At that Friam I was talking about the difference between token causation (or
"actual" causation) and statistical causation (or "type" causation).  Here
is a Wikipedia article that may help further the discussion:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Problem_of_mental_causation

 

Frank

 

From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf
Of Nicholas Thompson
Sent: Monday, November 12, 2007 12:30 AM
To: friam@redfish.com
Cc: [EMAIL PROTECTED]; [EMAIL PROTECTED]; caleb.thompson
Subject: [FRIAM] FRIAM and causality

 

"The truth arises from arguments amongst friends" -- David Hume

 

One of my goals at Friam, believe it or not, is actually to get some
fundamental issues settled amongst us.  We had, last week, a brisk
discussion about causality.  I don't think I was particularly articulate,
and so, to push that argument forward, I would like to try to state my
position clearly and succinctly.    

 

The argument was between some who felt that causality was "real" and those
that felt that it was basically a figment of our imaginations.   The
argument may seem frivolous, but actually becomes of consequence anytime
anyone starts to think about how one proves that X is the cause of Y.
Intuitively, X is the cause of Y if Y is X's "fault".  To say that X is the
cause of Y is to accuse X of Y.   Given my current belief that story-telling
is at the base of EVERYTHING, I think you convince somebody that X is the
cause of Y just by telling the most reasonable story in which it seems
obvious that Y would not have occurred had not X occurred.  But there is no
particular reason that the world should always be a reasonable place, and
therefore, it is also ALWAYS possible to tell an UNREASONABLE story that
shows that Y's occurrence was not the responsibility of X, no matter how
reasonable the original causal attribution is.  One of us asked for a hammer
and nail, claiming that if he could but drive a nail into the surface of one
of St. John's caf? tables, none of us would be silly enough to doubt that
his hammering had been the cause of the nails penetration of the table.  Not
withstanding his certainty on this matter, several of us instantly offered
to be JUST THAT SILLY!  We would claim, we said, that contrary to his
account, his hammering had had nothing to do with the nail's penetration,
but that the accommodating molecules of wood directly under the nail had
randomly parted and sucked the nail into their midst.   

 

How validate a reasonable causal story against the infinite number of
unreasonable causal stories that can always be proposed as alternatives.  By
experience, obviously.  We have seen hundreds of cases where nails were
driven into wood when struck by hammers (and a few cases where the hammer
missed the nail, the nail remained where it was, and the thumb was driven
into the wood.)  Also, despite its theoretical possibility, none of us has
EVER seen a real world object sucked into a surface by random motion of the
surface's molecules.  So it is the comparative analysis of our experience
with hammers and nails that would have convinced us that the hammering had
driven in the nail.  

 

            So what is the problem?  Why did we not just agree to that
proposition and go on?  The reason to me is simple: the conventions of our
language prevent us from arriving at that conclusion.  We not only  say that
Hammers Cause Nails to embed in tables, which is what we know to be true, we
also  say that THIS Hammer caused THIS nail to be embedded in the wood.
Thus our use of causality is a case of misplaced concreteness.  Causality is
easily attributed to the pattern of relations amongst hammers and nails, but
we err when we allow ourselves to assert that that higher order pattern is
exhibited by any of its contributory instances.  In fact, that in our
experience the missed nails have not been driven into the wood is as much a
real part of our notions of causality and hammering as the fact that a hit
nail is.   Causality just cannot be attributed to an individual instance.   

 

            The fallacy of misplaced concreteness is so widespread in our
conversation that we could barely speak without it,  but it is a fallacy all
the same.  Other instances of it are intentions, dispositions, personality
traits, communication, information etc., etc., and such mathematical
fictions as the slope of a line at a point.   Whenever we use any of these
terms, we attribute to single instances properties of aggregates of which
they are part.  

 

            Now, how do we stop arguing about this?  First of all, we stop
and give honor to the enormous amount of information that actually goes into
making a rational causal attribution that hammering causes embedding,
information which is not available in any of its instances.   Second, we
then stop and give honor to  the incredible power of the human mind to sift
through this data and identify patterns in it.  Third, and finally,  we stop
and wonder at whatever flaw it is in our evolution, our neurology, our
cognition, our culture, or our language that causes us to lodge this
knowledge in the one place it can never be . single instances.  

 

            Are we done?

 

Nick 

 

 

Nicholas S. Thompson

Research Associate, Redfish Group, Santa Fe, NM ([EMAIL PROTECTED])

Professor of Psychology and Ethology, Clark University
([EMAIL PROTECTED])

 

 

 

============================================================
FRIAM Applied Complexity Group listserv
Meets Fridays 9a-11:30 at cafe at St. John's College
lectures, archives, unsubscribe, maps at http://www.friam.org

Reply via email to