Re: FW: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires Acceptance of Secular Reasons As Well

2014-06-08 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
Eugene:

Are you asking whether religion is a one way ratchet? Under at least one
reading of Smith/Lukumi, as typified in the Tenafly eruv case, if there are
(at least some kinds of) secular exceptions, then there must also be a
religious exception. But if there is a religious exception, must there also
be secular exceptions? And if so, what kinds of secular exceptions must
there be--those that rise to the level of conscientious objection status,
or others as well?

For what it is worth, I get an email from UGA each year reminding me that
it is university policy to accommodate (to the maximum degree possible,
whatever that means) religious students' ability to miss class for
religious observances. I do not get such an email regarding students who
miss class because their siblings are getting married, their pets are in
poor health, or their great aunts (who were like second mothers) died. What
to make of that?

On Saturday, June 7, 2014, Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu
wrote:

  I would always want to know the rationale and why it didn't apply to the
 religious person as well. But if ever I'm disinclined to be sympathetic to
 the flat out equal treatment, it's in this instance, and I continue to
 wonder why there's a religious exemption. I presume that a religious person
 wouldn't be allowed to smoke on premises even if she belonged to a
 religious sect that commanded chain smoking. I see no difference with
 regard to the flu shot. But, by stipulation, if the rule had nothing to do
 with patients' health, then I'd be inclined to treat secular and religious
 alike.

  Sandy

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Jun 7, 2014, at 9:02 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

  I agree entirely on the bottom line, but let me ask what
 would happen in the absence of concerns about harm to the sick.  Say an
 employer has a uniform policy that bars headgear, but exempts religious
 objectors; and say that a secular employee insists on wearing a hat to
 work, and is fired for it.  Should the employee be seen as constitutionally
 entitled to unemployment compensation, on a rationale similar to that given
 by the New Jersey appellate court?



Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Levinson,
 Sanford V
 *Sent:* Friday, June 06, 2014 9:00 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* RE: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires
 Acceptance of Secular Reasons As Well



 OK, I’ll bite;  Religious exemptions, at the end of the day,  honor
 beliefs that secularists by definition must regard as “irrational,” i.e.,
 incapable of being defended by reference to “standard-model” scientific
 argument.  There may be good reasons for allowing such exemption in the
 name of preserving civil peace, etc., or it may simply boil down to the
 presence of the Free Exercise Clause and the collapse  of  the
 belief/conduct distinction.  But it is hard to think of “secular” reasons
 for a nurse to refuse to get a flu vaccination, given the risk not only to
 herself—which raises obvious questions about paternalism—but also potential
 risks to her patients should she in fact come down with the flu and infect
 others in the hospital, who are by definition more vulnerable than ordinary
 persons with whom she might also come into contact.  So, unless there
 really is some good reason to refuse flu vaccines—perhaps she is unusually
 sensitive to egg-based vaccines or something similar—I am disinclined to be
 at all sympathetic to her argument and would regard her firing as fully for
 cause.  I think the “freedom of expression” argument in this case is wacky
 given her job and responsibility for doing no harm to the sick.  Were I to
 receive this as an answer to a final exam question, I would be inclined to
 give it a very bad grade.  I leave it to my colleagues on this list,
 including Eugene, to tell me if (and why) I am off-base in my response.



 sandy

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Volokh, Eugene
 *Sent:* Friday, June 06, 2014 10:50 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 javascript:_e(%7B%7D,'cvml','Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu');
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.



-- 
Hillel Y. Levin
Associate Professor
University of Georgia
School of Law
120 Herty Dr.
Athens, GA 30602
(678) 641-7452
hle...@uga.edu
hillelle...@gmail.com
SSRN Author Page:

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread mallamud
Because my concern applies to other areas and this is a religion law 
list, I understand that my comment (4) needs more explanation.
1. The extreme partisanship in our political system needs 
ameliorating.  Some years ago I wrote that in the confirmation process 
Senators needed to exercise restraint in the consideration of 
prospective Justices because to tie them to politically acceptable 
positions would undercut the preservation of rights, essentially an 
anti-majoritarian process.  7 St. John's Journal of Legal Commentary 203 
(1991).
2. I am much taken with Justice Douglas' idea that it takes 5 to 10 
years for a new Justice to develop a good approach to making decisions 
because a Justice needs to put aside ideas and positions held before 
joining the Court and seek a perspective based on the Supreme Court's 
unique role.
3. I was impressed with the Supreme Court's handling of Brown v. 
Bd.of Ed. when it stressed the need for everyone to defer to the 
decisions of the Court.  See Cooper v. Aaron.  Today I find it unhelpful 
that so many people criticize the Court using the Court as a whipping 
boy in discussing cases such as Bush v. Gore, Citizens United and Shelby 
County (re Sec. 5 of the VRA).  At some point confessional issues need 
to be put to rest by the Court.  Otherwise our society may become unduly 
fractured by political disagreement.  In an appropriate forum I can 
defend all three decisions.
4. I am concerned that the dissenters in affirmative action and 
voting rights cases do not see the changes that have taken place and 
refuse to admit that achieving a society not based on race may require 
change in the legal stances taken in the 1960s, 70s and 80s.
5. When I defend the actions of the Court to non-lawyers, I would 
like to argue that the Supreme Court does not decide cases based on 
personal political predilections, but takes a broader view based on the 
overall functioning of our political system and their best judgment of 
the good of the society as a whole.  I find this hard to do in the light 
of many recent decisions.
6. I find that the reasons behind Employment Division v. Smith 
(which I have come to believe stated the best rule) apply to the evils 
of using the standard rejected in Smith in applying all federal 
statutes.  So in Hobby Lobby I would like to see Justice Scalia find a 
way to apply his wisdom rather than his past predilection to enforce 
statutes no matter what the result. I was upset when he failed to 
enforce limits to the Commerce Clause in extending federal law to state 
authorization of the use of medical marijuana.  Perhaps some day I will 
get to see why he did that and come to appreciate his view as I have his 
views in Smith.

  Jon



On 2014-06-07 16:40, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

Jon Mallamud writes:


4. Hobby Lobby represents to me an important test in how politically

motivated


the Court is becoming. In Boerne the Court held that in enforcing

the fourteenth


amendment, the Congress had to stick to the Supreme Court's

interpretation of


the constitution. In Employment Division v. Smith, Scalia

interpreted the


constitution for the Court and Congress tried to impose its own

interpretation.


If Scalia decides that a statute purporting to deal with all federal

law just as the


constitution does, and thus uses the rule of decision in RFRA to

decide a religious


exemption case, I would be concerned. Of course I am sure one could

write a


persuasive argument that Congress has full authority over statutes

it enacts and


Scalia could defer to the statute.


 I'm not sure why we should be concerned [i]f Scalia decides that 
a

statute purporting to deal with all federal law just as the
constitution does, and thus uses the rule of decision in RFRA to
decide a religious exemption case. Congress has the power to carve
out exemptions from federal laws (even if lacks such power to carve
out exemptions from state laws, see Boerne). Smith simply holds that
the _Free Exercise Clause_ doesn't provide such exemptions - it
doesn't preclude statutory exemptions, no?

 By the way, if we should be concerned by Scalia's possible
pro-Hobby-Lobby vote, I take it we should be equally concerned by
Stevens' votes in Smith, Boerne, and O Centro, as well as by
Ginsburg's votes in Boerne and O Centro (since her vote in Boerne
suggests that she would have voted with the majority in Smith), no?

 Eugene


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate the general concerns raised in Jon Mallamud's post -- but 
I just don't see how items 1 to 5 lead to the conclusion in item 6 about Hobby 
Lobby.  Could you elaborate, please, why it would not be wis[e] for Justice 
Scalia to view RFRA as constitutional as to federal laws, and as justifying 
Hobby Lobby's claims in this case?  The conclusion that the standard rejected 
in Smith is an unsound interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause doesn't 
obviously mean that Congress lacks the power to implement such a standard in a 
statute.  Maybe that is ultimately the correct conclusion, but I think that it 
needs some more justification.

Eugene 

Jon Mallamud writes:

  6. I find that the reasons behind Employment Division v. Smith (which I 
 have
 come to believe stated the best rule) apply to the evils of using the standard
 rejected in Smith in applying all federal statutes.  So in Hobby Lobby I 
 would like
 to see Justice Scalia find a way to apply his wisdom rather than his past
 predilection to enforce statutes no matter what the result. I was upset when 
 he
 failed to enforce limits to the Commerce Clause in extending federal law to
 state authorization of the use of medical marijuana.  Perhaps some day I will 
 get
 to see why he did that and come to appreciate his view as I have his views in
 Smith.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread mallamud
People with whom I speak view Justice Scalia as a staunch conservative. 
They also associate deference to religion as a conservative position. 
If Scalia were to use what he obviously knows from his decision in Smith 
to deny religious exemptions based on tenuous connections where they 
interfere with the rights and freedoms of others, I think some people 
might take a more nuanced view of him.  One small step in convincing 
people that the Supreme Court deserves respect because the Justices 
decide based on their best judgment of the good of the country and not 
on preconceived liberal or conservative biases.  [Sub-point: Just as 
Scalia pointed to the wildly overwhelming majority by which Sec. 5 of 
the VRA was extended for 25 years, I feel that one reason for the 
enactment or RFRA, again, an overwhelming majority, stemmed from 
liberals' dislike of Scalia.  Clearly not suitable as a decisional 
factor, but it undermines the statute in my personal opinion.]


Jon

On 2014-06-08 12:24, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

I appreciate the general concerns raised in Jon Mallamud's post --
but I just don't see how items 1 to 5 lead to the conclusion in item 
6

about Hobby Lobby.  Could you elaborate, please, why it would not be
wis[e] for Justice Scalia to view RFRA as constitutional as to
federal laws, and as justifying Hobby Lobby's claims in this case?
The conclusion that the standard rejected in Smith is an unsound
interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause doesn't obviously mean 
that

Congress lacks the power to implement such a standard in a statute.
Maybe that is ultimately the correct conclusion, but I think that it
needs some more justification.

Eugene

Jon Mallamud writes:

 6. I find that the reasons behind Employment Division v. Smith 
(which I have
come to believe stated the best rule) apply to the evils of using 
the standard
rejected in Smith in applying all federal statutes.  So in Hobby 
Lobby I would like
to see Justice Scalia find a way to apply his wisdom rather than his 
past
predilection to enforce statutes no matter what the result. I was 
upset when he
failed to enforce limits to the Commerce Clause in extending federal 
law to
state authorization of the use of medical marijuana.  Perhaps some 
day I will get
to see why he did that and come to appreciate his view as I have his 
views in

Smith.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can
(rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: FW: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires Acceptance of Secular Reasons As Well

2014-06-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   I’m not positive what the right answer is (though I don’t agree 
with the Free Exercise Clause cases holding that, if the government provides 
secular exceptions, it must also provide religious exceptions).  I’m just 
curious about what other people think should happen in situations such as the 
ones involved in the New Jersey case.

As I understand it, Cutter v. Wilkinson concludes that exemptions limited to 
religious believers are generally constitutionally permissible, so the UGA 
policy you describe is sound even in the absence of comparable secular 
exemptions.  The New Jersey decision, on the other hand, seems to point in the 
opposite direction, albeit in an unusual procedural posture.  Which is right?

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 3:12 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: FW: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires 
Acceptance of Secular Reasons As Well

Eugene:

Are you asking whether religion is a one way ratchet? Under at least one 
reading of Smith/Lukumi, as typified in the Tenafly eruv case, if there are (at 
least some kinds of) secular exceptions, then there must also be a religious 
exception. But if there is a religious exception, must there also be secular 
exceptions? And if so, what kinds of secular exceptions must there be--those 
that rise to the level of conscientious objection status, or others as well?

For what it is worth, I get an email from UGA each year reminding me that it is 
university policy to accommodate (to the maximum degree possible, whatever that 
means) religious students' ability to miss class for religious observances. I 
do not get such an email regarding students who miss class because their 
siblings are getting married, their pets are in poor health, or their great 
aunts (who were like second mothers) died. What to make of that?

On Saturday, June 7, 2014, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
I would always want to know the rationale and why it didn't apply to the 
religious person as well. But if ever I'm disinclined to be sympathetic to the 
flat out equal treatment, it's in this instance, and I continue to wonder why 
there's a religious exemption. I presume that a religious person wouldn't be 
allowed to smoke on premises even if she belonged to a religious sect that 
commanded chain smoking. I see no difference with regard to the flu shot. But, 
by stipulation, if the rule had nothing to do with patients' health, then I'd 
be inclined to treat secular and religious alike.

Sandy

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Jun 7, 2014, at 9:02 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

   I agree entirely on the bottom line, but let me ask what would 
happen in the absence of concerns about harm to the sick.  Say an employer has 
a uniform policy that bars headgear, but exempts religious objectors; and say 
that a secular employee insists on wearing a hat to work, and is fired for it.  
Should the employee be seen as constitutionally entitled to unemployment 
compensation, on a rationale similar to that given by the New Jersey appellate 
court?



   Eugene



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Friday, June 06, 2014 9:00 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires Acceptance of 
Secular Reasons As Well



OK, I’ll bite;  Religious exemptions, at the end of the day,  honor beliefs 
that secularists by definition must regard as “irrational,” i.e., incapable of 
being defended by reference to “standard-model” scientific argument.  There may 
be good reasons for allowing such exemption in the name of preserving civil 
peace, etc., or it may simply boil down to the presence of the Free Exercise 
Clause and the collapse  of  the belief/conduct distinction.  But it is hard to 
think of “secular” reasons for a nurse to refuse to get a flu vaccination, 
given the risk not only to herself—which raises obvious questions about 
paternalism—but also potential risks to her patients should she in fact come 
down with the flu and infect others in the hospital, who are by definition more 
vulnerable than ordinary persons with whom she might also come into contact.  
So, unless there really is some good reason to refuse flu vaccines—perhaps she 
is unusually sensitive to egg-based vaccines or something similar—I am 
disinclined to be at all sympathetic to her argument and would regard her 
firing as fully for cause.  I think the “freedom of expression” argument in 
this case is wacky given her job and responsibility for doing no harm to the 
sick.  Were I to receive this as an answer to a final exam 

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm still not sure I understand.  Let's say Justice Scalia thinks -- as 
seems quite plausible -- that the Free Exercise Clause is best interpreted as 
not securing religious exemptions.  And let's say that he also thinks, as is 
also quite possible, that (1) there's no constitutional bar to Congress's 
providing by statute what the Free Exercise Clause does not itself provide, (2) 
it's not for secular courts to second-guess claimants' sincere claims that the 
law violates their religious beliefs, based on a judgment that those beliefs 
are based on too tenuous causal connections, and (3) the proposed exemption 
doesn't interfere with the rights and freedoms of others.  I can't really see 
how it would be proper for him to take a different approach because he wants 
people to take a more nuanced view of him or because he wants to convic[e] 
people that the Supreme Court deserves respect.

Now of course if there's a sound substantive argument for why, for 
instance, RFRA is unconstitutional, then by hypothesis Justice Scalia should be 
persuaded by it.  But what would that argument be?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of mallamud
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 9:44 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz
 
 People with whom I speak view Justice Scalia as a staunch conservative.
 They also associate deference to religion as a conservative position.
 If Scalia were to use what he obviously knows from his decision in Smith to 
 deny
 religious exemptions based on tenuous connections where they interfere with
 the rights and freedoms of others, I think some people might take a more
 nuanced view of him.  One small step in convincing people that the Supreme
 Court deserves respect because the Justices decide based on their best 
 judgment
 of the good of the country and not on preconceived liberal or conservative
 biases.  [Sub-point: Just as Scalia pointed to the wildly overwhelming 
 majority by
 which Sec. 5 of the VRA was extended for 25 years, I feel that one reason for 
 the
 enactment or RFRA, again, an overwhelming majority, stemmed from liberals'
 dislike of Scalia.  Clearly not suitable as a decisional factor, but it 
 undermines the
 statute in my personal opinion.]
 
  Jon
 
 On 2014-06-08 12:24, Volokh, Eugene wrote:
  I appreciate the general concerns raised in Jon Mallamud's post -- but
  I just don't see how items 1 to 5 lead to the conclusion in item
  6
  about Hobby Lobby.  Could you elaborate, please, why it would not be
  wis[e] for Justice Scalia to view RFRA as constitutional as to
  federal laws, and as justifying Hobby Lobby's claims in this case?
  The conclusion that the standard rejected in Smith is an unsound
  interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause doesn't obviously mean that
  Congress lacks the power to implement such a standard in a statute.
  Maybe that is ultimately the correct conclusion, but I think that it
  needs some more justification.
 
  Eugene
 
  Jon Mallamud writes:
 
   6. I find that the reasons behind Employment Division v. Smith
  (which I have come to believe stated the best rule) apply to the
  evils of using the standard rejected in Smith in applying all federal
  statutes.  So in Hobby Lobby I would like to see Justice Scalia find
  a way to apply his wisdom rather than his past predilection to
  enforce statutes no matter what the result. I was upset when he
  failed to enforce limits to the Commerce Clause in extending federal
  law to state authorization of the use of medical marijuana.  Perhaps
  some day I will get to see why he did that and come to appreciate his
  view as I have his views in Smith.
  ___
  To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,
  unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
  http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
  Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
  private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
  posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can
  (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe,
 change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get 

Re: FW: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires Acceptance of Secular Reasons As Well

2014-06-08 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
I'm fairly certain that the current court would uphold the current uga
policy without extending it to secular excuses. I'm just not sure that we
can come up with a justification for it that makes any sense as a policy
matter.

On Sunday, June 8, 2014, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

I’m not positive what the right answer is (though I don’t
 agree with the Free Exercise Clause cases holding that, if the government
 provides secular exceptions, it must also provide religious exceptions).
 I’m just curious about what other people think should happen in situations
 such as the ones involved in the New Jersey case.



 As I understand it, Cutter v. Wilkinson concludes that exemptions limited
 to religious believers are generally constitutionally permissible, so the
 UGA policy you describe is sound even in the absence of comparable secular
 exemptions.  The New Jersey decision, on the other hand, seems to point in
 the opposite direction, albeit in an unusual procedural posture.  Which is
 right?



Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 javascript:_e(%7B%7D,'cvml','religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu');
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 javascript:_e(%7B%7D,'cvml','religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu');] *On
 Behalf Of *Hillel Y. Levin
 *Sent:* Sunday, June 08, 2014 3:12 AM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: FW: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires
 Acceptance of Secular Reasons As Well



 Eugene:



 Are you asking whether religion is a one way ratchet? Under at least one
 reading of Smith/Lukumi, as typified in the Tenafly eruv case, if there are
 (at least some kinds of) secular exceptions, then there must also be a
 religious exception. But if there is a religious exception, must there also
 be secular exceptions? And if so, what kinds of secular exceptions must
 there be--those that rise to the level of conscientious objection status,
 or others as well?



 For what it is worth, I get an email from UGA each year reminding me that
 it is university policy to accommodate (to the maximum degree possible,
 whatever that means) religious students' ability to miss class for
 religious observances. I do not get such an email regarding students who
 miss class because their siblings are getting married, their pets are in
 poor health, or their great aunts (who were like second mothers) died. What
 to make of that?

 On Saturday, June 7, 2014, Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu
 wrote:

 I would always want to know the rationale and why it didn't apply to the
 religious person as well. But if ever I'm disinclined to be sympathetic to
 the flat out equal treatment, it's in this instance, and I continue to
 wonder why there's a religious exemption. I presume that a religious person
 wouldn't be allowed to smoke on premises even if she belonged to a
 religious sect that commanded chain smoking. I see no difference with
 regard to the flu shot. But, by stipulation, if the rule had nothing to do
 with patients' health, then I'd be inclined to treat secular and religious
 alike.



 Sandy



 Sandy


 Sent from my iPhone


 On Jun 7, 2014, at 9:02 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

I agree entirely on the bottom line, but let me ask what
 would happen in the absence of concerns about harm to the sick.  Say an
 employer has a uniform policy that bars headgear, but exempts religious
 objectors; and say that a secular employee insists on wearing a hat to
 work, and is fired for it.  Should the employee be seen as constitutionally
 entitled to unemployment compensation, on a rationale similar to that given
 by the New Jersey appellate court?



Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Levinson,
 Sanford V
 *Sent:* Friday, June 06, 2014 9:00 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* RE: Religious Exemption From Vaccination Policy Requires
 Acceptance of Secular Reasons As Well



 OK, I’ll bite;  Religious exemptions, at the end of the day,  honor
 beliefs that secularists by definition must regard as “irrational,” i.e.,
 incapable of being defended by reference to “standard-model” scientific
 argument.  There may be good reasons for allowing such exemption in the
 name of preserving civil peace, etc., or it



-- 
Hillel Y. Levin
Associate Professor
University of Georgia
School of Law
120 Herty Dr.
Athens, GA 30602
(678) 641-7452
hle...@uga.edu
hillelle...@gmail.com
SSRN Author Page:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe 

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread mallamud

Eugene,

I agree that it would [not] be proper for him to take a different

approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court
deserves respect.


Judges must make decisions based on their best judgment without 
regard to whether people would like them.  It is for law professors, 
lawyers and others to evaluate decisions.  I do think there is an 
obligation for legally trained people to defend as well as criticize the 
Supreme Court and I believe that given the partisanship that may tear 
our country apart, the time to do so is now. I also do not believe 
Justices must stick to the views they had before they were appointed. 
They need to reevaluate those views in the light of changed 
circumstances and the broader perspective from the view from the highest 
court.


Thus, I just hope he sees the problem as he did in Smith and weighs 
that against a statute that, if interpreted broadly, would go against 
the policy of the free speech clauses: to let people of many different 
views to live together in harmony.  The application of strict scrutiny 
to protect all religious views would be extremely disruptive.


 I believe based on arguments Marci makes that RFRA is 
unconstitutional, but despite her brief, I do not think that that is at 
issue in Hobby Lobby.


   Jon







On 2014-06-08 12:58, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

I'm still not sure I understand.  Let's say Justice Scalia thinks --
as seems quite plausible -- that the Free Exercise Clause is best
interpreted as not securing religious exemptions.  And let's say that
he also thinks, as is also quite possible, that (1) there's no
constitutional bar to Congress's providing by statute what the Free
Exercise Clause does not itself provide, (2) it's not for secular
courts to second-guess claimants' sincere claims that the law 
violates

their religious beliefs, based on a judgment that those beliefs are
based on too tenuous causal connections, and (3) the proposed
exemption doesn't interfere with the rights and freedoms of others.  
I

can't really see how it would be proper for him to take a different
approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court
deserves respect.

Now of course if there's a sound substantive argument for why, for
instance, RFRA is unconstitutional, then by hypothesis Justice Scalia
should be persuaded by it.  But what would that argument be?

Eugene


-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of mallamud
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 9:44 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

People with whom I speak view Justice Scalia as a staunch 
conservative.
They also associate deference to religion as a conservative 
position.
If Scalia were to use what he obviously knows from his decision in 
Smith to deny
religious exemptions based on tenuous connections where they 
interfere with
the rights and freedoms of others, I think some people might take a 
more
nuanced view of him.  One small step in convincing people that the 
Supreme
Court deserves respect because the Justices decide based on their 
best judgment
of the good of the country and not on preconceived liberal or 
conservative
biases.  [Sub-point: Just as Scalia pointed to the wildly 
overwhelming majority by
which Sec. 5 of the VRA was extended for 25 years, I feel that one 
reason for the
enactment or RFRA, again, an overwhelming majority, stemmed from 
liberals'
dislike of Scalia.  Clearly not suitable as a decisional factor, but 
it undermines the

statute in my personal opinion.]

 Jon

On 2014-06-08 12:24, Volokh, Eugene wrote:
 I appreciate the general concerns raised in Jon Mallamud's post -- 
but

 I just don't see how items 1 to 5 lead to the conclusion in item
 6
 about Hobby Lobby.  Could you elaborate, please, why it would not 
be

 wis[e] for Justice Scalia to view RFRA as constitutional as to
 federal laws, and as justifying Hobby Lobby's claims in this case?
 The conclusion that the standard rejected in Smith is an unsound
 interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause doesn't obviously mean 
that
 Congress lacks the power to implement such a standard in a 
statute.
 Maybe that is ultimately the correct conclusion, but I think that 
it

 needs some more justification.

Eugene

 Jon Mallamud writes:

  6. I find that the reasons behind Employment Division v. 
Smith

 (which I have come to believe stated the best rule) apply to the
 evils of using the standard rejected in Smith in applying all 
federal
 statutes.  So in Hobby Lobby I would like to see Justice Scalia 
find

 a way to apply his wisdom rather than his past predilection to
 enforce statutes no matter what the result. 

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
Unlike Jon, I believe RFRA was constitutional, but, as I've posted earlier, I 
regret ever more every day that Rehnquist did not assign the opinion to 
O'Connor, whose opinion at the time at detested because of what I thought was 
her lassitude on what counted as a compelling interest, but that is small beer 
indeed compared to the fact that had she been writing for the Court, the 
(perhaps fiction of) the compelling interest test would have been maintained 
even as it became ever more clear that compelling was not to be interpreted 
with inordinate strictness.  Instead, it is possible that we will get, courtesy 
of Justice Scalia and four allies, a remarkably wooden and divisive 
interpretation of RFRA that will have at least some of the consequences that 
Jon predicts.  Perhaps they will split the baby, a la Bakker, and decide, as I 
think is Doug's position, that Hobby Lobby is entitled to be heard on its 
claim, but that it fails becauses there is in fact what they will accept a!
 s a compelling interest' in favor of the contraception aspect of the mandate. 
 

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of mallamud
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 2:29 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Eugene,

 I agree that it would [not] be proper for him to take a different
 approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
 or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court 
 deserves respect.

 Judges must make decisions based on their best judgment without regard to 
whether people would like them.  It is for law professors, lawyers and others 
to evaluate decisions.  I do think there is an obligation for legally trained 
people to defend as well as criticize the Supreme Court and I believe that 
given the partisanship that may tear our country apart, the time to do so is 
now. I also do not believe Justices must stick to the views they had before 
they were appointed. 
They need to reevaluate those views in the light of changed circumstances and 
the broader perspective from the view from the highest court.

 Thus, I just hope he sees the problem as he did in Smith and weighs that 
against a statute that, if interpreted broadly, would go against the policy of 
the free speech clauses: to let people of many different views to live together 
in harmony.  The application of strict scrutiny to protect all religious views 
would be extremely disruptive.

  I believe based on arguments Marci makes that RFRA is unconstitutional, 
but despite her brief, I do not think that that is at issue in Hobby Lobby.

Jon







On 2014-06-08 12:58, Volokh, Eugene wrote:
 I'm still not sure I understand.  Let's say Justice Scalia thinks -- 
 as seems quite plausible -- that the Free Exercise Clause is best 
 interpreted as not securing religious exemptions.  And let's say that 
 he also thinks, as is also quite possible, that (1) there's no 
 constitutional bar to Congress's providing by statute what the Free 
 Exercise Clause does not itself provide, (2) it's not for secular 
 courts to second-guess claimants' sincere claims that the law violates 
 their religious beliefs, based on a judgment that those beliefs are 
 based on too tenuous causal connections, and (3) the proposed 
 exemption doesn't interfere with the rights and freedoms of others.
 I
 can't really see how it would be proper for him to take a different 
 approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
 or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court 
 deserves respect.

   Now of course if there's a sound substantive argument for why, for 
 instance, RFRA is unconstitutional, then by hypothesis Justice Scalia 
 should be persuaded by it.  But what would that argument be?

   Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw- 
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of mallamud
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 9:44 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

 People with whom I speak view Justice Scalia as a staunch 
 conservative.
 They also associate deference to religion as a conservative position.
 If Scalia were to use what he obviously knows from his decision in 
 Smith to deny religious exemptions based on tenuous connections where 
 they interfere with the rights and freedoms of others, I think some 
 people might take a more nuanced view of him.  One small step in 
 convincing people that the Supreme Court deserves respect because the 
 Justices decide based on their best judgment of the good of the 
 country and not on preconceived liberal or conservative biases.  
 [Sub-point: Just as Scalia pointed to the wildly overwhelming 
 majority by which Sec. 5 of the VRA was extended for 25 years, I feel 
 that one reason for the enactment or RFRA, again, 

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
Sandy (and Jon. etc.)--Why is an interpretation of RFRA for Hobby Lobby more 
divisive than an interpretation against?

And would any ruling for Hobby Lobby automatically be wooden? Given Kennedy's 
conflicting signals at oral argument, I suspect that if he has voted for Hobby 
Lobby--which I assume is necessary for Hobby Lobby to win--he might well be 
trying to craft his opinion narrowly. (Not that he always succeeds in making 
the confines of his opinions clear.)

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 3:37 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Unlike Jon, I believe RFRA was constitutional, but, as I've posted earlier, I 
regret ever more every day that Rehnquist did not assign the opinion to 
O'Connor, whose opinion at the time at detested because of what I thought was 
her lassitude on what counted as a compelling interest, but that is small beer 
indeed compared to the fact that had she been writing for the Court, the 
(perhaps fiction of) the compelling interest test would have been maintained 
even as it became ever more clear that compelling was not to be interpreted 
with inordinate strictness.  Instead, it is possible that we will get, courtesy 
of Justice Scalia and four allies, a remarkably wooden and divisive 
interpretation of RFRA that will have at least some of the consequences that 
Jon predicts.  Perhaps they will split the baby, a la Bakker, and decide, as I 
think is Doug's position, that Hobby Lobby is entitled to be heard on its 
claim, but that it fails becauses there is in fact what they will accept a!
 s a compelling interest' in favor of the contraception aspect of the mandate.

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of mallamud
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 2:29 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Eugene,

 I agree that it would [not] be proper for him to take a different
 approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
 or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court
 deserves respect.

 Judges must make decisions based on their best judgment without regard to 
whether people would like them.  It is for law professors, lawyers and others 
to evaluate decisions.  I do think there is an obligation for legally trained 
people to defend as well as criticize the Supreme Court and I believe that 
given the partisanship that may tear our country apart, the time to do so is 
now. I also do not believe Justices must stick to the views they had before 
they were appointed.
They need to reevaluate those views in the light of changed circumstances and 
the broader perspective from the view from the highest court.

 Thus, I just hope he sees the problem as he did in Smith and weighs that 
against a statute that, if interpreted broadly, would go against the policy of 
the free speech clauses: to let people of many different views to live together 
in harmony.  The application of strict scrutiny to protect all religious views 
would be extremely disruptive.

  I believe based on arguments Marci makes that RFRA is unconstitutional, 
but despite her brief, I do not think that that is at issue in Hobby Lobby.

Jon







On 2014-06-08 12:58, Volokh, Eugene wrote:
 I'm still not sure I understand.  Let's say Justice Scalia thinks --
 as seems quite plausible -- that the Free Exercise Clause is best
 interpreted as not securing religious exemptions.  And let's say that
 he also thinks, as is also quite possible, that (1) there's no
 constitutional bar to Congress's providing by statute what the Free
 Exercise Clause does not itself provide, (2) it's not for secular
 courts to second-guess claimants' sincere claims that the law violates
 their religious beliefs, based on a judgment that those beliefs are
 based on too tenuous causal connections, and (3) the proposed
 exemption doesn't interfere with the rights and freedoms of others.
 I
 can't really see how it would be proper for him to take a different
 approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
 or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court
 deserves respect.

   Now of course if there's a sound substantive argument for why, for
 instance, RFRA is 

Re: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Douglas Laycock
Protecting the civil liberties of all Americans used to be a liberal position. 
Now it's characterized as conservative if it includes free exercise of religion.

More Orwellian yet is the idea that crushing free exercise is the way to let 
people of many different views live together in harmony. Forcing religious 
minorities to suffer for conscience was the path to the wars of religion, not a 
path to living together in harmony. 

On Sun, 08 Jun 2014 15:28:56 -0400
 mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:
Eugene,

 I agree that it would [not] be proper for him to take a different
 approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
 or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court
 deserves respect.

 Judges must make decisions based on their best judgment without regard to 
 whether people would like them.  It is for law professors, lawyers and others 
 to evaluate decisions.  I do think there is an obligation for legally trained 
 people to defend as well as criticize the Supreme Court and I believe that 
 given the partisanship that may tear our country apart, the time to do so is 
 now. I also do not believe Justices must stick to the views they had before 
 they were appointed. They need to reevaluate those views in the light of 
 changed circumstances and the broader perspective from the view from the 
 highest court.

 Thus, I just hope he sees the problem as he did in Smith and weighs that 
 against a statute that, if interpreted broadly, would go against the policy 
 of the free speech clauses: to let people of many different views to live 
 together in harmony.  The application of strict scrutiny to protect all 
 religious views would be extremely disruptive.

  I believe based on arguments Marci makes that RFRA is unconstitutional, 
 but despite her brief, I do not think that that is at issue in Hobby Lobby.

Jon







On 2014-06-08 12:58, Volokh, Eugene wrote:
 I'm still not sure I understand.  Let's say Justice Scalia thinks --
 as seems quite plausible -- that the Free Exercise Clause is best
 interpreted as not securing religious exemptions.  And let's say that
 he also thinks, as is also quite possible, that (1) there's no
 constitutional bar to Congress's providing by statute what the Free
 Exercise Clause does not itself provide, (2) it's not for secular
 courts to second-guess claimants' sincere claims that the law violates
 their religious beliefs, based on a judgment that those beliefs are
 based on too tenuous causal connections, and (3) the proposed
 exemption doesn't interfere with the rights and freedoms of others.  I
 can't really see how it would be proper for him to take a different
 approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
 or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court
 deserves respect.

  Now of course if there's a sound substantive argument for why, for
 instance, RFRA is unconstitutional, then by hypothesis Justice Scalia
 should be persuaded by it.  But what would that argument be?

  Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of mallamud
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 9:44 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

 People with whom I speak view Justice Scalia as a staunch conservative.
 They also associate deference to religion as a conservative position.
 If Scalia were to use what he obviously knows from his decision in Smith to 
 deny
 religious exemptions based on tenuous connections where they interfere with
 the rights and freedoms of others, I think some people might take a more
 nuanced view of him.  One small step in convincing people that the Supreme
 Court deserves respect because the Justices decide based on their best 
 judgment
 of the good of the country and not on preconceived liberal or conservative
 biases.  [Sub-point: Just as Scalia pointed to the wildly overwhelming 
 majority by
 which Sec. 5 of the VRA was extended for 25 years, I feel that one reason 
 for the
 enactment or RFRA, again, an overwhelming majority, stemmed from liberals'
 dislike of Scalia.  Clearly not suitable as a decisional factor, but it 
 undermines the
 statute in my personal opinion.]

  Jon

 On 2014-06-08 12:24, Volokh, Eugene wrote:
  I appreciate the general concerns raised in Jon Mallamud's post -- but
  I just don't see how items 1 to 5 lead to the conclusion in item
  6
  about Hobby Lobby.  Could you elaborate, please, why it would not be
  wis[e] for Justice Scalia to view RFRA as constitutional as to
  federal laws, and as justifying Hobby Lobby's claims in this case?
  The conclusion that the standard rejected in Smith is an unsound
  interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause doesn't obviously mean that
  Congress lacks the power to implement such 

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
The answer to Tom's question is not only that it creates an incentive for 
strategic misrepresentations (which I don't regard as dispositive, because that 
arises in all religious exemption claims, including conscientious objection), 
but also, and far more seriously, that it would be yet one more grant by this 
ultra conservative Court of power to management at the cost of their employees 
(who are increasingly viewed by this Court as having only such rights as 
management chooses to respect).  I'm quite willing to support the right of the 
isolated baker or florist to refuse to bake a wedding cake or supply flowers 
because that has very few externalities (other, of course, than the stigma 
visited on the same sex would-be customers, but I agree with Doug that that is 
the price we pay for recognizing the rights of people we might regard as 
personally unattractive--I speak as someone who defended the right of the Ku 
Klux Klan to march down Congress Avenue in Austin).  

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Sandy (and Jon. etc.)--Why is an interpretation of RFRA for Hobby Lobby more 
divisive than an interpretation against?

And would any ruling for Hobby Lobby automatically be wooden? Given Kennedy's 
conflicting signals at oral argument, I suspect that if he has voted for Hobby 
Lobby--which I assume is necessary for Hobby Lobby to win--he might well be 
trying to craft his opinion narrowly. (Not that he always succeeds in making 
the confines of his opinions clear.)

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. Thomas 
School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 3:37 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Unlike Jon, I believe RFRA was constitutional, but, as I've posted earlier, I 
regret ever more every day that Rehnquist did not assign the opinion to 
O'Connor, whose opinion at the time at detested because of what I thought was 
her lassitude on what counted as a compelling interest, but that is small beer 
indeed compared to the fact that had she been writing for the Court, the 
(perhaps fiction of) the compelling interest test would have been maintained 
even as it became ever more clear that compelling was not to be interpreted 
with inordinate strictness.  Instead, it is possible that we will get, courtesy 
of Justice Scalia and four allies, a remarkably wooden and divisive 
interpretation of RFRA that will have at least some of the consequences that 
Jon predicts.  Perhaps they will split the baby, a la Bakker, and decide, as I 
think is Doug's position, that Hobby Lobby is entitled to be heard on its 
claim, but that it fails becauses there is in fact what they will accept a!
 s a compelling interest' in favor of the contraception aspect of the mandate.

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of mallamud
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 2:29 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Eugene,

 I agree that it would [not] be proper for him to take a different
 approach because he wants people to take a more nuanced view of him
 or because he wants to convic[e] people that the Supreme Court 
 deserves respect.

 Judges must make decisions based on their best judgment without regard to 
whether people would like them.  It is for law professors, lawyers and others 
to evaluate decisions.  I do think there is an obligation for legally trained 
people to defend as well as criticize the Supreme Court and I believe that 
given the partisanship that may tear our country apart, the time to do so is 
now. I also do not believe Justices must stick to the views they had before 
they were appointed.
They need to reevaluate those views in the light of changed circumstances and 
the broader perspective from the view from the highest court.

 Thus, I just hope he sees the problem as he did in Smith and weighs that 
against a statute that, if interpreted broadly, would go against the policy of 
the free speech clauses: to let people of many different views to live together 
in harmony.  The application of strict scrutiny to protect all religious views 
would be extremely disruptive.

 

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for Hobby 
Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively wrong. 
One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being divisive 
(undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the first 
place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should do 
only very limited work in religion cases.) 

On the substance, I too am not a fan of some Roberts Court rulings for 
employers (e.g. Ledbetter). But it seems to me there are possible rulings for 
Hobby Lobby that would not affect employees greatly--for example, the 
possibility, explored at oral argument, of extending to for-profit employers 
the same insurer-pays accommodation that now covers religious nonprofits.

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 5:58 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

The answer to Tom's question is not only that it creates an incentive for 
strategic misrepresentations (which I don't regard as dispositive, because that 
arises in all religious exemption claims, including conscientious objection), 
but also, and far more seriously, that it would be yet one more grant by this 
ultra conservative Court of power to management at the cost of their employees 
(who are increasingly viewed by this Court as having only such rights as 
management chooses to respect).  I'm quite willing to support the right of the 
isolated baker or florist to refuse to bake a wedding cake or supply flowers 
because that has very few externalities (other, of course, than the stigma 
visited on the same sex would-be customers, but I agree with Doug that that is 
the price we pay for recognizing the rights of people we might regard as 
personally unattractive--I speak as someone who defended the right of the Ku 
Klux Klan to march down Congress Avenue in Austin).

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Sandy (and Jon. etc.)--Why is an interpretation of RFRA for Hobby Lobby more 
divisive than an interpretation against?

And would any ruling for Hobby Lobby automatically be wooden? Given Kennedy's 
conflicting signals at oral argument, I suspect that if he has voted for Hobby 
Lobby--which I assume is necessary for Hobby Lobby to win--he might well be 
trying to craft his opinion narrowly. (Not that he always succeeds in making 
the confines of his opinions clear.)

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. Thomas 
School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 3:37 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Unlike Jon, I believe RFRA was constitutional, but, as I've posted earlier, I 
regret ever more every day that Rehnquist did not assign the opinion to 
O'Connor, whose opinion at the time at detested because of what I thought was 
her lassitude on what counted as a compelling interest, but that is small beer 
indeed compared to the fact that had she been writing for the Court, the 
(perhaps fiction of) the compelling interest test would have been maintained 
even as it became ever more clear that compelling was not to be interpreted 
with inordinate strictness.  Instead, it is possible that we will get, courtesy 
of Justice Scalia and four allies, a remarkably wooden and divisive 
interpretation of RFRA that will have at least some of the consequences that 
Jon predicts.  Perhaps they will split the baby, a la Bakker, and decide, as I 
think is Doug's position, that Hobby Lobby is entitled to be heard on its 
claim, but that it fails becauses there is in fact what they will accept a!
 

RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I agree with Tom that divisiveness arguments are best shied away from.  This 
was a favorite of Brennan in the school funding cases, and I never understood 
why those who supported funding on the basis that they could not otherwise 
enjoy their presumptive constitutional right to send their children to 
religious schools (Pierce) weren't as upset with the Court as, presumably, 
secularists would have been by knowing that their tax dollars were going to 
religious schools.   

The insurer pays accommodation depends, does it not, on the brute fact that 
contraception, when all is said and done, is less costly than pregnancy.  What 
if it were more costly?

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 6:34 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for Hobby 
Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively wrong. 
One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being divisive 
(undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the first 
place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should do 
only very limited work in religion cases.) 

On the substance, I too am not a fan of some Roberts Court rulings for 
employers (e.g. Ledbetter). But it seems to me there are possible rulings for 
Hobby Lobby that would not affect employees greatly--for example, the 
possibility, explored at oral argument, of extending to for-profit employers 
the same insurer-pays accommodation that now covers religious nonprofits.

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. Thomas 
School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 5:58 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

The answer to Tom's question is not only that it creates an incentive for 
strategic misrepresentations (which I don't regard as dispositive, because that 
arises in all religious exemption claims, including conscientious objection), 
but also, and far more seriously, that it would be yet one more grant by this 
ultra conservative Court of power to management at the cost of their employees 
(who are increasingly viewed by this Court as having only such rights as 
management chooses to respect).  I'm quite willing to support the right of the 
isolated baker or florist to refuse to bake a wedding cake or supply flowers 
because that has very few externalities (other, of course, than the stigma 
visited on the same sex would-be customers, but I agree with Doug that that is 
the price we pay for recognizing the rights of people we might regard as 
personally unattractive--I speak as someone who defended the right of the Ku 
Klux Klan to march down Congress Avenue in Austin).

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Sandy (and Jon. etc.)--Why is an interpretation of RFRA for Hobby Lobby more 
divisive than an interpretation against?

And would any ruling for Hobby Lobby automatically be wooden? Given Kennedy's 
conflicting signals at oral argument, I suspect that if he has voted for Hobby 
Lobby--which I assume is necessary for Hobby Lobby to win--he might well be 
trying to craft his opinion narrowly. (Not that he always succeeds in making 
the confines of his opinions clear.)

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. Thomas 
School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 3:37 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Unlike Jon, I believe RFRA was constitutional, but, as I've posted 

Divisiveness

2014-06-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most controversies, both 
sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be labeled as divisive.  
Government religious speech may be seen as divisive, because it may alienate 
members of other religious groups; but prohibitions on such speech, or 
litigation seeking such prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A 
pro-Hobby-Lobby decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision 
might be divisive.  Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision 
(or an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the 
implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, as Tom 
points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen as divisive -- 
but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which makes controversial 
judicially implemented religious accommodations possible, can apparently be 
divisive, too.

Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally here, and 
not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the potential divisiveness of 
decisions they dislike on substantive grounds, but don't even notice the 
divisiveness of decisions they think are sound.  After all, if one thinks a 
decision is sound, it's easy to view those who disagree as just unreasonable, 
so that their feelings of alienation don't really count (since they deserved to 
lose, and are now just being sore losers).

Of course, 

Eugene

Tom Berg writes:

 I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for 
 Hobby
 Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively 
 wrong.
 One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being divisive
 (undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the 
 first
 place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should do
 only very limited work in religion cases.)
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
Yes, the insurer-pays accommodation depends on contraception being less costly 
on net.  But since the administration has asserted that such is the case (in 
support of both the mandate itself and the accommodation), it seems to me the 
Court can and should proceed on that basis.  If the facts start turning out 
noticeably different, that might affect the whole politics of the issue (who 
knows?).

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 6:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

I agree with Tom that divisiveness arguments are best shied away from.  This 
was a favorite of Brennan in the school funding cases, and I never understood 
why those who supported funding on the basis that they could not otherwise 
enjoy their presumptive constitutional right to send their children to 
religious schools (Pierce) weren't as upset with the Court as, presumably, 
secularists would have been by knowing that their tax dollars were going to 
religious schools.

The insurer pays accommodation depends, does it not, on the brute fact that 
contraception, when all is said and done, is less costly than pregnancy.  What 
if it were more costly?

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 6:34 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for Hobby 
Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively wrong. 
One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being divisive 
(undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the first 
place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should do 
only very limited work in religion cases.)

On the substance, I too am not a fan of some Roberts Court rulings for 
employers (e.g. Ledbetter). But it seems to me there are possible rulings for 
Hobby Lobby that would not affect employees greatly--for example, the 
possibility, explored at oral argument, of extending to for-profit employers 
the same insurer-pays accommodation that now covers religious nonprofits.

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. Thomas 
School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 5:58 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

The answer to Tom's question is not only that it creates an incentive for 
strategic misrepresentations (which I don't regard as dispositive, because that 
arises in all religious exemption claims, including conscientious objection), 
but also, and far more seriously, that it would be yet one more grant by this 
ultra conservative Court of power to management at the cost of their employees 
(who are increasingly viewed by this Court as having only such rights as 
management chooses to respect).  I'm quite willing to support the right of the 
isolated baker or florist to refuse to bake a wedding cake or supply flowers 
because that has very few externalities (other, of course, than the stigma 
visited on the same sex would-be customers, but I agree with Doug that that is 
the price we pay for recognizing the rights of people we might regard as 
personally unattractive--I speak as someone who defended the right of the Ku 
Klux Klan to march down Congress Avenue in Austin).

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Sandy (and Jon. etc.)--Why is an interpretation of RFRA for Hobby Lobby more 
divisive than an interpretation against?

And would any ruling for 

Re: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Rick Garnett
Thanks, Tom. Here is the link, if anyone is interested, to the paper (now about 
8 years old!):

http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=855104

It seems to me, for what it's worth, that a ruling for Hobby Lobby would not 
(or need not) be wooden, divisive, or conservative, even if we think (or some 
of us think) that it highlights or confirms what some us might think are 
problems with the RFRA approach.

Best, Rick

Sent from my iPhone

 On Jun 8, 2014, at 4:36 PM, Berg, Thomas C. tcb...@stthomas.edu wrote:

 I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for 
 Hobby Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) 
 substantively wrong. One could just as easily charge the Obama administration 
 with being divisive (undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting 
 the mandate in the first place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments 
 about divisiveness should do only very limited work in religion cases.)

 On the substance, I too am not a fan of some Roberts Court rulings for 
 employers (e.g. Ledbetter). But it seems to me there are possible rulings for 
 Hobby Lobby that would not affect employees greatly--for example, the 
 possibility, explored at oral argument, of extending to for-profit employers 
 the same insurer-pays accommodation that now covers religious nonprofits.

 -
 Thomas C. Berg
 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
 University of St. Thomas School of Law
 MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
 Phone: 651 962 4918
 Fax: 651 962 4881
 E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
 Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 5:58 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

 The answer to Tom's question is not only that it creates an incentive for 
 strategic misrepresentations (which I don't regard as dispositive, because 
 that arises in all religious exemption claims, including conscientious 
 objection), but also, and far more seriously, that it would be yet one more 
 grant by this ultra conservative Court of power to management at the cost of 
 their employees (who are increasingly viewed by this Court as having only 
 such rights as management chooses to respect).  I'm quite willing to support 
 the right of the isolated baker or florist to refuse to bake a wedding cake 
 or supply flowers because that has very few externalities (other, of course, 
 than the stigma visited on the same sex would-be customers, but I agree with 
 Doug that that is the price we pay for recognizing the rights of people we 
 might regard as personally unattractive--I speak as someone who defended the 
 right of the Ku Klux Klan to march down Congress Avenue in Austin).

 sandy

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:18 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

 Sandy (and Jon. etc.)--Why is an interpretation of RFRA for Hobby Lobby more 
 divisive than an interpretation against?

 And would any ruling for Hobby Lobby automatically be wooden? Given 
 Kennedy's conflicting signals at oral argument, I suspect that if he has 
 voted for Hobby Lobby--which I assume is necessary for Hobby Lobby to win--he 
 might well be trying to craft his opinion narrowly. (Not that he always 
 succeeds in making the confines of his opinions clear.)

 -
 Thomas C. Berg
 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. Thomas 
 School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
 Phone: 651 962 4918
 Fax: 651 962 4881
 E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
 Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 3:37 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

 Unlike Jon, I believe RFRA was constitutional, but, as I've posted earlier, I 
 regret ever more every day that Rehnquist did not assign the opinion to 
 O'Connor, whose opinion at the time at detested because of what I thought was 
 her lassitude on what counted as a compelling interest, but that is small 
 beer indeed compared to the fact that had she been writing for the Court, the 
 (perhaps 

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Whoops, hit enter too early -- please disregard the Of course,.

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:55 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Divisiveness
 
   I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most controversies, both
 sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be labeled as divisive.
 Government religious speech may be seen as divisive, because it may alienate
 members of other religious groups; but prohibitions on such speech, or 
 litigation
 seeking such prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A pro-Hobby-Lobby
 decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision might be 
 divisive.
 Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision (or an anti-Hobby-
 Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the implementation of the
 mandate without a broad religious exemption, as Tom points out.  The
 Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen as divisive -- but the RFRA
 regime, or the Sherbert regime, which makes controversial judicially
 implemented religious accommodations possible, can apparently be divisive,
 too.
 
   Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally here, and not
 with a focus on this list -- can easily see the potential divisiveness of 
 decisions
 they dislike on substantive grounds, but don't even notice the divisiveness of
 decisions they think are sound.  After all, if one thinks a decision is 
 sound, it's
 easy to view those who disagree as just unreasonable, so that their feelings 
 of
 alienation don't really count (since they deserved to lose, and are now just 
 being
 sore losers).
 
   Of course,
 
   Eugene
 
 Tom Berg writes:
 
  I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling
  for Hobby Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly)
 substantively wrong.
  One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being 
  divisive
  (undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in
  the first place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about
  divisiveness should do only very limited work in religion cases.)
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe,
 change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-08 Thread mallamud
I am not suggesting that divisiveness should be a rule of decision.  
Rather the purpose of the religion clauses is to allow people with 
strong, differing views live together in reasonable harmony.  Thus in 
interpreting religious exemptions the Court needs to keep that principle 
in mind.  Perhaps the Hobby Lobby decision itself is not important, but 
it will set a precedent.  As far as I am concerned medical insurance 
provided by the employer is compensation and the employer should not be 
able to limit an employee's use of compensation. If the religious view 
that enabling someone else to get an abortion, or birth control that the 
employer, but not the medical profession, regards as abortion, then 
almost any arguably religious based claim must be upheld.  That, I 
suggest, would give people defining their own religious beliefs an 
exemption to interfere with the rights of others.  And a country where 
religious people, but not others, need not obey the general laws of the 
land is not the way to help the religious and the non-religious live 
together in reasonable peace.  So what I am talking about is not the 
consequences of any one decision, but of a general interpretation of 
religious exemptions.


I do realize that Congress has the right to enact federal law with 
exceptions, but as with conscientious objection, I do not think it is 
proper to treat non-religious people unequally.  I have never seen an 
argument that the due process clause limits the religion clauses 
although I have seen equal protection reasoning use in free speech 
cases.


Someone (maybe off-list) suggested that treating for-profit companies 
like non-profit groups and allowing them to put the cost of coverage on 
the insurance companies on the theory that there is no significant cost 
to the companies of covering contraception would solve the problem.  But 
as I understand it, the Little Sisters of the Poor will not certify that 
they have a religious objection to covering abortion because that 
certification would facilitate their employees in obtaining such 
services.


Finally, I realize that there are many other problems with other 
freedoms stemming from mandated health insurance coverage.  For example, 
should employers be allowed to refuse to hire smokers, or people who eat 
junk food, or who drink the Big Gulp at fast food places?  There was a 
case argued before the NY Court of Appeals last week about whether the 
Board of Health in New York City had the power to prohibit serving sodas 
in containers larger than a specified size.  But I realize this goes 
beyond the list. To avoid an inconsistency argument  in stating that 
employers should not control the use of compensation by employees based 
on the employers' religious views I mention this.  I know there might be 
competing considerations in other areas.  And I am not taking a position 
on them now.


   Jon

On 2014-06-08 19:54, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most controversies,
both sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be labeled as
divisive.  Government religious speech may be seen as divisive,
because it may alienate members of other religious groups; but
prohibitions on such speech, or litigation seeking such prohibition,
may be as divisive or more so.  A pro-Hobby-Lobby decision might be
divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision might be divisive.  
Indeed,

academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision (or an
anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the
implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, as
Tom points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen
as divisive -- but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which
makes controversial judicially implemented religious accommodations
possible, can apparently be divisive, too.

Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally here, and
not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the potential
divisiveness of decisions they dislike on substantive grounds, but
don't even notice the divisiveness of decisions they think are sound.
After all, if one thinks a decision is sound, it's easy to view those
who disagree as just unreasonable, so that their feelings of
alienation don't really count (since they deserved to lose, and are
now just being sore losers).

Of course,

Eugene

Tom Berg writes:

I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a 
ruling for Hobby
Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) 
substantively wrong.
One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being 
divisive
(undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate 
in the first
place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness 
should do

only very limited work in religion cases.)

___
To post, send message to 

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-08 Thread Alan Brownstein
If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision than 
Eugene is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a 
decision was one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the 
sense that if government could promote religion (or interfere with religion) 
religious groups would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as 
religious groups in order to make sure that it was their faith that the 
government promoted and that it was not their faith that was subject to 
government interference. Placing a church-state issue beyond the scope of 
political decision-making by subjecting it to constitutional constraints 
avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of political/religious divisions. 

There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

Alan Brownstein














From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:54 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Divisiveness

I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most controversies, both 
sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be labeled as divisive.  
Government religious speech may be seen as divisive, because it may alienate 
members of other religious groups; but prohibitions on such speech, or 
litigation seeking such prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A 
pro-Hobby-Lobby decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision 
might be divisive.  Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision 
(or an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the 
implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, as Tom 
points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen as divisive -- 
but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which makes controversial 
judicially implemented religious accommodations possible, can apparently be 
divisive, too.

Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally here, and 
not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the potential divisiveness of 
decisions they dislike on substantive grounds, but don't even notice the 
divisiveness of decisions they think are sound.  After all, if one thinks a 
decision is sound, it's easy to view those who disagree as just unreasonable, 
so that their feelings of alienation don't really count (since they deserved to 
lose, and are now just being sore losers).

Of course,

Eugene

Tom Berg writes:

 I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for 
 Hobby
 Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively 
 wrong.
 One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being divisive
 (undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the 
 first
 place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should do
 only very limited work in religion cases.)
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

2014-06-08 Thread Alan Brownstein
And, of course, the government could pick up the additional costs to the 
insurer. That would spread the costs of protecting religious liberty so that it 
would not fall exclusively (and heavily) on the employees of religiously exempt 
employers.

Alan


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Berg, Thomas C. [tcb...@stthomas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 5:34 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

Yes, the insurer-pays accommodation depends on contraception being less costly 
on net.  But since the administration has asserted that such is the case (in 
support of both the mandate itself and the accommodation), it seems to me the 
Court can and should proceed on that basis.  If the facts start turning out 
noticeably different, that might affect the whole politics of the issue (who 
knows?).

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 6:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

I agree with Tom that divisiveness arguments are best shied away from.  This 
was a favorite of Brennan in the school funding cases, and I never understood 
why those who supported funding on the basis that they could not otherwise 
enjoy their presumptive constitutional right to send their children to 
religious schools (Pierce) weren't as upset with the Court as, presumably, 
secularists would have been by knowing that their tax dollars were going to 
religious schools.

The insurer pays accommodation depends, does it not, on the brute fact that 
contraception, when all is said and done, is less costly than pregnancy.  What 
if it were more costly?

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 6:34 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for Hobby 
Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively wrong. 
One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being divisive 
(undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the first 
place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should do 
only very limited work in religion cases.)

On the substance, I too am not a fan of some Roberts Court rulings for 
employers (e.g. Ledbetter). But it seems to me there are possible rulings for 
Hobby Lobby that would not affect employees greatly--for example, the 
possibility, explored at oral argument, of extending to for-profit employers 
the same insurer-pays accommodation that now covers religious nonprofits.

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. Thomas 
School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Levinson, Sanford V [slevin...@law.utexas.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 5:58 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby/Ellen Katz

The answer to Tom's question is not only that it creates an incentive for 
strategic misrepresentations (which I don't regard as dispositive, because that 
arises in all religious exemption claims, including conscientious objection), 
but also, and far more seriously, that it would be yet one more grant by this 
ultra conservative Court of power to management at the cost of their employees 
(who are increasingly viewed by this Court as having only such rights as 
management chooses to respect).  I'm quite willing to support the right of the 
isolated baker or florist to refuse to bake a wedding cake or supply flowers 
because that has very few externalities (other, of course, than the stigma 
visited on the same sex would-be customers, but I agree with Doug that that is 
the price we pay for recognizing the rights of people we might regard as