Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-18 Thread Hal Finney

I've read the paper more closely and I think I understand it somewhat
better.

The paradox in the paper is actually closely related to the comments with
which I concluded my earlier message.  What they are saying is that if
we are part of a Poincare recurrence, it is overwhelmingly likely that
the past is false.  And worse, it is overwhelmingly likely that the past
is inconsistent; that we were or are on a trajectory that could not be
continued all the way back to the Big Bang.

That is because the entropy at the time of the Big Bang was very low
compared to today, so the vast majority of today-like worlds have no
plausible continuation back to a Big Bang.

The specific example they give is, what if the cosmic microwave
background was 10 degrees rather than 2.7 degrees?  If we think about a
Poincare recurrence in the process of forming, time running backwards,
a hotter than usual microwave background will not cause any problems.
You could still get planets being un-destroyed, life becoming un-extinct
and running backwards, etc.  Eventually you get back to the present day.
And we look around and see a universe that's at 10 degrees.

That's a big problem.  There's no way our universe could have formed from
a Big Bang if the microwave background was that hot.  It means the Big
Bang was completely different, we wouldn't see the elemental abundances we
see today, galaxies wouldn't have formed properly, and so on.  We would
see a world which was inconsistent with its putative past.

Yet we don't.  Broadly speaking we seem to live in a universe to which we
can ascribe a reasonably consistent model of the past.  This contradicts
what we would predict if we lived in a Poincare recurrence, hence we
probably don't.

Now you might say, so what, the whole idea that we formed in this way
was so absurd that no one would ever take it seriously anyway.  But the
authors of this paper seem to be saying that if you assume that there is
a positive cosmological constant (as the cosmological evidence seems to
show), eventually we will get into this de Sitter state, and based on
some assumptions (which I didn't follow) we really should see Poincare
recurrences.  Then by the anthropic principle we should be overwhelmingly
likely to be living in one.  Hence there may be something wrong with
our cosmological theories.

Another point, Tim is of course right that the time for one of these
recurrences to happen is enormous.  The formula they give is
t = exp(S1-S2), where S1 is the entropy of the equilibrium state, which
they estimate as 10^120 for the de Sitter universe, and S2 is the entropy
of the state we are going to chance into, which they say would be about
10^10 for time near the Big Bang.  So this means that the time until
something interesting happens is about exp(10^120).  The authors comment,
This seems like an absurdly big time between interesting events, which by
comparison last for a very short time. Nevertheless dismissing such long
times as 'unphysical' may be a symptom of extreme temporal provincialism.

As far as the de Sitter model, the references I have found agree that
it has rapid, exponential expansion, with no beginning and no ending,
and that it is a steady state model of the universe, which looks the
same to all observers at all times.  However some authors say that it has
no matter, and others say that it has a constant density of mass-energy,
and I'm not sure how to reconcile that.  In this paper the authors do a
coordinate change where the de Sitter model can be considered to have a
constant volume and density, so that sooner or later recurrences should,
well, recur.

Hal Finney




Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-18 Thread Tim May


On Saturday, August 17, 2002, at 11:37  PM, Hal Finney wrote:
 Now you might say, so what, the whole idea that we formed in this way
 was so absurd that no one would ever take it seriously anyway.  But the
 authors of this paper seem to be saying that if you assume that there is
 a positive cosmological constant (as the cosmological evidence seems to
 show), eventually we will get into this de Sitter state, and based on
 some assumptions (which I didn't follow) we really should see Poincare
 recurrences.  Then by the anthropic principle we should be 
 overwhelmingly
 likely to be living in one.

OK, let us assume for the sake of argument that we should be 
overwhelmingly likely to be living in one of these time-reversed 
cycles (which I distinguish from bounces back to a Big Bang state, 
the more common view of cycles).

By the same Bayesian reasoning, it is overwhelmingly likely that any 
observer would find himself in a TRC in which other parts of the 
universe eventually visible to him (with telescopes) are incompletely 
reversed. Let me give a scenario to make the point clearer.

It is 1860. Telescopes exist, but are still crude. The Milky Way is only 
known to be a nebula, a swirl of stars. The existence of galaxies other 
than our own is unknown.

Professor Ludwig calls together several of us friends (perhaps on the 
Vienna version of the Everything List) and outlines his theory.

We are very probably in a recurrence phase of the Universe, where a 
worn-out, gaseous phase of the Universe has randomly arranged us into 
this low-entropy, highly-ordered state we find ourselves in today. It 
took a very long time for this to happen, perhaps 1,000,000,000,000,000 
million years, but here we are.

(Reactions of his audience not presented here...maybe in the novel some 
distant version of me will write.)

All that we see around us, our Sun, the planets, even the gas balls we 
call stars, were formed thusly out of a random rearrangement of gas 
molecules. My young mathematician friend in Paris, Msr. Poincare, says 
this sort of recurrence is inevitable in any sufficiently rich phase 
space.

Now, if this is correct, it is overwhelmingly likely that of all of the 
time-reversed cycles, or TRCs, the TRC we find ourselves in will have 
only reversed time (or created low entropy structures) in our particular 
region of the Universe. In a hugely greater amount of time, even more 
regions of the Universe we will be soon be able to observe would be 
subject to this reversal, but the times involved are even more hideously 
enormous than the very long times needed to create our own TRC pocket in 
which we find ourselves.

So, overwhelmingly, observers who draw the conclusions I have reached 
will find themselves in a Universe where only a region sufficient to 
have built them and their supporting civilization will have the low 
entropy order of a TRC.

Thus, gentlemen, by a principle I call falsifiability, I predict that 
when the new telescopes being built now in Paris and London become 
operational, we will see nothing around our region of the Universe 
except gas and disorder.

And, of course, within his remaining lifetime Professor Ludwig was 
astonished to learn that distant galaxies looking very much like nearby 
galaxies existed, that if a Poincare recurrence had in fact happened, it 
must have happened encompassing truly vast swathes of the Universe...in 
fact, the entire visible Universe, reaching out ten billion light years 
in all directions. The unlikelihood that an observer (affected causally 
only by events within a few light years of his home planet) would find 
himself in one of the comparatively-rare TRCs which affected such a big 
chunk of the Universe convinced Professor Ludwig that his theory was 
wrong, that the new ideas just being proposed of an initial singularity, 
weird as that might be, better explained the visible Universe.

--Tim May (who also thinks the difficulty of time-reversing things like 
ripples in a pond, radiation in general, and all sorts of other things 
makes the Poincare recurrence a useful topological dynamics idea, but 
one of utterly no cosmological significance)




Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-18 Thread Hal Finney

Tim May writes:

 OK, let us assume for the sake of argument that we should be 
 overwhelmingly likely to be living in one of these time-reversed 
 cycles (which I distinguish from bounces back to a Big Bang state, 
 the more common view of cycles).

 By the same Bayesian reasoning, it is overwhelmingly likely that any 
 observer would find himself in a TRC in which other parts of the 
 universe eventually visible to him (with telescopes) are incompletely 
 reversed. Let me give a scenario to make the point clearer.
 [Example elided]

Yes, that's a good point, it seems completely correct.  It is consistent
with the basic argument in the paper, a better example than the one they
gave about the microwave background being too hot.

These kinds of considerations were summed up by Wei Dai in his original
comment:

 This is a variant on the Doomsday argument. The core argument of the paper 
 is this:

 If we live in a world with a true cosmological constant, then the 
 observers whose observable universe is macroscopically indistinguishable 
 from ours are a tiny fraction of all observers. Therefore the only 
 reasonable conclusion is that we do not live in a world with a true 
 cosmological constant.

When Wei writes about universes macroscopically indistinguishable from
ours, I believe he means ones that don't suffer from the kinds of flaws
that Tim describes.  Clearly the vast majority of observers spawned in
time-reversed universes would have the smallest possible time-reversed
region sufficient to generate life, and the rest of the universe would
still be chaotic.  The fact that we observe a huge, complete universe,
rich in structure, which appears to have a consistent history, means that
we are very special and unusual in a universe dominated by recurrences.

I think I see Wei's point that this is similar in flavor to the Doomsday
argument.  The paper's cosmological theory predicts that the vast majority
of observers would see a universe more like Tim describes, and not what
we see.  Therefore, either we are very special, or the theory is wrong.
In the Doomsday argument, the theory that life will go on far into the
future predicts that the vast majority of observers would see a history
very different from what we see.  Again we can conclude that either we
are very special, or the theory is wrong.

I haven't yet tried to understand Wei's use of the Self Indication Axiom
and how there can be a universe model which is supported by the Doomsday
type argument but not contradicted by the SIA.

Hal Finney




Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-17 Thread Hal Finney

 Dyson, L., Kleban, M.  Susskind, L. Disturbing implications of a 
 cosmological constant. Preprint http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/hep-th/0208013, 
 (2002). 

Most of this paper is way over my head.  I need to read the ending much
more carefully in order to understand its conclusions.  But I wanted to
make one point which IMO is really amazing and not often appreciated.
I'm not 100% sure that it applies to the specific model considered in
this paper, but it does apply in general.  I think I got this idea from
the Huw Price book on The Arrow of Time.

The authors use the example of a box containing a gas, which starts in
a low-entropy state with all the molecules in a small region.  Then as
time moves forward the molecules spread out and we get entropy increase,
allowing for dissipating structures to form such as vortices, and in
the general case even life.

Then the gas reaches equilibrium, and all the dissipative states die out.
All structure and order is lost, and in a sense, time is no longer
passing, as far as causality is concerned.  Causal time is something
that only happens when there is entropy increase.

After an extremely long interval, we may get a Poincare recurrence.
(Actually, I'm not sure this is the right term for this; I think a
Poincare recurrence is a more general thermodynamic effect. But I will
use the phrase here to specifically talk about a low-entropy fluctuation
out of a high-energy equilibrium state.)  The gas will randomly happen to
move back into a low-energy state, perhaps even the same state we started
with, all the molecules in one corner.  At that point we once again get
dissipation, structures, the passage of time, and the possibility of life.
This cycle can and will repeat indefinitely.

The authors suggest, applying this concept to cosmology, In the
recurrent view of cosmology the second law of thermodynamics and the
arrow of time would have an unusual significance. In fact they are not
laws at all. What is true is that interesting events, such as life,
can only occur during the brief out-of-equilibrium periods while the
system is returning to equilibrium.

The amazing thing is that this is wrong.  Life and other dissipating
events are not restricted to the period when the system is returning to
equilibrium.  Here is the surprise: these events also occur, to exactly
the same extent, while the system is *departing* from equilibrium.

That is, if we wait long enough for a Poincare recurrence of the kind
described here, where the gas goes into a low entropy state and then
goes through some kind of complex evolution back to equilibrium, we must
pay attention to how exactly the gas goes into the low entropy state.
And given the microscopic reversibility of the system, the most likely
path into the low entropy state is a mirror of the most likely path out
of it.

That is, if we really assume that somehow this gas in the corner evolved
life which then died out in the heat death of the universe, then the
most likely path back into the corner is to evolve life backwards.
We would see the formless void of space begin to cluster together to form
structure.  That structure would include the pattern of dead life-forms.
These life-forms would come to life, and they would live their lives
backwards.  They would grow young and be un-born.  Each generation
would be replaced by its ancestors.  Life would un-evolve back to a
primordial state, and eventually to simpler dissipative structures and
chemical reactions.  The whole clock of the universe would continue
to turn back until it reached the peak of the Poincare recurrence, the
point of minimal entropy, and then it would start to run forward again.

Now, this does not mean that we would see exactly the same path out
of the low entropy state as in; but rather, that both paths would be
governed by the same statistical constraints.  The path out of the
recurrence shows constant increases in entropy which guide its path.
The path into the recurrence shows constant decreases in entropy which
guide it in exactly the corresponding manner.

I know this is pretty amazing; so amazing that I can hardly believe it
myself.  But it follows immediately from the time-symmetry of the laws
of physics.  If Poincare recurrences did not occur in this way, it would
mean that physics had an absolute arrow of time.  We could watch a movie
of a low-entropy state forming and then dissipating, and the two phases
would look different, showing that physics is not symmetric in time.

One more point: during the entropy-decrease phase of the Poincare
recurrence, what force pushes us backwards in time?  Why does entropy
continue to decrease?  The answer is, there is no such force.  At every
point during the recurrence, it is *overwhelmingly* more likely to turn
around and start heading towards higher entropy than to continue towards
further decreases in entropy.  It is no more likely for time to continue
to run backwards during the first half of a Poincare recurrence than it

Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-17 Thread Brent Meeker

On 17-Aug-02, Hal Finney wrote:
 Dyson, L., Kleban, M.  Susskind, L. Disturbing
 implications of a cosmological constant. Preprint
 http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/hep-th/0208013, (2002).

 Most of this paper is way over my head. I need to read the
 ending much more carefully in order to understand its
 conclusions. But I wanted to make one point which IMO is
 really amazing and not often appreciated. I'm not 100%
 sure that it applies to the specific model considered in
 this paper, but it does apply in general. I think I got
 this idea from the Huw Price book on The Arrow of Time.

 The authors use the example of a box containing a gas,
 which starts in a low-entropy state with all the molecules
 in a small region. Then as time moves forward the
 molecules spread out and we get entropy increase, allowing
 for dissipating structures to form such as vortices, and
 in the general case even life.

 Then the gas reaches equilibrium, and all the dissipative
 states die out. All structure and order is lost, and in a
 sense, time is no longer passing, as far as causality is
 concerned. Causal time is something that only happens when
 there is entropy increase.

 After an extremely long interval, we may get a Poincare
 recurrence. (Actually, I'm not sure this is the right term
 for this; I think a Poincare recurrence is a more general
 thermodynamic effect. But I will use the phrase here to
 specifically talk about a low-entropy fluctuation out of a
 high-energy equilibrium state.) The gas will randomly
 happen to move back into a low-energy state, perhaps even
 the same state we started with, all the molecules in one
 corner. At that point we once again get dissipation,
 structures, the passage of time, and the possibility of
 life. This cycle can and will repeat indefinitely.

 The authors suggest, applying this concept to cosmology,
 In the recurrent view of cosmology the second law of
 thermodynamics and the arrow of time would have an unusual
 significance. In fact they are not laws at all. What is
 true is that interesting events, such as life, can only
 occur during the brief out-of-equilibrium periods while
 the system is returning to equilibrium.

 The amazing thing is that this is wrong. Life and other
 dissipating events are not restricted to the period when
 the system is returning to equilibrium. Here is the
 surprise: these events also occur, to exactly the same
 extent, while the system is *departing* from equilibrium.

 That is, if we wait long enough for a Poincare recurrence
 of the kind described here, where the gas goes into a low
 entropy state and then goes through some kind of complex
 evolution back to equilibrium, we must pay attention to
 how exactly the gas goes into the low entropy state. And
 given the microscopic reversibility of the system, the
 most likely path into the low entropy state is a mirror of
 the most likely path out of it.

 That is, if we really assume that somehow this gas in the
 corner evolved life which then died out in the heat death
 of the universe, then the most likely path back into the
 corner is to evolve life backwards. We would see the
 formless void of space begin to cluster together to form
 structure. That structure would include the pattern of
 dead life-forms. These life-forms would come to life, and
 they would live their lives backwards. They would grow
 young and be un-born. Each generation would be replaced by
 its ancestors. Life would un-evolve back to a primordial
 state, and eventually to simpler dissipative structures
 and chemical reactions. The whole clock of the universe
 would continue to turn back until it reached the peak of
 the Poincare recurrence, the point of minimal entropy, and
 then it would start to run forward again.

 Now, this does not mean that we would see exactly the same
 path out of the low entropy state as in; but rather, that
 both paths would be governed by the same statistical
 constraints. The path out of the recurrence shows constant
 increases in entropy which guide its path. The path into
 the recurrence shows constant decreases in entropy which
 guide it in exactly the corresponding manner.

 I know this is pretty amazing; so amazing that I can
 hardly believe it myself. But it follows immediately from
 the time-symmetry of the laws of physics. If Poincare
 recurrences did not occur in this way, it would mean that
 physics had an absolute arrow of time. We could watch a
 movie of a low-entropy state forming and then dissipating,
 and the two phases would look different, showing that
 physics is not symmetric in time.

 One more point: during the entropy-decrease phase of the
 Poincare recurrence, what force pushes us backwards in
 time? Why does entropy continue to decrease? The answer
 is, there is no such force. At every point during the
 recurrence, it is *overwhelmingly* more likely to turn
 around and start heading towards higher entropy than to
 continue towards further decreases in entropy. It is no
 more 

Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-17 Thread Wei Dai

On Sat, Aug 17, 2002 at 04:55:59PM -0700, Brent Meeker wrote:
 I think what the paper says is that when matter/energy have
 thinned out enough so that we have essentially empty space
 again, a de Sitter universe, a vacuum fluctuation can start
 a new universe.

You're not understanding the paper correctly. A de Sitter universe never
thins out to essentially empty space. It thins out to a certain density
and no further (I think because new vacuum energy is created as the
universe expands.) So at any given moment there is always a minimal chance
that the very sparse matter/energy can come together and recreate the
present.




Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-17 Thread Brent Meeker

On 17-Aug-02, Wei Dai wrote:
 On Sat, Aug 17, 2002 at 04:55:59PM -0700, Brent Meeker
 wrote:
 I think what the paper says is that when matter/energy
 have thinned out enough so that we have essentially empty
 space again, a de Sitter universe, a vacuum fluctuation
 can start a new universe.

 You're not understanding the paper correctly. A de Sitter
 universe never thins out to essentially empty space. It
 thins out to a certain density and no further (I think
 because new vacuum energy is created as the universe
 expands.) So at any given moment there is always a minimal
 chance that the very sparse matter/energy can come
 together and recreate the present.

My understanding was from Weinberg, Gravitation and
Cosmology. He takes the Einstein cosmology with
cosmological constant, sets k=alpha=0 and says, In the de
Sitter model space is essentially empty and flat...there is
no matter.  

Maybe by vacuum energy you mean the closed loop Feynman
diagrams of QFT.  However, I think the bosonic closed loops
give a positive vacuum energy, while the fermionic loops
give a negative term - so the speculation is that they
cancel and that is why the (or a) universe can pop out of
the vacuum and not violate conservation of energy. 

Brent Meeker
I am very interested in the Universe - I am specializing in
the
Universe and all that surrounds it.
  --- Peter Cook




Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-15 Thread Wei Dai

- Forwarded message from Wei Dai [EMAIL PROTECTED] -

Date: Thu, 15 Aug 2002 13:28:43 -0700
From: Wei Dai [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: Re: Nature Article

On Thu, Aug 15, 2002 at 12:45:17AM -0400, [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 Dyson, L., Kleban, M.  Susskind, L. Disturbing implications of a 
 cosmological constant. Preprint http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/hep-th/0208013, 
 (2002). 

This is a variant on the Doomsday argument. The core argument of the paper 
is this:

If we live in a world with a true cosmological constant, then the 
observers whose observable universe is macroscopically indistinguishable 
from ours are a tiny fraction of all observers. Therefore the only 
reasonable conclusion is that we do not live in a world with a true 
cosmological constant.

Compare this with the Doomsday argument (see 
http://www.anthropic-principle.com/primer1.html):

If we live in a world without a doomsday in the near future, then the 
observers whose birth ranks are similar to ours are a tiny fraction of all 
observers. Therefore the only reasonble conclusion is that we do not live 
in a world without a doomsday in the near future.

So you should accept the conclusion of this paper only if you think 
the Doomsday type of argument is sound.

- End forwarded message -




Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-15 Thread Saibal Mitra

I think that the difference is that invoking the SIA  does not affect the
conclusion of the paper.

Saibal

Wei Dai wrote:
 On Thu, Aug 15, 2002 at 12:45:17AM -0400, [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
  Dyson, L., Kleban, M.  Susskind, L. Disturbing implications of a
  cosmological constant. Preprint
http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/hep-th/0208013,
  (2002).

 This is a variant on the Doomsday argument. The core argument of the paper
 is this:

 If we live in a world with a true cosmological constant, then the
 observers whose observable universe is macroscopically indistinguishable
 from ours are a tiny fraction of all observers. Therefore the only
 reasonable conclusion is that we do not live in a world with a true
 cosmological constant.

 Compare this with the Doomsday argument (see
 http://www.anthropic-principle.com/primer1.html):

 If we live in a world without a doomsday in the near future, then the
 observers whose birth ranks are similar to ours are a tiny fraction of all
 observers. Therefore the only reasonble conclusion is that we do not live
 in a world without a doomsday in the near future.

 So you should accept the conclusion of this paper only if you think
 the Doomsday type of argument is sound.

 - End forwarded message -







Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-15 Thread Wei Dai

On Thu, Aug 15, 2002 at 11:28:28PM +0200, Saibal Mitra wrote:
 I think that the difference is that invoking the SIA  does not affect the
 conclusion of the paper.

Why do you say that? I think SIA affects the conclusion of the paper the
same way it affects the Doomsday argument. 

It's kind of funny that the authors of this paper is playing the role of
the presumptuous philosopher (in the thought experiment I just discussed
in a previous post), except they're physicists, and they're making the
opposite argument (in favor of the hypothesis that implies fewer observers 
rather than the one that implies more observers).




Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-15 Thread Saibal Mitra

I haven't read the paper in detail, so I could be wrong. Consider the two
alternatives:

1) true cosmological constant

2) no true cosmological constant

We also assume SIA. Is it the case that there are much fewer observers in
case of 2) than in case of 1) ? I haven't seen such a statement in the paper
(but again, I could have missed it).

So, I would say that given our observations of the universe a probability
shift takes place, such that 2) is favored (assuming that 1) and 2) have a
priory probabilities of the same order).

Saibal

- Oorspronkelijk bericht -
Van: Wei Dai [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Aan: Saibal Mitra [EMAIL PROTECTED]
CC: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Verzonden: donderdag 15 augustus 2002 23:46
Onderwerp: Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology


 On Thu, Aug 15, 2002 at 11:28:28PM +0200, Saibal Mitra wrote:
  I think that the difference is that invoking the SIA  does not affect
the
  conclusion of the paper.

 Why do you say that? I think SIA affects the conclusion of the paper the
 same way it affects the Doomsday argument.

 It's kind of funny that the authors of this paper is playing the role of
 the presumptuous philosopher (in the thought experiment I just discussed
 in a previous post), except they're physicists, and they're making the
 opposite argument (in favor of the hypothesis that implies fewer observers
 rather than the one that implies more observers).






Re: Doomsday-like argument in cosmology

2002-08-15 Thread Wei Dai

On Fri, Aug 16, 2002 at 12:26:10AM +0200, Saibal Mitra wrote:
 I haven't read the paper in detail, so I could be wrong. Consider the two
 alternatives:
 
 1) true cosmological constant
 
 2) no true cosmological constant
 
 We also assume SIA. Is it the case that there are much fewer observers in
 case of 2) than in case of 1) ? I haven't seen such a statement in the paper
 (but again, I could have missed it).

You're right, we need to look at the alternative hypothesis. But there's 
not just one alternative, there are several.

1) True cosmological constant, therefore heat death and endless Poincare 
recurrences.
2a) The universe ends soon.
2b) The universe runs for a while longer, then gets reset to a low entropy 
state and starts over. This happens in an endless cycle.
2c) The universe never ends, and life become ever more complex and 
intelligent.
2d) No true cosmological constant, but we get heat death and endless 
Poincare recurrences for some other reason.
2e) The universe never ends, but the total number of observers is a 
relatively small finite number.

I think these exhaust all of the possibilities. A huge problem with SIA is
that 1, 2b, 2c, and 2d all imply an infinite number of observers, which
makes SIA impossible to use. But for sake of argument let's say these
universes do eventually end, and they all have the same (very large)  
number of observers. Applying just DA (Doomsday argument) favors 2a, 2b
and 2e. Applying both SIA and DA favors 2b. So I guess you're right,
whether or not you apply the SIA does not affect the the paper's
conclusion that a shift away from 1 is warranted.

This makes me realize that SIA doesn't perfectly counteract the Doomsday 
argument. DA makes you shift to 2a, 2b, and 2e. SIA then makes you shift 
to 2b, whereas what we really want is to shift back to the original 
distribution so we don't have to rule out 2c.