RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Newsom Michael









Would it have been
acceptable during National Prohibition to force Episcopalians, Eastern Orthodox
and Catholics to assimilate by giving up wine and using grape
juice instead in celebrating the Eucharist? Is the use of wine no different
than the religiously motivated practices that you described below? 



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, March 11, 2005 7:02
AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions





It is
lamentable whenan accommodation that makes good sense is turned
down by a legislature. But I see no reason to think that forcing
assimilation of many behaviors is lamentable. Only the most rose-colored
vision of religion thatcan thinkthat it should not assimilate in
many circumstances. Religiously motivatedpractices have included
slavery, the oppression of women, and polygamy. The oppression of
children for religious purposes continues to this day, putting them at risk of
sex abuse, physical abuse, and the suffering and death associated with medical
neglect.











Marci











It's
just unavoidable that the Smith rule, without 
 strong and frequent legislative protection for religious 
 exemptions, will force religious observers to convert 
 outright, to minimize their own religiosity, or to change it 
 to fit the government regulation -- religious people will 
 have to convert, to pass and to cover. I find that
lamentable. 
   
   Chris Lund














___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Newsom Michael
Title: Message









I dont understand the distinction
between across the board and ad hoc exemptions, particularly as applied to
something like National Prohibition and the exemption for the religious use of
wine.



How are you going to know whether a practice
of a religion about which you know, hypothetically speaking, little or nothing,
was significant enough to warrant an exemption?



I dont understand how the
indeterminacy of text renders any reliance on it unprincipled. If that were
true then none of the Religion Clause cases (or Equal Protection or Due Process
cases) could be said to have been principled. Is that your position?



I might agree with you that the founders
would have thought that at least *some*
religious exemptions were not guaranteed. But of course the question that
matters is which ones were and which ones were not, and whether or not the
topography of the domain of freedom from and freedom of religion might have
changed over time.



-Original Message-
From: West, Ellis
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Sunday, March 13, 2005 2:43 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: FW: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions











In response to Prof.
Newsome's questions below, I would, first, simply repeat that my original
question was whether anacross-the-board exemption from valid, secular
laws given, by either a legislature or the Supreme Court,to religious
persons/groups, and them alone, can be justified on the basis of
sometheory orprinciple (other thanthat the majority has
a right to pass whatever laws it wants to pass). Second, as explained in
an earlier message, byan across-the-board exemption, I mean an exemption
from all laws or a large category of laws that is given unconditionally or
given unless the government, on the basis of some test like the strict scrutiny
test,can convince a judge that in any given situation an exemptionshould
notbe given. Third, I am not opposed in principle to legislatures'
granting ad hoc exemptions, i.e., exemptions from particular laws granted to
certain categories of persons/groups,religious or otherwise,who
would be significantly harmed by the application of those laws to them.
Therefore, and fourth, I would not be opposed in principle to churches' being
given an exemption from a prohibition law so that they could use wine in their
rituals. Moreover, although I am not familiar with how essential the use
of wine is in various churches, if I were a legislator being asked to include
such an exemption in a prohibition law, I would certainly be open to being
shown that the harm caused the churchesby the law was significant enough
to warranttheir being given an exemption.Finally, I am not
sure how to respond to your second question because I do not understand its
import. My initial question, stated above, was predicated on the
assumption that there was such disagreement about the meaning of the free exercise
clause that one could not simply cite the free exercise clause as a principled
reason for across-the-board religion-based exemptions. Although I
personally believe, having researched and written on this matter for some years
now, that the free exercise clause as originally understood does not guarantee
a right to religion-based exemptions, if I could be shown otherwise, then,
given my own theory of constitutional adjudication, I would not object to the
courts' granting religion-based exemptions on the basis of the free exercise
clause.











Ellis M. West 
Political
Science Department 
University
of Richmond, VA 23173 
804-289-8536

[EMAIL PROTECTED]






-Original
Message-
From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Friday, March 11, 2005 6:40
PM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions

I have to ask Professor
West whether it would have been OK with him if during National Prohibition no
exemption had been allowed for the religious use of wine. His answer to *that* question will be most
revealing. A second question deserving a response is what conclusions
should one draw if it turns out that the meaning(s) of the Religion Clauses are
contestable or contingent. (His answer to the first question should have
some bearing on his answer to the second question.) A third question is
when did I say that I favored across the board exemptions.
I still dont know, however, what that term means, as Professor West uses
it. As I said before the exemption in the Volstead Act is probably not
across the board.) 












___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Anthony Picarello



Then, with the sole exception of federal 
constitutional amendments, religious groups can expect Establishment Clause 
challenges to their hard-won legislative accommodations: as "blind 
giveaways" if they are too broad (Cutter), as "denominational preferences" if 
too tailored (Kiryas Joel). They may also face separation of powers 
challenges on the (ironic) theory that in providing accommodations, the 
legislature is usurping the role of judiciary.

In 
other words, the unifying theme in this position is not deference to legislative 
acts, but hostility to legislative acts and judicial rules alike if they help 
religious litigants.


  -Original Message-From: 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]On Behalf Of 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED]Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 4:15 
  PMTo: religionlaw@lists.ucla.eduSubject: Re: 
  Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions
  
  As Justice Scalia notes in Smith, the likelihood in this society that 
  such an exemption would not go forward is highly unlikely. It is 
  harmless to others, and the religious entities had ready access to the 
  governing powers that be. That is how the system works -- entities who 
  want to amend the law or to force it to accommodate them before it is enacted, 
  lobby their representatives and every other power center they can. There 
  has never been an era in the United States when religious entities felt shy 
  about such political pressure. 
  
  Marci
  
  
  In a message dated 3/14/2005 2:05:54 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
  
Would it have been 
acceptable during National Prohibition to force Episcopalians, Eastern 
Orthodox and Catholics to assimilate by giving up wine and using grape 
juice instead in celebrating the Eucharist? Is the use of wine no 
different than the religiously motivated practices that you described below? 

  
  
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Steven Jamar
I take it that challenges are improper even if well grounded?  Not all challenges, of course, prevail (Rosenberger).

On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 04:53  PM, Anthony Picarello wrote:

Then, with the sole exception of federal constitutional amendments, religious groups can expect Establishment Clause challenges to their hard-won legislative accommodations:  as blind giveaways if they are too broad (Cutter), as denominational preferences if too tailored (Kiryas Joel).  They may also face separation of powers challenges on the (ironic) theory that in providing accommodations, the legislature is usurping the role of judiciary.
 
In other words, the unifying theme in this position is not deference to legislative acts, but hostility to legislative acts and judicial rules alike if they help religious litigants.

Hostility by whom toward whom?  The ACLU and other groups defend religious people's rights as well as the rights of others, including in schools when teachers, principals or school boards utterly ban religious expression

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW	mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar

Nothing that is worth anything can be achieved in a lifetime; therefore we must be saved by hope.

Reinhold Neibuhr

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




As I have said repeatedly, plenty of legislative accommodations are 
constitutional and legitimate. Blind accommodation, though, (RFRA/RLUIPA) 
in particular, presents legislators at their worst-- deferential to the point of 
being brain-dead, when there are obvious harms to others in the process. 
It's not that legislators have to come out on the side of the third-party 
victims every time. Rather, a legislator that does not question the 
religious entity's request for exemption has sold out.

Marci


In a message dated 3/14/2005 4:54:30 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

  In other words, the unifying theme in this 
  position is not deference to legislative acts, but hostility to legislative 
  acts and judicial rules alike if they help religious litigants.
  


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-11 Thread Hamilton02



It is lamentable whenan accommodation that makes good sense is 
turned down by a legislature. But I see no reason to think that 
forcing assimilation of many behaviors is lamentable. Only the most 
rose-colored vision of religion thatcan thinkthat it should not 
assimilate in many circumstances. Religiously motivatedpractices 
have included slavery, the oppression of women, and polygamy. The 
oppression of children for religious purposes continues to this day, putting 
them at risk of sex abuse, physical abuse, and the suffering and death 
associated with medical neglect.

Marci

It's just 
  unavoidable that the Smith rule, without  strong and frequent 
  legislative protection for religious  exemptions, will force religious 
  observers to convert  outright, to minimize their own religiosity, or 
  to change it  to fit the government regulation -- religious people 
  will  have "to convert, to pass and to cover." I find that 
  lamentable.   Chris 
Lund


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-11 Thread RJLipkin



Isn't the 
attitudeAlan's identifies as "the idea that religious people will somehow 
stop existing" better stated as the idea that religion should be privatized? 
Many who hold the latter view sincerely believe in a robust and well-defended 
area of religious worship, conduct,and _expression_. Indeed many believe 
that such privatization is precisely the point of the religion clauses in the 
First Amendment. This idea contends that it is constitutionally a mistake 
to think that religion should be privatized and (with privatization) have 
(arguably) special protections while at the same time be considered an equal 
regarding governmentalbenefits. 

Bobby

Robert Justin 
LipkinProfessor of LawWidener University School of 
LawDelaware
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-11 Thread Hamilton02



I think it is hard to say any decision is not political, but leaving that 
aside, the judicial decisions cannot be principled, because they rest on and are 
made by unelected individuals who always have an inadequate factual basis to 
assess and judge the public policy at stake. They cannot call hearings, 
enlarge the record at will, or call witnesses to explain what they do not 
understand, or even do not know. They are not contacted by constituents 
and not in contact with the other legislators who are also thinking about 
similar issues and contacted by their own constituents. They are not 
accountable tothe public good or to voters.

Yoder suffered in particular from the myopic quality of a judicial window 
into an important social problem. Years later we learn that the Amish 
children are suffering tremendously, which may or may not be attributable to a 
small horizon generated by inadequate schooling in this culture. No court 
can assess what is the best policy then or now. I criticize legislators for 
failing to ask the hard questions regarding religious exemptions, but at least 
they can ask them and answer them in some depth.

Marci


  Judicial decisions on exemptions are sometimes 
  political and sometimes principled. Legislative decisions on exemptions 
  are nearly always political. 


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-11 Thread Douglas Laycock





There are multiple issues 
mixed together in Marci's sentence about "forcing assimilation of many 
behaviors."

I think assimilation is 
generally a good thing, especially for religious and cultural practices so small 
or so odd that their members have difficulty functioning in the larger 
society. That is of course a controversial view, but I have never 
understood the intense desire in some quarters to preserve odd practices 
anddying languages that communicateonly among a few hundred 
people.

But that is not what Marci says. She is for 
"forcing assimilation." Forced assimilation is very different from 
voluntary assimilation, with a vastly higher cost in human suffering and social 
conflict. Forced assimilation should be reserved for cases where forced 
assimilationis necessary to avoid greater harms. The point 
ofthe compelling interest is to identify those cases.

Douglas 
Laycock

University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX 78705
512-232-1341
512-471-6988 (fax)


From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on 
behalf of [EMAIL PROTECTED]Sent: Fri 3/11/2005 6:01 AMTo: 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.eduSubject: Re: Institutional Capacity to 
Manage Exemptions

It is lamentable whenan accommodation that makes good sense is 
turned down by a legislature. But I see no reason to think that 
forcing assimilation of many behaviors is lamentable. Only the most 
rose-colored vision of religion thatcan thinkthat it should not 
assimilate in many circumstances. Religiously motivatedpractices 
have included slavery, the oppression of women, and polygamy. The 
oppression of children for religious purposes continues to this day, putting 
them at risk of sex abuse, physical abuse, and the suffering and death 
associated with medical neglect.

Marci

It's just 
  unavoidable that the Smith rule, without  strong and frequent 
  legislative protection for religious  exemptions, will force religious 
  observers to convert  outright, to minimize their own religiosity, or 
  to change it  to fit the government regulation -- religious people 
  will  have "to convert, to pass and to cover." I find that 
  lamentable.   Chris 
Lund


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-11 Thread Newsom Michael









The privatization
principle or norm does not get at the problem of religious practices which may
be the subject of some police power prohibition. It really is more a
matter of driving those practices underground and the prospect of turning some
people of faith into lawbreakers, a very real issue confronting the Drys during
their push for National Prohibition, for example. Did they really want to
turn Episcopalian  and Catholic  clergy into lawbreakers. An
Episcopal Journal published some time in the 1910s at least one article calling
on Episcopalian priests to break any law that did not exempt the religious use
of wine, and continue to use wine in celebrating Holy Communion. An
article in a Catholic journal published in the same time period urged pretty
much the same thing. I am not sure what the considered opinion of Jews
and Eastern Orthodox on the point was. But my guess would be that they
would have taken the same position. 



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, March 11, 2005 8:38
AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions





Isn't
the attitudeAlan's identifies as the idea that religious people
will somehow stop existing better stated as the idea that religion should
be privatized? Many who hold the latter view sincerely believe in a robust and
well-defended area of religious worship, conduct,and _expression_. Indeed
many believe that such privatization is precisely the point of the religion
clauses in the First Amendment. This idea contends that it is
constitutionally a mistake to think that religion should be privatized and
(with privatization) have (arguably) special protections while at the same time
be considered an equal regarding governmentalbenefits. 











Bobby











Robert Justin Lipkin
Professor of Law
Widener University School of Law
Delaware








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-10 Thread A.E. Brownstein

There are a variety of answers to this question -- about why religion is 
special and merits distinct constitutional consideration. I have written 
about several of them -- as have many other list members.
But let me add one answer that suggests something of an analogy between 
religious liberty and gay rights. My colleague, Tobias Wolff, in writing 
about gay rights, discusses a dynamic that he describes as the denial of 
the homosexual possibility. What he means by this is that the arguments of 
some opponents of gay rights seem to be predicated on the idea that gay 
people and their relationships don't exist or that they will somehow stop 
existing (or being who they are) if only we do not adopt laws that 
recognize their presence in our communities and their humanity.

I sometimes think a similar dynamic applies to religious identity, belief 
and practices -- what we might call the denial of the religious 
possibility. The arguments of some opponents of religious exemptions and 
accommodations seem to be predicated on the idea that religious people will 
somehow stop existing (or being who they are, e.g., taking their religion 
seriously) if only we do not adopt laws that recognize their presence in 
our communities and their humanity.

But, of course, both gay people and religious people do exist. Laws that 
ignore their existence do not change that reality -- any more than shutting 
one's eyes to the hardships such laws cause makes those hardships any less 
painful.

Alan Brownstein
UC Davis



Prof Scarberry, I'm not sure that I understand your first point below.  If 
it assumes that the majority's religion is being taught in the public 
schools, then the law that authorizes that teaching is not a valid, 
secular law in the first place, i.e., it is unconstitutional.  As for your 
second point, although I happen to think that my own religion is special, 
at least to me, I don't think that all religions are special.  Do you?  If 
so, why?  Even if you do think that all religions are special, do you 
really think that that is enough to justify government's granting 
religious persons/groups across-the-board exemptions from valid, secular 
laws?  Would such an argument appeal to non-religious persons?  If not, 
then isn't the only justification you are giving for across-the-board 
religion-based exemptions the fact that the majority of Americans are 
religious, favor such exemptions, and have a right to get what they want?

Ellis M. West
Political Science Department
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, March 09, 2005 7:50 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

One might ask, why should those who object to the majority's views on 
religion alone be given across-the-board exemptions from the majority's 
views taught to their children in public schools? My third-grade daughter 
is subject to being taught about all sorts of things that I might not 
like. (Not another unit on why we must protect all rain forests ...)


I'm happy that there is an Establishment Clause that has some bite. But 
then I also think the Free Exercise Clause should have some bite. Religion 
is special; the state can't do much to support it, and the state must 
provide some extra space for private expression of it.


Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law

P.S. I'm not in favor of eradicating rain forests, but I feel about them 
sort of the same way Mark Twain felt about Michelangelo after Twain had 
been in Italy for a while.


-Original Message-
From: West, Ellis [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wednesday, March 09, 2005 2:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

Although the issue of whether legislatures or courts are better qualified 
or more likely to grant religion-based exemptions is an interesting one, 
it is not the fundamental one, which is: Why should religious 
persons/groups, and they alone, be given across-the-board exemptions, 
whether by courts or legislatures, from valid, secular laws?  Of course, 
religious persons/groups, like other person/groups, should be able to 
obtain from legislatures exemptions from specific laws that impose undue 
hardships on them in some way or the other.  But why should they be 
granted across-the-board exemptions?  It won't do to say that the First 
Amendment requires such, because that is the issue.  Why should the First 
Amendment be interpreted to require such?  I don't think members of this 
list-serv have ever adequately answered this question.

Ellis M. West
Political Science Department
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-10 Thread Lund, Christopher
I think Professor Brownstein's analogy between gay rights and free
exercise is a very important one.

Kenji Yoshino points out that having constitutional protections for
status but not for conduct means that groups that can assimilate are forced
to do so.  And the pressure to assimilate takes many forms; Yoshino points
out how gay people are encouraged to convert, to pass, and to cover.
Kenji Yoshino, Covering, 111 Yale L.J. 769, 774 (2002).  (Though I'm being a
little loose here, 'to pass' means essentially to lie about one's sexual
identity, while 'to cover' means to downplay it.)

The word convert should flag for us the obvious parallels between
Yoshino's work and the law-and-religion context.  So should the phrase
status but not conduct as it is the rule of Employment Division v. Smith.


It's just unavoidable that the Smith rule, without strong and
frequent legislative protection for religious exemptions, will force
religious observers to convert outright, to minimize their own religiosity,
or to change it to fit the government regulation -- religious people will
have to convert, to pass and to cover.  I find that lamentable. 

Chris Lund

Christopher C. Lund
Visiting Assistant Professor
University of Houston Law Center
100 Law Center
Houston, TX  77204-6060
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(713) 743-2553 (direct)
(713) 743-2122 (fax)

-Original Message-
From: A.E. Brownstein [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, March 10, 2005 6:12 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions


There are a variety of answers to this question -- about why religion is 
special and merits distinct constitutional consideration. I have written 
about several of them -- as have many other list members.

But let me add one answer that suggests something of an analogy between 
religious liberty and gay rights. My colleague, Tobias Wolff, in writing 
about gay rights, discusses a dynamic that he describes as the denial of 
the homosexual possibility. What he means by this is that the arguments of 
some opponents of gay rights seem to be predicated on the idea that gay 
people and their relationships don't exist or that they will somehow stop 
existing (or being who they are) if only we do not adopt laws that 
recognize their presence in our communities and their humanity.

I sometimes think a similar dynamic applies to religious identity, belief 
and practices -- what we might call the denial of the religious 
possibility. The arguments of some opponents of religious exemptions and 
accommodations seem to be predicated on the idea that religious people will 
somehow stop existing (or being who they are, e.g., taking their religion 
seriously) if only we do not adopt laws that recognize their presence in 
our communities and their humanity.

But, of course, both gay people and religious people do exist. Laws that 
ignore their existence do not change that reality -- any more than shutting 
one's eyes to the hardships such laws cause makes those hardships any less 
painful.

Alan Brownstein
UC Davis






Prof Scarberry, I'm not sure that I understand your first point below.  If 
it assumes that the majority's religion is being taught in the public 
schools, then the law that authorizes that teaching is not a valid, 
secular law in the first place, i.e., it is unconstitutional.  As for your 
second point, although I happen to think that my own religion is special, 
at least to me, I don't think that all religions are special.  Do you?  If 
so, why?  Even if you do think that all religions are special, do you 
really think that that is enough to justify government's granting 
religious persons/groups across-the-board exemptions from valid, secular 
laws?  Would such an argument appeal to non-religious persons?  If not, 
then isn't the only justification you are giving for across-the-board 
religion-based exemptions the fact that the majority of Americans are 
religious, favor such exemptions, and have a right to get what they want?

Ellis M. West
Political Science Department
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, March 09, 2005 7:50 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

One might ask, why should those who object to the majority's views on 
religion alone be given across-the-board exemptions from the majority's 
views taught to their children in public schools? My third-grade daughter 
is subject to being taught about all sorts of things that I might not 
like. (Not another unit on why we must protect all rain forests ...)



I'm happy that there is an Establishment Clause that has some bite. But 
then I also think the Free Exercise Clause should have some bite. Religion 
is special; the state can't do much

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-10 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Any thoughts on how this analysis applies to Bob Jones
University, which was in fact required to change its religiosity -- or
at least to violate its felt religious obligations -- to fit the
government regulation?  Or to the various landlords to whom marital
status housing discrimination law has been applied?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Lund, Christopher 
 Sent: Thursday, March 10, 2005 6:44 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions
 
 
   I think Professor Brownstein's analogy between gay 
 rights and free exercise is a very important one.
 
   Kenji Yoshino points out that having constitutional 
 protections for status but not for conduct means that groups 
 that can assimilate are forced to do so.  And the pressure to 
 assimilate takes many forms; Yoshino points out how gay 
 people are encouraged to convert, to pass, and to cover. 
 Kenji Yoshino, Covering, 111 Yale L.J. 769, 774 (2002).  
 (Though I'm being a little loose here, 'to pass' means 
 essentially to lie about one's sexual identity, while 'to 
 cover' means to downplay it.)
 
   The word convert should flag for us the obvious 
 parallels between Yoshino's work and the law-and-religion 
 context.  So should the phrase status but not conduct as it 
 is the rule of Employment Division v. Smith.
 

   It's just unavoidable that the Smith rule, without 
 strong and frequent legislative protection for religious 
 exemptions, will force religious observers to convert 
 outright, to minimize their own religiosity, or to change it 
 to fit the government regulation -- religious people will 
 have to convert, to pass and to cover.  I find that lamentable. 
   
   Chris Lund
 
 Christopher C. Lund
 Visiting Assistant Professor
 University of Houston Law Center
 100 Law Center
 Houston, TX  77204-6060
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 (713) 743-2553 (direct)
 (713) 743-2122 (fax)
 
 -Original Message-
 From: A.E. Brownstein [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Thursday, March 10, 2005 6:12 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions
 
 
 There are a variety of answers to this question -- about why 
 religion 
 is
 special and merits distinct constitutional consideration. I 
 have written 
 about several of them -- as have many other list members.
 
 But let me add one answer that suggests something of an 
 analogy between 
 religious liberty and gay rights. My colleague, Tobias Wolff, 
 in writing 
 about gay rights, discusses a dynamic that he describes as 
 the denial of 
 the homosexual possibility. What he means by this is that 
 the arguments of 
 some opponents of gay rights seem to be predicated on the 
 idea that gay 
 people and their relationships don't exist or that they will 
 somehow stop 
 existing (or being who they are) if only we do not adopt laws that 
 recognize their presence in our communities and their humanity.
 
 I sometimes think a similar dynamic applies to religious 
 identity, belief 
 and practices -- what we might call the denial of the religious 
 possibility. The arguments of some opponents of religious 
 exemptions and 
 accommodations seem to be predicated on the idea that 
 religious people will 
 somehow stop existing (or being who they are, e.g., taking 
 their religion 
 seriously) if only we do not adopt laws that recognize their 
 presence in 
 our communities and their humanity.
 
 But, of course, both gay people and religious people do 
 exist. Laws that 
 ignore their existence do not change that reality -- any more 
 than shutting 
 one's eyes to the hardships such laws cause makes those 
 hardships any less 
 painful.
 
 Alan Brownstein
 UC Davis
 
 
 
 
 
 
 Prof Scarberry, I'm not sure that I understand your first 
 point below.  
 If
 it assumes that the majority's religion is being taught in 
 the public 
 schools, then the law that authorizes that teaching is not a valid, 
 secular law in the first place, i.e., it is 
 unconstitutional.  As for your 
 second point, although I happen to think that my own 
 religion is special, 
 at least to me, I don't think that all religions are 
 special.  Do you?  If 
 so, why?  Even if you do think that all religions are 
 special, do you 
 really think that that is enough to justify government's granting 
 religious persons/groups across-the-board exemptions from 
 valid, secular 
 laws?  Would such an argument appeal to non-religious 
 persons?  If not, 
 then isn't the only justification you are giving for 
 across-the-board 
 religion-based exemptions the fact that the majority of 
 Americans are 
 religious, favor such exemptions, and have a right to get 
 what they want?
 
 Ellis M. West
 Political Science Department
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-10 Thread Douglas Laycock
Bob Jones was forced to abandon or violate a religious belief.  Given the 
unique history of race in this country, given the importance of education, the 
centrality of the effort to desegregate public schools, and the percentage of 
the education market filled by segregation academies and other private schools 
in the South, probably there was a compelling interest in Bob Jones.  Certainly 
there was a compelling interest in the companion case, which involved K-12; 
private schools to avoid desegregation were much more of a problem in K-12 than 
in colleges and universities.
 
The landlords in the marital status cases are forced to abandon a more central 
and credible religious belief.  But in none of those cases has there been the 
slightest evidence that any unmarried couple actually had any difficulty 
finding housing.  Until such evidence emerges, the claim of compelling interest 
is frivolous.  Unmarried sex has quite properly been deregulated, and even 
constitutionally protected; the religious objection to unmarried sex is also 
constitutionally protected.  This is such an easy case of letting both sides 
live their own lives in peace, but the anti-religious liberty side is unwilling 
to accept that.  Religious landlords must be forced to provide the bedrooms 
whatever their beliefs.  
 
 
 
Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
512-232-1341
512-471-6988 (fax)



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thu 3/10/2005 9:24 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions



Any thoughts on how this analysis applies to Bob Jones
University, which was in fact required to change its religiosity -- or
at least to violate its felt religious obligations -- to fit the
government regulation?  Or to the various landlords to whom marital
status housing discrimination law has been applied?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
 Lund, Christopher
 Sent: Thursday, March 10, 2005 6:44 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions


   I think Professor Brownstein's analogy between gay
 rights and free exercise is a very important one.

   Kenji Yoshino points out that having constitutional
 protections for status but not for conduct means that groups
 that can assimilate are forced to do so.  And the pressure to
 assimilate takes many forms; Yoshino points out how gay
 people are encouraged to convert, to pass, and to cover.
 Kenji Yoshino, Covering, 111 Yale L.J. 769, 774 (2002). 
 (Though I'm being a little loose here, 'to pass' means
 essentially to lie about one's sexual identity, while 'to
 cover' means to downplay it.)

   The word convert should flag for us the obvious
 parallels between Yoshino's work and the law-and-religion
 context.  So should the phrase status but not conduct as it
 is the rule of Employment Division v. Smith.


   It's just unavoidable that the Smith rule, without
 strong and frequent legislative protection for religious
 exemptions, will force religious observers to convert
 outright, to minimize their own religiosity, or to change it
 to fit the government regulation -- religious people will
 have to convert, to pass and to cover.  I find that lamentable.
  
   Chris Lund

 Christopher C. Lund
 Visiting Assistant Professor
 University of Houston Law Center
 100 Law Center
 Houston, TX  77204-6060
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 (713) 743-2553 (direct)
 (713) 743-2122 (fax)

 -Original Message-
 From: A.E. Brownstein [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Thursday, March 10, 2005 6:12 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions


 There are a variety of answers to this question -- about why
 religion
 is
 special and merits distinct constitutional consideration. I
 have written
 about several of them -- as have many other list members.

 But let me add one answer that suggests something of an
 analogy between
 religious liberty and gay rights. My colleague, Tobias Wolff,
 in writing
 about gay rights, discusses a dynamic that he describes as
 the denial of
 the homosexual possibility. What he means by this is that
 the arguments of
 some opponents of gay rights seem to be predicated on the
 idea that gay
 people and their relationships don't exist or that they will
 somehow stop
 existing (or being who they are) if only we do not adopt laws that
 recognize their presence in our communities and their humanity.

 I sometimes think a similar dynamic applies to religious
 identity, belief
 and practices -- what we might call the denial of the religious
 possibility. The arguments of some opponents of religious
 exemptions and
 accommodations seem to be predicated on the idea that
 religious people will
 somehow stop

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-09 Thread West, Ellis
I asked one of my colleagues who is a student of the legislative process
to comment on Prof. Brownstein's view of law-making (see below).  Here
is what he had to say:

Ellis: There is plenty of literature on this subject, from the
standpoint of interest groups and legislative decision making. For lack
of a better term, Brownstein accepts a rational choice view of the
legislative process, whereby costs and benefits are calculated for
maximum effect and that a benefit often comes at a price, and frequent
investors in the capital of decision makers are compensated. This
process of trades certainly goes on, particularly on low salience issues
such as the sort of contracts described by the local government
official. But the process is not completely void of deliberation and
most projects that are awarded are meritorious in the first place. The
fact that a political supporter was awarded a project does not mean that
the award itself was based solely or even principally on the capital.
Providing capital is a necessary, but not a sufficient condition for
reward. Indeed, many studies of interest group influence, using PAC
contributions as the group's measure of influence, do not show the quid
pro quo described in the story below. Some studies do show that PAC
giving effects legislative outputs, others do not (again the literature
is fairly extensive). Moreover, once the decision making process gets
beyond the calculation of individual members, larger contextual forces
come into play: party, bicameralism, roles of competing groups,
leadership, and electoral constituency. Moreover, other studies (perhaps
Bessette's extensive analysis of case studies done on congressional
decision making is the most prominent) show that legislation is often
the process of deliberation rather than simply exchanging favors. 

So, to summarize. Yes, it happens, but the extent to which it happens
depends on the issue; the causal connection between a favor and a
benefits is murky; and there is some debate over the extent to which
legislation generally is a product of bargaining over costs and benefits
as opposed to deliberation. I don't know enough about how religious
groups operate and how they would figure into this scheme, but I will
try to find out. DP

Daniel J. Palazzolo
Associate Professor of Political Science
Coordinator of the DC Initiative
University of Richmond
Richmond, VA 23173
804 289-8973

Ellis M. West
Political Science Department
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
[EMAIL PROTECTED]


-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of A.E. Brownstein
Sent: Tuesday, March 08, 2005 1:28 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions


To follow up on Doug's point, one of the problem's I have with Marci's 
arguments about judicial exemptions and legislative accommodations is
that 
it sometimes appears as if Marci views religious groups seeking
legislative 
accommodations or constitutionally mandated exemptions as self
interested 
actors concerned only with their own well being while she views
legislative 
and administrative bodies as principled seekers and defenders of the
public 
good.

Many of us see legislative and administrative decisions differently.
These 
are often political responses to various self interested constituencies
-- 
some of whose goals conflict with those of particular religious 
communities. Religious groups have learned to play that game because it
is 
the only game in town -- and some have gotten pretty good at it. But not

all religious groups have sufficient political capital in every
community 
in which they live to protect their interests. Moreover, in many cases, 
there is no reason to think that a religious accommodation protecting a 
religious group's ability to practice its faith is less related to the 
public good than a decision to reject the accommodation in order to
further 
the interests of other constituencies with conflicting interests. When 
fundamental rights are at stake, I, and others, are less inclined to
accept 
this kind of political interest balancing without some judicial
supervision.

To use RLUIPA as an example, in the land use regulation process, in many

disputes, there are often specific groups whose personal interests
conflict 
with the development needs of a religious congregation. The resulting
land 
use decision will often reflect a political evaluation of the competing 
interest groups more than it does a principled promotion of the public 
good. In the prison context, in California, an association representing 
state correctional officers is a major political player that often
opposes 
religious accommodations in prisons. Government attention to this 
association's demands on many issues is at least as likely to be 
politically motivated as principled.

I have a very close acquaintance who has spent 30 years working in local

government in California. He describes

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-09 Thread Hamilton02



I completely agree with Alan these issues are not black and white. 
The question is the lesser of two evils in determining accommodation: the courts 
or the legislature. I think it is very hard to argue the courts are better 
suited to make such a determination than a legislature. That is not to say 
legislatures always get it right. No governing system always gets it 
right. But, on average, they are better at asking whether this particular 
accommodation has victims who need to be taken into account before it is 
granted. The victims of religious conduct (whether they are individual or 
the general public good)are rarely at the table in a litigation. 


You seem to make the point that in the arena of "fundamental rights," you 
are inclined to presume that the public good is coincident with the 
accommodation. I used to think that as well, but I do not now. There 
is no fundamental right to engage in religious conduct, because conduct has the 
inherent capacity to hurt others. But let's just assume that religious 
conduct is a fundamental right; even so, there are often legitimate competing 
fundamental rights, like a child's right not to die for his or her parent's 
religious beliefs. This country must move beyond this easy equation of 
accommodation and public good. They are wholly distinctive and any 
accommodation granted without consideration of the public good holds the 
potential to harm others.

We will have to agree to disagree on how land use decisions are made. 
Given the fact that public hearings are always required, it is hardly a bank 
teller scenario. There are always multiple concerns and multiple factors, 
along with state and local land use law, not to mention sec. 1983. The 
unfettered discretion that was attempted to be painted in the RLPA hearings 
underlying RLUIPA does not square with my experience in this arena.

Marci



To follow up on 
  Doug's point, one of the problem's I have with Marci's arguments about 
  judicial exemptions and legislative accommodations is that it sometimes 
  appears as if Marci views religious groups seeking legislative 
  accommodations or constitutionally mandated exemptions as self interested 
  actors concerned only with their own well being while she views 
  legislative and administrative bodies as principled seekers and defenders 
  of the public good.Many of us see legislative and administrative 
  decisions differently. These are often political responses to various self 
  interested constituencies -- some of whose goals conflict with those of 
  particular religious communities. Religious groups have learned to play 
  that game because it is the only game in town -- and some have gotten 
  pretty good at it. But not all religious groups have sufficient political 
  capital in every community in which they live to protect their interests. 
  Moreover, in many cases, there is no reason to think that a religious 
  accommodation protecting a religious group's ability to practice its faith 
  is less related to the public good than a decision to reject the 
  accommodation in order to further the interests of other constituencies 
  with conflicting interests. When fundamental rights are at stake, I, and 
  others, are less inclined to accept this kind of political interest 
  balancing without some judicial supervision.To use RLUIPA as an 
  example, in the land use regulation process, in many disputes, there are 
  often specific groups whose personal interests conflict with the 
  development needs of a religious congregation. The resulting land use 
  decision will often reflect a political evaluation of the competing 
  interest groups more than it does a principled promotion of the public 
  good. In the prison context, in California, an association representing 
  state correctional officers is a major political player that often opposes 
  religious accommodations in prisons. Government attention to this 
  association's demands on many issues is at least as likely to be 
  politically motivated as principled.I have a very close 
  acquaintance who has spent 30 years working in local government in 
  California. He describes local government this way. When a citizen seeks a 
  discretionary decision from local government, he or she is treated very 
  much like someone going to the local bank and asking for money. The bank 
  typically wants to know two things. Have you deposited money in the bank 
  that you can withdraw from your account?(What have you given to the bank?) 
  Or, alternatively, if we give you money (a loan), what will you do 
  in the future for us (like paying back the loan with interest)? And in 
  considering the latter inquiry, they will examine the customer's credit 
  rating. What have you done for institutions that have loaned you money in 
  the past? Politicians operate pretty much the same way. If you want them 
  to decide an issue in your favor, they want to know what you have done 
  politically that has 

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-09 Thread Berg, Thomas C.









I dont get the argument
that individual victims of religious conduct or the public good are
rarely at the table in [religious freedom] litigation. Sometimes
they are directly at the table in that its a tort or other civil suit by
a plaintiff affected by religious conduct. Even if its a criminal
or regulatory case, these interests are regularly at the table in the sense
that the case doesnt exist unless the government entity is trying to
enforce the law in question against the religious claimant. Why doesnt
the enforcing agency represent the individual or the public good? We rely
on prosecutors and other executive officers to represent individual or social
interests in litigation all the time. If for some reason executive
officials are inadequate representatives of these interests, then our whole
system will have to change dramatically. Prosecutors and other executive
officials are also perfectly good at pointing out to judges the potential
implications of an exemption  in fact, in my experience they tend to
exaggerate the effects of exemption. And if executive officials are
inadequate, why would the legislature of the same government do any better?



If Marcis answer is that the compelling
interest test doesnt allow enough consideration of the effects on
others or society, then: (1) That would not be a reason for eliminating judicial
accommodations altogether; it would only be a reason for judging them under a
more intermediate standard. Marcis argument below seems to be
directed against judicial accommodations under any standard. (2) Its
simply not true that the compelling interest standard has ignored
the interests of others or of society. Anyone who has read the compelling
interest cases can see that courts have been quite willing to reject
religious freedom claims to protect those other interests. The question
is whether the religious freedom claim gets a judicial hearing.





---

Thomas C. Berg

Professor of Law

Co-Director, Terrence J. Murphy Institute

 for Catholic
Thought, Law, and Public Policy

University of St. Thomas School of Law

MSL 400 -- 1000 La Salle Avenue

Minneapolis, MN 55403-2015

Phone: (651) 962-4918

Fax:(651) 962-4996

E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]

---









-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, March 09, 2005
10:00 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions





I
completely agree with Alan these issues are not black and white. The
question is the lesser of two evils in determining accommodation: the courts or
the legislature. I think it is very hard to argue the courts are better suited
to make such a determination than a legislature. That is not to say
legislatures always get it right. No governing system always gets it
right. But, on average, they are better at asking whether this particular
accommodation has victims who need to be taken into account before it is
granted. The victims of religious conduct (whether they are individual or
the general public good)are rarely at the table in a litigation. 











You
seem to make the point that in the arena of fundamental rights, you
are inclined to presume that the public good is coincident with the
accommodation. I used to think that as well, but I do not now.
There is no fundamental right to engage in religious conduct, because conduct
has the inherent capacity to hurt others. But let's just assume that
religious conduct is a fundamental right; even so, there are often legitimate
competing fundamental rights, like a child's right not to die for his or her
parent's religious beliefs. This country must move beyond this easy
equation of accommodation and public good. They are wholly distinctive
and any accommodation granted without consideration of the public good holds
the potential to harm others.











We will
have to agree to disagree on how land use decisions are made. Given the
fact that public hearings are always required, it is hardly a bank teller
scenario. There are always multiple concerns and multiple factors, along
with state and local land use law, not to mention sec. 1983. The
unfettered discretion that was attempted to be painted in the RLPA hearings
underlying RLUIPA does not square with my experience in this arena.











Marci























To
follow up on Doug's point, one of the problem's I have with Marci's 
arguments about judicial exemptions and legislative accommodations is that 
it sometimes appears as if Marci views religious groups seeking legislative 
accommodations or constitutionally mandated exemptions as self interested 
actors concerned only with their own well being while she views legislative 
and administrative bodies as principled seekers and defenders of the public 
good.

Many of us see legislative and administrative decisions differently. These 
are often political responses

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-09 Thread Douglas Laycock





This is not responsive to 
Tom's point. Why are the courts better than legislatures at balancing the 
competing interests when the legislature is accused of going to far for 
religion, but not when it is accused of not doing enough?

I would have the courts take a second look in both 
cases, but if only the legislature is capable of balancing these interests, then 
the courts should not take a second look in either case.


Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX 78705
512-232-1341
512-471-6988 (fax)


From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on 
behalf of [EMAIL PROTECTED]Sent: Wed 3/9/2005 2:57 PMTo: 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.eduSubject: Re: Institutional Capacity to 
Manage Exemptions


  Byhaving 
  legislatures makethe accommodation, I am not repealingthe 
  Establishment Clause, which was the reason those cases came out the way they 
  did.The Smith decision is rather explicit that there is not an 
  unlimited right to accommodate. Where the accommodation is a bonus, 
  notnarrowly tailored to lift the burden on the conduct, there would be a 
  strong EC argument.

Marci

  



  If, as Marci 
  says, legislatures are better [than 
  courts] at asking whether this particular accommodation has victims who need 
  to be taken into account before it is granted, 
  would that also mean that legislative accommodations should not be struck down 
  by courts on the ground that they impose costs on third parties? In 
  other words, Thornton v. Caldor 
  (striking down the required day off for all religious worshipers) was wrongly 
  decided, and likely Texas 
  Monthly as well  and probably TWA v. Hardison too, since the Court 
  there probably interpreted the Title VII religious-accommodation provision 
  more narrowly than Congress intended, based on the Courts concerns about the 
  effect of accommodation on other employees. Moreover, under the trust 
  the political body more than the courts view, Zorach was correctly decided; the school 
  board is in the best position to weigh the interests of religious students and 
  nonreligious students concerning the availability of release time. If 
  the legislature is truly better at making these determinations, then courts 
  also have to trust it when it choose to accommodate, even when there are 
  arguable effects on third parties. But if courts strike down these 
  legislative accommodations while never declaring any constitutional 
  accommodations, then the principle is not let the legislature decide, but 
  rather religious claims should lose no matter who decides.
  
  


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-09 Thread Newsom Michael
 of a judgment that suasion, rather than coercion,
was the more appropriate manner for dealing with a particular minority
religion, at that time and in that place. This conclusion could be
reached as a result of an internal decision of the Protestant Empire as to the
proper course of action to follow, or as a result of pressure brought by
minority religions, and the resultant concern by the Protestant Empire that
resort to coercion would, in that time and place, be ultimately
counterproductive. The distinction here is remarkably thin, but it has
everything to do with the dynamic relation between coercion and suasion, a
relation that defies easy or simple definition or description, although history
gives us a pretty good idea of how it has worked in the past. I have an
article coming out this spring which tries to explain all of this in the
context of the Volstead Acts exemption for the religious use of wine.)
It does not follow that all exemptions sought by these minority religions should
be granted, but the burden lies on the courts and the legislature to justify
the refusal to grant an exemption.). (Protestant Empire theory tends to
reject the idea that there are Protestant minority religions, a conclusion with
which many on this list-serv would flatly disagree. Protestant Empire
theory holds that pan-Protestantism means that there can be no Protestant
minority religions, all Protestants being members of the broader pan-Protestant
structure, a structure settled by the Act of Toleration (if not before, in
Elizabethan times).) 



The foregoing may or may not be an
adequate answer, but I am convinced that many on this list-serv have adequately
answered the question, both on this list-serv and elsewhere. The claim that
members of this list-serv may not have ever adequately answered this question
is, to put it charitably, overly broad, and flat-out wrong. 





-Original Message-
From: West, Ellis
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday,
 March 09, 2005 5:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions





Although
the issue of whether legislatures or courts are better qualified or more likely
to grant religion-based exemptions is an interesting one, it is not the
fundamental one, which is: Why should religious persons/groups, and they
alone,be given across-the-board exemptions, whether by courts or
legislatures, from valid, secular laws? Of course, religious
persons/groups, like other person/groups, should be able to obtain
fromlegislatures exemptions from specific laws that impose undue hardships
on them in some way or the other. But why should they be granted
across-the-board exemptions? It won't do to say that the First Amendment
requires such, because that is the issue. Why should the First Amendment
be interpreted to require such? I don't think members of this list-serv
have ever adequately answered this question.



Ellis M. West 
Political Science Department 
University of Richmond, VA 23173 
804-289-8536 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] 



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On
Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Wednesday, March 09, 2005
4:30 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics; religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions





This is
not responsive to Tom's point. Why are the courts better than
legislatures at balancing the competing interests when the legislature is
accused of going to far for religion, but not when it is accused of not doing
enough?











I would
have the courts take a second look in both cases, but if only the legislature
is capable of balancing these interests, then the courts should not take a
second look in either case.















Douglas
Laycock





University
of Texas Law School





727 E.
Dean Keeton St.





Austin,
TX 78705





512-232-1341





512-471-6988
(fax)















From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wed 3/9/2005 2:57 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions







Byhaving
legislatures makethe accommodation, I am not repealingthe
Establishment Clause, which was the reason those cases came out the way they
did.The Smith decision is rather explicit that there is not an
unlimited right to accommodate. Where the accommodation is a bonus,
notnarrowly tailored to lift the burden on the conduct, there would be a
strong EC argument.











Marci























If, as
Marci says, legislatures are
better [than courts] at asking whether this particular accommodation has
victims who need to be taken into account before it is granted, would that also mean that legislative accommodations should not be
struck down by courts on the ground that they impose costs on third
parties? In other words, Thornton v.
Caldor (striking down the required day off for all religious
worshipers) was wrongly decided, and likely Texas
Monthly as well  and probably

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-09 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Title: Message









One might ask, why should those who object
to the majority's views on religion alone be given across-the-board
exemptions from the majority's views taught to their children in public
schools? My third-grade daughter is subject to being taught about all sorts of
things that I might not like. (Not another unit on why we must protect all rain
forests ...) 



I'm happy that there is an
Establishment Clause that has some bite. But then I also think the Free
Exercise Clause should have some bite. Religion is special; the state can't
do much to support it, and the state must provide some extra space for private
_expression_ of it.





Mark S. Scarberry

Pepperdine University School of Law



P.S. I'm not in favor of eradicating
rain forests, but I feel about them sort of the same way Mark Twain felt about
Michelangelo after Twain had been in Italy for a while.





-Original Message-
From: West, Ellis
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, March 09, 2005
2:40 PM
To: Law 
 Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions





Although
the issue of whether legislatures or courts are better qualified or more likely
to grant religion-based exemptions is an interesting one, it is not the
fundamental one, which is: Why should religious persons/groups, and they
alone,be given across-the-board exemptions, whether by courts or
legislatures, from valid, secular laws? Of course, religious
persons/groups, like other person/groups, should be able to obtain
fromlegislatures exemptions from specific laws that impose undue hardships
on them in some way or the other. But why should they be granted
across-the-board exemptions? It won't do to say that the First Amendment
requires such, because that is the issue. Why should the First Amendment
be interpreted to require such? I don't think members of this list-serv
have ever adequately answered this question.



Ellis M. West 
Political Science Department 
University of Richmond, VA 23173 
804-289-8536 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] 



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On
Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Wednesday, March 09, 2005
4:30 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics; religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions





This is
not responsive to Tom's point. Why are the courts better than
legislatures at balancing the competing interests when the legislature is
accused of going to far for religion, but not when it is accused of not doing
enough?











I would
have the courts take a second look in both cases, but if only the legislature
is capable of balancing these interests, then the courts should not take a
second look in either case.















Douglas
Laycock





University
of Texas Law School





727 E.
Dean Keeton St.





Austin,
TX 78705





512-232-1341





512-471-6988
(fax)















From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wed 3/9/2005 2:57 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions







Byhaving
legislatures makethe accommodation, I am not repealingthe
Establishment Clause, which was the reason those cases came out the way they
did.The Smith decision is rather explicit that there is not an
unlimited right to accommodate. Where the accommodation is a bonus,
notnarrowly tailored to lift the burden on the conduct, there would be a
strong EC argument.











Marci























If, as
Marci says, legislatures "are
better [than courts] at asking whether this particular accommodation has victims
who need to be taken into account before it is granted," would that also mean that legislative accommodations should not be
struck down by courts on the ground that they impose costs on third
parties? In other words, Thornton v.
Caldor (striking down the required day off for all religious
worshipers) was wrongly decided, and likely Texas
Monthly as well - and probably TWA v. Hardison too, since the Court there probably
interpreted the Title VII religious-accommodation provision more narrowly than
Congress intended, based on the Court's concerns about the effect of
accommodation on other employees. Moreover, under the "trust the
political body more than the courts" view, Zorach was correctly decided; the school board is in the
best position to weigh the interests of religious students and nonreligious
students concerning the availability of release time. If the legislature
is truly better at making these determinations, then courts also have to trust
it when it choose to accommodate, even when there are arguable effects on third
parties. But if courts strike down these legislative accommodations while
never declaring any constitutional accommodations, then the principle is not
"let the legislature decide," but rather "religious claim

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-08 Thread A.E. Brownstein
To follow up on Doug's point, one of the problem's I have with Marci's 
arguments about judicial exemptions and legislative accommodations is that 
it sometimes appears as if Marci views religious groups seeking legislative 
accommodations or constitutionally mandated exemptions as self interested 
actors concerned only with their own well being while she views legislative 
and administrative bodies as principled seekers and defenders of the public 
good.

Many of us see legislative and administrative decisions differently. These 
are often political responses to various self interested constituencies -- 
some of whose goals conflict with those of particular religious 
communities. Religious groups have learned to play that game because it is 
the only game in town -- and some have gotten pretty good at it. But not 
all religious groups have sufficient political capital in every community 
in which they live to protect their interests. Moreover, in many cases, 
there is no reason to think that a religious accommodation protecting a 
religious group's ability to practice its faith is less related to the 
public good than a decision to reject the accommodation in order to further 
the interests of other constituencies with conflicting interests. When 
fundamental rights are at stake, I, and others, are less inclined to accept 
this kind of political interest balancing without some judicial supervision.

To use RLUIPA as an example, in the land use regulation process, in many 
disputes, there are often specific groups whose personal interests conflict 
with the development needs of a religious congregation. The resulting land 
use decision will often reflect a political evaluation of the competing 
interest groups more than it does a principled promotion of the public 
good. In the prison context, in California, an association representing 
state correctional officers is a major political player that often opposes 
religious accommodations in prisons. Government attention to this 
association's demands on many issues is at least as likely to be 
politically motivated as principled.

I have a very close acquaintance who has spent 30 years working in local 
government in California. He describes local government this way. When a 
citizen seeks a discretionary decision from local government, he or she is 
treated very much like someone going to the local bank and asking for 
money. The bank typically wants to know two things. Have you deposited 
money in the bank that you can withdraw from your account?
(What have you given to the bank?) Or, alternatively, if we give you 
money  (a loan), what will you do in the future for us (like paying back 
the loan with interest)? And in considering the latter inquiry, they will 
examine the customer's credit rating. What have you done for institutions 
that have loaned you money in the past? Politicians operate pretty much the 
same way. If you want them to decide an issue in your favor, they want to 
know what you have done politically that has benefited them -- then you can 
draw on the political capital you have developed in your account. Or, 
alternatively, they want to know what you can do in the future that will be 
politically helpful -- and a proven track record of delivering political 
goods is very helpful in establishing your political credit.

I don't say that legislative and administrative bodies never act for the 
public good. Sometimes they do. But it is also the case that religious 
groups seeking accommodations often are willing to take into account the 
needs of third parties and will support a compromise that promotes the 
broader interests of the community. These issues are rarely entirely black 
and white.

Alan Brownstein
UC Davis


At 10:03 PM 3/7/2005 -0600, you wrote:
Content-class: urn:content-classes:message
Content-Type: multipart/alternative;
boundary=_=_NextPart_001_01C52393.C070ECAC
Small religions can get exemptions if they somehow get on the legislative 
agenda; the if is large.  Even reviled  religions can get exemptions if 
they are large enough to have political clout; the Catholic vote in 1919 
was critical in big northeastern states with large Congressional 
delegations and lots of electoral votes.

A small and reviled religion cannot get an exemption from a legislature, 
and generally cannot even get equal treatment from a legislature in a 
single issue vote.  Everyone now says Lukumi was a clear case of 
discrimination.  But in the Congress that passed RFRA unanimously and 
97-3, Steve Solarz could not get a single office to even talk to him about 
an amicus brief in Lukumi.

Politics also works the other way.  No one could get permission to 
withhold medical care from children from a court under the compelling 
interest test.  But the Christian Scientists got all these exemptions from 
legislatures on sheer politics, and a number of legislators have enacted 
vaccination exemptions.

Judicial decisions on exemptions are 

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-08 Thread Newsom Michael








I
am going to respond to this off list. There is a serious disagreement regarding
the relevant facts, and I will have that discussion privately. 



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 07, 2005 10:49
PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions



I couldn't agree more, Mike, that
the facts determinative here, but I strongly disagree with your
characterization of the facts. 

Not every accommodation should be granted, indeed, many should not. Since
I don't know what the Pagans requested, I don't know how to judge the
denials. It is nonsense to assume that every accommodation denied is
evidence of discrimination. It may just show common sense on the part of
the legislature.

The fact the Episcopalians helped the Catholics achieve their goal hardly
undermines my point that even reviled or small groups have succeeded.
There are many instances where religious groups have helped others to obtain
exemptions. 

The Baptists and the Presbyterians have gone to the mat for the Catholic Church
to obtain exemptions from child-abuse reporting statutes in numerous
states. The Presbyterian Church, along with the Catholic, was behind a
Colorado bill that would have immunized churches' finances completely in clergy
abuse cases. The bill only narrowly was defeated. 

Of course the faith-healing exemptions came from the Christian Scientists, but
don't get maudlin on me. They were kick-started by two powerful CS,
Haldeman and Ehrlichman in the Nixon Administration, who instituted a
regulation that required states to enact such exemptions in order to receive
federal medical funding. It's not just hard work; it's the exercise of
raw political power. Over 30 states capitulated. When children's
groups finally figured out what was going on, they were able to start fighting
such exemptions, but with so many states, it was extremely difficult and
children remain at risk in numerous states. This is one of those
exemptions where the denial makes perfect policy sense to me, though it is not
constitutionally required.

The Native American Church was hardly pushed around when drug counselors who
agreed not to use illegal drugs as part of their job were denied unemployment
compensation. The NAC had already obtained exemptions in certain states,
as the Court pointed out in Smith, and continued to the point where states
where they are present have such exemptions. Where is the injustice here?

Please provide examples of small (all religions are minorities) religions with
claims for exemptions that were denied and that denial was inconsistent
with the public good.

Marci




I really didnt want to get into this, but, Marci, you are
wrong with respect to some critical facts. I am not going to address the
first paragraph (or the third and the fourth, for that matter,) even though I
entirely disagree with your position. I am more concerned, however, with
some of your claims in the second paragraph. There are small groups with cohesive
messages, like the Pagans, that have not obtained exemptions or
accommodations. Quite the contrary, they routinely get stomped on.
See Barner-Barrys book on the subject. Second, I have an article coming
out in a few weeks that, by looking closely at the legal and other materials
available to me covering the years leading up to National Prohibition,
establishes that Catholics did not get the exemption for the use of sacramental
wine during National Prohibition  the motive force for the exemption was the
appeasement of Episcopalians. (And I would hope that one day Catholics
and Episcopalians would bring themselves to sit down and have an honest and
frank discussion about the exemption and how it came to be. For it is
true that Catholics have routinely taken the credit for the exemption, and the
facts dont bear Catholics out.) And there is no credible argument that
anti-Catholicism did not high in the land in the period, say, 1910-1930.
Early twentieth-century anti-Catholicism is a fact. On the child abuse
matter, I find your reference to Baptists and Presbyterians providing backup
support interesting. But why isnt the reverse the truth, that the
Protestants were deeply involved in the subject and that there was a resulting
interest convergence, just as was the case with National Prohibition?

 

Your use of the term faith healing groups masks the
important fact that the real group in interest was the Christian
Scientists. A student in my church-state seminar last year, wrote a paper
on how Christian Scientists were able to obtain these exemptions. The
answer is hard work, lots of money, and an ethnic identity with the law
makers. The native American Church finally got justice in Oregon, no
thanks to the Courts, however. I dont know what to make of a claim that
even though a group got pushed around  unnecessarily so  that because the
finally got what they should have gotten earlier that things

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-07 Thread Newsom Michael








I
really didnt want to get into this, but, Marci, you are wrong with
respect to some critical facts. I am not going to address the first paragraph
(or the third and the fourth, for that matter,) even though I entirely disagree
with your position. I am more concerned, however, with some of your claims
in the second paragraph. There are small groups with cohesive messages,
like the Pagans, that have not obtained exemptions or accommodations.
Quite the contrary, they routinely get stomped on. See Barner-Barrys
book on the subject. Second, I have an article coming out in a few weeks
that, by looking closely at the legal and other materials available to me
covering the years leading up to National Prohibition, establishes that
Catholics did not get the exemption for the use of sacramental wine during National
Prohibition  the motive force for the exemption was the appeasement of
Episcopalians. (And I would hope that one day Catholics and Episcopalians
would bring themselves to sit down and have an honest and frank discussion
about the exemption and how it came to be. For it is true that Catholics
have routinely taken the credit for the exemption, and the facts dont
bear Catholics out.) And there is no credible argument that
anti-Catholicism did not high in the land in the period, say, 1910-1930.
Early twentieth-century anti-Catholicism is a fact. On the child abuse
matter, I find your reference to Baptists and Presbyterians providing backup
support interesting. But why isnt the reverse the truth, that the
Protestants were deeply involved in the subject and that there was a resulting
interest convergence, just as was the case with National Prohibition?



Your use of the term faith healing
groups masks the important fact that the real group in interest was the
Christian Scientists. A student in my church-state seminar last year,
wrote a paper on how Christian Scientists were able to obtain these
exemptions. The answer is hard work, lots of money, and an ethnic
identity with the law makers. The native American Church finally got
justice in Oregon, no thanks to the Courts, however. I dont know what
to make of a claim that even though a group got pushed around  unnecessarily
so  that because the finally got what they should have gotten earlier
that things are somehow OK. What is justice denied? That small
evangelical groups got exemptions is no big deal in a Protestant Empire.



Facts always trump political theory, I am
afraid. Some religious minorities fare better than others, no matter what
the theory says. People who say that things are going well with
religious minorities should take the time to look at the narratives that
suggest the contrary. These narratives thoroughly demolish the theories.
And they make the case for exemptions on a case-by-case basis. 



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Sunday, March 06, 2005 8:03
PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions



Doug-- You missed my point
here. Taking exemptions on a case-by-case basis is illegitimate, because
it drives the consideration by the courts toward one individual believer and
away from the larger public good that needs to be factored in. Courts are
simply inadequate to make that public good determination; they cannot hold
hearings or consider facts beyond the record. The record, instead, is
manufactured by the parties, a fact you used to great and admirable advantage
in the Lukumi case.

The factual premise that the legislative arena drives results toward mainstream
religious practices and away from the smaller religions is not borne out in
political theory (Mancur Olson's now widely accepted work showing that small
groups with cohesive messages do better in the legis process than do
disaggregated majorities), or in practice. Faith-healing groups have obtained
unimaginable numbers of exemptions from the laws intended to protect children
--without the benefit of any Supreme Court publicity; the Native American
Church is using peyote; and the military are wearing yarmulkes. Small
evangelical groups have obtained exemptions from the laws that govern safety in
day care centers and camps. Catholics even got an exemption for the use
of sacramental wine during Prohibition when it is argued that anti-Catholic
sentiment ran high in the land. Clergy in many states are exempted
from reporting childhood sexual abuse they know about -- a move pushed hardest
by the Catholic Church (with the Baptists and the dwindling Presbyterians
providing backup when desired). 

As an empirical matter, the compelling interest test and the least restrictive
means test has led courts to focus on the believer at the expense of society,
see, e.g., Yoder and most of Posner's free exercise decisions. Yoder pays
the slightest lip service to the public good in the midst of its love affair with
the Amish. 

Legislatures have a time-honored and regularized procedure for hearing

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-07 Thread Hamilton02
I couldn't agree more, Mike, that the facts determinative here, but I strongly disagree with your characterization of the facts. 

Not every accommodation should be granted, indeed, many should not. Since I don't know what the Pagans requested, I don't know how to judge the denials. It is nonsense to assume that every accommodation denied is evidence of discrimination. It may just show common sense on the part of the legislature.

The fact the Episcopalians helped the Catholics achieve their goal hardly undermines my point that even reviled or small groups have succeeded. There are many instances where religious groups have helped others to obtain exemptions. 

The Baptists and the Presbyterians have gone to the mat for the Catholic Church to obtain exemptions from child-abuse reporting statutes in numerous states. The Presbyterian Church, along with the Catholic, was behind a Colorado bill that would have immunized churches' finances completely in clergy abuse cases. The bill only narrowly was defeated. 

Of course the faith-healing exemptions came from the Christian Scientists, but don't get maudlin on me. They were kick-started by two powerful CS, Haldeman and Ehrlichman in the Nixon Administration, who instituted a regulation that required states to enact such exemptions in order to receive federal medical funding. It's not just hard work; it's the exercise of raw political power. Over 30 states capitulated. When children's groups finally figured out what was going on, they were able to start fighting such exemptions, but with so many states, it was extremely difficult and children remain at risk in numerous states. This is one of those exemptions where the denial makes perfect policy sense to me, though it is not constitutionally required.

The Native American Church was hardly pushed around when drug counselors who agreed not to use illegal drugs as part of their job were denied unemployment compensation. The NAC had already obtained exemptions in certain states, as the Court pointed out in Smith, and continued to the point where states where they are present have such exemptions. Where is the injustice here?

Please provide examples of small (all religions are minorities) religions with claims for exemptions that were denied and that denial was inconsistent with the public good.

Marci

I really didnt want to get into this, but, Marci, you are wrong with respect to some critical facts. I am not going to address the first paragraph (or the third and the fourth, for that matter,) even though I entirely disagree with your position. I am more concerned, however, with some of your claims in the second paragraph. There are small groups with cohesive messages, like the Pagans, that have not obtained exemptions or accommodations. Quite the contrary, they routinely get stomped on. See Barner-Barrys book on the subject. Second, I have an article coming out in a few weeks that, by looking closely at the legal and other materials available to me covering the years leading up to National Prohibition, establishes that Catholics did not get the exemption for the use of sacramental wine during National Prohibition  the motive force for the exemption was the appeasement of Episcopalians. (And I would hope that one day Catholics and Episcopalians would bring themselves to sit down and have an honest and frank discussion about the exemption and how it came to be. For it is true that Catholics have routinely taken the credit for the exemption, and the facts dont bear Catholics out.) And there is no credible argument that anti-Catholicism did not high in the land in the period, say, 1910-1930. Early twentieth-century anti-Catholicism is a fact. On the child abuse matter, I find your reference to Baptists and Presbyterians providing backup support interesting. But why isnt the reverse the truth, that the Protestants were deeply involved in the subject and that there was a resulting interest convergence, just as was the case with National Prohibition?

 

Your use of the term faith healing groups masks the important fact that the real group in interest was the Christian Scientists. A student in my church-state seminar last year, wrote a paper on how Christian Scientists were able to obtain these exemptions. The answer is hard work, lots of money, and an ethnic identity with the law makers. The native American Church finally got justice in Oregon, no thanks to the Courts, however. I dont know what to make of a claim that even though a group got pushed around  unnecessarily so  that because the finally got what they should have gotten earlier that things are somehow OK. What is justice denied? That small evangelical groups got exemptions is no big deal in a Protestant Empire.

 

Facts always trump political theory, I am afraid. Some religious minorities fare better than others, no matter what the theory says. People who say that things are going well with religious minorities should take the time to look at the narratives 

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-07 Thread Douglas Laycock




Small religions can get 
exemptions if they somehow get on the legislative agenda; the if is large. 
Even reviledreligions can get exemptions if they are large enough to 
have political clout; the Catholic vote in 1919 was critical in big northeastern 
states with large Congressional delegations and lots of electoral votes. 


A small and reviled religion cannot get an 
exemption from a legislature, and generally cannot even get equal treatment from 
a legislature in a single issue vote. Everyone now says Lukumi was a clear 
case of discrimination. But in the Congress that passed RFRA unanimously 
and 97-3, Steve Solarz could not get a single office to even talk to him about 
an amicus brief in Lukumi.

Politics also works the other way. No one 
could get permission to withhold medical care from children from a court under 
the compelling interest test. But the Christian Scientists got all these 
exemptions from legislatures on sheer politics, and a number of legislators have 
enacted vaccination exemptions. 

Judicial decisions on exemptions are sometimes 
political and sometimes principled. Legislative decisions on exemptions 
are nearly always political. 

Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX 78705
512-232-1341
512-471-6988 (fax)


From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on 
behalf of [EMAIL PROTECTED]Sent: Mon 3/7/2005 9:49 PMTo: 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.eduSubject: Re: Institutional Capacity to 
Manage Exemptions
I couldn't agree 
more, Mike, that the facts determinative here, but I strongly disagree with your 
characterization of the facts. Not every accommodation should be 
granted, indeed, many should not. Since I don't know what the Pagans 
requested, I don't know how to judge the denials. It is nonsense to 
assume that every accommodation denied is evidence of discrimination. It 
may just show common sense on the part of the legislature.The fact the 
Episcopalians helped the Catholics achieve their goal hardly undermines my point 
that even reviled or small groups have succeeded. There are many instances 
where religious groups have helped others to obtain exemptions. 
The Baptists and the Presbyterians have gone to the mat for the Catholic 
Church to obtain exemptions from child-abuse reporting statutes in numerous 
states. The Presbyterian Church, along with the Catholic, was behind a 
Colorado bill that would have immunized churches' finances completely in clergy 
abuse cases. The bill only narrowly was defeated. Of course 
the faith-healing exemptions came from the Christian Scientists, but don't get 
maudlin on me. They were kick-started by two powerful CS, Haldeman and 
Ehrlichman in the Nixon Administration, who instituted a regulation that 
required states to enact such exemptions in order to receive federal medical 
funding. It's not just hard work; it's the exercise of raw political 
power. Over 30 states capitulated. When children's groups finally 
figured out what was going on, they were able to start fighting such exemptions, 
but with so many states, it was extremely difficult and children remain at risk 
in numerous states. This is one of those exemptions where the denial 
makes perfect policy sense to me, though it is not constitutionally 
required.The Native American Church was hardly pushed around when drug 
counselors who agreed not to use illegal drugs as part of their job were denied 
unemployment compensation. The NAC had already obtained exemptions in 
certain states, as the Court pointed out in Smith, and continued to the point 
where states where they are present have such exemptions. Where is the 
injustice here?Please provide examples of small (all religions are 
minorities) religions with claims for exemptions that were denied and that 
denial was inconsistent with the public good.Marci
I really didnt want to get into this, but, Marci, you 
  are wrong with respect to some critical facts. I am not going to address 
  the first paragraph (or the third and the fourth, for that matter,) even 
  though I entirely disagree with your position. I am more concerned, 
  however, with some of your claims in the second paragraph. There are 
  small groups with cohesive messages, like the Pagans, that have not obtained 
  exemptions or accommodations. Quite the contrary, they routinely get 
  stomped on. See Barner-Barrys book on the subject. Second, I have 
  an article coming out in a few weeks that, by looking closely at the legal and 
  other materials available to me covering the years leading up to National 
  Prohibition, establishes that Catholics did not get the exemption for the use 
  of sacramental wine during National Prohibition  the motive force for the 
  exemption was the appeasement of Episcopalians. (And I would hope that 
  one day Catholics and Episcopalians would bring themselves to sit down and 
  have an honest and frank discussion about the exemption and how it came to 
  be. For it is true that Catholics have routinely