various
 services, e.g., Pap smears, and physicals, etc.  That means that the
 employer buying a plan can only buy plans that include the mandatory
 coverage.  The HHS regs follow this model of including the health protection
 that reduces health costs and increases health -- particularly for women,
 whose health issues historically have seemed to be easier to exclude than
 men's.  So the approach taken in the regs is actually not a new approach
 to keeping health care costs down and achieving the greatest health for the
 largest number.

  What is new is this attempt to avoid cost and health-driven decisions
 about coverage by interposing personal religious requirements on others.
  It is a weaker
 claim than any yet brought against government regulations on free exercise
 grounds.



  Marci




 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com


 -Original Message-
 From: Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org
 To: religionlaw religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 2:47 pm
 Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  Dear Marci,

 The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual
 iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like
 *Yoder* to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against
 an individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs
 (whatever those beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I
 noted earlier, the proper focus of whether there is a government imposed
 substantial burden  is an objective test that focuses on the action taken
 by the government, not the subjective feelings of the believer.   An
 objective substantial burden is an action by the government that coerces or
 tend to inhibit any religious exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear
 that being fined for engaging in a particular act of religious exercise is
 objectively a substantial burden regardless of the particular nature of the
 religious exercise involved (e.g., wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the
 public school, or being forced to purchase a product or service contrary to
 your beliefs).Objectively focusing on the nature of the action taken by
 the government avoids getting into a quagmire of analyzing

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-04 Thread hamilton02
First, let me applaud Marty's memory.  I am certain I could not tell you what 
was discussed on this list in 1999!  I'm not sure I was even reading it then.


In any event, this is not the Thomas case.  In Thomas, the objection was based 
on the believer avoiding taking action that he would find in conflict with his 
faith.
He could not, consistent with his faith, participate in the manufacture of 
materials used in arms.  In this case, the alleged violation is in the 
financial support of a system
in which others engage in acts that conflict with his religion.  That is a step 
farther.  That is what makes me most uncomfortable about this (along with the 
fact it singles out women's health).


I understand that the argument is that the payment into the fund itself is a 
burden, but that cannot be a winning argument after Lee, or after Zelman or the 
4-person plurality in Mitchell v. Helms, either.  Under the Religion Clauses, 
money is fungible, and the entity/person sending money into a stream no longer 
has power/say/responsibility for how the money is used by independent actors 
who pluck it from that stream.   So we are back to the question whether there 
is a free exercise right for a for-profit company to deter employees from 
engaging in acts that conflict with the employer's religion.  


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Thu, Oct 4, 2012 11:25 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


Marci:  As this thread has demonstrated, I certainly have concerns about the 
nature of the cooperation with evil theory of substantial burden being 
asserted here.  But the theory is anything but new.  It is also not based on 
the notion that others' use of contraception would violate the employers' 
religious liberty--indeed, I think most of these employers likely assume that 
their employees will continue to use contraception regularly in any event, 
albeit at a greater cost to the employees.

The claim here is that the employer's involvement in allegedly facilitating the 
employees' conduct implicates the employers themselves in wrongdoing.  As I've 
explained, I think this theory raises serious, difficult questions.  But it's 
hardly novel.  It was the theory in Thomas (he wasn't the one using the tanks 
to shot enemy soldiers).  It's the theory we discussed on this list back in 
1999-2000, when confronted by cases of landlords who didn't want to rent to 
unmarrieds.  It's the theory raised in the Posner and related cases about 
police protection of abortion facilities.  And it's the theory underlying the 
current disputes about proprietors -- BBs, florists, photographers, caterers, 
etc. -- who wish to discriminate against gay couples. 

Indeed, what makes it interesting and important is precisely that, post-Thomas, 
so many different religious liberty claims take this form.


On Thu, Oct 4, 2012 at 11:08 AM,  hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

Actually, this free exercise theory is new.  It is the first time that a 
religious believer has made a free exercise claim because they
don't want others (with different beliefs) to potentially violate the 
believer's religious rules for conduct.  The company owner and family won't use 
the plan for women's health benefits involving contraception or sterilization, 
and are not required to.  The owner will not even know if the plan ever covers 
these services because
of the doctor-patient privilege.  It is a potential event, over which the owner 
has no control or right to control and will have no knowledge, and the conduct 
is the employee's conduct, not the employer's.  The purported violation is that 
a for-profit company, which is not permitted to discriminate on the basis of 
religion, must pay health insurance that includes coverage for independent acts 
obtained solely for health reasons that differ from the employer's religious 
beliefs.  


The approach taken in the HHS regs also is not new.  States have routinely 
required insurance companies to include in their plans various services, e.g., 
Pap smears, and physicals, etc.  That means that the employer buying a plan can 
only buy plans that include the mandatory coverage.  The HHS regs follow this 
model of including the health protection that reduces health costs and 
increases health -- particularly for women, whose health issues historically 
have seemed to be easier to exclude than men's.  So the approach taken in the 
regs is actually not a new approach to keeping health care costs down and 
achieving the greatest health for the largest number.


What is new is this attempt to avoid cost and health-driven decisions about 
coverage by interposing

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-04 Thread Douglas Laycock
Marci, you are arbitarily singling out different steps in a parallel sequence 
of events. 

Thomas was asked to help assemble tank turrets. Others would put the turrets 
into tanks. Still others, maybe, would use the tanks to kill people. Or maybe 
not. 

The bishops' view is that they are being asked to contract for and pay for 
policies that cover contraception and very early abortifacients. That is what 
they object to, whether or not anything happens thereafter. Other people will 
use those policies to pay for medical care. Maybe some of them will pay for 
contraception or emergency contraception. Or maybe not, although here the odds 
seem higher than with the tanks. But it doesn't matter. The objection is to 
contracting for and paying for the coverage.


On Thu, 4 Oct 2012 11:44:49 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
First, let me applaud Marty's memory.  I am certain I could not tell you what 
was discussed on this list in 1999!  I'm not sure I was even reading it then.


In any event, this is not the Thomas case.  In Thomas, the objection was based 
on the believer avoiding taking action that he would find in conflict with his 
faith.
He could not, consistent with his faith, participate in the manufacture of 
materials used in arms.  In this case, the alleged violation is in the 
financial support of a system
in which others engage in acts that conflict with his religion.  That is a 
step farther.  That is what makes me most uncomfortable about this (along with 
the fact it singles out women's health).


I understand that the argument is that the payment into the fund itself is a 
burden, but that cannot be a winning argument after Lee, or after Zelman or 
the 4-person plurality in Mitchell v. Helms, either.  Under the Religion 
Clauses, money is fungible, and the entity/person sending money into a stream 
no longer has power/say/responsibility for how the money is used by 
independent actors who pluck it from that stream.   So we are back to the 
question whether there is a free exercise right for a for-profit company to 
deter employees from engaging in acts that conflict with the employer's 
religion.  


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com





Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-04 Thread Marty Lederman
Cathy Kaveny asked me to send along this reaction to some of the issues
we've been discussing:

Hi all,

This is a fascinating discussion. I'm sorry I can't participate more
because I have to get ready for a couple of talks.

So I'll limit myself to three quick points.

1. Is the cooperation permissible according to Catholic teaching? This
seems to me to be, at the very least, a question Catholics can publicly
raise and discuss. In my view, the insurance issue is remote mediate
material cooperation with evil--the sort of thing that is justifiable with
proportionate reason.  The type of arrangement has been signed off on by
moral theologians many times before.  Much closer cooperation with graver
evils has been justified --for example, the manualists have said that it is
permissible for a nurse to hand the instruments to a doctor whom she knows
is performing an abortion.  What's the difference here? I think the key
issue isn't the cooperation itself, but the scandal--the current bishops
discern a need to take a stand against the culture of death.

2. Some have argued that the cooperation with evil is formal--i.e.,
intentionally furthering the wrongdoing because it is under a contractual
arrangement. You're buying the insurance policy, it has contraception in
it. You're intending to buy contraception.  In my view, that's a mistake.
 The cooperation is intentional, but the contribution to the evil is
praeter intentionem--beside the intention of the person contracting for
the policy.

3.  The more vexing question for me is the relationship between the ad
intra discussion and the legal analysis.  On the one hand, I don't think
it's a good idea for courts to go mucking around in religious traditions,
turning themselves into theologians of various faiths. On the other hand, I
am leery of reading the notion of substantial out of the jurisprudence,
so that any burden is substantial if any religious believer claims it is.

Take care, and special thanks to Marty for organizing such a wonderful
conversation!

Best,

Cathleen


On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 11:31 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.comwrote:

 Mark:  My point is that, as far as I know, for centuries *neither *case
 has been considered impermissible cooperation with evil under the mode of
 moral analysis you invoke (which I agree is respectable, indeed).  Of
 course if the employer affirmatively *chose* to cover contraception, or
 had a legal choice whether to accept a plan with it or without it, and
 chose the former, that would be a form of *formal *cooperation with evil,
 which is proscribed (assuming, as I am here for sake of argument, that
 contraception is in fact evil from the employer's perspective).  But
 absent such consent or choice, as here, the question is whether the
 material cooperation is sufficiently proximate -- and my understanding is
 that the proximity in these cases would be the same, and *not *sufficient
 to raise the prospect of impermissible cooperation.

 FWIW, Cathy Kaveny (copied here) offered a really fantastic summary of the
 Catholic doctrine on this at the beginning of our second panel:

 http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=1J4rCsq732c

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug, 

  

Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be 
different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care, etc. 
actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer money? Would 
saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a substantial burden even if 
the saving resulted a government mandate to provide health care that the 
employer found religiously objectionable? 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  


On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote: 
 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
 from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
 special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just 
 the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing 
 against conscience protections for medical providers. 
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
 the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
 The salary payments could have been used for anything. 
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the 
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is 
 highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling 
 interest in paying taxes. 
 
 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the 
 money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a 
 package of services that includes the services the employer believes to be 
 immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer 
 believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those 
 services and pays for those services, and these employers say they cannot in 
 conscience do those things. 
 
 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400 
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote: 
 Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state 
 can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle. 
 It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the 
 money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of 
 which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even 
 abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to 
 partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is 
 used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve 
 contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it 
 for that purpose. (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require 
 plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.) 
  
 Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of 
 salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial 
 burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be 
 overcome by a compelling government interest. For anyone who starts from 
 that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question. But I am not 
 aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the 
 payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows 
 that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of 
 salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful 
 in the eyes of the employer. 
  
 Thus the question here is whether the state ought to take at face value the 
 assertions of some employers that the moral obligation changes dramatically 
 when the money is used for partial subsidization of an insurance plan, 
 rather than for taxes or salaries. I actually think this is a complex 
 question, as to which I deeply appreciate the many thoughtful views others 
 have contributed to this thread. But whatever the merits of that 
 distinction, the case is a far cry from compelling the employer to kill 
 another human being. 
  
 On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 7:27 PM, Douglas Laycock 
 dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in
virtually all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the
employer is prohibited from permitting its money to be used for
contraception, even as mediated by independent decisions of others; and if,
as the government alleges, in fact the actual cost to the employer of
providing the plan is *lower* because of the inclusions of contraception
(the use of which avoids much higher costs associated with pregnancy), then
in a very real sense the employers' dollars are not being used, even
remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  Seems to me that,
too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden claim, and not
because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of religious
obligations.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is
 arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer
 believes to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t
 matter whether it costs money or saves money.

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *b...@jmcenter.org
 *Sent:* Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Doug, 

   

 Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be
 different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care, etc.
 actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer money?
 Would saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a substantial
 burden even if the saving resulted a government mandate to provide health
 care that the employer found religiously objectionable? 

   

 Bob Ritter 

   

 Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

 A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

 Falls Church, VA 22042 

 703-533-0236 

   


 On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote:
  My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and
 exemption from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be
 nothing special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim
 than just the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice movement
 pushing against conscience protections for medical providers.
 
  As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays
 salary, and the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer
 considers immoral. The salary payments could have been used for anything.
 
  I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral,
 is highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's
 compelling interest in paying taxes.
 
  The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because
 the money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer
 buys a package of services that includes the services the employer believes
 to be immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the
 employer believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for
 those services and pays for those services, and these employers say they
 cannot in conscience do those things.
 
  On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
  Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
  Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the
 state
  can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in
 battle.
  It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of
 the
  money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some
 of
  which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or
 even
  abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
  partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
  used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
  contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use
 it
  for that purpose. (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to
 require
  plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)
  
  Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases
 of
  salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
  burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
  overcome by a compelling government interest. For anyone who starts
 from
  that view, the HHS would certainly raise

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread hamilton02
The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.  


From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power. 
 That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.


On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:


The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.




Marci





 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.


On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:


The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

 

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

 


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


 

Doug, 


  

Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be 
different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care, etc. 
actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer money? Would 
saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a substantial burden even if 
the saving resulted a government mandate to provide health care that the 
employer found religiously objectionable? 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  


On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote: 
 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
 from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
 special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just 
 the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing 
 against conscience protections for medical providers. 
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
 the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
 The salary payments could have been used for anything. 
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the 
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is 
 highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling 
 interest in paying taxes. 
 
 The ACA looks different to those objecting

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
Can I ask a quick question for people like Marci, Marty, and others who 
doubt the existence of a “substantial burden”?



What about United States v. Lee?  The Amish object to paying Social Security 
taxes.  The government makes them.  The decision to use the taxes for Social 
Security is the government’s, not the Amish.  The Amish say, “Well, we 
object to giving you money to pay for that.”  The Court says there’s a 
burden.  Isn’t this case just Lee again?  What am I missing?  (If I’ve 
missed earlier posts discussing this, I’m sorry.)



Best, Chris


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Scarberry, Mark
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546tel:434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Ira Lupu
Re: Chris Lund's question about Lee -- The Amish take care of their own who
are disabled or no longer able to work.  They didn't want to pay twice --
once for FICA contributions, and again in their own community.  And the
FICA contributions were earmarked for just that use.

Employers objecting to the ACA mandate are not concerned about paying
twice.  They want to be immune from even the appearance of support for
these services, even in a context where they can openly condemn the
services.  The religious entity employers (who can refuse to hire those who
use such services) don't even have to pay once.  They just want to be
entirely out of the causation loop between ACA  policies and the provision
of pregnancy prevention services.

Many taxpayers would like to be out of the causation loop between paying
taxes and financing causes they find deeply immoral -- the death penalty,
some or all wars, etc.  Of course, we can handle this on the compelling
interest side (need for uniformity), but the question of attenuation and
distance between the status (employer, taxpayer) and the conduct remains.
The question does not disappear because the claimant says so.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:35 AM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 Can I ask a quick question for people like Marci, Marty, and others who
 doubt the existence of a “substantial burden”?

 ** **

 What about *United States v. Lee*?  The Amish object to paying Social
 Security taxes.  The government makes them.  The decision to use the taxes
 for Social Security is the government’s, not the Amish.  The Amish say,
 “Well, we object to giving you money to pay for that.”  The Court says
 there’s a burden.  Isn’t this case just *Lee *again?  What am I missing?
 (If I’ve missed earlier posts discussing this, I’m sorry.)

 ** **

 Best, Chris

 ** **


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




-- 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Isn't that like saying, if it's OK for you to 'produc[e] the 
raw product necessary for the production of any kind of tank,' why is working 
on tank turrets any different??  Why isn't the answer much like that given in 
Thomas:  But Thomas' statements reveal no more than that he found work in the 
roll foundry sufficiently insulated from producing weapons of war.  We see, 
therefore, that Thomas drew a line, and it is not for us to say that the line 
he drew was an unreasonable one.?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection, enters 
into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in exchange for 
labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used for 
contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the employer 
considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be changed 
slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only wages (in 
effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance), but also access 
to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was getting at here was:  
If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why is the second any 
different?
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546tel:434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
I think Doug is right that it doesn't matter whether it costs money or
saves money.  The objection is any money going to the religiously
prohibited use.

 

You see this kind of argument in Establishment Clause cases.  The
government says to a taxpayer, You need to pay money to fund a religious
school.  The taxpayer says, I object to my money supporting the
religious functions of the school.  The government says, Well, you'd
have to pay for a public school anyway, and that would cost more.  So
you're just saving money this way.  

 

The government's logic here was rejected, and I think rightly, in Smith v.
Jefferson County Bd. of School Com'rs, 641 F.3d 197, 211 (6th Cir. 2011)
(A municipal taxpayer has standing to challenge any unconstitutional
appropriation or expenditure, regardless of whether more money would have
been spent had the government remained within constitutional bounds.
Taxpayer standing in this context will not turn on whether it was a
bargain to violate the Constitution.).

 

Best, 

Chris

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:03 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in
virtually all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the
employer is prohibited from permitting its money to be used for
contraception, even as mediated by independent decisions of others; and
if, as the government alleges, in fact the actual cost to the employer of
providing the plan is lower because of the inclusions of contraception
(the use of which avoids much higher costs associated with pregnancy),
then in a very real sense the employers' dollars are not being used, even
remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  Seems to me that,
too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden claim, and not
because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of religious
obligations.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer
believes to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't
matter whether it costs money or saves money.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM


To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug, 

  

Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be
different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care,
etc. actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer
money? Would saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a
substantial burden even if the saving resulted a government mandate to
provide health care that the employer found religiously objectionable? 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  


On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote: 
 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and
exemption from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should
be nothing special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader
claim than just the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice
movement pushing against conscience protections for medical providers. 
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays
salary, and the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer
considers immoral. The salary payments could have been used for anything. 
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the
government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral,
is highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's
compelling interest in paying taxes. 
 
 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because
the money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer
buys a package of services that includes the services the employer
believes to be immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills
that the employer believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer
contracts for those services and pays for those services, and these
employers say they cannot in conscience do those things. 
 
 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400 
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Scarberry, Mark
And the point then, Marty, is that for centuries there has been a respectable 
mode of moral analysis in which the directness of involvement in an action is 
related to moral complicity. Buying an insurance policy that constitutes an 
agreement by the employer to subsidize a specific activity is a much more 
direct involvement than just paying wages that an employee may use in any way 
the employee chooses.

Mark



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection, enters 
into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in exchange for 
labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used for 
contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the employer 
considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be changed 
slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only wages (in 
effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance), but also access 
to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was getting at here was:  
If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why is the second any 
different?
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546tel:434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Mark:  My point is that, as far as I know, for centuries *neither *case
has been considered impermissible cooperation with evil under the mode of
moral analysis you invoke (which I agree is respectable, indeed).  Of
course if the employer affirmatively *chose* to cover contraception, or had
a legal choice whether to accept a plan with it or without it, and chose
the former, that would be a form of *formal *cooperation with evil, which
is proscribed (assuming, as I am here for sake of argument, that
contraception is in fact evil from the employer's perspective).  But
absent such consent or choice, as here, the question is whether the
material cooperation is sufficiently proximate -- and my understanding is
that the proximity in these cases would be the same, and *not *sufficient
to raise the prospect of impermissible cooperation.

FWIW, Cathy Kaveny (copied here) offered a really fantastic summary of the
Catholic doctrine on this at the beginning of our second panel:

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=1J4rCsq732c



On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 11:15 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 And the point then, Marty, is that for centuries there has been a
 respectable mode of moral analysis in which the directness of involvement
 in an action is related to moral complicity. Buying an insurance policy
 that constitutes an agreement by the employer to subsidize a specific
 activity is a much more direct involvement than just paying wages that an
 employee may use in any way the employee chooses.

 ** **

 Mark

 ** **

 ** **

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection,
 enters into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in
 exchange for labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used
 for contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the
 employer considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be
 changed slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only
 wages (in effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance),
 but also access to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was
 getting at here was:  If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why
 is the second any different?

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the
 employer’s money mediated by independent decisions of others. It’s the
 requirement that the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions
 that the employer believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has
 claimed that he or she can withhold payment of wages because the employee
 might choose to use the money to obtain contraceptives or other services.
 

  

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM


 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  

 Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in
 virtually all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the
 employer is prohibited from permitting its money to be used for
 contraception, even as mediated by independent decisions of others; and if,
 as the government alleges, in fact the actual cost to the employer of
 providing the plan is *lower* because of the inclusions of contraception
 (the use of which avoids much higher costs associated with pregnancy), then
 in a very real sense the employers' dollars are not being used, even
 remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  Seems to me that,
 too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden claim, and not
 because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of religious
 obligations.

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote:

 The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is
 arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer
 believes to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t
 matter whether it costs money or saves money.

  

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Eugene has it exactly right.

On a related note, if, as some people have claimed, insurance premiums would be 
higher if contraceptive, sterilization etc. services were not covered (due to 
additional pregnancies), then it becomes perfectly obvious that the objection 
is not a disguised attempt to avoid costs. The analogy is imperfect, but it's 
like a taxpayer being allowed to check a box on a tax return that will cause 
the taxpayer to have to pay 10% extra in taxes, but will also cause the govt to 
segregate the taxpayer's payment (into a lockbox?) so that none of the money 
is traceable to payment for armaments. A taxpayer who checks the box certainly 
can't be accused of claiming a conscientious objection to war in order to save 
money.

(The analogy is imperfect for various reasons. For example, one who pays taxes 
is not being required to assent to the use of the taxes for any purpose. It 
also seems unlikely that insurance rates actually will be lower if 
contraception is covered. The main effect of the HHS requirement, insofar as it 
deals with contraception, may be that people switch from inexpensive birth 
control methods - e.g., generic pills that have been on the market for a long 
time - to more expensive kinds - e.g., the latest name brand version that is 
still under patent. The requirement, if I understand it correctly, requires 
coverage of all FDA approved contraceptives (without a copay and without a 
higher copay for nongeneric drugs. I wonder whether the pharmaceutical 
companies helped write it.)

Mark

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 8:07 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Isn't that like saying, if it's OK for you to 'produc[e] the 
raw product necessary for the production of any kind of tank,' why is working 
on tank turrets any different??  Why isn't the answer much like that given in 
Thomas:  But Thomas' statements reveal no more than that he found work in the 
roll foundry sufficiently insulated from producing weapons of war.  We see, 
therefore, that Thomas drew a line, and it is not for us to say that the line 
he drew was an unreasonable one.?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection, enters 
into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in exchange for 
labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used for 
contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the employer 
considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be changed 
slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only wages (in 
effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance), but also access 
to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was getting at here was:  
If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why is the second any 
different?
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
Thanks, Chip.  A couple responses.

 

The way I read Lee, the burden was not that the Amish had to pay twice.
The burden was that they had to pay the government at all.  See, e.g.,
Lee, 455 U.S. at 257 (We therefore accept appellee's contention that both
payment and receipt of social security benefits is forbidden by the Amish
faith.  Because the payment of the taxes or receipt of benefits violates
Amish religious beliefs, compulsory participation in the social security
system interferes with their free exercise rights.).  True enough that
the Amish took care of their own.  But this seems like a background fact
necessary to explain (and tacitly validate) the Amish's religious beliefs;
it does not seem necessary to the finding of a burden.  Footnote 6 of the
opinion refers to another organization (Sai Baba) that the Court says does
not provide for their own members.  The Court mentions their views as a
reason to think that the Amish belief is bona fide; the Court does not
suggest that there would be no burden in that case.

 

But your post also led me down a logical trail that makes me think the
burden in the ACA case might be clearer than the burden in Lee.  The
Amish's religious objection in Lee starts with a Biblical requirement that
religious communities provide for their own members.  The government's
brief in Lee sensibly asks, Why is this a burden?  You can provide for
your own people, but still pay social security taxes.  (See U.S. Br. in
Lee, at 10-11.)  The Amish respond in their brief by saying, No, well,
also it's a sin to pay the taxes at all.  It's not clear to me this is
the most natural reading of the Biblical text.  But the Supreme Court
doesn't want to get into that.  So they (again citing Thomas) say, We
therefore accept appellee's contention that both payment and receipt of
social security benefits is forbidden by the Amish faith.  I think that
whole accept appellee's contention language is important-the Court may
not necessarily believe it, but will not investigate it further.

 

The Court in Lee thus goes to lengths to interpret the religious objection
as the kind of religious objection that the ACA plaintiffs raise: The
government is requiring us to pay money that will go toward things to
which we religiously object.  And the Court unanimously finds that to be a
burden.

 

Of course, none of this speaks to the sincerity or the compelling-interest
parts of it.  

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:59 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Re: Chris Lund's question about Lee -- The Amish take care of their own
who are disabled or no longer able to work.  They didn't want to pay twice
-- once for FICA contributions, and again in their own community.  And the
FICA contributions were earmarked for just that use.

Employers objecting to the ACA mandate are not concerned about paying
twice.  They want to be immune from even the appearance of support for
these services, even in a context where they can openly condemn the
services.  The religious entity employers (who can refuse to hire those
who use such services) don't even have to pay once.  They just want to be
entirely out of the causation loop between ACA  policies and the provision
of pregnancy prevention services.

Many taxpayers would like to be out of the causation loop between paying
taxes and financing causes they find deeply immoral -- the death penalty,
some or all wars, etc.  Of course, we can handle this on the compelling
interest side (need for uniformity), but the question of attenuation and
distance between the status (employer, taxpayer) and the conduct remains.
The question does not disappear because the claimant says so.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:35 AM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

Can I ask a quick question for people like Marci, Marty, and others who
doubt the existence of a substantial burden?

 

What about United States v. Lee?  The Amish object to paying Social
Security taxes.  The government makes them.  The decision to use the taxes
for Social Security is the government's, not the Amish.  The Amish say,
Well, we object to giving you money to pay for that.  The Court says
there's a burden.  Isn't this case just Lee again?  What am I missing?
(If I've missed earlier posts discussing this, I'm sorry.)

 

Best, Chris

 


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
wrongly) forward

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
Chris, I respectfully disagree with the ipso facto view that a plaintiff is
substantially burdened when ever compelled to do something their religion
forbids. Burdened yes, substantially burdened maybe. This may sound cold, but
it's business. I would suggest to people who oppose the mandate to move on
but I know that isn't going to happen.

I believe that current mandate found the correct accommodation in balancing
the interests of employers and employees. Obviously, some disagree.

Not said in this discussion so far is that in the name of religion much ill is
done (including war and discrimination). In my view, broadening the
accommodation would add to the list. (I would see granting the accommodation to
O'Brien like granting a religious exemption to parents from seeking medical care
for their sick children.)

Bob Ritter


On October 2, 2012 at 1:05 PM Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 
  As for Chip and Bob Ritter’s point about the burden being “substantial,” I
 think that anytime a plaintiff is forced to do something their religion
 forbids, that is not just a burden but a substantial burden.  I think the
 Court made this clear by implication in Hernandez.  See Hernandez v.
 Commissioner, 490 U.S. 680, 699 (1989) (“We do, however, have doubts whether
 the alleged burden imposed by the deduction disallowance on the
 Scientologists' practices is a substantial one.  Neither the payment nor the
 receipt of taxes is forbidden by the Scientology faith generally, and
 Scientology does not proscribe the payment of taxes in connection with
 auditing or training sessions specifically.”).  This is not to say that the
 word “substantial” makes no difference.  It may be important in other kinds of
 cases like, say, Braunfeld—cases where the government makes the religious
 practice more onerous but does not forbid it.  (For another example, we could
 go back to my discussion with Marci about a prison that doesn’t force a Jew to
 eat non-Kosher food, but puts him on a Kosher diet that is significantly worse
 than that of other inmates.)
 
 
 
  I think Chip has rightly diagnosed the deep divide between the two groups.  I
 think there are merits and demerits to both sides.  But I think the Court has
 chosen the first position.  Subject to the sincerity inquiry, churches do
 indeed get to “self-declare” what their religious views are.  I know that
 sounds weird, but wouldn’t it be weirder if they didn’t?  Certainly this broad
 conception of “burden” will lead to outcomes like Lee: As the scope of the
 religious objection grows wider and wider, the government’s claim of a
 compelling interest becomes more and more persuasive.  Maybe the Court’s
 adoption of a broad sense of “burden” in cases like Lee helped lead to
 Employment Division v. Smith.  Gosh knows, it was part of Boerne.  See City of
 Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507, 535 (1997) (“It is a reality of the modern
 regulatory state that numerous state laws, such as the zoning regulations at
 issue here, impose a substantial burden on a large class of individuals.”)
  But it seems to me that this is the path we’re on.
 
 
 
  Best,
 
  Chris
 
 
 
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
  Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:10 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
 
 
 
  The formal findings in RFRA reference Sherbert and Yoder, but not Thomas.
  Significant?
 
 
 
  Should Thomas even apply to artificial persons, like holding companies,
 corporations, and religious non-profits?  Shouldn't they be required to
 articulate with clarity and precision just how their religious exercise is
 burdened?
 
 
 
  I have not yet seen a reply to Bob Ritter's very good question about what
 work is being done by the word substantial in RFRA. It has to mean
 something.  Does it refer to material burdens (e.g., one must pay a fine of $X
 if one insists on compliance with one's own religious conscience)?  Or does it
 refer to the religious substantiality of the burden?
 
 
 
  The list appears to divide into two groups on this burden question.  One one
 side, the claimant gets to self-declare, and that triggers the strict scrutiny
 of RFRA.   That seems to wildly over-enforce religious freedom.  Consider the
 religiously idiosyncratic and libertarian employer who objects to FLSA, OSHA,
 Title VII, etc.
 
 
 
  On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess and
 decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden on
 that is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That seems
 unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on Establishment
 Clause limits on the state's resolving internal religious questions).
 
 
 
   Chip
 
 
 
  On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Scarberry, Mark
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
Marty, obviously worthy questions.  No answers, just some thoughts.

 

1.   I think I feel the same way you do.  Burden, sincerity, and
centrality all were used to restrict the scope of the compelling-interest
test.  The Court has junked centrality, and has limited inquiries on
sincerity.  All that is left is burden, and if we interpret it broadly,
then there's a risk of a taffy pull-every claim receives some
constitutional protection, which dilutes the compelling-interest test,
ultimately meaning that strong claims get treated much worse.  I don't
have an answer to this; I wish I did.  But I wonder if this fear is a bit
overblown.  We got rid of the centrality inquiry 20 years ago, and
rigorous inquiries into sincerity 30 years ago, and RFRA/state RFRAs seems
to work fine without them.  My sense is that-apart from prisons-the
weakest claims aren't brought, or don't find lawyers, or get dismissed on
doctrinally-unjustifiable-but-realistically-understandable grounds.  But I
do worry about the taffy pull.   What has alarmed me most about the HHS
litigation is the private employers.  I am sympathetic to the claims of
the Catholic Church (in all of its iterations); I am less sympathetic to
the private owner of a for-profit business wanting not to provide
contraception coverage.  Maybe I shouldn't feel this way, but I do.  And I
bet judges do too. 

 

2.   (I agree about the difficulties of Gillette.)  One thing: The
claimant's say-so of a religious burden.  A plaintiff's subjective views
of a burden are irrelevant-that's Lyng and Bowen.  But plaintiffs'
subjective views of their own religion are controlling-that's Thomas, and
Lee, and others.  There's a difference there, and the gap creates a real
check.  Yes, plaintiffs can create a burden by willing to plead whatever
religious beliefs necessary to get them there, but I'm not convinced they
would do that.  And I think sincerity is a legitimate attack there.

 

3.   I think this issue comes ultimately before the Court, but as a
sincerity issue not as a burden issue.  And to be clear, I don't think it
should be off the table.  At various times, quite maddeningly, the
Catholic Church has confused the issue of (1) whether they should be
required to provide contraception to their employees, with (2) whether
contraception should be provided at all (whether by other employers or the
government).  The first is a religious liberty claim, where I am
sympathetic to the Church; the second is a public policy claim, where I am
not.  That the Church has sometimes mixed the two together opens the door
to a doubt about sincerity: Maybe the Catholic Church just doesn't like
contraception generally, and this is just another tactic to minimize its
spread.  But I think a plausible reading of the Church's position is that
while they dislike contraception across-the-board, there are special
problems with them being forced to provide it.  

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 11:17 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Chris:  You and Marc raise absolutely valid points about doctrine during
the Sherbert/Yoder era:  The argument I'm suggesting (I'm not advocating
it yet -- merely thinking it through) is in at least some tension with the
sheet-metal/turrets portion of Thomas, and perhaps the burden discussion
in Lee (I can't recall offhand what the Amish theory was about why the
Social Security taxes violated their religion, but I assume it was
something akin to the cooperation with evil theory being floated here;
although as Chip suggests, it also involved some aspect of
double-payment).

So, simply in terms of what the right answer is or ought to be under RFRA,
the government will obviously have to contend with those cases, either by
suggesting (as someone here did) that perhaps RFRA did not incorporate
their burden analysis wholesale (I'm dubious, but haven't thought it
through), or that this case is distinguishable.

But I'm not simply asking what the right answer is under RFRA.  I'm
trying to address at least three other questions raised by these claims:

1.  Was Burger right on the turrets/sheet-metal point?  Should the courts
actually treat all religious claims of substantial burden uncritically,
without even asking whether and to what extent the claimant's own conduct
calls into question whether the burden is in fact substantial from the
claimant's own religious perspective?  If the courts do not differentiate
at all between the plausibility and strength of such claims, and treat all
alleged substantial burdens alike, is that a good thing for religious
liberty?  After all, it means that if the government were to voluntarily
give exemptions, or be compelled by the FEC/RFRA to do so, it would have
to cover a much, much wider class

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

Derek L. Gaubatz
IMB General Counsel

Our vision is a multitude from every language, people, tribe and nation knowing 
and worshipping our Lord Jesus Christ.

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

Derek L. Gaubatz
IMB General Counsel

Our vision is a multitude from every language, people, tribe and nation knowing 
and worshipping our Lord Jesus Christ.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman  
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock   wrote

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it's merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I'm not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can't use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power. 
 That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman  
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock   wrote

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
It cannot be the answer that the coverage is mandated. Whether the coverage can 
be mandated is the question. The employer signs a contract, and pays for a 
contract, that covers these services. But for the regulation, he could sign and 
pay for a very similar contract that does not cover these services. 

 

Re saving money: I’m going to tweak the facts to isolate the issue of cost 
saving. I’m going to make the religious objection one that everyone would 
share. I understand that  these hypothetical facts are extreme. The point is 
only to separate the issue of saving money from all the other issues.

 

Suppose the church runs an orphanage with 1000 children. It invites bids on a 
contract to feed the children for a year. It specifies the quantity and quality 
of food. It gets two bids. 

 

The first bid is $1.5 million.  The second bid is $1.3 million. The second 
bidder specifies that after the contract is awarded, it will take the 100 
oldest children, drive them to the nearest big city, and dump them on the 
street. There will be no need to feed them anymore. The church should not worry 
that it is paying for this immoral act, because it isn’t paying – it is 
actually paying less instead of more. But of course the church would think 
itself morally responsible if it signed that contract.

 

From the church’s perspective, if contraception saves money, it will do so by 
preventing children from being born. Most of us think that contraception is 
good thing. But if you think it an evil thing, the fact that it saves money 
does not make it morally acceptable to contract for it, or to pay for a 
package that includes it.

 

 

 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: b...@jmcenter.org [mailto:b...@jmcenter.org] 
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 1:23 PM
To: Douglas Laycock
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug, thank you for responding but I still don't comprehend your point. (By the 
way, you slipped the money back into the argument.) 

  

Since the coverage is mandated and operative clauses are likely boilerplate 
(thus no or virtually no arranging and contracting: for the contraceptive, 
etc. coverage) and under the scenario I presented that the employer is charged 
nothing additional, I suspect that what is left is merely that an employer 
maybe upset that his or her employees have an opportunity to participated in 
the mandated services. Much to attenuated for me to call the mandate a 
substantial burden on the employer's free exercise of religion. 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
, 2012 1:23 PM
 *To:* Douglas Laycock
 *Subject:* RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Doug, thank you for responding but I still don't comprehend your point.
 (By the way, you slipped the money back into the argument.) 

   

 Since the coverage is mandated and operative clauses are likely
 boilerplate (thus no or virtually no arranging and contracting: for the
 contraceptive, etc. coverage) and under the scenario I presented that the
 employer is charged nothing additional, I suspect that what is left is
 merely that an employer maybe upset that his or her employees have an
 opportunity to participated in the mandated services. Much to attenuated
 for me to call the mandate a substantial burden on the employer's free
 exercise of religion. 

   

 Bob Ritter 

   

 Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

 A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

 Falls Church, VA 22042 

 703-533-0236 

   

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Alan Brownstein
A couple of quick thoughts regarding your points, Chris.


1.   If we are talking about existing laws such as RFRA or other laws that 
require strict scrutiny review, there may be a dilution problem (although like 
you I have seen strict scrutiny diluted in state RFRA cases and in RLUIPA cases 
without any evidence that this has crossed over to other areas of law.) Also, 
because courts often do not really apply strict scrutiny in RFRA and RLUIPA 
cases, notwithstanding the clear language of the statutes, the insistence that 
courts rigorously enforce a substantial burden threshold seems harder to 
justify. In any case, from a more abstract perspective, we can re-think both 
the standard of review and the substantial burden threshold. That's at least 
the focus of my posts.


2.   When you talk about plaintiff's creating a burden that sounds like 
religious beliefs have clear parameters governed by logical rules. I'm 
certainly not a theologian, but for a lot of individuals, religious beliefs and 
duties are relational and they are evolving in the sense that individuals don't 
always think about what their religion requires in hypothetical situations.  
Relational beliefs and duties are rarely logical. (Certainly, my relationships 
with people who are important to me aren't logical.) As for evolving 
understandings,  it seems just as plausible to say that a religious individual 
confronted with a new question or situation realizes that a government mandate 
burdens his or her faith than it is to say that they create a burden to get 
their claim adjudicated on the merits. Outside of the prison context, I have 
seen very few free exercise or RFRA claims where plaintiffs are asserting sham 
beliefs to benefit unfairly from religious liberty legislation. (List members 
can correct me if I'm wrong about this.)



3.I can't summarize the position of the Catholic Church on 
contraceptive mandate laws at the national level or in other states. But in 
California, when the Women's Contraceptive Equity Act (the state forerunner of 
the HHS regulations) was debated in the legislature, the Catholic Conference 
took a neutral position on the law but strongly insisted on a religious 
exemption for Catholic Charities and other Catholic non-profits (which it did 
not receive.)

Alan

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 9:41 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Marty, obviously worthy questions.  No answers, just some thoughts.


1.   I think I feel the same way you do.  Burden, sincerity, and centrality 
all were used to restrict the scope of the compelling-interest test.  The Court 
has junked centrality, and has limited inquiries on sincerity.  All that is 
left is burden, and if we interpret it broadly, then there's a risk of a 
taffy pull-every claim receives some constitutional protection, which dilutes 
the compelling-interest test, ultimately meaning that strong claims get 
treated much worse.  I don't have an answer to this; I wish I did.  But I 
wonder if this fear is a bit overblown.  We got rid of the centrality inquiry 
20 years ago, and rigorous inquiries into sincerity 30 years ago, and 
RFRA/state RFRAs seems to work fine without them.  My sense is that-apart from 
prisons-the weakest claims aren't brought, or don't find lawyers, or get 
dismissed on doctrinally-unjustifiable-but-realistically-understandable 
grounds.  But I do worry about the taffy pull.   What has alarmed me most about 
the HHS litigation is the private employers.  I am sympathetic to the claims of 
the Catholic Church (in all of its iterations); I am less sympathetic to the 
private owner of a for-profit business wanting not to provide contraception 
coverage.  Maybe I shouldn't feel this way, but I do.  And I bet judges do too.


2.   (I agree about the difficulties of Gillette.)  One thing: The 
claimant's say-so of a religious burden.  A plaintiff's subjective views of a 
burden are irrelevant-that's Lyng and Bowen.  But plaintiffs' subjective views 
of their own religion are controlling-that's Thomas, and Lee, and others.  
There's a difference there, and the gap creates a real check.  Yes, plaintiffs 
can create a burden by willing to plead whatever religious beliefs necessary 
to get them there, but I'm not convinced they would do that.  And I think 
sincerity is a legitimate attack there.



3.   I think this issue comes ultimately before the Court, but as a 
sincerity issue not as a burden issue.  And to be clear, I don't think it 
should be off the table.  At various times, quite maddeningly, the Catholic 
Church has confused the issue of (1) whether they should be required to provide 
contraception to their employees, with (2) whether contraception should be 
provided

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
Well, Marty's response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn't
take away the claim.

 

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
would take away the church's choice - but the church would not feel at all
exonerated.

 

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not.
And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations
of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims
are never filed because people with religious objections go along when their
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the
government.

 

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in
that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause
abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other position. With
respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to
believe they take the rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so
stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and to some conservative
Catholics, and they are saying that following orders cannot justify them in
paying for a policy that will provide these drugs. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the church
will have chosen to save the $200,000 by having the kids dumped.  That would
be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal cooperation with evil.

But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite -- because
the employer can still make the payment to the government instead of
offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for purposes of Catholic
(and most other) moral reasoning, because now we're asking the question not
of whether your volitional choice was impermissible (as in your hypo), but
instead whether your proximity to the evil, in and of itself, is so great
that your cooperation is immoral even though you were well-intentioned.

You're right, of course, that the fact that coverage is legally mandated
can't categorically eliminate the prospect of a substantial burden, because
in that case there'd never be a valid RFRA claim.  So, for example, a
religion might teach that certain action is immoral, even if done under
duress -- indeed, even if done under threat of criminal sanction.  In such a
case, a state law requiring the conduct surely imposes a substantial burden
on religious exercise, at least if the person in question otherwise is
committed to abiding by that norm.  

But in most cases, including this one, the fact of legal compulsion does
radically alter the moral calculus, because it eliminates the principal
thing that made the conduct in your hypo wrongful, namely, the choice to
sacrifice the kids for $200,000 savings.

Suppose, for example, that in City A, taxi drivers have complete discretion
which fares to accept, and a taxi driver who believes that prostitution is
immoral chooses to prefer fares going to so-called houses of ill-repute,
because they much more remunerative (because of distance, clientele,
whatever).  That choice would be a violation of the norm against formal
cooperation with evil.

City B, however, has decided to treat cab drivers as common carriers -- they
must accept all fares, no matter the destination.  Our same cab driver,
thinking that prostitution is unlawful, but now working in City B, abides by
the law, picks up all fares without discrimination . . . and occasionally
finds himself being asked to drop the passenger at a so-called house of
ill-repute, a request that (like all others) he honors.  In this case, he
has performed exactly the same act as he did in City A, but this time, he
has not violated religious tenets.

Seems to be that in most material respects, the HHS Rule is more like my
taxi driver in City B -- or the taxpayer in any jurisdiction -- than like
your hypo of a Church that would gladly leave kids on the street in order to
save a few bucks.




On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 3:04 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

It cannot be the answer that the coverage is mandated. Whether the coverage
can

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Doug:  Is it actually the case that the bishops say these rules are too
important to them for a following orders defense to provide moral
justification?  That is to say, have the bishops, or any other Catholic
authority, actually articulated the view that a Catholic employer will
engage in forbidden proximate material cooperation with evil if it complies
with the HHS Rule?  And if so, have they provided any explanation of why
that is the case here and not, e.g., in the cases of paying taxes and
salaries, or in the case of my hypothetical common carrier taxi driver
who takes a woman to a clinic for an abortion?

I'm not saying there have been no such statements -- I simply haven't heard
them, and would be very grateful to be pointed to any such statement.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:46 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 Well, Marty’s response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn’t
 take away the claim.

 ** **

 Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
 notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
 orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
 would take away the church’s choice – but the church would not feel at all
 exonerated.

 ** **

 Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do
 not. And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify
 violations of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of
 RFRA claims are never filed because people with religious objections go
 along when their objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult
 fight with the government.

 ** **

 The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following
 orders defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing
 implausible in that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe
 sometimes cause abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other
 position. With respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are
 finding it hard to believe they take the rule so seriously, because we
 think the rule is so stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and
 to some conservative Catholics, and they are saying that following orders
 cannot justify them in paying for a policy that will provide these drugs.
 

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Cc:* M Cathleen Kaveny
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the
 church will have *chosen* to save the $200,000 by having the kids
 dumped.  That would be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal
 cooperation with evil.

 But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite --
 because the employer can still make the payment to the government instead
 of offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
 it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
 unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for purposes of Catholic
 (and most other) moral reasoning, because now we're asking the question *
 not* of whether your *volitional choice* was impermissible (as in your
 hypo), but instead whether your proximity to the evil, in and of itself, is
 so great that your cooperation is immoral *even though you were
 well-intentioned*.

 You're right, of course, that the fact that coverage is legally mandated
 can't categorically eliminate the prospect of a substantial burden, because
 in that case there'd never be a valid RFRA claim.  So, for example, a
 religion might teach that *certain *action is immoral, even if done under
 duress -- indeed, even if done under threat of criminal sanction.  In such
 a case, a state law requiring the conduct surely imposes a substantial
 burden on religious exercise, at least if the person in question otherwise
 is committed to abiding by that norm.

 But in most cases, including this one, the fact of legal compulsion does
 radically alter the moral calculus, because it eliminates the principal
 thing that made the conduct in your hypo wrongful, namely, the *choice*to 
 sacrifice the kids for $200,000 savings.

 Suppose, for example, that in City A, taxi drivers have complete
 discretion which fares to accept, and a taxi driver who believes that
 prostitution is immoral chooses to prefer fares going to so-called houses
 of ill-repute, because they much more remunerative (because of distance,
 clientele, whatever).  That choice would be a violation

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
I did not mean to say that the bishops are saying that no Catholic employer
can comply. I don't know what they are saying about that. Quite possibly
nothing. But they are saying loud and clear that the Catholic institutions
for which they are responsible cannot comply, and they are saying that in
the face of government coercion. They are obviously saying that government
coercion does not justify them in complying.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 4:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug:  Is it actually the case that the bishops say these rules are too
important to them for a following orders defense to provide moral
justification?  That is to say, have the bishops, or any other Catholic
authority, actually articulated the view that a Catholic employer will
engage in forbidden proximate material cooperation with evil if it complies
with the HHS Rule?  And if so, have they provided any explanation of why
that is the case here and not, e.g., in the cases of paying taxes and
salaries, or in the case of my hypothetical common carrier taxi driver who
takes a woman to a clinic for an abortion?

I'm not saying there have been no such statements -- I simply haven't heard
them, and would be very grateful to be pointed to any such statement. 

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:46 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

Well, Marty's response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn't
take away the claim.

 

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
would take away the church's choice - but the church would not feel at all
exonerated.

 

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not.
And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations
of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims
are never filed because people with religious objections go along when their
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the
government.

 

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in
that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause
abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other position. With
respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to
believe they take the rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so
stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and to some conservative
Catholics, and they are saying that following orders cannot justify them in
paying for a policy that will provide these drugs. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM


To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the church
will have chosen to save the $200,000 by having the kids dumped.  That would
be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal cooperation with evil.

But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite -- because
the employer can still make the payment to the government instead of
offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for purposes of Catholic
(and most other) moral reasoning, because now we're asking the question not
of whether your volitional choice was impermissible (as in your hypo), but
instead whether your proximity to the evil, in and of itself, is so great
that your cooperation is immoral even though you were well-intentioned.

You're right, of course, that the fact that coverage is legally mandated
can't categorically eliminate the prospect of a substantial burden, because
in that case there'd never be a valid RFRA claim.  So, for example, a
religion might teach that certain action is immoral, even if done under
duress -- indeed, even if done under threat of criminal sanction.  In such a
case, a state law requiring

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Loud -- I agree.  Clear?  Not so much.  Have they said that such
institutions cannot comply?  Indeed, I'm not even sure they've instructed
such institutions that they must make the alternative payment to the
government if they are not exempted.  Again, I genuinely don't know --
perhaps the Bishops have said just that, in which case it would be very
useful to be referred to whatever they've said.



On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:59 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 I did not mean to say that the bishops are saying that no Catholic
 employer can comply. I don’t know what they are saying about that. Quite
 possibly nothing. But they are saying loud and clear that the Catholic
 institutions for which they are responsible cannot comply, and they are
 saying that in the face of government coercion. They are obviously saying
 that government coercion does not justify them in complying.

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 4:57 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Cc:* M Cathleen Kaveny
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Doug:  Is it actually the case that the bishops say these rules are too
 important to them for a following orders defense to provide moral
 justification?  That is to say, have the bishops, or any other Catholic
 authority, actually articulated the view that a Catholic employer will
 engage in forbidden proximate material cooperation with evil if it complies
 with the HHS Rule?  And if so, have they provided any explanation of why
 that is the case here and not, e.g., in the cases of paying taxes and
 salaries, or in the case of my hypothetical common carrier taxi driver
 who takes a woman to a clinic for an abortion?

 I'm not saying there have been no such statements -- I simply haven't
 heard them, and would be very grateful to be pointed to any such statement.
 

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:46 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote:

 Well, Marty’s response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn’t
 take away the claim.

  

 Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
 notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
 orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
 would take away the church’s choice – but the church would not feel at all
 exonerated.

  

 Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do
 not. And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify
 violations of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of
 RFRA claims are never filed because people with religious objections go
 along when their objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult
 fight with the government.

  

 The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following
 orders defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing
 implausible in that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe
 sometimes cause abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other
 position. With respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are
 finding it hard to believe they take the rule so seriously, because we
 think the rule is so stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and
 to some conservative Catholics, and they are saying that following orders
 cannot justify them in paying for a policy that will provide these drugs.
 

  

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

  

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM


 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 *Cc:* M Cathleen Kaveny
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  

 If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the
 church will have *chosen* to save the $200,000 by having the kids
 dumped.  That would be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal
 cooperation with evil.

 But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite --
 because the employer can still make the payment to the government instead
 of offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
 it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
 unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Alan Brownstein
To follow up on Doug's point, in some cases whether a religious person is 
relieved of an obligation because of duress might depend on the kind and 
magnitude of the duress. Obligations may be excused if compliance places the 
individual's life at risk, for example. Under Marty's analysis, would this mean 
that the greater the punishment imposed by the state in requiring someone to 
violate their religious obligations, the less likely it will be that this 
requirement constitutes a substantial burden on religion? The greater the 
duress - the less choice the religious individual has to refuse to comply - 
therefore the weaker the claim to a substantial burden on religion.

Alan

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 1:46 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Cc: 'M Cathleen Kaveny'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, Marty's response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn't take 
away the claim.

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty 
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the 
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it would 
take away the church's choice - but the church would not feel at all exonerated.

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not. And 
I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations of 
minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims are 
never filed because people with religious objections go along when their 
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the 
government.

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders 
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in that 
claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause abortions, I 
would be astonished if they took any other position. With respect to ordinary 
contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to believe they take the 
rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so stupid. But it is very 
important to the bishops, and to some conservative Catholics, and they are 
saying that following orders cannot justify them in paying for a policy that 
will provide these drugs.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Sanford Levinson
I really don't understand Mark's argument here:  If one accepts a (strong 
version of) Romans 13:1 re the legitimacy of magistrates and therefore feels 
impelled to obey them (as Scalia has suggested he does), then why is it a 
burden at all, since by definition what the magistrate (appointed by God, 
even if one can't quite undersatnd why) is a legitimate authority.  We're not 
talking about authoritarian personalities with a psychological predisposition 
to follow authority, but, rather religions that have strong belief in obeying 
the authorities (presumably because of a theology that derives from Romans 
13:1.)  It's tricker if we're talking about a belief that one should obey 
rather than avoid civil strife.  But isn't avoiding civil strife generally 
desirable.  Of course, the argument is that there shouldn't be such strife 
because the rest of us should tolerate the disobedience.  But doesn't that 
depend on the specifics of what is being disobeyed?

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark [mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 4:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: 'M Cathleen Kaveny'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

A “following orders” defense disadvantages religions that have strong belief in 
obeying the authorities, or that balance the need to avoid civil strife against 
the need to follow religious precepts. I don’t think the successful coercion of 
religious people should cut against their right to free exercise. Coercion is 
not freedom. If you send your kids to a public school that has Bible readings 
and prayers, because you can’t afford private school, and because there are 
mandatory education laws, does the successful coercion eliminate the invasion 
of religious freedom? If your kids tell your kids to go ahead and recite the 
pledge because otherwise they will be punished, do you and they forfeit your 
First Amendment claim? (Of course, any other approach is circular; if you are 
willing to suffer the consequences, then you don’t have to suffer the 
consequences, because (or assuming) your religious freedom claim succeeds.)

Do people have to be willing to go to jail or to pay large fines in order to 
have religious freedom claims? We may test sincerity, but we don’t require 
heroism.

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
Malibu, CA 90263
(310)506-4667

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 1:46 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Cc: 'M Cathleen Kaveny'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, Marty’s response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn’t take 
away the claim.

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty 
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the 
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it would 
take away the church’s choice – but the church would not feel at all exonerated.

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not. And 
I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations of 
minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims are 
never filed because people with religious objections go along when their 
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the 
government.

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders 
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in that 
claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause abortions, I 
would be astonished if they took any other position. With respect to ordinary 
contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to believe they take the 
rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so stupid. But it is very 
important to the bishops, and to some conservative Catholics, and they are 
saying that following orders cannot justify them in paying for a policy that 
will provide these drugs.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the church 
will have chosen to save the $200,000 by having the kids

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-02 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Mr. Ritter,

First off, this isn’t a blog.

Second, it isn’t helpful or persuasive to dismiss the arguments of those with 
whom you disagree as “disguised whining.”

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 6:05 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

The beliefs can be serious and strong. But that alone is not sufficient to make 
the burden substantial.

Reminds me of taxpayer standing cases. A federal taxpayer generally doesn't 
have standing to challenge appropriations because his or her tax dollars cannot 
be specifically traced to the objection expenditure. De minimis. So no standing.

On the other end is Barnette -- where Barnette was compelled to salute the 
American flag.

The contraceptive mandate is somewhere in between. The employer isn't forced to 
use contraceptives. Isn't even forced to say their use is morally OK. In fact, 
as Judge Jackson notes, can even suggest to employees not to use them. The line 
unfortunately must be drawn somewhere on the slippery slope.

A lot of what I'm reading on the is blog written by those who oppose Judge 
Jackson's decision sounds more like disguised whining than sound arguments that 
the mandate imposes a substantial burden on employers with a religious 
viewpoint opposed to contraception.

Bob Ritter


On September 30, 2012 at 2:30 PM Berg, Thomas C. 
tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu wrote:
 Marty,



 The fact that services must be covered in the plan by virtue of legal 
 mandate (are required by law) can't be enough to counter the asserion of a 
 burden, can it--or even be a significant factor in countering it? That would 
 do away with virtually every free exercise claim (I'm only providing 
 facilities for an abortion, or I'm only receiving a blood transfusion, under 
 legal compulsion).



 You place a lot of weight on the claim that most Catholic theologians say 
 this isn't cooperation with evil, and that no one has articulated a serious 
 argument that distinguishes this and paying salaries or taxes. I don't think 
 those things are true (can one conference show it?): consider, for example, 
 Robbie George and Sharif Girgis's exchange with you a few months ago, or 
 Mark's argument here about inclusion of the services in the plan language. 
 You and others may not find those arguments convincing. But rejecting the 
 burden claim based on finding the distinction unconvincing, or on the 
 existence of a great deal of skepticism among [Catholic] theologians, can't 
 be squared--can it?--with Thomas v. Review Board, where the Court said that 
 Thomas's judgment on what work would cooperate with the evil of arms 
 production should be deferred to even though other Jehovah's Witnesses 
 disagreed. Courts are not arbiters of scriptural interpretation; the court 
 can't dismiss the!
 claim at the threshold because it concludes the asserted belief is not 
 logical, not consistent, etc.



 Occasionally you seem to be treating this as a question of remoteness of 
 facilitation for burden purposes independent of Catholic moral thought; but 
 more often you return (as I think one must in assessing burden) to asking why 
 claimants believe this is material cooperation with evil, from a Catholic 
 moral perspective. That latter question, it seems to me, falls squarely 
 within the restrictions of Thomas v. Review Board not to second-guess the 
 claimant's understanding of its obligations.



 Tom



 -
 Thomas C. Berg
 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
 University of St. Thomas School of Law
 MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN 55403-2015
 Phone: 651 962 4918
 Fax: 651 962 4881
 E-mail: 
 tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu%3cmailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
 Weblog: 
 http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.comhttp://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com%3chttp:/www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/
 
 
 From: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Marty Lederman 
 [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
 Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 11:56 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

 My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients! Resending 
 without so many cc's. Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

 On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman 
 lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com%3cmailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
A characterization of abortion as a killing, is a religious assessment, not a 
medical or constitutional category.  
A fetus is not a person for constitutional purposes.  Even abortion foe 
Justice Scalia has publicly acknowledged that.
Therefore, analyzing the cases as though abortion fits into killing cases is 
weaker than Doug has conceded.



Moreover, in the conscientious objection cases, the religious objection on the 
part of Quakers is in favor of peaceful
resolution of conflict, which is different from an objection to killing per se, 
and many COs are not objecting to war in general but rather
a particular war.  


There is no justification for treating those who oppose the medical procedure 
of abortion on religious
grounds any differently than any other religious objector to another medical 
procedure.  For all the reasons that Native Americans
cannot avoid the social security number requirement in the welfare context, the 
Amish cannot avoid Social Security taxes (absent an
exemption), and Native Americans cannot force the federal government to use its 
property according to their beliefs, religiously affiliated employers
cannot avoid a neutral, generally applicable requirement that medical insurance 
include the option, that is triggered solely the patient's 
decision in consultation with her doctor, of reproductive medical care.  


Marci





Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 7:30 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA  
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


We have a long political tradition of treating objections to killing as a 
special claim, deserving special protection. We have exempted conscientious 
objectors in all our wars, even when national existence was on the line, and 
notwithstanding powerful incentives to dubious conversions or false claims. 

This protection has not been as broad as objectors would like; it is not immune 
to limitation when government chooses to assert its compelling interests. But 
it 
received very strong protection that grew stronger over time. 

In the war case, we all agree that draftees may be asked to kill other human 
beings, but the majority says these are lawful killings, and the minority says 
they are killings prohibited by God. 

In the abortion case, the majority believes it is not a killing of a human 
being; the conscientious objector believes it is. The disagreement over the 
nature of the killing comes at a slightly different point; I do not claim that 
the cases are identical. 

I do believe that there are sound reasons, reflected in our legal and political 
tradition, to give special deference to what the conscientious objector 
believes 
is a refusal to kill another human being.

The cases also differ in the weight of the government's interest; it is almost 
never essential that an abortion be performed or assisted by a particular 
medical provider.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 17:16:55 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
In response to Rick, the answer to the question from my perspective is that a 
religiously affiliated organization (not a church) could be required to provide
insurance that includes all possible medically feasible and advisable 
treatments.  That is a classic, neutral, generally applicable law.


Obviously, abortion is at times a medically feasible and medically advisable 
treatment.  The employer buys an ombnibus insurance plan, and employers, 
consistent with medical advice and their own religious and personal views, 
choose what treatments they obtain.  That seems to me constitutional.  This is 
not distinguishable
from the objections raised by Quakers having to pay taxes that support war or 
the Amish having to pay into social security that supports a set of 
relationships
they believe are religiously wrong.


I'm glad you asked this question, because it seems to indicate that the 
argument against the ACA at base appears to be that the belief against abortion 
is somehow more important than other beliefs.  I don't see how the 
Establishment 
Clause permits that kind of religious belief prioritizing, or any of the free 
exercise cases either.


No employer should be able to exclude blood transfusions, which are abhorrent 
to Jehovahs Witnesses, from medical coverage. I haven't heard anyone
get behind such an exemption.But those opposing the ACA's reproductive 
health care provisions seem to be suggesting that somehow abortion opposition 
is 
a superior belief that deserves extra constitutional protection.  


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Rick Garnett
Dear Marty,

For what it's worth, Doug states succinctly and well what is also my view 
(though, with respect to religious institutions, I believe that the mandate 
burdens religious freedom in the additional, integrity-compromising way that 
has been mentioned).  I do not believe that our commitment to religious freedom 
means that we need to treat as burdens on that freedom (a) requirements that 
employers pay salaries to employees who might use the funds in ways to which 
the employer objects or (b) requirements that citizens pay taxes to governments 
who might use the funds in ways to which the taxpayer objects.  (So, the whole 
it burdens the religious freedom of objectors for governments to provide 
scholarships to kids attending parochial schools line is, I think, misguided.) 
 But, as others have pointed out, the compelled-insurance-coverage context is 
(the district court's ruling notwithstanding) at least distinguishable and, it 
seems to me, rises to the level of a substantial burden!
  -- even if, ultimately, one concludes that complying with the mandate does 
not amount to culpable cooperation with evil and even if, ultimately, one 
concludes that it is a justifiable and unavoidable (given the compelling 
interest, etc.) one.  

True, if one believes that, as a general rule, we should not accommodate 
religious believers and institutions who object to complying with duly enacted 
laws and promulgated regulations (at least some of the plaintiffs in the ACA 
cases have challenged the mandate on administrative-law grounds), then one is 
not going to think the argument for a broader exemption from the mandate is 
very strong.   But, if one does believe that our commitments translate into at 
least a rebuttable presumption in favor of feasible accommodations, this 
strikes me as a good case for one.

Best,

Rick 


Richard W. Garnett
Professor of Law and Associate Dean
Notre Dame Law School
P.O. Box 780
Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

574-631-6981 (w)
574-276-2252 (cell)

SSRN page

Blogs:

Prawfsblawg
Mirror of Justice 


-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:01 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just the 
ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing against 
conscience protections for medical providers.

As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
The salary payments could have been used for anything.

I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the government 
will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is highly 
attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling interest in 
paying taxes.

The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the money 
is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a package 
of services that includes the services the employer believes to be immoral, 
including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer believes 
sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those services and pays 
for those services, and these employers say they cannot in conscience do those 
things.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the 
state can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in 
battle.
It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of 
the money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- 
some of which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception 
(or even abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use 
it to partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and 
taxes, is used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which 
involve contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) 
chooses to use it for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not 
allow HHS to require plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore 
does not do so.)

Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases 
of salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a 
substantial burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that 
might be overcome by a compelling government interest.  For anyone who 
starts from that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question.  
But I am not aware of any employer, or Catholic

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
Rick- Are you saying that RFRA stands for the proposition that there is a 
rebuttable presumption in favor of 
feasible accommodations?  I hadn't heard it characterized in that way before.  


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 8:19 am
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To  ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


Dear Marty,

For what it's worth, Doug states succinctly and well what is also my view 
(though, with respect to religious institutions, I believe that the mandate 
burdens religious freedom in the additional, integrity-compromising way that 
has 
been mentioned).  I do not believe that our commitment to religious freedom 
means that we need to treat as burdens on that freedom (a) requirements that 
employers pay salaries to employees who might use the funds in ways to which 
the 
employer objects or (b) requirements that citizens pay taxes to governments who 
might use the funds in ways to which the taxpayer objects.  (So, the whole it 
burdens the religious freedom of objectors for governments to provide 
scholarships to kids attending parochial schools line is, I think, misguided.) 
 
But, as others have pointed out, the compelled-insurance-coverage context is 
(the district court's ruling notwithstanding) at least distinguishable and, it 
seems to me, rises to the level of a substantial burden!
  -- even if, ultimately, one concludes that complying with the mandate does 
not amount to culpable cooperation with evil and even if, ultimately, one 
concludes that it is a justifiable and unavoidable (given the compelling 
interest, etc.) one.  

True, if one believes that, as a general rule, we should not accommodate 
religious believers and institutions who object to complying with duly enacted 
laws and promulgated regulations (at least some of the plaintiffs in the ACA 
cases have challenged the mandate on administrative-law grounds), then one is 
not going to think the argument for a broader exemption from the mandate is 
very 
strong.   But, if one does believe that our commitments translate into at least 
a rebuttable presumption in favor of feasible accommodations, this strikes me 
as 
a good case for one.

Best,

Rick 


Richard W. Garnett
Professor of Law and Associate Dean
Notre Dame Law School
P.O. Box 780
Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

574-631-6981 (w)
574-276-2252 (cell)

SSRN page

Blogs:

Prawfsblawg
Mirror of Justice 


-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:01 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just the 
ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing against 
conscience protections for medical providers.

As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
The salary payments could have been used for anything.

I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the government 
will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is highly 
attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling interest in 
paying taxes.

The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the money 
is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a package 
of services that includes the services the employer believes to be immoral, 
including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer believes 
sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those services and pays 
for those services, and these employers say they cannot in conscience do those 
things.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the 
state can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in 
battle.
It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of 
the money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- 
some of which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception 
(or even abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use 
it to partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and 
taxes, is used to pay for countless

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Steven Jamar
Rick,

I understand the first part -- on which much of the disagreement has centered.  
(One can make the distinctions some are advocating, but should one is the hard 
part (for some).  Drawing the line elsewhere makes more sense to others of us.)

But I'm not sure how the second part works.  If a court decides (or society 
decides) that giving insurance benefits mandated by the government is not 
cooperation with evil, then doesn't the  substantial burden evaporate?  
Because isn't that what the erstwhile substantial burden is?  So isn't this 
properly to be decided on the predicate which the adherent has the burden of 
proving and not on the strict scrutiny which places an insurmountable burden in 
many instances on the government?

Steve

On Oct 2, 2012, at 8:17 AM, Rick Garnett wrote:

  But, as others have pointed out, the compelled-insurance-coverage context is 
 (the district court's ruling notwithstanding) at least distinguishable and, 
 it seems to me, rises to the level of a substantial burden!
  -- even if, ultimately, one concludes that complying with the mandate does 
 not amount to culpable cooperation with evil and even if, ultimately, one 
 concludes that it is a justifiable and unavoidable (given the compelling 
 interest, etc.) one.  

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/

“Enjoy the little things, for one day you may look back and realize they were 
the big things.”
Robert Brault




___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-02 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 on behalf of Marc DeGirolami [marc.degirol...@stjohns.edu]
  Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 10:36 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate
 
 
  I wonder what sort of evidence Marty is looking for.  What arguments qualify

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-02 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
Guys, I had to repeat the obvious but mere burden is not the legal standard
for a violation of RFRA. Substantial burden is. Thus, some burden is
permissible and, quite frankly, we all suffer burdens all day long but as the
saying goes: There's no use complaining.

Bob Ritter

On September 30, 2012 at 3:24 PM Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:

  Colleagues,
 
  I think it needs to be recalled that the cooperation with evil / violation
 of conscience issue is not, in the context of the RFRA and other arguments
 against the HHS mandate, the whole story. Religious freedom, both as a moral
 matter and as a legal one, can be burdened, in ways that call for
 justification, by laws that do not command (what the objector regards as )
 immoral acts.
 
  Even if, for example, Marty were right that no serious
 cooperation-with-evil argument has been or could be advanced by, say, Notre
 Dame, it could still be (and, I think, clearly is) the case that the mandate
 burdens, say, Notre Dame's legally protected religious freedom rights
 
  Best, Rick
 
  (Sorry for the iPhone).
 
  Sent from my iPhone
 
  On Sep 30, 2012, at 2:39 PM, Christopher Lund  l...@wayne.edu
 mailto:l...@wayne.edu  wrote:
 
 

   We’ve talked about this before a bit on the listserv, and I don’t want
  to rehash old arguments—although I think I agree with Eugene Volokh’s
  comments when Marty raised this issue earlier,
  http://lists.ucla.edu/pipermail/religionlaw/2012-February/025600.html
  http://lists.ucla.edu/pipermail/religionlaw/2012-February/025600.html .
  
  
  
   But let’s assume for the moment that Marty is right, because it raises
  another issue.  So let’s stipulate that Catholic Church’s traditional
  doctrine of cooperation-with-evil actually doesn’t forbid this.  The
  Catholic Bishops’ position is entirely new.  It’s not a mere application of
  the church’s old cooperation-with-evil doctrine.  To help us imagine this,
  let’s say the Church issues the following statement:
  
  
  
   For a long time, as you all know, we have found abortion immoral.
   But this new Health Care Act has brought the issue to prominence and
  crystallized it for us.  We have had reason to consider more deeply certain
  particular issues.  And we decide today that abortion is so grievously
  sinful that we must change our position on cooperation-with-evil
  accordingly.  We today expand the doctrine to apply in this situation.  We
  will work out the theological details later; maybe a wholesale revision of
  the doctrine of cooperation-with-evil is in order.  But we are convinced
  that the Health Care Act will cause us to violate God’s will.  That is what
  matters; the doctrinal details can be worked out later.
  
  
  
   It seems to me that this is okay, that churches can change their
  theologies, and that they can choose to do theology by adjudication rather
  than rulemaking.  Is there a reason why this should be wrong?  Is it
  necessarily insincere?  It seems to me to be pretty consistent with the way
  human beings reason generally.
  
  
  
   Best,
  
   Chris
  
  
  
   From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
  mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
  [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
  mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu ] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
   Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 12:57 PM
   To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
   Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate
  
  
  
   My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!
   Resending without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.
  
   On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman
  lederman.ma...@gmail.com mailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com  wrote:
  
   For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last
  week (a video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great
  deal of skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present
  (some of whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference)
  that where an employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance
  plan on compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan
  virtue of legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular
  heath care service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and her
  physician, the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation with
  evil just because some employees might choose to use the plan (unbeknownst
  to the employer) to subsidize the use of contraception.
  
   I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I,
  for one, have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the
  Rule that compliance would result in a violation of religious obligations on
  account of such cooperation.  That doesn't mean there is no such argument
  out there, of course.  But I think it helps to explain

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
I think Lyng (which explicitly relies on Bowen) is indeed relevan to a 
substantial burden analysis, because it states that even a potentially 
disastrous burden is not the sort of burden that supports a finding of a free 
exercise violation.  It supports the view that a subjective view of burden does 
not establish burden, and that an incidental
burden is insufficient.  The possibility that an employee who does not share 
the faith will use, in conjunction with a doctor's advice, contraception
and abortion medical services is a classic incidental burden.  The employer has 
not been foreclosed from preaching against contraception and abortion in 
every conceivable context, and need never purchase it for an employee, and in 
fact cannot even know if the employee is using it given doctor-patient 
privilege.  (Honestly, as others have implied, if parochial schools are going 
to rely on the intervening actor theory to avoid an Establishment Clause 
violation, they have real problems here.)  


This is from the Lyng syllabus, which I'm including because it is more compact 
than the full language of the opinion:


In Bowen v. Roy, 476 U.S. 693 -- which held that a federal statute requiring 
States to use Social Security numbers in administering certain welfare programs 
did not violate Indian religious rights under the Free Exercise Clause -- this 
Court rejected the same kind of challenge that respondents assert. Just as 
inRoy, the affected individuals here would not be coerced by the Government's 
action into violating their religious beliefs; nor would the governmental 
action penalize the exercise of religious rights by denying religious adherents 
an equal share of the rights, benefits, and privileges enjoyed by other 
citizens. Incidental effects of government programs, which may interfere with 
the practice of certain religions, but which have no tendency to coerce 
individuals into acting contrary to their religious beliefs, do not require 
government to bring forward a compelling justification for its otherwise lawful 
actions. The Free Exercise Clause is written in terms of what the government 
cannot do to the individual, not in terms of what the individual can exact from 
the government. Even assuming that the Government's actions here will virtually 
destroy the Indians' ability to practice their religion, the Constitution 
simply does not provide a principle that could justify upholding respondents' 
legal claims. 


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 12:38 pm
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To  ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Oops. Writing too fast.
 
What I meant to say is that neither Lyng, nor Bowen, nor Lee supports a 
no-burden holding in the ACA cases.  Lyng and Bowen do indeed appear 
irrelevant. But Lee is not irrelevant; it supports a holding of substantial 
burden. The Court accepted the Amish claim that payment of social security 
taxes was forbidden by their faith, and concluded that requiring this payment 
“interferes with their free exercise rights.” But “not all burdens are 
unconstitutional. That state may justify a limitation on religious liberty . . 
.” And it went on to find a compelling interest in collecting taxes, including 
social security taxes.
 
So in Lee, the Court said that payment of funds to the government, for a stated 
purpose that is religiously objectionable, is a constitutionally cognizable 
burden on free exercise. 
 

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 
Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
burden issue in the ACA cases.
 
And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.
 
Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Douglas Laycock
Marci, read what you quoted. Read the passages I have boldfaced below. Bowen 
and Lyng were explicitly about government actions that required nothing of the 
plaintiffs. Those plaintiffs were not required to take any action at all.  The 
government caused problems for plaintiffs’ religion, but it did not require 
them to do anything that violated their own understanding of their religion. A 
lot of people don’t like that distinction, but that’s what it was.  

 

The ACA plaintiffs are required to take action that violates their own 
understanding of their religious obligations. Many arguments remain beyond that 
point, but Bowen and Lyng do not address those arguments. Bowen and Lyng were 
cases that did not reach that first step.

 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 9:44 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

I think Lyng (which explicitly relies on Bowen) is indeed relevan to a 
substantial burden analysis, because it states that even a potentially 
disastrous burden is not the sort of burden that supports a finding of a free 
exercise violation.  It supports the view that a subjective view of burden does 
not establish burden, and that an incidental 

burden is insufficient.  The possibility that an employee who does not share 
the faith will use, in conjunction with a doctor's advice, contraception

and abortion medical services is a classic incidental burden.  The employer has 
not been foreclosed from preaching against contraception and abortion in 

every conceivable context, and need never purchase it for an employee, and in 
fact cannot even know if the employee is using it given doctor-patient 
privilege.  (Honestly, as others have implied, if parochial schools are going 
to rely on the intervening actor theory to avoid an Establishment Clause 
violation, they have real problems here.)  

 

This is from the Lyng syllabus, which I'm including because it is more compact 
than the full language of the opinion:

 

In Bowen v. Roy,  http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-us-cite/476/693 
476 U.S. 693 -- which held that a federal statute requiring States to use 
Social Security numbers in administering certain welfare programs did not 
violate Indian religious rights under the Free Exercise Clause -- this Court 
rejected the same kind of challenge that respondents assert. Just as inRoy, the 
affected individuals here would not be coerced by the Government's action into 
violating their religious beliefs; nor would the governmental action penalize 
the exercise of religious rights by denying religious adherents an equal share 
of the rights, benefits, and privileges enjoyed by other citizens. Incidental 
effects of government programs, which may interfere with the practice of 
certain religions, but which have no tendency to coerce individuals into acting 
contrary to their religious beliefs, do not require government to bring forward 
a compelling justification for its otherwise lawful actions. The Free Exercise 
Clause is written in terms of what the government cannot do to the individual, 
not in terms of what the individual can exact from the government. Even 
assuming that the Government's actions here will virtually destroy the Indians' 
ability to practice their religion, the Constitution simply does not provide a 
principle that could justify upholding respondents' legal claims. 

 

Marci

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 12:38 pm
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Oops. Writing too fast.

 

What I meant to say is that neither Lyng, nor Bowen, nor Lee supports a 
no-burden holding in the ACA cases.  Lyng and Bowen do indeed appear 
irrelevant. But Lee is not irrelevant; it supports a holding of substantial 
burden. The Court accepted the Amish claim that payment of social security 
taxes was forbidden by their faith, and concluded that requiring this payment 
“interferes with their free exercise rights.” But “not all burdens are 
unconstitutional. That state may justify a limitation on religious liberty . . 
.” And it went on to find a compelling interest in collecting taxes, including 
social security taxes.

 

So in Lee, the Court said that payment of funds to the government, for a stated 
purpose

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Douglas Laycock
One does not have to believe that early abortions kill human beings to 
recognize the profound significance of performing, assisting, or procuring an 
abortion to those who believe it is a killing of a human being. 

 

If we all took the same view of every issue, we would not need a regime of 
religious liberty. Religious liberty is a response to disagreement on issues 
that some people on both sides find non-compromisable. It is never an adequate 
response to a religious liberty claim to say that the claimant is just wrong in 
how he views the disputed issue.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 8:16 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

A characterization of abortion as a killing, is a religious assessment, not a 
medical or constitutional category.   

A fetus is not a person for constitutional purposes.  Even abortion foe 
Justice Scalia has publicly acknowledged that.

Therefore, analyzing the cases as though abortion fits into killing cases is 
weaker than Doug has conceded.

 

Moreover, in the conscientious objection cases, the religious objection on the 
part of Quakers is in favor of peaceful

resolution of conflict, which is different from an objection to killing per se, 
and many COs are not objecting to war in general but rather

a particular war.  

 

There is no justification for treating those who oppose the medical procedure 
of abortion on religious

grounds any differently than any other religious objector to another medical 
procedure.  For all the reasons that Native Americans

cannot avoid the social security number requirement in the welfare context, the 
Amish cannot avoid Social Security taxes (absent an

exemption), and Native Americans cannot force the federal government to use its 
property according to their beliefs, religiously affiliated employers

cannot avoid a neutral, generally applicable requirement that medical insurance 
include the option, that is triggered solely the patient's 

decision in consultation with her doctor, of reproductive medical care.  

 

Marci

 

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Ordinarily we should accept a person's view of whether the actions required by 
the state relate closely enough to something prohibited by the person's 
religion so as to make the person complicit. Thomas drew a line, and it is not 
for us to say that the line he drew was an unreasonable one. Thomas v. Review 
Board. Remember that the kind of analysis applied by the Court in Sherbert and 
Thomas is the kind Congress wanted to bring back under RFRA.

Here is a longer excerpt from Thomas. I think it is fair to say that the Court 
held that what counts is the religious person's view of whether actions make 
them complicit with evil:

When asked at the hearing to explain what kind of work his religious 
convictions would permit, Thomas said that he would have no difficulty doing 
the type of work that he had done at the roll foundry. He testified that he 
could, in good conscience, engage indirectly in the production of materials 
that might be used ultimately to fabricate arms -- for example, as an employee 
of a raw material supplier or of a roll foundry. (Footnote omitted.]
...
In reaching its conclusion, the Indiana court seems to have placed 
considerable reliance on the facts that Thomas was 'struggling' with his 
beliefs, and that he was not able to 'articulate' his belief precisely. It 
noted, for example, that Thomas admitted before the referee that he would not 
object to 'working for United States Steel or Inland Steel . . . produc[ing] 
the raw product necessary for the production of any kind of tank . . . [because 
I] would not be a direct party to whoever they shipped it to [and] would not be 
. . . chargeable in . . . conscience. . . .'  271 Ind. at ___, 391 N.E.2d at 
1131. The court found this position inconsistent with Thomas' stated opposition 
to participation in the production of armaments. But Thomas' statements reveal 
no more than that he found work in the roll foundry sufficiently insulated from 
producing weapons of war. We see, therefore, that Thomas drew a line, and it is 
not for us to say that the line he drew was an unreasonable on!
 e. Courts should not undertake to dissect religious beliefs because the 
believer admits that he is 'struggling' with his position or because his 
beliefs are not articulated with the clarity and precision that a more 
sophisticated person might employ.
...
The narrow function of a reviewing court in this context is to determine 
whether there was an appropriate finding that petitioner terminated his work 
because of an honest conviction that such work was forbidden by his religion.

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 5:43 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Rick,

I understand the first part -- on which much of the disagreement has centered.  
(One can make the distinctions some are advocating, but should one is the hard 
part (for some).  Drawing the line elsewhere makes more sense to others of us.)

But I'm not sure how the second part works.  If a court decides (or society 
decides) that giving insurance benefits mandated by the government is not 
cooperation with evil, then doesn't the  substantial burden evaporate?  
Because isn't that what the erstwhile substantial burden is?  So isn't this 
properly to be decided on the predicate which the adherent has the burden of 
proving and not on the strict scrutiny which places an insurmountable burden in 
many instances on the government?

Steve

On Oct 2, 2012, at 8:17 AM, Rick Garnett wrote:

  But, as others have pointed out, the compelled-insurance-coverage context is 
 (the district court's ruling notwithstanding) at least distinguishable and, 
 it seems to me, rises to the level of a substantial burden!
  -- even if, ultimately, one concludes that complying with the mandate does 
 not amount to culpable cooperation with evil and even if, ultimately, one 
 concludes that it is a justifiable and unavoidable (given the compelling 
 interest, etc.) one.  

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/

Enjoy the little things, for one day you may look back and realize they were 
the big things.
Robert Brault




___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe, 
change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Of course, as Doug pointed out, here it is precisely what the govt is doing to 
the religious employer that is at issue.

In terms of the intervening actor theory:

We can accept that different people have different views of moral complicity – 
and respect those views in determining whether the law is requiring a person to 
violate his or her own religious conscience. For Establishment Clause purposes 
we can’t have multiple views of whether the government is illicitly aiding or 
inhibiting religion. For better or for worse, we either need a judicially 
constructed theory, or at least a judicially constructed theory of what the 
permitted range of approaches may be that a legislature may adopt.

I don’t think there is an inconsistency in the arguments (1) that a requirement 
to enter into an insurance contract providing for payment for abortions makes 
the employer complicit, and the  (2) that providing funds to parents for them 
to use for whatever kind of education for their children that they choose does 
not make the state “complicit” in the relevant Establishment Clause sense. More 
later if I have the time to amplify this thought. (Is that a promise or a 
threat?) Even if there is an inconsistency, the courts do not necessarily have 
to adopt the same view for point (2) that we allow people to hold on point (1).

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 6:44 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

I think Lyng (which explicitly relies on Bowen) is indeed relevan to a 
substantial burden analysis, because it states that even a potentially 
disastrous burden is not the sort of burden that supports a finding of a free 
exercise violation.  It supports the view that a subjective view of burden does 
not establish burden, and that an incidental
burden is insufficient.  The possibility that an employee who does not share 
the faith will use, in conjunction with a doctor's advice, contraception
and abortion medical services is a classic incidental burden.  The employer has 
not been foreclosed from preaching against contraception and abortion in
every conceivable context, and need never purchase it for an employee, and in 
fact cannot even know if the employee is using it given doctor-patient 
privilege.  (Honestly, as others have implied, if parochial schools are going 
to rely on the intervening actor theory to avoid an Establishment Clause 
violation, they have real problems here.)

[snip]

This is from the Lyng syllabus, which I'm including because it is more compact 
than the full language of the opinion:

In Bowen v. Roy, 476 U.S. 
693http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-us-cite/476/693 -- which held 
that a federal statute requiring States to use Social Security numbers in 
administering certain welfare programs did not violate Indian religious rights 
under the Free Exercise Clause -- this Court rejected the same kind of 
challenge that respondents assert. Just as inRoy, the affected individuals here 
would not be coerced by the Government's action into violating their religious 
beliefs; nor would the governmental action penalize the exercise of religious 
rights by denying religious adherents an equal share of the rights, benefits, 
and privileges enjoyed by other citizens. Incidental effects of government 
programs, which may interfere with the practice of certain religions, but which 
have no tendency to coerce individuals into acting contrary to their religious 
beliefs, do not require government to bring forward a compelling justification 
for its otherwise lawful actions. The Free Exercise Clause is written in terms 
of what the government cannot do to the individual, not in terms of what the 
individual can exact from the government. Even assuming that the Government's 
actions here will virtually destroy the Indians' ability to practice their 
religion, the Constitution simply does not provide a principle that could 
justify upholding respondents' legal claims.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Marc DeGirolami
Chip raises a problem I've been having a hard time understanding too.  A 
burden does seem to imply the willingness to suffer to some unspecified 
degree (rising to the level of being substantial) on behalf of the claimed 
belief.  On the specific question of whether one should interpret the adjective 
substantial to require some sort of material burden, I believe that this is 
what the ED of Missouri court means when it says that the claimant must be 
willing to forfeit a benefit, pay a fine, or even face criminal prosecution 
(though I do not believe that the cases cited for this proposition support the 
view that this is a necessary condition).  One might interpret this statement 
as a requirement that the plaintiff must be willing to suffer *at least* one of 
these three kinds of penalties in order for the burden to be substantial, or 
maybe to suffer at least some sort of penalty period (again provided that the 
penalty is substantial).  It's difficult for me to see that we would want to 
test the religious liberty claim in all cases against a willingness to go to 
prison, for example (Chip writes about a related issue in his Failure of RFRA 
piece, I think).

But even if we thought that willingness to pay a fine would be a good test for 
substantiality (which I'll admit doesn't seem unreasonable to me, in some 
cases), I wonder about how this would work in practice.  That is, how would we 
know that the plaintiff was really willing to pay a fine rather than be forced 
to do something alleged to violate religious conscience?  What would be the 
proof?

I'll add that I am genuinely confused about the issue of substantiality of the 
burden, because it does seem to me to require more than something like 
subjective sincerity, but also to forbid courts from inquiring into the 
importance of the belief, or the degree to which the belief has been ratified 
by other religious adherents.  If that is right, then what is left to determine 
the substantiality of the burden other than the degree to which the claimant is 
willing to suffer for his or her beliefs?

Marc


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The formal findings in RFRA reference Sherbert and Yoder, but not Thomas.  
Significant?

Should Thomas even apply to artificial persons, like holding companies, 
corporations, and religious non-profits?  Shouldn't they be required to 
articulate with clarity and precision just how their religious exercise is 
burdened?

I have not yet seen a reply to Bob Ritter's very good question about what work 
is being done by the word substantial in RFRA. It has to mean something.  
Does it refer to material burdens (e.g., one must pay a fine of $X if one 
insists on compliance with one's own religious conscience)?  Or does it refer 
to the religious substantiality of the burden?

The list appears to divide into two groups on this burden question.  One one 
side, the claimant gets to self-declare, and that triggers the strict scrutiny 
of RFRA.   That seems to wildly over-enforce religious freedom.  Consider the 
religiously idiosyncratic and libertarian employer who objects to FLSA, OSHA, 
Title VII, etc.

On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess and 
decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden on that 
is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That seems 
unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on Establishment Clause 
limits on the state's resolving internal religious questions).

 Chip


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
Actually, I do not recognize my position under either of Chip's either/or 
choices.  Rather, I would look to the cases, which have dealt with interpreting 
substantial burden repeatedly.  Courts have held in the vast majority of 
cases that cost and convenience are not substantial.   That weighs heavily 
against the ACA plaintiffs, to the extent they are complaining about having to 
pay for insurance.  
Substantial means that the religious practice has become impracticable or 
severely curtailed.   


The ACA case creates a new, more extreme, demand, which is not that the 
religious believer is being forced or prohibited from taking a particular act, 
beyond purchasing an omnibus health care plan.  Rather, it is that the 
religious believer does not want to pay for a health insurance plan that 
permits employees potentially to obtain health care with which the employer 
disagrees.  The employee (who, under Title VII or state anti-discrimination law 
could not be hired or fired based on religious belief, and who has the benefit 
of doctor/patient confidentiality) may well be fine, on religious grounds, in 
obtaining the contraception and/or abortion (indeed, their religious beliefs 
may actually require or encourage such medical care), but the employer's 
objection is that someone may use a health benefit in a way the religious 
employer doesn't want it used.  Under existing case law, this is an attenuated 
argument that induces an incidental burden, not a substantial burden, for 
purposes of free exercise analysis.   


Moreover, the slippery slope is steep.  Jehovah's witnesses and blood 
transfusion; Scientologists and mental health care; Catholics and evangelicals 
and palliative care for the terminal, elderly patientetc., etc.


I am not persuaded by Mark's distinction between the voucher cases, where 
private decisions wash government money of its Establishment Clause 
restrictions, and the ACA situation, where, again, a private actor, is acting 
in an independent way that cannot be attributed reasonably to the provider of 
the benefit.


Marci




On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess and 
decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden on that 
is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That seems 
unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on Establishment Clause 
limits on the state's resolving internal religious questions).

 

 Chip

 





 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marc DeGirolami marc.degirol...@stjohns.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 11:45 am
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Chip raises a problem I’ve been having a hard time understanding too.  A 
“burden” does seem to imply the willingness to suffer to some unspecified 
degree (rising to the level of being “substantial”) on behalf of the claimed 
belief.  On the specific question of whether one should interpret the adjective 
“substantial” to require some sort of “material burden,” I believe that this is 
what the ED of Missouri court means when it says that the claimant must be 
willing to “forfeit a benefit, pay a fine, or even face criminal prosecution” 
(though I do not believe that the cases cited for this proposition support the 
view that this is a necessary condition).  One might interpret this statement 
as a requirement that the plaintiff must be willing to suffer *at least* one of 
these three kinds of penalties in order for the burden to be substantial, or 
maybe to suffer at least some sort of penalty period (again provided that the 
penalty is substantial).  It’s difficult for me to see that we would want to 
test the religious liberty claim in all cases against a willingness to go to 
prison, for example (Chip writes about a related issue in his “Failure of RFRA” 
piece, I think).  
 
But even if we thought that willingness to pay a fine would be a good test for 
substantiality (which I’ll admit doesn’t seem unreasonable to me, in some 
cases), I wonder about how this would work in practice.  That is, how would we 
know that the plaintiff was really willing to pay a fine rather than be forced 
to do something alleged to violate religious conscience?  What would be the 
proof?  
 
I’ll add that I am genuinely confused about the issue of substantiality of the 
burden, because it does seem to me to require more than something like 
subjective sincerity, but also to forbid courts from inquiring into the 
importance of the belief, or the degree to which the belief has been ratified 
by other religious adherents.  If that is right, then what is left to determine 
the substantiality of the burden other than the degree

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
Doug--The government in Bowen required the applicant to obtain a social 
security number to obtain benefits.   They did not want to obtain it, because 
it would sacrifice their child's soul.  Looks like forced complicity with evil 
to me.   How does that work under your distinction?

I have to say it looks like a distinction without a difference to me.



Lyng is certainly relevant re: whether the subjective sense of the burden is 
relevant.  It is not.


Marci 


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 10:42 am
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To  ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Marci, read what you quoted. Read the passages I have boldfaced below. Bowen 
and Lyng were explicitly about government actions that required nothing of the 
plaintiffs. Those plaintiffs were not required to take any action at all.  The 
government caused problems for plaintiffs’ religion, but it did not require 
them to do anything that violated their own understanding of their religion. A 
lot of people don’t like that distinction, but that’s what it was.  
 
The ACA plaintiffs are required to take action that violates their own 
understanding of their religious obligations. Many arguments remain beyond that 
point, but Bowen and Lyng do not address those arguments. Bowen and Lyng were 
cases that did not reach that first step.
 
 
Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 9:44 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 
I think Lyng (which explicitly relies on Bowen) is indeed relevan to a 
substantial burden analysis, because it states that even a potentially 
disastrous burden is not the sort of burden that supports a finding of a free 
exercise violation.  It supports the view that a subjective view of burden does 
not establish burden, and that an incidental 

burden is insufficient.  The possibility that an employee who does not share 
the faith will use, in conjunction with a doctor's advice, contraception

and abortion medical services is a classic incidental burden.  The employer has 
not been foreclosed from preaching against contraception and abortion in 

every conceivable context, and need never purchase it for an employee, and in 
fact cannot even know if the employee is using it given doctor-patient 
privilege.  (Honestly, as others have implied, if parochial schools are going 
to rely on the intervening actor theory to avoid an Establishment Clause 
violation, they have real problems here.)  

 

This is from the Lyng syllabus, which I'm including because it is more compact 
than the full language of the opinion:

 

In Bowen v. Roy, 476 U.S. 693 -- which held that a federal statute requiring 
States to use Social Security numbers in administering certain welfare programs 
did not violate Indian religious rights under the Free Exercise Clause -- this 
Court rejected the same kind of challenge that respondents assert. Just as 
inRoy, the affected individuals here would not be coerced by the Government's 
action into violating their religious beliefs; nor would the governmental 
action penalize the exercise of religious rights by denying religious adherents 
an equal share of the rights, benefits, and privileges enjoyed by other 
citizens. Incidental effects of government programs, which may interfere with 
the practice of certain religions, but which have no tendency to coerce 
individuals into acting contrary to their religious beliefs, do not require 
government to bring forward a compelling justification for its otherwise lawful 
actions. The Free Exercise Clause is written in terms of what the government 
cannot do to the individual, not in terms of what the individual can exact from 
the government. Even assuming that the Government's actions here will virtually 
destroy the Indians' ability to practice their religion, the Constitution 
simply does not provide a principle that could justify upholding respondents' 
legal claims. 

 

Marci

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 12:38 pm

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
Doug-- What is wrong, with all due respect, is treating the religious 
believer's characterization of the act as the legal characterization of it.
The religious believer's belief that it is a killing does not make it one for 
purposes of legal analysis.  That was my very simple point.


Marci




 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 10:43 am
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To  ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



One does not have to believe that early abortions kill human beings to 
recognize the profound significance of performing, assisting, or procuring an 
abortion to those who believe it is a killing of a human being. 
 
If we all took the same view of every issue, we would not need a regime of 
religious liberty. Religious liberty is a response to disagreement on issues 
that some people on both sides find non-compromisable. It is never an adequate 
response to a religious liberty claim to say that the claimant is just wrong in 
how he views the disputed issue.
 
Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 8:16 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 
A characterization of abortion as a killing, is a religious assessment, not a 
medical or constitutional category.   

A fetus is not a person for constitutional purposes.  Even abortion foe 
Justice Scalia has publicly acknowledged that.

Therefore, analyzing the cases as though abortion fits into killing cases is 
weaker than Doug has conceded.

 


Moreover, in the conscientious objection cases, the religious objection on the 
part of Quakers is in favor of peaceful

resolution of conflict, which is different from an objection to killing per se, 
and many COs are not objecting to war in general but rather

a particular war.  

 

There is no justification for treating those who oppose the medical procedure 
of abortion on religious

grounds any differently than any other religious objector to another medical 
procedure.  For all the reasons that Native Americans

cannot avoid the social security number requirement in the welfare context, the 
Amish cannot avoid Social Security taxes (absent an

exemption), and Native Americans cannot force the federal government to use its 
property according to their beliefs, religiously affiliated employers

cannot avoid a neutral, generally applicable requirement that medical insurance 
include the option, that is triggered solely the patient's 

decision in consultation with her doctor, of reproductive medical care.  

 

Marci

 

 


Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Alan Brownstein
I think Marty's point about alternative payments in lieu of purchasing 
insurance with the required coverage is an important one. I don't know how this 
alternative is structured or characterized in the challenged regulations. But 
as an abstract matter when we are talking about regulations that require 
religious individuals or institutions to do something that their religion 
prohibits them to do, we can often resolve the religious liberty issue by 
granting an exemption from the obligation (here, the requirement to contract 
for the insurance coverage) while requiring as a condition to that exemption 
that the religious individual incur costs or duties of less than or equivalent 
secular value which would be directed toward some public good that is 
consistent with their faith (here, contributing the cost of the disputed 
insurance coverage into a fund to be used for some alternative public purpose.)

This is the model we use for conscientious objection statutes which require the 
religious pacifist exempt from military service to perform alternative service 
consistent with his or her religious obligations.

Alan
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 5:28 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Thanks for the clarification, Doug.  I had missed that particular part of the 
exchange.

On the distinction you suggest, I think that the characterization of the 
requirement as purchasing a package of services does not fairly describe 
what's going on here.  Or at the very least, this is nothing like what comes to 
mind when one hears that phrase -- such as the employer hiring a contractor to 
paint the walls, install new fixtures, etc.

The Rule requires the employer to make available to its employees a group 
health plan.  (In fact, not even that -- the employer can instead make a 
payment to the government, a payment that Robin Wilson suggested at our 
Conference would typically be much less than the cost of the employer's portion 
of the plan premiums.)  The law does not even require the employer to pay 
premiums into the plan, although that might end up being a practical necessity, 
since the plan must be one that is affordable to the employees, which in most 
cases will presumably not include a plan subsidized entirely by employee 
premiums.

So let's assume for sake of argument that as a practical matter the Rule 
requires employers to pay a certain premium to the insurance company.  (I'm 
putting aside here the serious question of whether the alternative payment to 
the Fed changes the burden analysis.)  That premium does not pay for a package 
of services to the employer.  It pays to partly subsidize (in part) an 
enormously wide range of goods and services -- virtually any related to health 
-- that will be used only if and when the employees need them and choose to use 
them.  (And even then, the employer will never know which services were used.)


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
, or from participating in a religious 
ritual such as communion. Instead, plaintiffs remain free to exercise their 
religion, by not using contraceptives and by discouraging employees from using 
contraceptives. Of course it's great that the government hasn't reached so far 
as to prevent him from doing these other things, but that doesn't address 
whether his particular religious exercise in this case is substantially 
burdened when he is fined for exercising it.   The Amish adherents in Yoder 
were free to exercise lots of other parts of their religion, but it was a 
substantial burden when the government fined them for refusing to take the 
affirmative step of sending their children to school after the 8th grade.   So 
too, it seems to me to be a natural application of Yoder to say it is a 
substantial burden here for fining these religious adherents for refusing to 
take the affirmative step of purchasing a plan that violates their religious 
beliefs.

One other note:  the language in RFRA's definition about religious exercise not 
being compelled by or central to a system of religious belief was added to RFRA 
by RLUIPA in 2000 because prior to that courts frequently short circuited the 
analysis of RFRA claims by concluding that the particular religious exercise 
involved in a case was not central to or mandated by the religious claimant's 
beliefs.There is no doubt that this definition of religious exercise is 
broad and will encompass lots of what others may think are idiosyncratic 
beliefs or beliefs that seem to them to be remote.   And undoubtedly this means 
that more cases will be subjected to the strict scrutiny analysis, but RFRA and 
RLUIPA were written with the intent of giving expanstive protection for 
religious exercise.

Blessings,
Derek

Derek L. Gaubatz
IMB General Counsel
(804) 219-1575 (o)

Our vision is a multitude from every language, people, tribe and nation knowing 
and worshipping our Lord Jesus Christ.

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The formal findings in RFRA reference Sherbert and Yoder, but not Thomas.  
Significant?

Should Thomas even apply to artificial persons, like holding companies, 
corporations, and religious non-profits?  Shouldn't they be required to 
articulate with clarity and precision just how their religious exercise is 
burdened?

I have not yet seen a reply to Bob Ritter's very good question about what work 
is being done by the word substantial in RFRA. It has to mean something.  
Does it refer to material burdens (e.g., one must pay a fine of $X if one 
insists on compliance with one's own religious conscience)?  Or does it refer 
to the religious substantiality of the burden?

The list appears to divide into two groups on this burden question.  One one 
side, the claimant gets to self-declare, and that triggers the strict scrutiny 
of RFRA.   That seems to wildly over-enforce religious freedom.  Consider the 
religiously idiosyncratic and libertarian employer who objects to FLSA, OSHA, 
Title VII, etc.

On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess and 
decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden on that 
is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That seems 
unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on Establishment Clause 
limits on the state's resolving internal religious questions).

 Chip

On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
Ordinarily we should accept a person's view of whether the actions required by 
the state relate closely enough to something prohibited by the person's 
religion so as to make the person complicit. Thomas drew a line, and it is not 
for us to say that the line he drew was an unreasonable one. Thomas v. Review 
Board. Remember that the kind of analysis applied by the Court in Sherbert and 
Thomas is the kind Congress wanted to bring back under RFRA.

Here is a longer excerpt from Thomas. I think it is fair to say that the Court 
held that what counts is the religious person's view of whether actions make 
them complicit with evil:

When asked at the hearing to explain what kind of work his religious 
convictions would permit, Thomas said that he would have no difficulty doing 
the type of work that he had done at the roll foundry. He testified that he 
could, in good conscience, engage indirectly in the production of materials 
that might be used ultimately to fabricate arms -- for example, as an employee 
of a raw material supplier or of a roll foundry. (Footnote omitted.]
...
In reaching its conclusion, the Indiana court seems to have placed 
considerable reliance on the facts that Thomas

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
, or from participating in a religious 
ritual such as communion. Instead, plaintiffs remain free to exercise their 
religion, by not using contraceptives and by discouraging employees from using 
contraceptives. Of course it's great that the government hasn't reached so far 
as to prevent him from doing these other things, but that doesn't address 
whether his particular religious exercise in this case is substantially 
burdened when he is fined for exercising it.   The Amish adherents in Yoder 
were free to exercise lots of other parts of their religion, but it was a 
substantial burden when the government fined them for refusing to take the 
affirmative step of sending their children to school after the 8th grade.   So 
too, it seems to me to be a natural application of Yoder to say it is a 
substantial burden here for fining these religious adherents for refusing to 
take the affirmative step of purchasing a plan that violates their religious 
beliefs.

One other note:  the language in RFRA's definition about religious exercise not 
being compelled by or central to a system of religious belief was added to RFRA 
by RLUIPA in 2000 because prior to that courts frequently short circuited the 
analysis of RFRA claims by concluding that the particular religious exercise 
involved in a case was not central to or mandated by the religious claimant's 
beliefs.There is no doubt that this definition of religious exercise is 
broad and will encompass lots of what others may think are idiosyncratic 
beliefs or beliefs that seem to them to be remote.   And undoubtedly this means 
that more cases will be subjected to the strict scrutiny analysis, but RFRA and 
RLUIPA were written with the intent of giving expanstive protection for 
religious exercise.

Blessings,
Derek

Derek L. Gaubatz
IMB General Counsel
(804) 219-1575 (o)

Our vision is a multitude from every language, people, tribe and nation knowing 
and worshipping our Lord Jesus Christ.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The formal findings in RFRA reference Sherbert and Yoder, but not Thomas.  
Significant?

Should Thomas even apply to artificial persons, like holding companies, 
corporations, and religious non-profits?  Shouldn't they be required to 
articulate with clarity and precision just how their religious exercise is 
burdened?

I have not yet seen a reply to Bob Ritter's very good question about what work 
is being done by the word substantial in RFRA. It has to mean something.  
Does it refer to material burdens (e.g., one must pay a fine of $X if one 
insists on compliance with one's own religious conscience)?  Or does it refer 
to the religious substantiality of the burden?

The list appears to divide into two groups on this burden question.  One one 
side, the claimant gets to self-declare, and that triggers the strict scrutiny 
of RFRA.   That seems to wildly over-enforce religious freedom.  Consider the 
religiously idiosyncratic and libertarian employer who objects to FLSA, OSHA, 
Title VII, etc.

On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess and 
decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden on that 
is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That seems 
unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on Establishment Clause 
limits on the state's resolving internal religious questions).

 Chip

On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
Ordinarily we should accept a person's view of whether the actions required by 
the state relate closely enough to something prohibited by the person's 
religion so as to make the person complicit. Thomas drew a line, and it is not 
for us to say that the line he drew was an unreasonable one. Thomas v. Review 
Board. Remember that the kind of analysis applied by the Court in Sherbert and 
Thomas is the kind Congress wanted to bring back under RFRA.

Here is a longer excerpt from Thomas. I think it is fair to say that the Court 
held that what counts is the religious person's view of whether actions make 
them complicit with evil:

When asked at the hearing to explain what kind of work his religious 
convictions would permit, Thomas said that he would have no difficulty doing 
the type of work that he had done at the roll foundry. He testified that he 
could, in good conscience, engage indirectly in the production of materials 
that might be used ultimately to fabricate arms -- for example, as an employee 
of a raw material supplier or of a roll foundry. (Footnote omitted.]
...
In reaching its conclusion, the Indiana court seems to have placed

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Ira Lupu
I think Marci's distinction between substantial and incidental burdens goes
to the question of the weight of the burden's materiality (penalty for
noncompliance with government-imposed norms -- though sometimes financial
harm is enough -- see Sherbert).  I take her question in this regard to be
a friendly addition to my own and to Marc's.

I think the either/or choices I attributed to others on the list
(self-declaration of burden vs. objective adjudication) go to the question
of the religious character and significance of the burden (e.g., degree of
complicity in evil from cooperation with the mandate).  That's a different
question.  But I think RFRA is stunningly ambiguous on the issue of whether
its focus is materiality, religious character, or some combination of the
two.

On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 12:08 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

 Actually, I do not recognize my position under either of Chip's either/or
 choices.  Rather, I would look to the cases, which have dealt with
 interpreting substantial burden repeatedly.  Courts have held in the vast
 majority of cases that cost and convenience are not substantial.   That
 weighs heavily against the ACA plaintiffs, to the extent they are
 complaining about having to pay for insurance.
 Substantial means that the religious practice has become impracticable
 or severely curtailed.

  The ACA case creates a new, more extreme, demand, which is not that the
 religious believer is being forced or prohibited from taking a particular
 act, beyond purchasing an omnibus health care plan.  Rather, it is that the
 religious believer does not want to pay for a health insurance plan that
 permits employees potentially to obtain health care with which the
 employer disagrees.  The employee (who, under Title VII or state
 anti-discrimination law could not be hired or fired based on religious
 belief, and who has the benefit of doctor/patient confidentiality) may well
 be fine, on religious grounds, in obtaining the contraception and/or
 abortion (indeed, their religious beliefs may actually require or encourage
 such medical care), but the employer's objection is that someone may use a
 health benefit in a way the religious employer doesn't want it used.  Under
 existing case law, this is an attenuated argument that induces an
 incidental burden, not a substantial burden, for purposes of free
 exercise analysis.

  Moreover, the slippery slope is steep.  Jehovah's witnesses and blood
 transfusion; Scientologists and mental health care; Catholics and
 evangelicals and palliative care for the terminal, elderly patientetc.,
 etc.

  I am not persuaded by Mark's distinction between the voucher cases,
 where private decisions wash government money of its Establishment Clause
 restrictions, and the ACA situation, where, again, a private actor, is
 acting in an independent way that cannot be attributed reasonably to the
 provider of the benefit.

  Marci

  On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess
 and decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden
 on that is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That
 seems unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on
 Establishment Clause limits on the state's resolving internal religious
 questions).

   Chip





 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com


 -Original Message-
 From: Marc DeGirolami marc.degirol...@stjohns.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 11:45 am
 Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  Chip raises a problem I’ve been having a hard time understanding too.  A
 “burden” does seem to imply the willingness to suffer to some unspecified
 degree (rising to the level of being “substantial”) on behalf of the
 claimed belief.  On the specific question of whether one should interpret
 the adjective “substantial” to require some sort of “material burden,” I
 believe that this is what the ED of Missouri court means when it says that
 the claimant must be willing to “forfeit a benefit, pay a fine, or even
 face criminal prosecution” (though I do not believe that the cases cited
 for this proposition support the view that this is a necessary condition).
 One might interpret this statement as a requirement that the plaintiff must
 be willing to suffer **at least** one of these three kinds of penalties
 in order for the burden to be substantial, or maybe to suffer at least some
 sort of penalty period (again provided that the penalty is substantial).
 It’s difficult for me to see that we would want to test the religious
 liberty claim in all cases against a willingness to go to prison, for
 example (Chip writes about a related issue in his “Failure of RFRA” piece,
 I

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Christopher Lund
As for Chip and Bob Ritter's point about the burden being substantial, I
think that anytime a plaintiff is forced to do something their religion
forbids, that is not just a burden but a substantial burden.  I think the
Court made this clear by implication in Hernandez.  See Hernandez v.
Commissioner, 490 U.S. 680, 699 (1989) (We do, however, have doubts
whether the alleged burden imposed by the deduction disallowance on the
Scientologists' practices is a substantial one.  Neither the payment nor
the receipt of taxes is forbidden by the Scientology faith generally, and
Scientology does not proscribe the payment of taxes in connection with
auditing or training sessions specifically.).  This is not to say that
the word substantial makes no difference.  It may be important in other
kinds of cases like, say, Braunfeld-cases where the government makes the
religious practice more onerous but does not forbid it.  (For another
example, we could go back to my discussion with Marci about a prison that
doesn't force a Jew to eat non-Kosher food, but puts him on a Kosher diet
that is significantly worse than that of other inmates.)  

 

I think Chip has rightly diagnosed the deep divide between the two groups.
I think there are merits and demerits to both sides.  But I think the
Court has chosen the first position.  Subject to the sincerity inquiry,
churches do indeed get to self-declare what their religious views are.
I know that sounds weird, but wouldn't it be weirder if they didn't?
Certainly this broad conception of burden will lead to outcomes like
Lee: As the scope of the religious objection grows wider and wider, the
government's claim of a compelling interest becomes more and more
persuasive.  Maybe the Court's adoption of a broad sense of burden in
cases like Lee helped lead to Employment Division v. Smith.  Gosh knows,
it was part of Boerne.  See City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507, 535
(1997) (It is a reality of the modern regulatory state that numerous
state laws, such as the zoning regulations at issue here, impose a
substantial burden on a large class of individuals.)  But it seems to me
that this is the path we're on.

 

Best,

Chris

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

The formal findings in RFRA reference Sherbert and Yoder, but not
Thomas.  Significant?

 

Should Thomas even apply to artificial persons, like holding companies,
corporations, and religious non-profits?  Shouldn't they be required to
articulate with clarity and precision just how their religious exercise is
burdened?  

 

I have not yet seen a reply to Bob Ritter's very good question about what
work is being done by the word substantial in RFRA. It has to mean
something.  Does it refer to material burdens (e.g., one must pay a fine
of $X if one insists on compliance with one's own religious conscience)?
Or does it refer to the religious substantiality of the burden?

 

The list appears to divide into two groups on this burden question.  One
one side, the claimant gets to self-declare, and that triggers the strict
scrutiny of RFRA.   That seems to wildly over-enforce religious freedom.
Consider the religiously idiosyncratic and libertarian employer who
objects to FLSA, OSHA, Title VII, etc.

 

On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess
and decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of
burden on that is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.
That seems unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on
Establishment Clause limits on the state's resolving internal religious
questions).

 

 Chip

 

On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Scarberry, Mark
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

Ordinarily we should accept a person's view of whether the actions
required by the state relate closely enough to something prohibited by the
person's religion so as to make the person complicit. Thomas drew a line,
and it is not for us to say that the line he drew was an unreasonable
one. Thomas v. Review Board. Remember that the kind of analysis applied
by the Court in Sherbert and Thomas is the kind Congress wanted to bring
back under RFRA.

Here is a longer excerpt from Thomas. I think it is fair to say that the
Court held that what counts is the religious person's view of whether
actions make them complicit with evil:

When asked at the hearing to explain what kind of work his religious
convictions would permit, Thomas said that he would have no difficulty
doing the type of work that he had done at the roll foundry. He testified
that he could, in good conscience, engage indirectly in the production of
materials that might be used ultimately to fabricate arms -- for example,
as an employee of a raw material

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
Chip-- With respect to RFRA, substantial burden was adopted from the case 
law.
Are you suggesting that it has evolved into a different standard?   


Marci  





 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 1:02 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


I think Marci's distinction between substantial and incidental burdens goes to 
the question of the weight of the burden's materiality (penalty for 
noncompliance with government-imposed norms -- though sometimes financial harm 
is enough -- see Sherbert).  I take her question in this regard to be a 
friendly addition to my own and to Marc's.

I think the either/or choices I attributed to others on the list 
(self-declaration of burden vs. objective adjudication) go to the question of 
the religious character and significance of the burden (e.g., degree of 
complicity in evil from cooperation with the mandate).  That's a different 
question.  But I think RFRA is stunningly ambiguous on the issue of whether its 
focus is materiality, religious character, or some combination of the two.  


On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 12:08 PM,  hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

Actually, I do not recognize my position under either of Chip's either/or 
choices.  Rather, I would look to the cases, which have dealt with interpreting 
substantial burden repeatedly.  Courts have held in the vast majority of 
cases that cost and convenience are not substantial.   That weighs heavily 
against the ACA plaintiffs, to the extent they are complaining about having to 
pay for insurance.  
Substantial means that the religious practice has become impracticable or 
severely curtailed.   


The ACA case creates a new, more extreme, demand, which is not that the 
religious believer is being forced or prohibited from taking a particular act, 
beyond purchasing an omnibus health care plan.  Rather, it is that the 
religious believer does not want to pay for a health insurance plan that 
permits employees potentially to obtain health care with which the employer 
disagrees.  The employee (who, under Title VII or state anti-discrimination law 
could not be hired or fired based on religious belief, and who has the benefit 
of doctor/patient confidentiality) may well be fine, on religious grounds, in 
obtaining the contraception and/or abortion (indeed, their religious beliefs 
may actually require or encourage such medical care), but the employer's 
objection is that someone may use a health benefit in a way the religious 
employer doesn't want it used.  Under existing case law, this is an attenuated 
argument that induces an incidental burden, not a substantial burden, for 
purposes of free exercise analysis.   


Moreover, the slippery slope is steep.  Jehovah's witnesses and blood 
transfusion; Scientologists and mental health care; Catholics and evangelicals 
and palliative care for the terminal, elderly patientetc., etc.


I am not persuaded by Mark's distinction between the voucher cases, where 
private decisions wash government money of its Establishment Clause 
restrictions, and the ACA situation, where, again, a private actor, is acting 
in an independent way that cannot be attributed reasonably to the provider of 
the benefit.


Marci




On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess and 
decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden on that 
is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That seems 
unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on Establishment Clause 
limits on the state's resolving internal religious questions).

 

 Chip

 






 

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com





-Original Message-
From: Marc DeGirolami marc.degirol...@stjohns.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu


Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 11:45 am
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Chip raises a problem I’ve been having a hard time understanding too.  A 
“burden” does seem to imply the willingness to suffer to some unspecified 
degree (rising to the level of being “substantial”) on behalf of the claimed 
belief.  On the specific question of whether one should interpret the adjective 
“substantial” to require some sort of “material burden,” I believe that this is 
what the ED of Missouri court means when it says that the claimant must be 
willing to “forfeit a benefit, pay a fine, or even face criminal prosecution” 
(though I do

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
Derek--   You don't mention, though, that the legislative history of RLUIPA is 
explicit that substantial burden means what it meant in the free exercise 
doctrine.
You can't use the definition of religious exercise (which I view as 
reflecting Smith's dictum on the same) to alter the definition of substantial.


Marci



 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org
To: Religionlaw Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 12:42 pm
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Dear Chip,
 
Thomas is not mentioned in the findings of RFRA, but it’s holding is certainly 
incorporated into the definition of religious exercise in RFRA (and RLUIPA).
 In fact, it seems to me that much of the discussion on this list and in the 
O’Brien case of whether there is a substantial burden in these 
contraception/abortifacient cases has failed to focus in on RFRA’s definition 
of religious exercise.   Obviously, it is an important threshold issue to 
identify the precise religious exercise at issue before determining whether 
there is a substantial burden on that religious exercise.
 
RFRA defines religious exercise (consistent with Thomas) as “any 
exercise of religion, whether or not compelled by, or central to, a system of 
religious belief.” 42 U.S.C. §2000bb-2(4); 42 U.S.C. §2000cc-5
 
There are three noteworthy things about this definition.   First, like the text 
of the Free Exercise Clause itself, which does not limit the range or types of 
religious exercise eligible for protection, the Act's definition makes clear 
that “any” discrete instance of religious exercise is covered by the Act. 
 
Second, not only does RFRA’s definition of “religious exercise” provide that 
“any” religious exercise is protected, it also makes explicit that this 
protection is not limited to practices that are compelled by the individual's 
religion. Thus, religious exercise that some might claim is discretionary on 
the part of the believer--e.g., a Catholic's desire to pray the rosary, a 
Muslim's desire to utilize prayer oils during daily prayers, or a Jewish 
believer's decision to wear a yarmulke--is also protected and may not be 
substantially burdened.   This aversion to adopting a requirement that 
religious exercise be mandated by a faith in order to be protected flows 
directly from the Supreme Court's holding in Thomas that “[c]ourts are not 
arbiters of scriptural interpretation.” To require a court to inquire into 
whether a particular religious practice is compelled by the believer's faith is 
to force a court into a role “not within the judicial function and judicial 
competence,” because it necessitates a judgment as to what a religion requires 
of its believers. If compulsion were a prerequisite, courts would soon be in 
the theological thicket as the state would seek to defeat a believer's claim of 
substantial burden by introducing testimony of another member of the believer's 
faith who opines that the particular practice is not mandated.
 
Finally, RFRA’s definition of religious exercise also makes explicit that 
consideration of whether the religious exercise at issue in the case is 
“central” (or fundamental) to a particular religion is irrelevant. Accordingly, 
particular acts of religious exercise are protected from being substantially 
burdened under RFRA, regardless of whether a judge (or government official or 
law professor or anybody else) feels they are not of sufficient importance to a 
religion to be worthy of protection. 
 
With RFRA’s definition of “religious exercise” in mind, what is the precise 
religious exercise involved in O’Brien and in other cases challenging the 
contraception/abortifacient mandate?   As I understand it, the religious 
exercise at issue is that the religious adherent (i.e., the employers in these 
cases) believes that it morally wrong to purchase a health care plan (in the 
case of a non-self insured employer) that includes 
contraceptives/abortifacients or to be forced to pay for 
contraceptives/abortifacients (in the case of an employer with a self-insured 
plan) As I understand it, there is no question in O’Brien (or any of the 
other cases) about the sincerity of this belief or that it is religiously 
based.  
 
Once the focus is placed on the actual religious belief that is being exercised 
here, the question is then whether the mandate substantially burdens this 
religious exercise.   As I understand the mandate’s operation, it says either 
you comply with the mandate and pay for a plan (or provide coverage in the case 
of a self-insured plan) that includes contraceptives/abortifacients or pay a 
penalty.   In other words, if the religious adherents here exercise their 
beliefs

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Ira Lupu
The free exercise case law does not come close to sufficiently fleshing it
out (and has internal contradictions), and a general term like substantial
burden inevitably must evolve in light of the facts of cases as they arise
and are decided.

If there had never been a Smith or a RFRA. I expect we would be having
exactly the same fight over whether the employer mandate under ACA was a
substantial burden under the free exercise clause.

On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 2:02 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

 Chip-- With respect to RFRA, substantial burden was adopted from the
 case law.
 Are you suggesting that it has evolved into a different standard?

  Marci




 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com


 -Original Message-
 From: Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 1:02 pm
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  I think Marci's distinction between substantial and incidental burdens
 goes to the question of the weight of the burden's materiality (penalty for
 noncompliance with government-imposed norms -- though sometimes financial
 harm is enough -- see Sherbert).  I take her question in this regard to be
 a friendly addition to my own and to Marc's.

 I think the either/or choices I attributed to others on the list
 (self-declaration of burden vs. objective adjudication) go to the question
 of the religious character and significance of the burden (e.g., degree of
 complicity in evil from cooperation with the mandate).  That's a different
 question.  But I think RFRA is stunningly ambiguous on the issue of whether
 its focus is materiality, religious character, or some combination of the
 two.

 On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 12:08 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

 Actually, I do not recognize my position under either of Chip's either/or
 choices.  Rather, I would look to the cases, which have dealt with
 interpreting substantial burden repeatedly.  Courts have held in the vast
 majority of cases that cost and convenience are not substantial.   That
 weighs heavily against the ACA plaintiffs, to the extent they are
 complaining about having to pay for insurance.
 Substantial means that the religious practice has become
 impracticable or severely curtailed.

  The ACA case creates a new, more extreme, demand, which is not that the
 religious believer is being forced or prohibited from taking a particular
 act, beyond purchasing an omnibus health care plan.  Rather, it is that the
 religious believer does not want to pay for a health insurance plan that
 permits employees potentially to obtain health care with which the
 employer disagrees.  The employee (who, under Title VII or state
 anti-discrimination law could not be hired or fired based on religious
 belief, and who has the benefit of doctor/patient confidentiality) may well
 be fine, on religious grounds, in obtaining the contraception and/or
 abortion (indeed, their religious beliefs may actually require or encourage
 such medical care), but the employer's objection is that someone may use a
 health benefit in a way the religious employer doesn't want it used.  Under
 existing case law, this is an attenuated argument that induces an
 incidental burden, not a substantial burden, for purposes of free
 exercise analysis.

  Moreover, the slippery slope is steep.  Jehovah's witnesses and blood
 transfusion; Scientologists and mental health care; Catholics and
 evangelicals and palliative care for the terminal, elderly patientetc.,
 etc.

  I am not persuaded by Mark's distinction between the voucher cases,
 where private decisions wash government money of its Establishment Clause
 restrictions, and the ACA situation, where, again, a private actor, is
 acting in an independent way that cannot be attributed reasonably to the
 provider of the benefit.

  Marci

  On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to
 second-guess and decide what someone's religion really requires, and what
 kind of burden on that is presumptively too great to force the claimant to
 endure.  That seems unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions
 on Establishment Clause limits on the state's resolving internal religious
 questions).

   Chip





  Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com


  -Original Message-
 From: Marc DeGirolami marc.degirol...@stjohns.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
   Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 11:45 am
 Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  Chip raises a problem I’ve been having a hard

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread hamilton02
Doug--Are you suggesting that Bowen would have come down differently, under the 
substantial burden analysis, depending on whether they, as the case started,
had to apply for a number, or, as the trial indicated, they had to live with 
one?   Why?


Marci  





 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 12:50 pm
Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious LibertyChallenges  To  ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



In Bowen, they discovered at trial that she already had a social security 
number By the time the case got to the Supreme Court, the claim was that the 
government could not use that social security number to maintain its records on 
the child.  Plaintiffs said that the government’s use of the number would sap 
the child’s spirit.
 
In Lyng, the government proposed to make noise that would disrupt religious 
mediation.
 
Neither case was about regulating the  religious believer’s behavior.  The ACA 
cases are about regulating the believer’s behavior.
 
Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 12:12 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 
Doug--The government in Bowen required the applicant to obtain a social 
security number to obtain benefits.   They did not want to obtain it, because 
it would sacrifice their child's soul.  Looks like forced complicity with evil 
to me.   How does that work under your distinction? 


I have to say it looks like a distinction without a difference to me.

 

Lyng is certainly relevant re: whether the subjective sense of the burden is 
relevant.  It is not.

 

Marci 

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 



 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Alan Brownstein
I admire the way that Marc addresses this issue. Very thoughtful post.

There are no easy answers here, as Marc recognizes.

Many religious obligations involve material sacrifices by believers.  What 
material loss do I incur if the government forces me work on Yom Kippur? It 
can't mean that this is not a substantial burden on religious liberty because I 
would not suffer a material burden if I complied with it.

Some accommodations are materially beneficial to the religious individuals that 
seek them. Sometimes we can test sincerity (and arguably substantiality) to 
some extent by limiting or eliminating those material benefits. (see my last 
post)

There is no way to test the claimant's willingness to incur to pay a fine or 
face criminal prosecution other than requiring the claimant to pay the fine or 
by prosecuting him. That solution has obvious difficulties. We do often 
indirectly use the temptation of increased benefits. When we pay people 
overtime to work on Saturday or Sunday, for example, the loss of increased 
income tests their commitment to observing the Sabbath.

If we are talking about laws that require an individual or institution to do 
something that they claim their religion prohibits them from doing, I don't see 
any way to move beyond subjective sincerity without crossing the lines that  
forbid courts from inquiring into the importance of the belief, or the degree 
to which the belief has been ratified by other religious adherents.

So what do we do. In this kind of a case (where the state allegedly obliges a 
person to do something their religion prohibits) I ask this question - what 
doctrinal approach is going to get us the best answer that both protects 
religious liberty and appropriately respects the countervailing state interests 
that may justify burdening religious liberty? I think we are more likely to get 
the right answer when courts look at the burden on the claimant, the importance 
of the state's interest and the availability of less restrictive alternatives 
as opposed to allowing some claims to be dismissed on the grounds that they are 
insufficiently substantial. We can argue about whether an allegedly attenuated 
burden should be assigned less weight than a more direct burden in adjudicating 
the case on the merits. But that is different than saying that a necessarily 
arbitrary ruling about the substantiality of the burden should preclude any 
consideration of the importance of the state's interest or the availability of 
less restrictive alternatives.

Alan




From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marc DeGirolami
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 8:44 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Chip raises a problem I've been having a hard time understanding too.  A 
burden does seem to imply the willingness to suffer to some unspecified 
degree (rising to the level of being substantial) on behalf of the claimed 
belief.  On the specific question of whether one should interpret the adjective 
substantial to require some sort of material burden, I believe that this is 
what the ED of Missouri court means when it says that the claimant must be 
willing to forfeit a benefit, pay a fine, or even face criminal prosecution 
(though I do not believe that the cases cited for this proposition support the 
view that this is a necessary condition).  One might interpret this statement 
as a requirement that the plaintiff must be willing to suffer *at least* one of 
these three kinds of penalties in order for the burden to be substantial, or 
maybe to suffer at least some sort of penalty period (again provided that the 
penalty is substantial).  It's difficult for me to see that we would want to 
test the religious liberty claim in all cases against a willingness to go to 
prison, for example (Chip writes about a related issue in his Failure of RFRA 
piece, I think).

But even if we thought that willingness to pay a fine would be a good test for 
substantiality (which I'll admit doesn't seem unreasonable to me, in some 
cases), I wonder about how this would work in practice.  That is, how would we 
know that the plaintiff was really willing to pay a fine rather than be forced 
to do something alleged to violate religious conscience?  What would be the 
proof?

I'll add that I am genuinely confused about the issue of substantiality of the 
burden, because it does seem to me to require more than something like 
subjective sincerity, but also to forbid courts from inquiring into the 
importance of the belief, or the degree to which the belief has been ratified 
by other religious adherents.  If that is right, then what is left to determine 
the substantiality of the burden other than the degree to which the claimant is 
willing to suffer for his or her beliefs?

Marc


From: 
religionlaw-boun

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

If you look back at what I stated below, I was not using the definition of 
“religious exercise” to alter what “substantial burden” means.   Instead, the 
point is that the Act provides a broad definition of what religious exercise 
may not be substantially burdened.   Therefore, the starting point is to 
precisely define what the religious exercise at issue is and see whether this 
religious exercise meet’s the Act’s definition of what may not be substantially 
burdened.  Once the threshold issue is cleared of determining whether the 
claimant has identified religious exercise protected by the Act, the analysis 
shifts to determining whether there is a government imposed substantial burden 
on that religious exercise.   I agree that the legislative history does say we 
should look to pre-Smith conceptions of substantial burden, which is why my 
analysis below applied Yoder, a pre-Smith case. 

I’d also add that the proper focus of whether there is a government imposed 
substantial burden  is an objective test that focuses on the action taken by 
the government, not the subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective 
substantial burden is an action by the government that coerces or tend to 
inhibit any religious exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being 
fined for engaging in a particular act of religious exercise is objectively a 
substantial burden regardless of the particular nature of the religious 
exercise involved (e.g., wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, 
or being forced to purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).    
Objectively focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids 
getting into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the 
claimant feels about the government action.     

Blessings,
Derek

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com

Derek--   You don't mention, though, that the legislative history of RLUIPA is 
explicit that substantial burden means what it meant in the free exercise 
doctrine. 
You can't use the definition of religious exercise (which I view as 
reflecting Smith's dictum on the same) to alter the definition of substantial.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org
Dear Chip,
 
   Thomas is not mentioned in the findings of RFRA, but it’s holding is 
certainly incorporated into the definition of religious exercise in RFRA (and 
RLUIPA). In fact, it seems to me that much of the discussion on this list 
and in the O’Brien case of whether there is a substantial burden in these 
contraception/abortifacient cases has failed to focus in on RFRA’s definition 
of religious exercise.   Obviously, it is an important threshold issue to 
identify the precise religious exercise at issue before determining whether 
there is a substantial burden on that religious exercise.
 
    RFRA defines religious exercise (consistent with Thomas) as “any 
exercise of religion, whether or not compelled by, or central to, a system of 
religious belief.” 42 U.S.C. §2000bb-2(4); 42 U.S.C. §2000cc-5
 
   There are three noteworthy things about this definition.   First, like 
the text of the Free Exercise Clause itself, which does not limit the range or 
types of religious exercise eligible for protection, the Act's definition makes 
clear that “any” discrete instance of religious exercise is covered by the Act. 
 
   Second, not only does RFRA’s definition of “religious exercise” provide 
that “any” religious exercise is protected, it also makes explicit that this 
protection is not limited to practices that are compelled by the individual's 
religion. Thus, religious exercise that some might claim is discretionary on 
the part of the believer--e.g., a Catholic's desire to pray the rosary, a 
Muslim's desire to utilize prayer oils during daily prayers, or a Jewish 
believer's decision to wear a yarmulke--is also protected and may not be 
substantially burdened.   This aversion to adopting a requirement that 
religious exercise be mandated by a faith in order to be protected flows 
directly from the Supreme Court's holding in Thomas that “[c]ourts are not 
arbiters of scriptural interpretation.” To require a court to inquire into 
whether a particular religious practice is compelled by the believer's faith is 
to force a court into a role “not within the judicial function and judicial 
competence,” because it necessitates a judgment as to what a religion requires 
of its believers. If compulsion were a prerequisite, courts would soon be in 
the theological thicket as the state would seek to defeat a believer's claim of 
substantial burden by introducing testimony of another member of the 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread Conkle, Daniel O.
If I’m not mistaken, Marci, a majority of the justices in fact so indicated in 
Bowen.  It was a fractured decision.  Two justices thought the issue of whether 
Roy could be required to provide a number for his daughter was moot (since, as 
it happened, there already was such a number).  Of the seven justices who 
reached that issue, four would have required a free exercise exemption, and a 
5th (Justice Blackmun), indicated that he would have agreed if he had reached 
the merits.  Only three justices joined the plurality opinion’s rejection of 
both aspects of the free exercise argument.

Dan Conkle

Daniel O. Conkle
Robert H. McKinney Professor of Law
Indiana University Maurer School of Law
Bloomington, Indiana  47405
(812) 855-4331
fax (812) 855-0555
e-mail con...@indiana.edu



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 2:32 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Doug--Are you suggesting that Bowen would have come down differently, under the 
substantial burden analysis, depending on whether they, as the case started,
had to apply for a number, or, as the trial indicated, they had to live with 
one?   Why?

Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, Oct 2, 2012 12:50 pm
Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
In Bowen, they discovered at trial that she already had a social security 
number By the time the case got to the Supreme Court, the claim was that the 
government could not use that social security number to maintain its records on 
the child.  Plaintiffs said that the government’s use of the number would sap 
the child’s spirit.

In Lyng, the government proposed to make noise that would disrupt religious 
mediation.

Neither case was about regulating the  religious believer’s behavior.  The ACA 
cases are about regulating the believer’s behavior.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 12:12 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Doug--The government in Bowen required the applicant to obtain a social 
security number to obtain benefits.   They did not want to obtain it, because 
it would sacrifice their child's soul.  Looks like forced complicity with evil 
to me.   How does that work under your distinction?
I have to say it looks like a distinction without a difference to me.

Lyng is certainly relevant re: whether the subjective sense of the burden is 
relevant.  It is not.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com


___

To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see

http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the

messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-02 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
Doug,

Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be different
if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care, etc. actually saved
the employer money rather than cost the employer money? Would saving money
(i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a substantial burden even if the saving
resulted a government mandate to provide health care that the employer found
religiously objectionable?

Bob Ritter

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty
A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter
Falls Church, VA 22042
703-533-0236


On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption
 from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing
 special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just
 the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing against
 conscience protections for medical providers.

 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and
 the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral.
 The salary payments could have been used for anything.

 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the government
 will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is highly
 attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling interest
 in paying taxes.

 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the
 money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a
 package of services that includes the services the employer believes to be
 immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer
 believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those
 services and pays for those services, and these employers say they cannot in
 conscience do those things.

 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
 can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
 It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the
 money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
 which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
 abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
 partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
 used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
 contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
 for that purpose. (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
 plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)
 
 Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
 salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
 burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
 overcome by a compelling government interest. For anyone who starts from
 that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question. But I am not
 aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the
 payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows
 that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of
 salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful
 in the eyes of the employer.
 
 Thus the question here is whether the state ought to take at face value the
 assertions of some employers that the moral obligation changes dramatically
 when the money is used for partial subsidization of an insurance plan,
 rather than for taxes or salaries. I actually think this is a complex
 question, as to which I deeply appreciate the many thoughtful views others
 have contributed to this thread. But whatever the merits of that
 distinction, the case is a far cry from compelling the employer to kill
 another human being.
 
 On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 7:27 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:
 
  We have a long political tradition of treating objections to killing as a
  special claim, deserving special protection. We have exempted conscientious
  objectors in all our wars, even when national existence was on the line,
  and notwithstanding powerful incentives to dubious conversions or false
  claims.
 
  In the abortion case, the majority believes it is not a killing of a human
  being; the conscientious objector believes it is. The disagreement over the
  nature of the killing comes at a slightly different point; I do not claim
  that the cases are identical.
 
  I do believe that there are sound reasons, reflected in our legal and
  political tradition, to give special deference to what the conscientious
  objector believes is a refusal to kill another human being.
 
  The cases also differ in the weight of the 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread hamilton02
Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial
for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado
initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact
that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.


The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing
the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate
substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the
governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these
decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sun, Sep 30, 2012 10:16 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate



On Sep 30, 2012, at 9:49 PM, Douglas Laycock wrote:

 Steve's second point -- the difference between historic exclusion of 
 Catholics 
as such and contemporary exclusion of those who adhere too strictly to certain 
Catholic teachings -- is just Smith's holding about generally applicable laws. 
The whole point of RFRA was to create statutory protection not restricted to 
that holding.

Agreed.  But that doesn't make the history of status-based exclusion 
controlling 
for what is and is not a substantial burden, or even particularly relevant.  
They are different types of exclusion.  There are reasons to protect 
pure-belief-based actions even in the commercial secular marketplace, but that 
history is not one of them.


 The ACA and the contraceptive mandate also have exceptions that cover rens of 
millions of people, so it is far from clear that this is a neutral and 
generally 
applicable law. The no-burden holding also saves the court from having to 
address that issue.

I am not overly fond of a number of substantial burden results.  But the test 
is 
substantial burden, not merely burden, and the term substantial should mean 
something.  I think it should mean something quite substantial and be something 
that really effectively prohibits the exercise of religion or really makes it 
so 
hard to practice one's beliefs that one has a hard time practicing them.  I 
understand others think it should be subjective and controlled by the adherent 
and that we should take his or her word for the substantiality of the effect.

You may believe that OSHA is the work of the devil.  But that doesn't relieve 
you from compliance if you choose to engage in the sort of commerce that OSHA 
regulates.  No one is making you do that sort of work.  You have alternatives.  

Do we really want to say the subjective burden as felt by the adherent gets 
past 
the first hurdle and then have courts start expanding compelling state 
interest to uphold the myriad regulations on commercial establishments?  That 
seems to me to be a greater mischief.

Perhaps RFRA should be revisited to address the back-end standard to make the 
balancing more like EP intermediate scrutiny.  Or to consider the 
substantiality 
of the burden, the importance of the state's interest, the effect on third 
parties (e.g. employees in an employer setting), and the effect of ruling one 
way or the other on all three -- what options are available for the religious 
adherent employer; what costs are there to society and the government in 
interests of equality, equity, administration of the laws; what options are 
there to the employee.  But that opens quite another can of worms and gives 
huge 
discretionary power to the courts.

Is that really what we want here?

Or do we really want the unit veto for any and all government regulations short 
of human sacrifice and child abuse as compelling interests?

Are we going to revisit the social security cases and now say they don't need 
to 
pay the tax?

I think the judge got it right here and that the alternatives are not 
necessarily good for free exercise in the bigger picture.

Steve

 
 On Sun, 30 Sep 2012 21:32:10 -0400
 Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com wrote:
 I was quite clearly talking about religious employers in secular commerce.   
The religious institutions engaging in secular/religious endeavors like 
religious schools and hospitals are different from someone making and selling 
widgets.
 
 There is also quite a difference

FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
burden issue in the ACA cases.

 

And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial 

for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado

initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact

that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.

 

The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing

the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate

substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the

governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these

decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.

 

Marci

 

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
Oops. Writing too fast.

 

What I meant to say is that neither Lyng, nor Bowen, nor Lee supports a 
no-burden holding in the ACA cases.  Lyng and Bowen do indeed appear 
irrelevant. But Lee is not irrelevant; it supports a holding of substantial 
burden. The Court accepted the Amish claim that payment of social security 
taxes was forbidden by their faith, and concluded that requiring this payment 
“interferes with their free exercise rights.” But “not all burdens are 
unconstitutional. That state may justify a limitation on religious liberty . . 
.” And it went on to find a compelling interest in collecting taxes, including 
social security taxes.

 

So in Lee, the Court said that payment of funds to the government, for a stated 
purpose that is religiously objectionable, is a constitutionally cognizable 
burden on free exercise. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
burden issue in the ACA cases.

 

And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial 

for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado

initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact

that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.

 

The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing

the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate

substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the

governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these

decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.

 

Marci

 

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Rick Garnett
Dear colleagues,

Rob Vischer (St. Thomas – MN) has a reaction – one that identifies well the 
decision’s many flaws -- to the decision we’re discussing, at the “Mirror of 
Justice” blog:  
http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/10/forcing-a-church-to-pay-for-its-employees-abortions-would-not-create-a-substantial-burden-on-religio.html

As Prof. Vischer reads the decision, its reasoning – i.e., no “substantial 
burden” -- would apply to a RFRA challenge brought by a Catholic diocese to an 
exemption-less requirement that the diocese provide insurance coverage for 
elective abortions.  Do those who have been welcoming this decision agree that 
RFRA would not / should not protect the diocese in such a case?

Best, R

Richard W. Garnett
Professor of Law and Associate Dean
Notre Dame Law School
P.O. Box 780
Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

574-631-6981 (w)
574-276-2252 (cell)

SSRN pagehttp://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235

Blogs:

Prawfsblawghttp://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/
Mirror of Justicehttp://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
burden issue in the ACA cases.

And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial
for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado
initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact
that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.

The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing
the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate
substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the
governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these
decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.

Marci


Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Rob's thoughts are well worth reading -- he puts his finger on a bunch of
questions that are sure to be central to these cases going forward.

One caveat on the equivalence point raised by Rob and Rick:

To the extent the court is rejecting a proximate cooperation with evil
theory of substantial burden here, then yes, that same theory would
presumably be subject to the same objections if the case involved a diocese
and elective abortion coverage.  But the diocese would have a much stronger
substantial burden argument on a different theory -- one of the
institutional autonomy theories that Rick referred to earlier.  In
particular, assuming the diocese exercises its title VII exemption, and
prefers coreligionists in employment, then I'd assume one of its principal
functions -- unlike that of the ceramics-processing O'Brien Industrial
Company -- is to create and nurture a particular kind of religious
community, one in which its employees are expected to advance its Catholic
mission, and to adhere to Catholic tenets in their own conduct.  The HHS
rule would arguably have a significant impact on the ability of the diocese
to so shape its community and to ensure that its employees act in
accordance with Catholic precepts.  In that respect, the diocese is very
differently situated for RFRA purposes from the O'Brien Industrial Company,
which hires many non-Catholics and that does not endeavor to require its
employees to conform their conduct to Catholic precepts.

On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 11:57 AM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:

 Dear colleagues,

 ** **

 Rob Vischer (St. Thomas – MN) has a reaction – one that identifies well
 the decision’s many flaws -- to the decision we’re discussing, at the
 “Mirror of Justice” blog:
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/10/forcing-a-church-to-pay-for-its-employees-abortions-would-not-create-a-substantial-burden-on-religio.html
 

 ** **

 As Prof. Vischer reads the decision, its reasoning – i.e., no “substantial
 burden” -- would apply to a RFRA challenge brought by a Catholic diocese to
 an exemption-less requirement that the diocese provide insurance coverage
 for elective abortions.  Do those who have been welcoming this decision
 agree that RFRA would not / should not protect the diocese in such a case?
   

 ** **

 Best, R

 ** **

 Richard W. Garnett

 Professor of Law and Associate Dean

 Notre Dame Law School

 P.O. Box 780

 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

 ** **

 574-631-6981 (w)

 574-276-2252 (cell)

 ** **

 SSRN page http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235
 

 ** **

 Blogs:

 ** **

 Prawfsblawg http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/

 Mirror of Justice http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/ 

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Douglas Laycock

 *Sent:* Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
 *To:* 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 *Subject:* FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly
 found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on
 compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the
 burden issue in the ACA cases.

 ** **

 And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edureligionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 *On Behalf Of *hamilto...@aol.com
 *Sent:* Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
 *To:* religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down
 substantial 

 for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither
 did the failed North Dakota or Colorado

 initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though
 it is also attributable to the fact

 that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their
 match in a number of opposing groups.

 ** **

 The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the
 interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing

 the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.
  That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which
 indicate

 substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing
 precedents (as of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee
 are the

 governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan
raises:  For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the
members of this list -- who have long argued that the state is
*not*responsible for the genuinely free and independent choices of
individuals
to use state $$ at a school of their choice, and that the state can surely
ameliorate any risk of misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear
disclaimer of neutrality and nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really
fair to attribute to the employer here the employee's decision to use
contraception when (i) the coverage in the insurance plan is compelled by
law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally hundreds of different types of
medical goods and services, of which contraception is but one; (iii) the
decisions whether or not to use the plan for contraception are the result
of genuinely free and independent private choice and could not reasonably
be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the employer is free to issue as
many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no uncertain terms that it
thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the law in question, that
it would strongly urge its employees not to use contraception, etc.?

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's
involvement in the student's choice of a religious school is far too
attenuated to implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of the
taxpayer whose funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many
intervening decisions, to the religious school's coffers, why should we
think there is a substantial burden on the employer's obligations of
conscience in this case?


On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 2:11 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:

 Dear Marty,

 ** **

 I agree with you that a religious institution (which, I think, should
 include most of the institution-plaintiffs challenging the
 preventive-services mandate -- Catholic Charities, EWTN, the University of
 Notre Dame, etc.) is better positioned to frame the “substantial burden” in
 terms of its institutional “mission”, though I also think that the better
 way to handle the objection of, say, the owner of a commercial business is
 by asking about feasibility (tailoring, alternatives, etc.) and not by
 asserting (as the court here did) that there is no burden because employees
 often do things with their salaries to which employers object on moral
 grounds, etc.  (I do agree that, generally speaking, there isn’t a strong
 “substantial burden on conscience” objection to expenditures by the
 government from funds raised through taxes, but also think that the problem
 presented by the mandate, even for commercial employers, is different.)***
 *

 ** **

 Also, I’d like to hear more from those who support the court’s reasoning
 in response to Alan Brownstein’s as-per-usual thoughtful e-mail, in which
 he expressed concerns about the “no burden here” assertion, given what
 would seem to be the tension between that assertion and claims that, say,
 allowing school-voucher recipients to send their kids to Catholic schools
 burdens the conscience of one who objects to such funding.  If this
 decision were right, then wouldn’t we have a(nother) reason to overrule
 Flast?

 ** **

 Best,

 ** **

 Rick

 ** **

 Richard W. Garnett

 Professor of Law and Associate Dean

 Notre Dame Law School

 P.O. Box 780

 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

 ** **

 574-631-6981 (w)

 574-276-2252 (cell)

 ** **

 SSRN page http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235
 

 ** **

 Blogs:

 ** **

 Prawfsblawg http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/

 Mirror of Justice http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/ 

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Monday, October 01, 2012 1:48 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Rob's thoughts are well worth reading -- he puts his finger on a bunch of
 questions that are sure to be central to these cases going forward.

 One caveat on the equivalence point raised by Rob and Rick:

 To the extent the court is rejecting a proximate cooperation with evil
 theory of substantial burden here, then yes, that same theory would
 presumably be subject to the same objections if the case involved a diocese
 and elective abortion coverage.  But the diocese would have a much stronger
 substantial burden argument on a different theory -- one of the
 institutional autonomy theories that Rick referred to earlier.  In
 particular, assuming the diocese exercises its title VII exemption, and
 prefers coreligionists in employment, then I'd assume one of its principal
 functions -- unlike that of the ceramics-processing O'Brien Industrial
 Company -- is to create and nurture a particular kind

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Christopher Lund
Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison
doesn't serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, This burdens my
religion.  The prison responds, No, it doesn't.  You're not responsible
for the food we choose to serve in prison.  That's a genuinely free and
independent choice that we made.  It has nothing to do with you.

 

So why is there a substantial burden there?  I think it's simple: The
state is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion
forbids.  Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of responsibility.  But
those notions are what they are, I think.  The state can't say, Your
theological notions of 'responsibility' are absurd, any more than it can
say, Your theological notions about the food God requires you to eat are
absurd.

 

Best,

Chris

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan
raises:  For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the
members of this list -- who have long argued that the state is not
responsible for the genuinely free and independent choices of individuals
to use state $$ at a school of their choice, and that the state can surely
ameliorate any risk of misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear
disclaimer of neutrality and nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really
fair to attribute to the employer here the employee's decision to use
contraception when (i) the coverage in the insurance plan is compelled by
law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally hundreds of different types
of medical goods and services, of which contraception is but one; (iii)
the decisions whether or not to use the plan for contraception are the
result of genuinely free and independent private choice and could not
reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the employer is free to
issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no uncertain terms
that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the law in
question, that it would strongly urge its employees not to use
contraception, etc.?  

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's
involvement in the student's choice of a religious school is far too
attenuated to implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of
the taxpayer whose funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many
intervening decisions, to the religious school's coffers, why should we
think there is a substantial burden on the employer's obligations of
conscience in this case?

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread hamilton02
Chris--  I take it you are arguing that for every religious prisoner with a 
dietary restriction, all of them can prove substantial burden,
but the state may or may not win under RLUIPA based on the state's evidence of 
compelling interest?   


Is it a substantial burden where the believer can obtain 50% of the foods 
he/she seeks?  I'm broadening this from the kosher
food context, obviously.


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 3:39 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA  
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison doesn’t 
serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, “This burdens my religion.”  The prison 
responds, “No, it doesn’t.  You’re not responsible for the food we choose to 
serve in prison.  That’s a genuinely free and independent choice that we made.  
It has nothing to do with you.”
 
So why is there a “substantial burden” there?  I think it’s simple: The state 
is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion forbids.  
Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of “responsibility.”  But those notions 
are what they are, I think.  The state can’t say, “Your theological notions of 
‘responsibility’ are absurd,” any more than it can say, “Your theological 
notions about the food God requires you to eat are absurd.”
 
Best,
Chris
 
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
 
Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises:  
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality and 
nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the employer 
here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the coverage in the 
insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally 
hundreds of different types of medical goods and services, of which 
contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or not to use the plan 
for contraception are the result of genuinely free and independent private 
choice and could not reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the 
employer is free to issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no 
uncertain terms that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the 
law in question, that it would strongly urge its employees not to use 
contraception, etc.?  

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's involvement 
in the student's choice of a religious school is far too attenuated to 
implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of the taxpayer whose 
funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many intervening decisions, to the 
religious school's coffers, why should we think there is a substantial burden 
on the employer's obligations of conscience in this case?
 

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Sanford Levinson
Must the prison supply kosher meat (and build a kosher kitchen) or is it enough 
that it supplies nutritious vegetarian food, even though other prisoners get 
meat?

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 4:28 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Chris--  I take it you are arguing that for every religious prisoner with a 
dietary restriction, all of them can prove substantial burden,
but the state may or may not win under RLUIPA based on the state's evidence of 
compelling interest?

Is it a substantial burden where the believer can obtain 50% of the foods 
he/she seeks?  I'm broadening this from the kosher
food context, obviously.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edumailto:l...@wayne.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 3:39 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison doesn’t 
serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, “This burdens my religion.”  The prison 
responds, “No, it doesn’t.  You’re not responsible for the food we choose to 
serve in prison.  That’s a genuinely free and independent choice that we made.  
It has nothing to do with you.”

So why is there a “substantial burden” there?  I think it’s simple: The state 
is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion forbids.  
Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of “responsibility.”  But those notions 
are what they are, I think.  The state can’t say, “Your theological notions of 
‘responsibility’ are absurd,” any more than it can say, “Your theological 
notions about the food God requires you to eat are absurd.”

Best,
Chris

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu?]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises:  
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality and 
nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the employer 
here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the coverage in the 
insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally 
hundreds of different types of medical goods and services, of which 
contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or not to use the plan 
for contraception are the result of genuinely free and independent private 
choice and could not reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the 
employer is free to issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no 
uncertain terms that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the 
law in question, that it would strongly urge its employees not to use 
contraception, etc.?

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's involvement 
in the student's choice of a religious school is far too attenuated to 
implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of the taxpayer whose 
funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many intervening decisions, to the 
religious school's coffers, why should we think there is a substantial burden 
on the employer's obligations of conscience in this case?


___

To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see

http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the

messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Steven Jamar
No.  The logic of the decision could be pushed that far in a parallel universe 
or by faculty like us who may indeed inhabit a parallel universe, but such a 
case is so easily distinguishable from a commercial business as to be 
essentially irrelevant.

Steve

On Oct 1, 2012, at 11:57 AM, Rick Garnett wrote:

 Dear colleagues,
  
 Rob Vischer (St. Thomas – MN) has a reaction – one that identifies well the 
 decision’s many flaws -- to the decision we’re discussing, at the “Mirror of 
 Justice” blog:  
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/10/forcing-a-church-to-pay-for-its-employees-abortions-would-not-create-a-substantial-burden-on-religio.html
  
 As Prof. Vischer reads the decision, its reasoning – i.e., no “substantial 
 burden” -- would apply to a RFRA challenge brought by a Catholic diocese to 
 an exemption-less requirement that the diocese provide insurance coverage for 
 elective abortions.  Do those who have been welcoming this decision agree 
 that RFRA would not / should not protect the diocese in such a case?
  
 Best, R
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Associate Dean
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
  
 574-631-6981 (w)
 574-276-2252 (cell)
  
 SSRN page
  
 Blogs:
  
 Prawfsblawg
 Mirror of Justice
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
 Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
  
 Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
 found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
 compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
 burden issue in the ACA cases.
  
 And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
  
 Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
 substantial
 for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did 
 the failed North Dakota or Colorado
 initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
 is also attributable to the fact
 that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
 match in a number of opposing groups.
  
 The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
 interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing
 the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
 That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate
 substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents 
 (as of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the
 governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part 
 of the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these
 decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.
  
 Marci
  
  
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com
  
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/

Education:  the path from cocky ignorance to miserable uncertainty.

Mark Twain




___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Alan Brownstein
Thanks for your post, Marty. Rick, of course, will have to speak for himself. 
But I don't believe that the independent choice of parents as to how they will 
spend education vouchers should end the Establishment Clause inquiry. And I 
also believe that the government's use of taxes to engage in activities that 
violate the taxpayer's religious beliefs burden the taxpayer's religious 
liberty. This doesn't mean that the individual's religious liberty interests 
should be always be vindicated in these kinds of cases. I support a religion 
clause jurisprudence that defines harm or burden or infringement fairly broadly 
so that claims can get on the constitutional playing field. I would assign most 
of the work in determining whether state action is constitutional to the 
adjudication of claims - not to a decision on burden that cuts off all other 
analysis. (I also think that while some burdens may not be sufficient to invoke 
judicial review standing alone, combined with other religious and equality 
interests they should be adjudicated on the merits.)

With regard to the several factors that Marty lists: To begin with, I would 
rephrase Marty's basic question this way. Is it really fair for religious 
liberty purposes to attribute to the employer here the employee's decision to 
use contraceptives when the employer sincerely believes that G-d prohibits him 
from facilitating the use of contraceptives in this way? I think the answer is 
Yes.

More specifically, as others have suggested, I don't see how the coverage being 
compelled by law alters the analysis.

The fact that a religious believer is compelled by a law to do hundreds of 
things that do not violate his faith does not alter the fact that one mandate 
requires him to do what his religion prohibits. One might argue that a broad 
law creates so many instances in which religious liberty might be abridged that 
the government has a strong administrative convenience justification for 
rejecting accommodations for everyone. But that argument goes to justification, 
not to burden.

As to disclaimers, I'm not persuaded that a disclaimer really resolves concerns 
about complicity with or facilitating wrongful acts. But let's assume that one 
of the concerns here has to do with perceptions of complicity by others. There 
are religious rules that are arguably prophylactic measures. There are rules 
that are designed to remind people of things they are supposed to do. There may 
be alternative ways to accomplish these religious goals. The question is 
whether religious individuals and institutions are permitted to follow the 
rules they believe are required by their faith to accomplish religious purposes 
or whether the state gets to require them to violate their beliefs because the 
state thinks that different means are available and preferable for furthering 
their religious purposes.

For example, one of the justifications for prohibiting Jews from eating chicken 
and cheese (milk and meat) even though a chicken obviously doesn't produce milk 
and doesn't really fit into the biblical prohibition is that people might see 
people eating a chicken and cheese sandwich, not understand that the meat in 
the sandwich is from a chicken, and begin to believe that it is OK to eat milk 
with meat. Obviously, there are alternative ways to avoid this 
misunderstanding.  I don't think that states or courts get to dismiss the way 
that Jewish tradition handles the problem because they think there is a better 
way to deal with the issue.

Alan



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 11:52 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises:  
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality and 
nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the employer 
here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the coverage in the 
insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally 
hundreds of different types of medical goods and services, of which 
contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or not to use the plan 
for contraception are the result of genuinely free and independent private 
choice and could not reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the 
employer is free to issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no 
uncertain terms that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Christopher Lund
To Sandy, the “substantial burden” part of this will depend on what the 
plaintiff believes.  If the Jewish prisoner believes that he has a religious 
obligation to eat Kosher meat, then there will be a “substantial burden” if 
the prison doesn’t provide Kosher meat.  But by having such a broad view of 
what his religion requires, the prisoner creates other difficulties for 
himself.  A sincerity problem perhaps, and certainly a compelling interest 
problem.  I haven’t read many of these cases, but I have read some.  And my 
sense is that if the prison supplies nutritious vegetarian food, no court 
would require the prison to build a Kosher kitchen.



To Marci, to the extent that the prisoner can only eat something his 
religion forbids, that’s the clearest form of a substantial burden.  That 
kind of burden is what the Catholic Church claims here.  No doubt that there 
are harder cases.  The prison provides some Kosher foods, maybe enough to 
survive on, but not enough for the kind of diet that other prisoners have. 
I don’t have firm views about those situations, although I think it’s clear 
that the “government-requires-what-my-religion-forbids” situation is not the 
only case of a substantial burden.



Best,

Chris



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford Levinson
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 4:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Must the prison supply kosher meat (and build a kosher kitchen) or is it 
enough that it supplies nutritious vegetarian food, even though other 
prisoners get meat?



sandy



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 4:28 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Chris--  I take it you are arguing that for every religious prisoner with a 
dietary restriction, all of them can prove substantial burden,

but the state may or may not win under RLUIPA based on the state's evidence 
of compelling interest?



Is it a substantial burden where the believer can obtain 50% of the foods 
he/she seeks?  I'm broadening this from the kosher

food context, obviously.



Marci



Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com



-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 3:39 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison doesn’t 
serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, “This burdens my religion.”  The 
prison responds, “No, it doesn’t.  You’re not responsible for the food we 
choose to serve in prison.  That’s a genuinely free and independent choice 
that we made.  It has nothing to do with you.”



So why is there a “substantial burden” there?  I think it’s simple: The 
state is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion 
forbids.  Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of “responsibility.”  But 
those notions are what they are, I think.  The state can’t say, “Your 
theological notions of ‘responsibility’ are absurd,” any more than it can 
say, “Your theological notions about the food God requires you to eat are 
absurd.”



Best,

Chris



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu? ] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises: 
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality 
and nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the 
employer here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the 
coverage in the insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be 
used for literally hundreds of different types of medical goods and 
services, of which contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or 
not to use the plan for contraception are the result of genuinely free and 
independent private choice and could

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
Steve -- I agree with what you've said. I would point out that you used the term
burden, not substantial burden. My point is that I the contraceptive mandate
burden's an employer's free exercise if they are opposed to the mandate for
religious reasons -- but, importantly, they are not substantially burdened in my
view (as I believe Judge Jackson correctly analyzed the burden). The religious
burden is de minimis and remote. And there is no economic burden as the mandated
coverage is, in the aggregate, is a cost saver.

In addition, I believe a fair analogy would be to the Lemon test's excessive
entanglement prong. Mere entanglement doesn't constitute an Establishment
Clause violation just as a mere burden doesn't establish a Free Exercise
Clause violation here.

Bob Ritter

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty
A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter
Falls Church, VA
703-533-0236

On September 29, 2012 at 11:44 PM Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com wrote:
 Of course the law burdens religious exercise -- if you take religious exercise
 to that extreme meaning. If you choose to take it to that extreme, then you
 cannot be in that line of work or you must pay the penalty for engaging in
 that kind of work.

 You can't simply ignore civil law because you don't like it. I didn't like my
 taxes going to the war in Iraq (and I can think of lots of other things I
 don't like. And I have moral objections to many things, though fewer things
 than those I don't like. And I think torture is violates just about every
 religion out there.

 And yet I must pay for these things I don't believe in.

 The social security cases and other cases were properly decided -- following
 the same economic rules as everyone else when you enter the market place is
 not a substantial burden on your exercise. If you can't do it, get out of the
 market and into something where you can follow your religion.

 Free exercise is not a free pass.

 Steve

 On Sep 29, 2012, at 10:52 PM, Walsh, Kevin wrote:

  The court appears to have recharacterized the allegations in the RFRA claim
  to make it easier to dismiss.
  
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
  [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Marty Lederman
  [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
  Sent: Saturday, September 29, 2012 10:30 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate
 
  For what it's worth, here are the allegations in the complaint relevant to
  establishing the alleged burden on religious exercise:
 
 
  Plaintiff O’Brien believes that he cannot pay for and provide coverage for
  contraceptives, sterilization, abortion or related education and counseling
  without violating his religious beliefs.
 
  Plaintiffs are . . . confronted with choosing between complying with [the
  HHS mandate] in violation of their religious beliefs, or paying ruinous
  fines that would have a crippling impact on their ability to survive
  economically.
 
  * * *
 
  The Mandate coerces Plaintiffs into complying with its requirements or
  abandoning integral components of the Plaintiffs’ religiously inspired
  mission and values.
 
  Plaintiffs’ sincerely held religious beliefs prevent them from providing
  coverage for “all FDA-approved contraceptive methods, sterilization
  procedures, and patient education and counseling related to such
  procedures.”
 
  The Mandate/Final Rule, by requiring Plaintiffs to provide said coverage,
  imposes a substantial burden on Plaintiffs’ free exercise of religion by
  coercing Plaintiffs to choose between conducting their business in
  accordance with their religious beliefs or paying substantial penalties to
  the government.
 
 
  On Sat, Sep 29, 2012 at 9:43 PM, Walsh, Kevin
  kwa...@richmond.edumailto:kwa...@richmond.edu wrote:
  The court's carelessness with respect to substantial burden prevented it
  from facing up to the more interesting legal question re: exercise of
  religion.
 
  I say that the court was careless because its analysis depends upon a
  tendentious characterization of the nature of the religious objection. How
  does someone run a business with 87 employees if his religion prohibits an
  outlay of funds that might eventually be used by a third party in a manner
  inconsistent with one's values? That kind of religious belief would make it
  difficult to gas up a car and head into work, or even just to stay home and
  surf the internet. Maybe, instead, the objection has something to do with
  being forced by the government to pay for a particular kind of policy
  (rather than pay taxes and have the government purchase the policy instead).
 
  In the law, there is such a thing as winning too much. I suspect that is the
  federal government's view of this sloppy decision.
  
  From:
  religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
We have a long political tradition of treating objections to killing as a 
special claim, deserving special protection. We have exempted conscientious 
objectors in all our wars, even when national existence was on the line, and 
notwithstanding powerful incentives to dubious conversions or false claims. 

This protection has not been as broad as objectors would like; it is not immune 
to limitation when government chooses to assert its compelling interests. But 
it received very strong protection that grew stronger over time. 

In the war case, we all agree that draftees may be asked to kill other human 
beings, but the majority says these are lawful killings, and the minority says 
they are killings prohibited by God. 

In the abortion case, the majority believes it is not a killing of a human 
being; the conscientious objector believes it is. The disagreement over the 
nature of the killing comes at a slightly different point; I do not claim that 
the cases are identical. 

I do believe that there are sound reasons, reflected in our legal and political 
tradition, to give special deference to what the conscientious objector 
believes is a refusal to kill another human being.

The cases also differ in the weight of the government's interest; it is almost 
never essential that an abortion be performed or assisted by a particular 
medical provider.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 17:16:55 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
In response to Rick, the answer to the question from my perspective is that a 
religiously affiliated organization (not a church) could be required to provide
insurance that includes all possible medically feasible and advisable 
treatments.  That is a classic, neutral, generally applicable law.


Obviously, abortion is at times a medically feasible and medically advisable 
treatment.  The employer buys an ombnibus insurance plan, and employers, 
consistent with medical advice and their own religious and personal views, 
choose what treatments they obtain.  That seems to me constitutional.  This is 
not distinguishable
from the objections raised by Quakers having to pay taxes that support war or 
the Amish having to pay into social security that supports a set of 
relationships
they believe are religiously wrong.


I'm glad you asked this question, because it seems to indicate that the 
argument against the ACA at base appears to be that the belief against 
abortion is somehow more important than other beliefs.  I don't see how the 
Establishment Clause permits that kind of religious belief prioritizing, or 
any of the free exercise cases either.


No employer should be able to exclude blood transfusions, which are abhorrent 
to Jehovahs Witnesses, from medical coverage. I haven't heard anyone
get behind such an exemption.But those opposing the ACA's reproductive 
health care provisions seem to be suggesting that somehow abortion opposition 
is a superior belief that deserves extra constitutional protection.  


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 1:49 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


Rob's thoughts are well worth reading -- he puts his finger on a bunch of 
questions that are sure to be central to these cases going forward.

One caveat on the equivalence point raised by Rob and Rick:

To the extent the court is rejecting a proximate cooperation with evil 
theory of substantial burden here, then yes, that same theory would presumably 
be subject to the same objections if the case involved a diocese and elective 
abortion coverage.  But the diocese would have a much stronger substantial 
burden argument on a different theory -- one of the institutional autonomy 
theories that Rick referred to earlier.  In particular, assuming the diocese 
exercises its title VII exemption, and prefers coreligionists in employment, 
then I'd assume one of its principal functions -- unlike that of the 
ceramics-processing O'Brien Industrial Company -- is to create and nurture a 
particular kind of religious community, one in which its employees are 
expected to advance its Catholic mission, and to adhere to Catholic tenets in 
their own conduct.  The HHS rule would arguably have a significant impact on 
the ability of the diocese to so shape its community and to ensure that its 
emplo
 yees act
in accordance with Catholic precepts.  In that respect, the diocese is very 
differently situated for RFRA purposes from the O'Brien Industrial Company, 
which hires many non-Catholics and that does not endeavor to require its 
employees to conform their conduct to Catholic precepts.


On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 11:57 AM, Rick Garnett rgarn

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
 that
 this tax money is being used to pay for abortions). But under this approach
 the employer is not forced to violate his or her religious conscience by
 agreeing to subsidize the activity. A few employers may believe payment of
 such a tax violates their religious conscience; if so, they can refuse to pay
 the tax, and the govt can use its normal coercive means to collect an unpaid
 tax. Unless the employer believes that armed resistance is required (consider
 a tax to subsidize slavery), even such an employer’s religious conscience will
 not be violated when the tax is taken.
 
 
 
  Note that there is a real imposition on religious freedom when a person is
 required to agree specifically to subsidize an action that violates the
 person’s religious conscience. This is analogous to Barnette; you can be
 required to pay taxes to support a government you consider to be illegitimate,
 but you cannot be required to agree to support it; you cannot even be required
 to say that you agree to support it.
 
 
 
  Brad is right.
 
 
 
  Mark S. Scarberry
 
  Professor of Law
 
  Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
  Sent: Saturday, September 29, 2012 8:50 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate
 
 
 
  I find the court's argument strong here.  You pay a salary, you pay FICA, you
 pay unemployment insurance, you pay pension benefits, you pay vacation time,
 holidays, and so on.  And you provide health insurance benefits.  Some of
 those who have health insurance will use contraceptives.  Just like some will
 use their salaries for gambling, or fornication, or contraception, or alcohol,
 or illegal drugs, or whatever else the religion of the employer thinks is
 wrong.  Health insurance is a benefit like any other, for purposes of this
 analysis.
 
 
 
  Steve
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
  On Sep 29, 2012, at 11:11 PM, Brad Pardee wrote:
 
 
 
  Second, they state, “[T]he contribution to a health care plan has no more
 than a de minimus impact on the plaintiff’s religious beliefs than paying
 salaries and other benefits to employees.”  The parallel is false, though.
  There are no limitations on what an employee can do with his salary (apart
 from things that are illegal on their own, i.e., drugs).  A health care plan,
 however, is not open-ended.  It lays out specifically what the plan pays for
 and how much.  Certain procedures are covered.  Certain procedures are not.
  Using certain providers will result in a different deductible or copy than
 using others.
 
 
 
  --
 
  Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
 
  Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice
 http://iipsj.org http://iipsj.org
 
  Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
 
  http://iipsj.com/SDJ/ http://iipsj.com/SDJ/
 
 
  A word is not a crystal, transparent and unchanged, it is the skin of a
 living thought and may vary greatly in color and content according to the
 circumstances and the time in which it is used.
 
  Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes in Towne v. Eisner, 245 U.S. 418, 425 (1918)
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 ___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
messages to others.___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
 abortion opposition is a superior belief that deserves extra constitutional
 protection.
 
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com
 
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 1:49 pm
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
 
 
 Rob's thoughts are well worth reading -- he puts his finger on a bunch of
 questions that are sure to be central to these cases going forward.
 
 One caveat on the equivalence point raised by Rob and Rick:
 
 To the extent the court is rejecting a proximate cooperation with evil
 theory of substantial burden here, then yes, that same theory would
 presumably be subject to the same objections if the case involved a diocese
 and elective abortion coverage.  But the diocese would have a much stronger
 substantial burden argument on a different theory -- one of the
 institutional autonomy theories that Rick referred to earlier.  In
 particular, assuming the diocese exercises its title VII exemption, and
 prefers coreligionists in employment, then I'd assume one of its principal
 functions -- unlike that of the ceramics-processing O'Brien Industrial
 Company -- is to create and nurture a particular kind of religious
 community, one in which its employees are expected to advance its Catholic
 mission, and to adhere to Catholic tenets in their own conduct.  The HHS
 rule would arguably have a significant impact on the ability of the diocese
 to so shape its community and to ensure that its emplo
  yees act
 in accordance with Catholic precepts.  In that respect, the diocese is
 very differently situated for RFRA purposes from the O'Brien Industrial
 Company, which hires many non-Catholics and that does not endeavor to
 require its employees to conform their conduct to Catholic precepts.
 
 
 On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 11:57 AM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 
 
 Dear colleagues,
 
 Rob Vischer (St. Thomas – MN) has a reaction – one that identifies well
 the decision’s many flaws -- to the decision we’re discussing, at the
 “Mirror of Justice” blog:
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/10/forcing-a-church-to-pay-for-its-employees-abortions-would-not-create-a-substantial-burden-on-religio.html
 
 As Prof. Vischer reads the decision, its reasoning – i.e., no
 “substantial burden” -- would apply to a RFRA challenge brought by a
 Catholic diocese to an exemption-less requirement that the diocese provide
 insurance coverage for elective abortions.  Do those who have been
 welcoming this decision agree that RFRA would not / should not protect the
 diocese in such a case?
 
 Best, R
 
 
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Associate Dean
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
 
 574-631-6981 (w)
 574-276-2252 (cell)
 
 SSRN page
 
 Blogs:
 
 Prawfsblawg
 Mirror of Justice
 
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
 
 Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 
 Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
 
 
 
 
 Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee
 expressly found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was
 decided on compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any
 relevance to the burden issue in the ACA cases.
 
 And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.
 
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
 
 
 Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down
 substantial
 
 for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither
 did the failed North Dakota or Colorado
 
 initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching,
 though it is also attributable to the fact
 
 that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met
 their match in a number of opposing groups.
 
 
 
 The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the
 interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing
 
 the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new
 standard.  That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history,
 which indicate
 
 substantial burden

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just the 
ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing against 
conscience protections for medical providers.

As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
The salary payments could have been used for anything.

I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the government 
will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is highly 
attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling interest in 
paying taxes.

The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the money 
is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a package 
of services that includes the services the employer believes to be immoral, 
including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer believes 
sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those services and pays 
for those services, and these employers say they cannot in conscience do those 
things.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the
money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)

Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
overcome by a compelling government interest.  For anyone who starts from
that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question.  But I am not
aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the
payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows
that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of
salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful
in the eyes of the employer.

Thus the question here is whether the state ought to take at face value the
assertions of some employers that the moral obligation changes dramatically
when the money is used for partial subsidization of an insurance plan,
rather than for taxes or salaries.  I actually think this is a complex
question, as to which I deeply appreciate the many thoughtful views others
have contributed to this thread.  But whatever the merits of that
distinction, the case is a far cry from compelling the employer to kill
another human being.

On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 7:27 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 We have a long political tradition of treating objections to killing as a
 special claim, deserving special protection. We have exempted conscientious
 objectors in all our wars, even when national existence was on the line,
 and notwithstanding powerful incentives to dubious conversions or false
 claims.

 In the abortion case, the majority believes it is not a killing of a human
 being; the conscientious objector believes it is. The disagreement over the
 nature of the killing comes at a slightly different point; I do not claim
 that the cases are identical.

 I do believe that there are sound reasons, reflected in our legal and
 political tradition, to give special deference to what the conscientious
 objector believes is a refusal to kill another human being.

 The cases also differ in the weight of the government's interest; it is
 almost never essential that an abortion be performed or assisted by a
 particular medical provider.

 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 17:16:55 -0400 (EDT)
  hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 
 I'm glad you asked this question, because it seems to indicate that the
 argument against the ACA at base appears to be that the belief against
 abortion is somehow more important than other beliefs.  I don't see how the
 Establishment Clause permits that kind of religious belief prioritizing, or
 any of the free exercise cases either.
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
About 45 years ago I left the Catholic Church and don't keep up with its
teachings. This being said, it is my understanding that the Catholic Church has
not always opposed abortion. If this true, is long tradition true?

I also take exception to characterizing the Affordable Care Act and/or the
contraceptive mandate as trampling on someone's religion. In a just society,
multiple interests have to be weighed. The employer is not the only person in
interest. I appears to me that those who disagreed with Judge Jackson's
reasoning ignore that (1) employment in a commercial setting is nonreligious and
(2) the purpose of the mandate is to provide health care for women, including
making it on par with health care for men. Like the judge, I find Smith rather
than RFRA controlling.

Bob Ritter


On September 30, 2012 at 11:56 AM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 Mark references a long tradition of religious thought about cooperation with
 evil, and how close is too close -- a tradition that is found in both
 Christian and Jewish teachings (and probably other faiths too, but I know less
 about those).

 This tradition was probably not explained to the court. It may or may not have
 made any difference. Judges have been attracted to no-burden holdings since
 RFRA was enacted, I think because it seems to make a hard case go away. They
 don't have to limit the reach of the government's program, they don't announce
 that some modest government interest is actually compelling, and they don't
 have to admit that they are letting the government trample on someone's
 religion.

 Intense believers in these cases are often represented by intensely believing
 attorneys, and they too often treat the burden on religion as obvious, and do
 a lousy job of developing the issue. I don't know if that happened here, but I
 suspect that it did, and of course I don't know whether it would have
 mattered.

 A substantial secular business as plaintiff likely affected the initial
 judicial reaction to this case. But the reasoning appears to be equally
 applicable to religious non-profits controlled by bishops or other religious
 authorities.


 On Sat, 29 Sep 2012 22:36:44 -0700
 Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Of course there is a long history of careful, thoughtful moral analysis that
 treats the directness of a person's involvement in an action as a key
 indicator of the person's moral responsibility for it. It is not
 idiosyncratic at all for the employer to believe that he or she is being
 coerced into violating religious conscience by being required specifically to
 subsidize an activity that he or she believes is wrong, and, even worse, by
 being required to agree specifically to subsidize that activity by entering
 into a contract providing for it to be subsidized.

 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA 22903
 434-243-8546
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Thanks for the clarification, Doug.  I had missed that particular part of
the exchange.

On the distinction you suggest, I think that the characterization of the
requirement as purchasing a package of services does not fairly describe
what's going on here.  Or at the very least, this is nothing like what
comes to mind when one hears that phrase -- such as the employer hiring a
contractor to paint the walls, install new fixtures, etc.

The Rule requires the employer to *make available* to its employees a group
health plan.  (In fact, not even that -- the employer can instead make a
payment to the government, a payment that Robin Wilson suggested at our
Conference would typically be much *less* than the cost of the employer's
portion of the plan premiums.)  The law does not even require the employer
to pay premiums into the plan, although that might end up being a practical
necessity, since the plan must be one that is affordable to the
employees, which in most cases will presumably not include a plan
subsidized entirely by employee premiums.

So let's assume for sake of argument that as a practical matter the Rule
requires employers to pay a certain premium to the insurance company.  (I'm
putting aside here the serious question of whether the alternative payment
to the Fed changes the burden analysis.)  That premium does not pay for a
package of services *to the employer*.  It pays to partly subsidize (in
part) an enormously wide range of goods and services -- virtually any
related to health -- that will be used only if and when the employees need
them and choose to use them.  (And even then, the employer will never know
which services were used.)

That feels to me quite a bit different from an employer purchasing a
package of services.  Imagine, for instance, that the Rule instead
required employers to pay the same amount of money to a *government* *agency
* (rather than to a private insurance company) for the specific purpose of
funding a government-provided health insurance plan . . . a plan that works
*exactly like the plans in question here*, covering the exact same goods
and services, including contraceptive services.

In the case of such a Medicare tax -- one that these same employers
probably pay currently -- would you describe it as the employer being
forced to purchase a package of services?  Would Catholic employers claim
that it forces them to cooperate with evil in a way that their religion
forbids?


On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and
 exemption from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be
 nothing special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim
 than just the ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement
 pushing against conscience protections for medical providers.

 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary,
 and the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers
 immoral. The salary payments could have been used for anything.

 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral,
 is highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's
 compelling interest in paying taxes.

 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the
 money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys
 a package of services that includes the services the employer believes to
 be immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the
 employer believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for
 those services and pays for those services, and these employers say they
 cannot in conscience do those things.

 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
  Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
 can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
 It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of
 the
 money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
 which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
 abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
 partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
 used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
 contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
 for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
 plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)
 
 Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
 salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
 burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
 overcome by a compelling government 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
The beliefs can be serious and strong. But that alone is not sufficient to make
the burden substantial.

Reminds me of taxpayer standing cases. A federal taxpayer generally doesn't have
standing to challenge appropriations because his or her tax dollars cannot be
specifically traced to the objection expenditure. De minimis. So no standing.

On the other end is Barnette -- where Barnette was compelled to salute the
American flag.

The contraceptive mandate is somewhere in between. The employer isn't forced to
use contraceptives. Isn't even forced to say their use is morally OK. In fact,
as Judge Jackson notes, can even suggest to employees not to use them. The line
unfortunately must be drawn somewhere on the slippery slope.

A lot of what I'm reading on the is blog written by those who oppose Judge
Jackson's decision sounds more like disguised whining than sound arguments that
the mandate imposes a substantial burden on employers with a religious viewpoint
opposed to contraception.

Bob Ritter


On September 30, 2012 at 2:30 PM Berg, Thomas C. tcb...@stthomas.edu wrote:
 Marty,



 The fact that services must be covered in the plan by virtue of legal
 mandate (are required by law) can't be enough to counter the asserion of a
 burden, can it--or even be a significant factor in countering it? That would
 do away with virtually every free exercise claim (I'm only providing
 facilities for an abortion, or I'm only receiving a blood transfusion, under
 legal compulsion).



 You place a lot of weight on the claim that most Catholic theologians say this
 isn't cooperation with evil, and that no one has articulated a serious
 argument that distinguishes this and paying salaries or taxes. I don't think
 those things are true (can one conference show it?): consider, for example,
 Robbie George and Sharif Girgis's exchange with you a few months ago, or
 Mark's argument here about inclusion of the services in the plan language. You
 and others may not find those arguments convincing. But rejecting the burden
 claim based on finding the distinction unconvincing, or on the existence of a
 great deal of skepticism among [Catholic] theologians, can't be squared--can
 it?--with Thomas v. Review Board, where the Court said that Thomas's judgment
 on what work would cooperate with the evil of arms production should be
 deferred to even though other Jehovah's Witnesses disagreed. Courts are not
 arbiters of scriptural interpretation; the court can't dismiss the!
 claim at the threshold because it concludes the asserted belief is not
 logical, not consistent, etc.



 Occasionally you seem to be treating this as a question of remoteness of
 facilitation for burden purposes independent of Catholic moral thought; but
 more often you return (as I think one must in assessing burden) to asking why
 claimants believe this is material cooperation with evil, from a Catholic
 moral perspective. That latter question, it seems to me, falls squarely
 within the restrictions of Thomas v. Review Board not to second-guess the
 claimant's understanding of its obligations.



 Tom



 -
 Thomas C. Berg
 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
 University of St. Thomas School of Law
 MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN 55403-2015
 Phone: 651 962 4918
 Fax: 651 962 4881
 E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
 Weblog:
 http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.comhttp://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
 Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 11:56 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

 My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients! Resending
 without so many cc's. Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

 On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman
 lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week (a
 video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal of
 skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present (some of
 whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference) that where
 an employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance plan on
 compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan virtue of
 legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular heath care
 service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and her physician,
 the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation with evil just
 because some employees might choose to use the plan (unbeknownst to the
 employer) to subsidize the use

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Steven Jamar
So it is just a question of line drawing after all.  
A.  Is it at taxation with taxes paying for things you don't like? 
B.  Or is it paying a salary or wages that will be used by some for things 
you don't like?  
C.  Or is it providing mandated benefits for things you don't like? 
D.  Or is it paying out of pocket for the thing you don't like?  
E.  Or is it being required to actually do the thing you don't like 
(administer the pill, do the abortion yourself)?  

I understand the distinction some want to make, but don't agree with it.  The 
requirement to provide health insurance vitiates the erstwhile agreement.  I 
get that some don't see it that way.  But it is not for the individual to 
decide where to draw the line for substantial burden -- that is a legal 
standard to be applied by the courts and drawing the line in the ACA case 
between C and D above is fully defensible on all grounds, philosophical and 
legal and practical -- though one can curtail the causal link elsewhere for 
other purposes.

Thus the substantial burden is the right place to decide this and many other 
cases, rather than compelling interest and least restrictive alternative test.  
As we have seen in the EP cases, least restrictive alternative can be a 
nearly insurmountable bar since a decent lawyer can always find some 
alternative that, upon reflection and analysis is less restrictive, and there 
is no telling what a compelling interest would be in this setting.  There 
simply are no standards for that yet.  If the court had ruled that there was a 
compelling interest here the same people would be attacking the decision on the 
grounds that ACA's provisions are not a compelling state interest and even if 
they are, the use of ACA to accomplish the provisions of those benefits is not 
the least restrictive alternative because less restrictive would be to have an 
exception granted to religious claimants, even those engaged in ordinary 
commerce as employers.

Steve



On Oct 1, 2012, at 8:01 PM, Douglas Laycock wrote:

 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
 from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
 special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just 
 the ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing 
 against conscience protections for medical providers.
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
 the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
 The salary payments could have been used for anything.
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the 
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is 
 highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling 
 interest in paying taxes.
 
 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the 
 money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a 
 package of services that includes the services the employer believes to be 
 immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer 
 believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those 
 services and pays for those services, and these employers say they cannot in 
 conscience do those things.
 
 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
 can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
 It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the
 money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
 which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
 abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
 partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
 used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
 contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
 for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
 plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)
 
 Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
 salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
 burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
 overcome by a compelling government interest.  For anyone who starts from
 that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question.  But I am not
 aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the
 payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows
 that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of
 salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful
 in the eyes of the employer.
 
 Thus the question 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
On the law we have, the employer buys the insurance policy.  Different policies 
cover different packages of benefits. These employers feel morally responsible 
for the package they buy. 

Of course they are generally entitled to define their own religious beliefs. 
But in any event, that sense of moral responsibility for the package they buy 
does not strike me as at all unreasonable. They are contracting with the 
insurer, and paying the insurer, to assume a contractual obligation to pay for 
contraception, emergency contraception, and (I think) sterilization. 

And of course, many of these plans are self-insured. In those cases, the 
connection is even more direct; the employer is commiting itself to pay for 
these services whenever asked, and it is paying for them.

 

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 20:28:06 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
Thanks for the clarification, Doug.  I had missed that particular part of
the exchange.

On the distinction you suggest, I think that the characterization of the
requirement as purchasing a package of services does not fairly describe
what's going on here.  Or at the very least, this is nothing like what
comes to mind when one hears that phrase -- such as the employer hiring a
contractor to paint the walls, install new fixtures, etc.

The Rule requires the employer to *make available* to its employees a group
health plan.  (In fact, not even that -- the employer can instead make a
payment to the government, a payment that Robin Wilson suggested at our
Conference would typically be much *less* than the cost of the employer's
portion of the plan premiums.)  The law does not even require the employer
to pay premiums into the plan, although that might end up being a practical
necessity, since the plan must be one that is affordable to the
employees, which in most cases will presumably not include a plan
subsidized entirely by employee premiums.

So let's assume for sake of argument that as a practical matter the Rule
requires employers to pay a certain premium to the insurance company.  (I'm
putting aside here the serious question of whether the alternative payment
to the Fed changes the burden analysis.)  That premium does not pay for a
package of services *to the employer*.  It pays to partly subsidize (in
part) an enormously wide range of goods and services -- virtually any
related to health -- that will be used only if and when the employees need
them and choose to use them.  (And even then, the employer will never know
which services were used.)

That feels to me quite a bit different from an employer purchasing a
package of services.  Imagine, for instance, that the Rule instead
required employers to pay the same amount of money to a *government* *agency
* (rather than to a private insurance company) for the specific purpose of
funding a government-provided health insurance plan . . . a plan that works
*exactly like the plans in question here*, covering the exact same goods
and services, including contraceptive services.

In the case of such a Medicare tax -- one that these same employers
probably pay currently -- would you describe it as the employer being
forced to purchase a package of services?  Would Catholic employers claim
that it forces them to cooperate with evil in a way that their religion
forbids?



Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Steven Jamar
I appreciate the analysis, Mark. But don't agree that every religion gets to 
decide where to draw the line on responsibility for remote effects of its 
actions any more than I get to draw the line on proximate cause because I view 
it differently from Anderson and Cardozo.  I don't have to agree that there is 
a difference between my knowing that my taxes will be spent on something and my 
being required to act to provide benefits to someone to do something.  The 
agreement is the same in both cases--required to do something with which one 
disagrees.  The employer buying insurance is no more agreeing to the terms of 
the insurance contract than to medicare funding abortion with taxes.  It is 
imposed in the same way.  Or can so be seen by the government without a right 
of an employer to avoid its civic responsibilities as a participant in society. 
 Free exercise does not mean license to drop out, to not conform to civil law.  

The analogous claim to exemption from providing health insurance by a religion 
is that of a religion claiming a right to conduct human sacrifices -- or where 
is the principled difference?  Both are prohibited from doing something that 
they believe in.  In both cases the civil society has decreed that such action 
(not providing health benefits; not killing people) is out of bounds.  Just as 
this analogy has its weaknesses, so does the chain created by Mark.  Both can 
be distinguished (as Mark points out in his post).  But the distinction is just 
as convincing or not convincing -- depending on the views of the listener of 
what the proper scope of the right to be a unit veto on government policy is.

Some employers don't like unions and think it is against their religion to 
bargain collectively.  Some employers think it is their right to use resources 
in wasteful ways that damage the environment.  Some employers think that 
working conditions with respect to safety are improper intrusions.  Some 
employers think they should be able to discriminate on the basis of race.  Some 
employers think they should be able to discriminate on the basis of gender.  
Some think they should be able to discriminate on the basis of religion.

And some of those employers who think those ways cloak their beliefs in 
religion.  Should those with the religious cloak get treated like it is a 
Potterish cloak of invisibility through which civil society is not allowed to 
see while others must be exposed to full scrutiny and the full force of civil 
regulation?  In most instances, no.  Employers are bound by the same rules 
whether religious or not, unless there is really a substantial burden.  No one 
is making the employer get an abortion (or the employer's decision makers, 
assuming it is a corporation).  Or do we push the idea that a corporation is a 
person so far as to make no distinctions at all, even though a corporation 
cannot really have an abortion?

We make exceptions for religious entities, quite properly, even corporate 
religious entities.  But requiring them to provide health benefits is too 
remote on the causation trail to be a substantial burden.  Indeed, the whole 
argument of being forced to facilitate something as a violation of religion is 
problematic and should be used with great care.  It has no logical or clear 
ending point.

Finally, yes, Mark, I think the employer could indeed be required to pay the 
clinic directly without it being a substantial burden.  Reverse your argument 
and the point becomes clear.  The employer is not doing the act, is not 
agreeing to do the act, and is doing nothing but funding something the law 
requires the employer to fund.  And paying money for something is not the moral 
equivalent of doing the thing, especially when that thing you are paying money 
for is something you are required to do from the outside.  If I willingly hire 
a doctor to pay for an abortion for another, I am indeed not able to wash my 
hands of responsibility for the action.  Indeed, it is my willingness that made 
the action possible (let's say).  But if I am required to do so, then my 
responsibility is far more attenuated.  If I believe in that thing strongly 
enough, then I should not be in business.  And it is OK for society to decide 
where to draw the line.

Steve


On Sep 30, 2012, at 1:36 AM, Scarberry, Mark wrote:

 So suppose the law specifically required the employer to pay directly to a 
 clinic its charges for an employee’s abortion. The employee has an abortion 
 at a clinic, tells the clinic to send the bill to the employer, and the 
 employer then must pay the bill on pain of fines that will put the employer 
 out of business. The employer is a practicing Catholic who follows the 
 Church’s teachings. Is this a substantial burden on the employer’s exercise 
 of religion? Will anyone argue that this is not?
 Now what if the law is changed to require the employer to buy insurance for 
 employees that specifically and only covers abortion procedures?

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Douglas Laycock
Mark references a long tradition of religious thought about cooperation with 
evil, and how close is too close --  a tradition that is found in both 
Christian and Jewish teachings (and probably other faiths too, but I know less 
about those).

This tradition was probably not explained to the court. It may or may not have 
made any difference. Judges have been attracted to no-burden holdings since 
RFRA was enacted, I think because it seems to make a hard case go away. They 
don't have to limit the reach of the government's program, they don't announce 
that some modest government interest is actually compelling, and they don't 
have to admit that they are letting the government trample on someone's 
religion.

Intense believers in these cases are often represented by intensely believing 
attorneys, and they too often treat the burden on religion as obvious, and do a 
lousy job of developing the issue. I don't know if that happened here, but I 
suspect that it did, and of course I don't know whether it would have mattered.

A substantial secular business as plaintiff likely affected the initial 
judicial reaction to this case. But the reasoning appears to be equally 
applicable to religious non-profits controlled by bishops or other religious 
authorities.


On Sat, 29 Sep 2012 22:36:44 -0700
 Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

Of course there is a long history of careful, thoughtful moral analysis that 
treats the directness of a person's involvement in an action as a key 
indicator of  the person's moral responsibility for it. It is not 
idiosyncratic at all for the employer to believe that he or she is being 
coerced into violating religious conscience by being required specifically to 
subsidize an activity that he or she believes is wrong, and, even worse, by 
being required to agree specifically to subsidize that activity by entering 
into a contract providing for it to be subsidized.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Marty Lederman
My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!  Resending
without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman
lederman.ma...@gmail.comwrote:

 For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week
 (a video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal
 of skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present
 (some of whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference)
 that where an employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance
 plan on compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan
 virtue of legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular
 heath care service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and
 her physician, the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation
 with evil just because some employees might choose to use the plan
 (unbeknownst to the employer) to subsidize the use of contraception.

 I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I, for
 one, have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the Rule
 that compliance would result in a violation of religious obligations on
 account of such cooperation.  That doesn't mean there is no such argument
 out there, of course.  But I think it helps to explain in part why
 plaintiffs in most of these cases have thus far not articulated a theory of
 substantial burden based on cooperation-with-evil, and why some courts are
 so skeptical of the allegation of a substantial burden -- namely, that such
 arguments appear to prove far too much w/r/t an employer who does not raise
 a similar objection to the inevitable use of its salary payments and taxes
 (via the intervention of genuinely independent choice on the part of the
 state or other private parties) for numerous forms of conduct that the
 employer deems to be wrongful.

 Doug (and others):  I would be extremely grateful for any citations to
 Jewish or other non-Catholic treatments of this issue of cooperation with
 evil, thanks.

 Mark S.:  You appear to place a good deal of stress on the fact that
 contraception is specifically mentioned in the health-insurance plans in
 question, whereas of course it is not specifically mentioned in the laws
 requiring employers to pay taxes and salaries, even though everyone knows
 that such taxes and salaries will be used in part to pay for
 contraception.  What difference does that specification make from a
 Catholic moral perspective?  To the extent you're suggesting that the
 inclusion of the words contraceptive services in the insurance plan might
 be understood by some observers to suggest the employer's own *endorsement
 * of contraception, I think that is unlikely:  After all, who reasonably
 thinks that any employer approves of all the myriad health-care services
 included in a health-insurance plan?  But in any event, an employer
 concerned about the prospect of such mistakenly attributed endorsement can
 tell its employees in no uncertain terms that the inclusion of
 contraception in the plan is required by law, and that the employer is
 morally opposed to such services and specifically discourages their use.


 On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 11:56 AM, Douglas Laycock 
 dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 Mark references a long tradition of religious thought about cooperation
 with evil, and how close is too close --  a tradition that is found in both
 Christian and Jewish teachings (and probably other faiths too, but I know
 less about those).

 This tradition was probably not explained to the court. It may or may not
 have made any difference. Judges have been attracted to no-burden holdings
 since RFRA was enacted, I think because it seems to make a hard case go
 away. They don't have to limit the reach of the government's program, they
 don't announce that some modest government interest is actually compelling,
 and they don't have to admit that they are letting the government trample
 on someone's religion.

 Intense believers in these cases are often represented by intensely
 believing attorneys, and they too often treat the burden on religion as
 obvious, and do a lousy job of developing the issue. I don't know if that
 happened here, but I suspect that it did, and of course I don't know
 whether it would have mattered.

 A substantial secular business as plaintiff likely affected the initial
 judicial reaction to this case. But the reasoning appears to be equally
 applicable to religious non-profits controlled by bishops or other
 religious authorities.


 On Sat, 29 Sep 2012 22:36:44 -0700
  Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Of course there is a long history of careful, thoughtful moral analysis
 that treats the directness of a person's involvement in an action as a key
 indicator of  the person's moral responsibility for it. It is not
 idiosyncratic at all for the employer to believe 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Marty Lederman
I'm not sure why the existence of a contract would fundamentally alter the
religious obligation question.  But even if it did, the employer is not
required to enter into a contract to provide contraception.  It is required
to offer its employees access to a health-insurance plan.  To be sure, that
obligation might, as a practical matter, mean that an employer might have
to enter into a contract with an insurance company . . . but that contract
would typically not mention contraception at all, let alone include a
promise by the *employer* to provide reimbursement for contraception.  The
employer merely promises the insurance company that it will offer
participation in the group plan to its employees, and perhaps also promises
the insurance company that it will pick up a percentage of the premiums
(not tied to whether any or all employees use contraception).

On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 1:10 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 A very quick comment as I’m running out the door. There is a difference
 between a law that takes money from a person to pay for something and a law
 that requires the person to enter into a contract for provision of that
 thing. Imagine a Quaker being required to enter into contracts with gun
 dealers for provision of guns to his or her employees. Beyond the question
 of directness, a contract is an agreement; contract is about assent.

 ** **

 Mark

 ** **

 *From:* Marty Lederman [mailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
 *Sent:* Sunday, September 30, 2012 9:53 AM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Cc:* Scarberry, Mark; M Cathleen Kaveny; Lisa Cahill;
 lang...@georgetown.edu; Patrick J. Deneen; Tracy Fessenden; Eduardo
 Moises Penalver; John Mikhail; David Luban; Amy Uelmen

 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate**
 **

 ** **

 For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week
 (a video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal
 of skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present
 (some of whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference)
 that where an employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance
 plan on compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan
 virtue of legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular
 heath care service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and
 her physician, the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation
 with evil just because some employees might choose to use the plan
 (unbeknownst to the employer) to subsidize the use of contraception.


 I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I, for
 one, have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the Rule
 that compliance would result in a violation of religious obligations on
 account of such cooperation.  That doesn't mean there is no such argument
 out there, of course.  But I think it helps to explain in part why
 plaintiffs in most of these cases have thus far not articulated a theory of
 substantial burden based on cooperation-with-evil, and why some courts are
 so skeptical of the allegation of a substantial burden -- namely, that such
 arguments appear to prove far too much w/r/t an employer who does not raise
 a similar objection to the inevitable use of its salary payments and taxes
 (via the intervention of genuinely independent choice on the part of the
 state or other private parties) for numerous forms of conduct that the
 employer deems to be wrongful.

 Doug (and others):  I would be extremely grateful for any citations to
 Jewish or other non-Catholic treatments of this issue of cooperation with
 evil, thanks.

 Mark S.:  You appear to place a good deal of stress on the fact that
 contraception is specifically mentioned in the health-insurance plans in
 question, whereas of course it is not specifically mentioned in the laws
 requiring employers to pay taxes and salaries, even though everyone knows
 that such taxes and salaries will be used in part to pay for
 contraception.  What difference does that specification make from a
 Catholic moral perspective?  To the extent you're suggesting that the
 inclusion of the words contraceptive services in the insurance plan might
 be understood by some observers to suggest the employer's own *endorsement
 * of contraception, I think that is unlikely:  After all, who reasonably
 thinks that any employer approves of all the myriad health-care services
 included in a health-insurance plan?  But in any event, an employer
 concerned about the prospect of such mistakenly attributed endorsement can
 tell its employees in no uncertain terms that the inclusion of
 contraception in the plan is required by law, and that the employer is
 morally opposed to such services and specifically discourages their use.
 

 On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 11:56 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Marc DeGirolami
I wonder what sort of evidence Marty is looking for.  What arguments qualify as 
serious arguments?  And serious for whom?  A serious argument is not 
necessarily an argument that one finds persuasive, though that might be the 
standard.  It could instead be an argument that one disagrees with but that one 
finds plausible.  Or perhaps not outrageous.  Or is it instead one which the 
religious claimant takes seriously, even if the court does not?  How should 
one measure the standard for seriousness?

The standard that RFRA sets is not whether a court believes that the argument 
raised by the objecting religious claimant is serious.  It is whether the 
claimant has alleged a substantial burden.  Alleging a substantial burden does 
not require that the court gauge the seriousness of the objector, or his or her 
objection, or the degree to which the argument has achieved theological 
consensus, or its importance or centrality within the overarching system of 
belief.  It does not demand the assent of a selection of theologians.  After 
all, other theologians, at other conferences, surely would disagree with the 
conclusions of the theologians at Marty's conference, but I take it that their 
feelings are also not the gauge by which we measure whether a burden is 
substantial.

One possibility is to demand some sort of pain threshold, as the Missouri court 
intimates, going so far as to suggest (in what I believe is a misreading of 
Wisconsin v. Yoder) that suffering a substantial burden may even require a 
willingness to suffer criminal prosecution.  Putting aside the objection that 
there is of course a difference between a necessary condition and a sufficient 
condition, would the argument become a serious argument if the owner of the 
company would prefer to be prosecuted rather than to comply?  Or to prefer to 
pay a fine?  Or does the seriousness of the argument not depend at all on the 
degree of suffering that the claimant is willing to endure?

Marc

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 12:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!  Resending 
without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.
On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week (a 
video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal of 
skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present (some of 
whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference) that where an 
employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance plan on 
compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan virtue of 
legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular heath care 
service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and her physician, 
the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation with evil just 
because some employees might choose to use the plan (unbeknownst to the 
employer) to subsidize the use of contraception.

I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I, for one, 
have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the Rule that 
compliance would result in a violation of religious obligations on account of 
such cooperation.  That doesn't mean there is no such argument out there, of 
course.  But I think it helps to explain in part why plaintiffs in most of 
these cases have thus far not articulated a theory of substantial burden based 
on cooperation-with-evil, and why some courts are so skeptical of the 
allegation of a substantial burden -- namely, that such arguments appear to 
prove far too much w/r/t an employer who does not raise a similar objection to 
the inevitable use of its salary payments and taxes (via the intervention of 
genuinely independent choice on the part of the state or other private parties) 
for numerous forms of conduct that the employer deems to be wrongful.

Doug (and others):  I would be extremely grateful for any citations to Jewish 
or other non-Catholic treatments of this issue of cooperation with evil, thanks.

Mark S.:  You appear to place a good deal of stress on the fact that 
contraception is specifically mentioned in the health-insurance plans in 
question, whereas of course it is not specifically mentioned in the laws 
requiring employers to pay taxes and salaries, even though everyone knows that 
such taxes and salaries will be used in part to pay for contraception.  What 
difference does that specification make from a Catholic moral perspective?  To 
the extent you're suggesting that the inclusion of the words contraceptive 
services in the insurance plan might be understood

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread hamilton02
The references to Barnett and Yoder are misplaced.  This case is closer to 
Bowen, Lee, and Lyng than to either of those cases.
In fact, Bowen, Lee, and Lyng cases are stronger for the believer, because the 
burden found to be insufficient in those cases is direct 
rather than indirect.


The notion that courts don't find substantial burden, because they are 
rooting for the government, which is Doug's explanation,
is insupportable.  Substantial burden is a legal term of art, not a measure 
of how the believer feels about the burden.  The burden
here is incidental to their religious beliefs, not direct or substantial.  


But let's look at this issue from a broader perspective.  Do those favoring the 
employee here favor the following arguments as well?


Jehovahs Witness business owner should not have to pay for coverage of blood 
transfusions
Scientology business owner should not have to pay for coverage of mental health 
benefits
LDS business owner should not have to pay for coverage for treatments that 
include caffeine 
Evangelical or Catholic business owner should not have to pay for coverage of 
MS treatments derived from embryonic stem cell research


There is no principled way to distinguish these demands from the demands made 
in this case.  


I also would point out that Title VII forbids business owners from 
discriminating on the basis of religion.  Granting the business owner
the right to tailor medical care to his or her religious beliefs strikes me as 
an end run around that principle.   The work place is supposed
to be neutral as to religion.  When the employer can tailor benefits to fit 
religious viewpoint, he or she is gerrymandering the employment
market so that conservative Catholics are going to be more likely to want to 
work for conservative Catholics and non-Catholics are going to 
be more inclined to avoid conservative Catholic employers.  Can businesses 
create an employment universe where their owners impose
their religious beliefs on the terms of employment consistent with Title VII?


Marci






 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marc DeGirolami marc.degirol...@stjohns.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sun, Sep 30, 2012 1:38 pm
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate



I wonder what sort of evidence Marty is looking for.  What arguments qualify as 
“serious” arguments?  And “serious” for whom?  A “serious” argument is not 
necessarily an argument that one finds persuasive, though that might be the 
standard.  It could instead be an argument that one disagrees with but that one 
finds plausible.  Or perhaps not outrageous.  Or is it instead one which the 
religious claimant takes “seriously,” even if the court does not?  How should 
one measure the standard for seriousness?
 
The standard that RFRA sets is not whether a court believes that the argument 
raised by the objecting religious claimant is “serious.”  It is whether the 
claimant has alleged a substantial burden.  Alleging a substantial burden does 
not require that the court gauge the seriousness of the objector, or his or her 
objection, or the degree to which the argument has achieved theological 
consensus, or its importance or centrality within the overarching system of 
belief.  It does not demand the assent of a selection of theologians.  After 
all, other theologians, at other conferences, surely would disagree with the 
conclusions of the theologians at Marty’s conference, but I take it that their 
feelings are also not the gauge by which we measure whether a burden is 
substantial. 
 
One possibility is to demand some sort of pain threshold, as the Missouri court 
intimates, going so far as to suggest (in what I believe is a misreading of 
Wisconsin v. Yoder) that suffering a substantial burden may even require a 
willingness to suffer criminal prosecution.  Putting aside the objection that 
there is of course a difference between a necessary condition and a sufficient 
condition, would the argument become a “serious” argument if the owner of the 
company would prefer to be prosecuted rather than to comply?  Or to prefer to 
pay a fine?  Or does the “seriousness” of the argument not depend at all on the 
degree of suffering that the claimant is willing to endure?
 
Marc
 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 12:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

 
My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!  Resending 
without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
wrote

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
Marty,



The fact that services must be covered in the plan by virtue of legal mandate 
(are required by law) can't be enough to counter the asserion of a burden, 
can it--or even be a significant factor in countering it?  That would do away 
with virtually every free exercise claim (I'm only providing facilities for an 
abortion, or I'm only receiving a blood transfusion, under legal compulsion).



You place a lot of weight on the claim that most Catholic theologians say this 
isn't cooperation with evil, and that no one has articulated a serious 
argument that distinguishes this and paying salaries or taxes.  I don't think 
those things are true (can one conference show it?): consider, for example, 
Robbie George and Sharif Girgis's exchange with you a few months ago, or Mark's 
argument here about inclusion of the services in the plan language.  You and 
others may not find those arguments convincing.  But rejecting the burden claim 
based on finding the distinction unconvincing, or on the existence of a great 
deal of skepticism among [Catholic] theologians, can't be squared--can 
it?--with Thomas v. Review Board, where the Court said that Thomas's judgment 
on what work would cooperate with the evil of arms production should be 
deferred to even though other Jehovah's Witnesses disagreed.  Courts are not 
arbiters of scriptural interpretation; the court can't dismiss the!
  claim at the threshold because it concludes the asserted belief is not 
logical, not consistent, etc.



Occasionally you seem to be treating this as a question of remoteness of 
facilitation for burden purposes independent of Catholic moral thought; but 
more often you return (as I think one must in assessing burden) to asking why 
claimants believe this is material cooperation with evil, from a Catholic 
moral perspective.  That latter question, it seems to me, falls squarely 
within the restrictions of Thomas v. Review Board not to second-guess the 
claimant's understanding of its obligations.



Tom



-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: 
http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.comhttp://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 11:56 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!  Resending 
without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week (a 
video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal of 
skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present (some of 
whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference) that where an 
employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance plan on 
compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan virtue of 
legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular heath care 
service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and her physician, 
the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation with evil just 
because some employees might choose to use the plan (unbeknownst to the 
employer) to subsidize the use of contraception.

I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I, for one, 
have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the Rule that 
compliance would result in a violation of religious obligations on account of 
such cooperation.  That doesn't mean there is no such argument out there, of 
course.  But I think it helps to explain in part why plaintiffs in most of 
these cases have thus far not articulated a theory of substantial burden based 
on cooperation-with-evil, and why some courts are so skeptical of the 
allegation of a substantial burden -- namely, that such arguments appear to 
prove far too much w/r/t an employer who does not raise a similar objection to 
the inevitable use of its salary payments and taxes (via the intervention of 
genuinely independent choice on the part of the state or other private parties) 
for numerous forms of conduct that the employer deems to be wrongful.

Doug (and others):  I would be extremely grateful for any citations to Jewish 
or other non-Catholic treatments of this issue of cooperation with evil, thanks.

Mark S

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Christopher Lund
We've talked about this before a bit on the listserv, and I don't want to
rehash old arguments-although I think I agree with Eugene Volokh's
comments when Marty raised this issue earlier,
http://lists.ucla.edu/pipermail/religionlaw/2012-February/025600.html.

 

But let's assume for the moment that Marty is right, because it raises
another issue.  So let's stipulate that Catholic Church's traditional
doctrine of cooperation-with-evil actually doesn't forbid this.  The
Catholic Bishops' position is entirely new.  It's not a mere application
of the church's old cooperation-with-evil doctrine.  To help us imagine
this, let's say the Church issues the following statement:

 

For a long time, as you all know, we have found abortion immoral.  But
this new Health Care Act has brought the issue to prominence and
crystallized it for us.  We have had reason to consider more deeply
certain particular issues.  And we decide today that abortion is so
grievously sinful that we must change our position on
cooperation-with-evil accordingly.  We today expand the doctrine to apply
in this situation.  We will work out the theological details later; maybe
a wholesale revision of the doctrine of cooperation-with-evil is in order.
But we are convinced that the Health Care Act will cause us to violate
God's will.  That is what matters; the doctrinal details can be worked out
later.

 

It seems to me that this is okay, that churches can change their
theologies, and that they can choose to do theology by adjudication rather
than rulemaking.  Is there a reason why this should be wrong?  Is it
necessarily insincere?  It seems to me to be pretty consistent with the
way human beings reason generally.

 

Best,

Chris

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 12:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

 

My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!
Resending without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman
lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week
(a video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great
deal of skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars
present (some of whom I am copying here, along with some others at the
conference) that where an employer provides employees with access to a
health-insurance plan on compulsion of law; the services in question are
part of the plan virtue of legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay
for any particular heath care service is entirely within the discretion of
the employee and her physician, the employer does not thereby engage in
material cooperation with evil just because some employees might choose to
use the plan (unbeknownst to the employer) to subsidize the use of
contraception.

I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I, for
one, have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the Rule
that compliance would result in a violation of religious obligations on
account of such cooperation.  That doesn't mean there is no such
argument out there, of course.  But I think it helps to explain in part
why plaintiffs in most of these cases have thus far not articulated a
theory of substantial burden based on cooperation-with-evil, and why some
courts are so skeptical of the allegation of a substantial burden --
namely, that such arguments appear to prove far too much w/r/t an employer
who does not raise a similar objection to the inevitable use of its salary
payments and taxes (via the intervention of genuinely independent choice
on the part of the state or other private parties) for numerous forms of
conduct that the employer deems to be wrongful.

Doug (and others):  I would be extremely grateful for any citations to
Jewish or other non-Catholic treatments of this issue of cooperation with
evil, thanks. 

Mark S.:  You appear to place a good deal of stress on the fact that
contraception is specifically mentioned in the health-insurance plans in
question, whereas of course it is not specifically mentioned in the laws
requiring employers to pay taxes and salaries, even though everyone knows
that such taxes and salaries will be used in part to pay for
contraception.  What difference does that specification make from a
Catholic moral perspective?  To the extent you're suggesting that the
inclusion of the words contraceptive services in the insurance plan
might be understood by some observers to suggest the employer's own
endorsement of contraception, I think that is unlikely:  After all, who
reasonably thinks that any employer approves of all the myriad health-care
services included in a health-insurance plan?  But in any event, an
employer concerned about the prospect of such mistakenly

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Rick Garnett
Colleagues,

I think it needs to be recalled that the cooperation with evil / violation 
of conscience issue is not, in the context of the RFRA and other arguments 
against the HHS mandate, the whole story. Religious freedom, both as a moral 
matter and as a legal one, can be burdened, in ways that call for 
justification, by laws that do not command (what the objector regards as ) 
immoral acts.

Even if, for example, Marty were right that no serious cooperation-with-evil 
argument has been or could be advanced by, say, Notre Dame, it could still be 
(and, I think, clearly is) the case that the mandate burdens, say, Notre Dame's 
legally protected religious freedom rights

Best, Rick

(Sorry for the iPhone).

Sent from my iPhone

On Sep 30, 2012, at 2:39 PM, Christopher Lund 
l...@wayne.edumailto:l...@wayne.edu wrote:

We’ve talked about this before a bit on the listserv, and I don’t want to 
rehash old arguments—although I think I agree with Eugene Volokh’s comments 
when Marty raised this issue earlier, 
http://lists.ucla.edu/pipermail/religionlaw/2012-February/025600.html.

But let’s assume for the moment that Marty is right, because it raises another 
issue.  So let’s stipulate that Catholic Church’s traditional doctrine of 
cooperation-with-evil actually doesn’t forbid this.  The Catholic Bishops’ 
position is entirely new.  It’s not a mere application of the church’s old 
cooperation-with-evil doctrine.  To help us imagine this, let’s say the Church 
issues the following statement:

For a long time, as you all know, we have found abortion immoral.  But this new 
Health Care Act has brought the issue to prominence and crystallized it for us. 
 We have had reason to consider more deeply certain particular issues.  And we 
decide today that abortion is so grievously sinful that we must change our 
position on cooperation-with-evil accordingly.  We today expand the doctrine to 
apply in this situation.  We will work out the theological details later; maybe 
a wholesale revision of the doctrine of cooperation-with-evil is in order.  But 
we are convinced that the Health Care Act will cause us to violate God’s will.  
That is what matters; the doctrinal details can be worked out later.

It seems to me that this is okay, that churches can change their theologies, 
and that they can choose to do theology by adjudication rather than rulemaking. 
 Is there a reason why this should be wrong?  Is it necessarily insincere?  It 
seems to me to be pretty consistent with the way human beings reason generally.

Best,
Chris

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 12:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!  Resending 
without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.
On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week (a 
video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal of 
skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present (some of 
whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference) that where an 
employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance plan on 
compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan virtue of 
legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular heath care 
service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and her physician, 
the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation with evil just 
because some employees might choose to use the plan (unbeknownst to the 
employer) to subsidize the use of contraception.

I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I, for one, 
have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the Rule that 
compliance would result in a violation of religious obligations on account of 
such cooperation.  That doesn't mean there is no such argument out there, of 
course.  But I think it helps to explain in part why plaintiffs in most of 
these cases have thus far not articulated a theory of substantial burden based 
on cooperation-with-evil, and why some courts are so skeptical of the 
allegation of a substantial burden -- namely, that such arguments appear to 
prove far too much w/r/t an employer who does not raise a similar objection to 
the inevitable use of its salary payments and taxes (via the intervention of 
genuinely independent choice on the part of the state or other private parties) 
for numerous forms of conduct that the employer deems to be wrongful.

Doug (and others):  I would be extremely grateful for any citations to Jewish 
or other non-Catholic treatments of this issue

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Sanford Levinson
With genuine respect to Tom, I don't think that one can really generalize from 
Thomas.  Burger did say what Tom says he said, but it simply can't be the case 
that the First Amendment allows highly idiosycratic religious believers 
effectively to torpedo important programs, especially when there is so much 
incentive to engage in strategic misrepresentation and where, unlike the CO 
cases, the dissidents apparently need do little or nothing more than assert 
their belief.  

And, I confess, I'm just not impressed by the phenomenological differences with 
the pacifist taxpayer, though as a lawyer I know how to construct the formal 
distinction.

Sandy

- Original Message -
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sun Sep 30 13:30:07 2012
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

Marty,



The fact that services must be covered in the plan by virtue of legal mandate 
(are required by law) can't be enough to counter the asserion of a burden, 
can it--or even be a significant factor in countering it?  That would do away 
with virtually every free exercise claim (I'm only providing facilities for an 
abortion, or I'm only receiving a blood transfusion, under legal compulsion).



You place a lot of weight on the claim that most Catholic theologians say this 
isn't cooperation with evil, and that no one has articulated a serious 
argument that distinguishes this and paying salaries or taxes.  I don't think 
those things are true (can one conference show it?): consider, for example, 
Robbie George and Sharif Girgis's exchange with you a few months ago, or Mark's 
argument here about inclusion of the services in the plan language.  You and 
others may not find those arguments convincing.  But rejecting the burden claim 
based on finding the distinction unconvincing, or on the existence of a great 
deal of skepticism among [Catholic] theologians, can't be squared--can 
it?--with Thomas v. Review Board, where the Court said that Thomas's judgment 
on what work would cooperate with the evil of arms production should be 
deferred to even though other Jehovah's Witnesses disagreed.  Courts are not 
arbiters of scriptural interpretation; the court can't dismiss the!
  claim at the threshold because it concludes the asserted belief is not 
logical, not consistent, etc.



Occasionally you seem to be treating this as a question of remoteness of 
facilitation for burden purposes independent of Catholic moral thought; but 
more often you return (as I think one must in assessing burden) to asking why 
claimants believe this is material cooperation with evil, from a Catholic 
moral perspective.  That latter question, it seems to me, falls squarely 
within the restrictions of Thomas v. Review Board not to second-guess the 
claimant's understanding of its obligations.



Tom



-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: 
http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.comhttp://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 11:56 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients!  Resending 
without so many cc's.  Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week (a 
video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal of 
skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present (some of 
whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference) that where an 
employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance plan on 
compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan virtue of 
legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular heath care 
service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and her physician, 
the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation with evil just 
because some employees might choose to use the plan (unbeknownst to the 
employer) to subsidize the use of contraception.

I am hardly an expert in such questions of Catholic doctrine; but I, for one, 
have yet to see any serious argument from those objecting to the Rule

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Douglas Laycock
My explanation was not that the judges are rooting for the government, although 
sometimes they are. My explanation was that a finding of no burden makes hard 
cases go away. 

These cases involve direct regulation of religiously motivated behavior. The 
Court's point in Bowen and Lyng was that there was no regulation of the 
plaintiff's behavior at all. So the direct/indirect point has no purchase here.

It is not at all clear to me that large commercial business should win these 
cases. That is partly because of government interests of the sort marci 
mentions, and partly because the connection to religious exercise becomes 
increasingly attenuated as the business grows, and especially as the number of 
owners increases. But religious institutions should win these cases, and 
probably very small businesses that are personal extensions of the individual 
owner.



On Sun, 30 Sep 2012 14:26:07 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
The references to Barnett and Yoder are misplaced.  This case is closer to 
Bowen, Lee, and Lyng than to either of those cases.
In fact, Bowen, Lee, and Lyng cases are stronger for the believer, because the 
burden found to be insufficient in those cases is direct 
rather than indirect.


The notion that courts don't find substantial burden, because they are 
rooting for the government, which is Doug's explanation,
is insupportable.  Substantial burden is a legal term of art, not a measure 
of how the believer feels about the burden.  The burden
here is incidental to their religious beliefs, not direct or substantial.  


But let's look at this issue from a broader perspective.  Do those favoring 
the employee here favor the following arguments as well?


Jehovahs Witness business owner should not have to pay for coverage of blood 
transfusions
Scientology business owner should not have to pay for coverage of mental 
health benefits
LDS business owner should not have to pay for coverage for treatments that 
include caffeine 
Evangelical or Catholic business owner should not have to pay for coverage of 
MS treatments derived from embryonic stem cell research


There is no principled way to distinguish these demands from the demands made 
in this case.  


I also would point out that Title VII forbids business owners from 
discriminating on the basis of religion.  Granting the business owner
the right to tailor medical care to his or her religious beliefs strikes me as 
an end run around that principle.   The work place is supposed
to be neutral as to religion.  When the employer can tailor benefits to fit 
religious viewpoint, he or she is gerrymandering the employment
market so that conservative Catholics are going to be more likely to want to 
work for conservative Catholics and non-Catholics are going to 
be more inclined to avoid conservative Catholic employers.  Can businesses 
create an employment universe where their owners impose
their religious beliefs on the terms of employment consistent with Title VII?


Marci






 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marc DeGirolami marc.degirol...@stjohns.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sun, Sep 30, 2012 1:38 pm
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate



I wonder what sort of evidence Marty is looking for.  What arguments qualify 
as “serious” arguments?  And “serious” for whom?  A “serious” argument is not 
necessarily an argument that one finds persuasive, though that might be the 
standard.  It could instead be an argument that one disagrees with but that 
one finds plausible.  Or perhaps not outrageous.  Or is it instead one which 
the religious claimant takes “seriously,” even if the court does not?  How 
should one measure the standard for seriousness?
 
The standard that RFRA sets is not whether a court believes that the argument 
raised by the objecting religious claimant is “serious.”  It is whether the 
claimant has alleged a substantial burden.  Alleging a substantial burden does 
not require that the court gauge the seriousness of the objector, or his or 
her objection, or the degree to which the argument has achieved theological 
consensus, or its importance or centrality within the overarching system of 
belief.  It does not demand the assent of a selection of theologians.  After 
all, other theologians, at other conferences, surely would disagree with the 
conclusions of the theologians at Marty’s conference, but I take it that their 
feelings are also not the gauge by which we measure whether a burden is 
substantial. 
 
One possibility is to demand some sort of pain threshold, as the Missouri 
court intimates, going so far as to suggest (in what I believe is a misreading 
of Wisconsin v. Yoder) that suffering a substantial burden may even require a 
willingness

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread hamilton02
So long as an organization is hiring outside the faith, I think these cases 
should not go in favor of the religious organization.
These arguments are religious liberty-creep arguments in that the argument is 
not that the believer will be forced to engage in conduct
that violates his or her beliefs, or be stopped from advocating for his/her 
beliefs.  The argument is that the religious believer feels burdened
when others exercise their religious beliefs with the money or benefits 
obtained from the employer.  This is an alarming slippery slope
in my view.  If there is a constitutionally cognizable burden on religious 
belief/conduct when a nonbeliever uses the employer's money
according to the believer's own principle, the employer is obtaining a right to 
deter and burden (economically) differing believer employees.


Lyng, Lee, and Bowen were not popular among legal scholars when decided, 
generally, but they have not been overturned, and their
reversal is highly unlikely. (I agree with Sandy that is very hard to 
distinguish between the pacifist cases and the ACA case(s).)
I do think they are as close to on-point as you can get, and with the believers 
losing in those cases,
it is very hard to permit the believer to win in these cases.  


The key here in my view is that the religious believers lost the political 
battle
and are trying to use the courts to obtain the exemptions they could not 
persuade Congress to include.  They are not constitutionally
mandated, nor are they cognizable under RFRA for lack of a substantial burden.  
 


Marci  




 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sun, Sep 30, 2012 4:17 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate


My explanation was not that the judges are rooting for the government, although 
sometimes they are. My explanation was that a finding of no burden makes hard 
cases go away. 

These cases involve direct regulation of religiously motivated behavior. The 
Court's point in Bowen and Lyng was that there was no regulation of the 
plaintiff's behavior at all. So the direct/indirect point has no purchase here.

It is not at all clear to me that large commercial business should win these 
cases. That is partly because of government interests of the sort marci 
mentions, and partly because the connection to religious exercise becomes 
increasingly attenuated as the business grows, and especially as the number of 
owners increases. But religious institutions should win these cases, and 
probably very small businesses that are personal extensions of the individual 
owner.



On Sun, 30 Sep 2012 14:26:07 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
The references to Barnett and Yoder are misplaced.  This case is closer to 
Bowen, Lee, and Lyng than to either of those cases.
In fact, Bowen, Lee, and Lyng cases are stronger for the believer, because the 
burden found to be insufficient in those cases is direct 
rather than indirect.


The notion that courts don't find substantial burden, because they are 
rooting for the government, which is Doug's explanation,
is insupportable.  Substantial burden is a legal term of art, not a measure 
of how the believer feels about the burden.  The burden
here is incidental to their religious beliefs, not direct or substantial.  


But let's look at this issue from a broader perspective.  Do those favoring 
the 
employee here favor the following arguments as well?


Jehovahs Witness business owner should not have to pay for coverage of blood 
transfusions
Scientology business owner should not have to pay for coverage of mental 
health 
benefits
LDS business owner should not have to pay for coverage for treatments that 
include caffeine 
Evangelical or Catholic business owner should not have to pay for coverage of 
MS treatments derived from embryonic stem cell research


There is no principled way to distinguish these demands from the demands made 
in this case.  


I also would point out that Title VII forbids business owners from 
discriminating on the basis of religion.  Granting the business owner
the right to tailor medical care to his or her religious beliefs strikes me as 
an end run around that principle.   The work place is supposed
to be neutral as to religion.  When the employer can tailor benefits to fit 
religious viewpoint, he or she is gerrymandering the employment
market so that conservative Catholics are going to be more likely to want to 
work for conservative Catholics and non-Catholics are going to 
be more inclined to avoid conservative Catholic employers.  Can businesses 
create an employment universe where their owners impose
their religious beliefs on the terms of employment consistent with Title

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Scarberry, Mark
In case this was confusing to list members, my quick comment to which Marty 
replied was bounced by the list (because it had too many addressees). Obviously 
it got through to Marty.

Perhaps someone who has more information about insurance policies will know 
whether they list particular matters that they cover, such as contraception. 
The point remains that to require someone to enter into a transaction by which 
the person agrees to pay for an action makes the person more complicit in the 
action than if the govt extracts the funds from the person and pays for the 
action itself. At least, it is quite reasonable to consider the entering into 
an agreement to subsidize an action to be a fairly direct connection to the 
action.

I will also say that the shift from abortion to contraception, as Marty has 
shifted it, may affect our analysis emotionally. Conceptually, there is no 
difference in whether there is a substantial burden, whether the issue is 
agreement to subsidize contraception or agreement to subsidize abortion. That 
is, there is no difference unless we think that abortion should be a bigger 
matter for a religious person than contraception, and that the stronger 
objection to abortion is relevant to the analysis. Now in fact abortion is a 
bigger matter than contraception for Catholics and for just about everyone who 
has a problem with being required to subsidize contraception. [In case anyone 
cares, I don't have a problem with my being required to subsidize 
contraception; I do have a problem with requiring people to subsidize it who 
have a sincere religious objection (which I do not have) to contraception.] But 
the law does not permit us to rely on the strength of the person's religious 
objection - for example, an objection to the taking of human life that is 
stronger than an objection to sexual immorality - to decide whether there is a 
substantial burden. We know that centrality, which is a very similar concept, 
is not to be considered in determining whether there is a substantial burden, 
so there can be a substantial burden even if the issue is not at the top of the 
religious person's list of religious moral concerns.

It shouldn't matter whether we are talking about abortions or contraception, 
but to the extent someone thinks it matters, some forms of contraception are 
considered by some religious persons to cause abortions by terminating rather 
than preventing pregnancies. Lots of us may disagree with that 
characterization, but even if the difference between abortion and contraception 
matters, our disagreement about whether  particular conduct causes abortions is 
irrelevant.

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

From: Marty Lederman [mailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 10:22 AM
To: Scarberry, Mark
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

I'm not sure why the existence of a contract would fundamentally alter the 
religious obligation question.  But even if it did, the employer is not 
required to enter into a contract to provide contraception.  It is required to 
offer its employees access to a health-insurance plan.  To be sure, that 
obligation might, as a practical matter, mean that an employer might have to 
enter into a contract with an insurance company . . . but that contract would 
typically not mention contraception at all, let alone include a promise by the 
employer to provide reimbursement for contraception.  The employer merely 
promises the insurance company that it will offer participation in the group 
plan to its employees, and perhaps also promises the insurance company that it 
will pick up a percentage of the premiums (not tied to whether any or all 
employees use contraception).
On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 1:10 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
A very quick comment as I'm running out the door. There is a difference between 
a law that takes money from a person to pay for something and a law that 
requires the person to enter into a contract for provision of that thing. 
Imagine a Quaker being required to enter into contracts with gun dealers for 
provision of guns to his or her employees. Beyond the question of directness, a 
contract is an agreement; contract is about assent.
Mark
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-09-30 Thread Steven Jamar
As I noted in an article some long time ago, there are (at least) 3 interests 
at stake in employment cases -- society's interest in non-discrimination and 
availability of employment for people; the employer's interest in practicing 
his or her faith in the workplace; and the employee's interest in a job, 
non-discrimination on the basis of religion, and getting the state-mandated 
benefits regardless of who his or her employer is.

If we had a Smith standard in place rather than RFRA, then I think we'd see 
better balancing going on perhaps, though it would be under title VII. I think 
Smith goes too far in not balancing anything and giving the government nearly 
carte blanche -- hence the RFRA response.  But who decides and on what basis 
does one decide when the threshold requirement of substantial burden is met?  
We now leave it to the judges and they do not just accept the word of the 
claimant -- polluting sacred mountains with sewage comes to mind as something 
adherents thought a substantial burden, but the court disagreed.  

Here, the employer is not stopped from doing anything.  He is required to 
provide a benefit same as anyone else who enters the marketplace as an 
employer.  The only burden comes from the employers own choice to (a) practice 
his beliefs in all aspects of his life and (b) to engage in a business that 
subjects him or her to offensive (to him or her) regulation.  This is thus, for 
the adherent, and entirely avoidable conflict and burden.  Unless one is 
willing to say a religious adherent needs to, or must, or is required to run a 
business that is subject to such regulation.

Substantial burden is a blunt instrument.  But it cannot be wielded the other 
way to give rise to unit vetoes in secular commerce.

Steve


-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/

“It’s all about you, using your own mind, without any method or schema, to 
restore order from chaos. And once you have, you can sit back and say, ‘Hey, 
the rest of my life may be a disaster, but at least I have a solution.’ ”
Marcel Danesi, in an interview about his book, “The Puzzle Instinct: The 
Meaning of Puzzles in Human Life.”

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

  1   2   >