First, I have been trying to construct proofs that various methods pass mutual majority. So far, I've managed to make proofs for elimination methods where the base method passes Majority (I've mentioned that proof before), for methods that are Smith (really just showing that Smith is a subset of the mutual majority set), and for Bucklin.

This suffices to cover almost all the methods condorcet.org mentions as passing mutual majority: Bucklin, Coombs (elimination with majority), IRV (ditto), pairwise elimination (ditto), Kemeny-Young (elects from the Smith set), Ranked Pairs, Schulze, and Smith//Minmax (all elect from the Smith set).

That leaves Borda-elimination (Baldwin) and Nanson, both of which are elimination methods based on Borda. Borda doesn't meet majority, and so one can't use that proof. However, if there is a Condorcet winner, he'll always have above-average Borda score. This secures the Smith set from being completely eliminated, therefore the Borda elimination methods meet Smith (and hence mutual majority).

This would suggest that, as I've mentioned before, for loser elimination methods where the base method that elect candidates with property X, the loser eliminatino method passes the criterion for all sets that reduce to the candidate with property X when there's only one left. If X is majority, the set property is mutual majority. If X is Condorcet, then the set property is Smith.

-

From investigating the various methods, I've found a semiproportional method based on Bucklin. It seems to often elect according to the constraints of the Droop Proportionality criterion. My question is, does it always do that?

The definition of the method is:

Start as Bucklin. Call each step a "round". A set of q candidates has a support equal to the support of that candidate in the set that has the least support. So, for instance, the set {A, B, C} has support 20 if the individual support of each candidate is A: 20, B: 30, C: 98. At round p, a candidate has support equal to the number of voters who placed that candidate in rank 1..p inclusive, where rank 1 is first preference, rank 2 second preference, etc.

At round p, if there's some set of cardinality p that's supported by a Droop quota more than the number of members we've already elected from it, pick a candidate from that set (use any method you want to decide which). Otherwise, go on to round p+1.

It's that simple.

Let's try it, using the PSC-CLE example:

33 A>D1>D2>D3>B>C
33 B>D1>D2>D3>A>C
32 C>D1>D2>D3>A>B
 2 D1>D2>D3>A>B>C

100 voters, 2 to be elected, so the Droop quota is 100/3 = 33.333^. For simplicity, I'll use the "method of first difference" to determine who gets picked within a set. The method of first difference is simply this: if two or more candidates are tied as far as support goes, pick the one who first scored above the others.

Round 1: support is: A: 33, B: 33, C: 32, D1: 2. No set of card 1 has reached the quota.

Round 2: support is: A: 33, B: 33, C: 32, D1: 100. No set of card 2 has reached the quota. Although D1 has reached the quota, it can't be paired with any other candidate to make a set that reached the quota, and therefore it can't be used yet.

Round 3: support is: A: 33, B: 33, C: 32, D1: 100, D2: 100. D1 and D2 are above quota, but can't make a set of cardinality 3.

Round 4: support is: A: 35, B: 33, C: 32, D1: 100, D2: 100, D3: 98
Now we have the set {D1 D2 D3 A} which is supported by 35, since the weakest candidate in the set, A, is supported by 35. 35 > 33.333, so we can elect a single candidate from the set. The method of first difference says to elect A, because the first round where A had a different score than any others was the first round, where A had the most support.

Round 5: support is: A: 100, B: 68 C: 32, D1: 100, D2: 100, D3: 100.
We have the set {A B D1 D2 D3} which is supported by 68. That's two Droop quotas (68 > 2/3), but we've already elected one from that set, so we can only elect one more. That candidate is B, since it had a greater score than the others in the first round.

All done, and the winners are A and B. The method of first difference may not be very good, but it shows the point.

Does this method (or group of methods) pass the DPC? If not, when does it not? If it does, that's quite interesting, because the method is summable.


If it does not pass the DPC, I think the reason would be something like what I'd call "shadowing". Consider the following situation for single-winner Bucklin, where the set in question is the mutual majority set:

2: A > B > ...
2: B > A > ...
2: A > ... > B
1: B > ... > A
1: C > B > ...
1: D > C > ...

9 voters

At round 2, we have
7: A, 6: B, 2: C

This suggests that {A, B} is a mutual majority set, but it is in fact not so. Shadowing is not a problem in single-winner Bucklin, since it implies that there is no mutual majority set, in which case Bucklin is free to pick whatever it wants. However, in the multiwinner version, one might have a shadowing candidate (that is, one that's picked due to shadowing) occupy the place that the DPC demands should be given to another candidate -- that is, unless shadowing requires enough voters that you couldn't make this work *and* set up other Droop sets at the same time.
----
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to