Jeff, responses interleaved again …

 

Gary f.

 

 

-----Original Message-----
From: Jeffrey Brian Downard [mailto:jeffrey.down...@nau.edu] 
Sent: 8-Dec-15 14:10



Hello Jon S., Gary F., List,

 

Jon, given what you say in 1&2 below, then we do have a question.  Gary F. says 
that qualisigns are always icons, while you say that the icons are always based 
on the relation of the sign to the dynamical interpretant.

 

GF: There you go again, Jeff, writing “interpretant” when you mean “object”. 
Anyway, the icon is one of a trichotomy which is based on the relation of the 
sign to its object, and it is First in that trichotomy. That relation cannot be 
more complex than the sign in itself is, and that’s why any sign which is a 
qualisign (First in its own trichotomy) is necessarily an icon, which is First 
in the second trichotomy (based on the S-O relation).

 

What, then, should we say about the following kind of case that Peirce 
explicitly considers in his writings on perception.  In seeing a yellow chair 
with a green cushion, the awareness of the chair and pillow is a percept that 
serves as the immediate object.

 

GF: I can only assume that you are referring to CP 7.619, and observe that 
Peirce does not say explicitly that the percept serves as immediate object. 
That proposition seems at best dubious to me, because the percept is precisely 
the point where the dynamic/immediate object distinction does not apply. In 
fact it’s difficult to apply the sign/object distinction to the percept. 
Moreover, Peirce has almost nothing to say about signs in that entire long 
essay, and the little he does say is in reference to the perceptual judgment 
considered as a kind of natural proposition:

 

 

633. The other mode of definiteness of the percept consists in its being 
perfectly explicit. The perceptual judgment carelessly pronounces the chair 
yellow. What the particular shade, hue, and purity of the yellow may be it does 
not consider. The percept, on the other hand, is so scrupulously specific that 
it makes this chair different from every other in the world; or rather, it 
would do so if it indulged in any comparisons. 

634. It may be objected that the terms of the judgment resemble the percept. 
Let us consider, first, the predicate, 'yellow' in the judgment that 'this 
chair appears yellow.' This predicate is not the sensation involved in the 
percept, because it is general. It does not even refer particularly to this 
percept but to a sort of composite photograph of all the yellows that have been 
seen. If it resembles the sensational element of the percept, this resemblance 
consists only in the fact that a new judgment will predicate it of the percept, 
just as this judgment does. It also awakens in the mind an imagination 
involving a sensational element. But taking all these facts together, we find 
that there is no relation between the predicate of the perceptual judgment and 
the sensational element of the percept, except forceful connections. 

635. As for the subject of the perceptual judgment, as subject it is a sign. 
But it belongs to a considerable class of mental signs of which introspection 
can give hardly any account. It ought not to be expected that it should do so, 
since the qualities of these signs as objects have no relevancy to their 
significative character; for these signs merely play the part of demonstrative 
and relative pronouns, like “that,” or like the A, B, C, of which a lawyer or a 
mathematician avails himself in making complicated statements. In fact, the 
perceptual judgment which I have translated into “that chair is yellow” would 
be more accurately represented thus: “ is yellow,” a pointing index-finger 
taking the place of the subject. On the whole, it is plain enough that the 
perceptual judgment is not a copy, icon, or diagram of the percept, however 
rough. It may be reckoned as a higher grade of the operation of perception. 

 

On that basis, I don’t think we can extract from this passage any good 
information about what a qualisign is or how it works. What it does make clear 
is that the perceptual judgment is not iconic. So at this point I’m going to 
jump down to your concluding paragraph.

 

JD: The percept does not represent the chair.  Rather, it is a vague awareness 
that is largely characterized in following terms:  "it appears to me," "makes 
no professions of any kind," "It does not stand for anything," "I can’t dismiss 
is, as I would a fancy."

 

Peirce asks:  what logical bearing does the percept have upon knowledge and 
belief?  He says that it can be summed up in three precepts:

a. It contributes something positive.

b. It compels the perceiver to acknowledge it. 

c. It neither offers any reason for such acknowledgement nor makes any 
pretension to reasonableness. 

 

If the person perceiving the chair attends to the feeling of yellow, then this 
quality of feeling can stand as a qualisign so long as it bears the right kind 
of relationship to an interpretant.  In this case, the immediate interpretant 
is something like a schema in the imagination, which he describes as having the 
form of a skeleton of a set, which is a formal set of relations that can serve 
as a diagram of sorts.  To put things in quite simple terms:  the quality of 
the feeling of "yellow" can be thought of as a dot (a monadic kind of thing), 
that stands in a relation to the quality of feeling of "color," which is also 
pictured by Peirce as a dot on a page, and the relation of containment between 
yellow and color is pictured as a line between the dots.

 

So, what is the qualisign? It is not the quality of the feeling of yellow 
considered in isolation.  In order for such a quality to serve as a qualisign, 
Peirce claims that it must be considered in its relation to other qualities of 
the feeling--such as the various shades of yellow, the color green or the 
quality of color itself.  What is the immediate interpretant?  It is a possible 
diagram consisting of a skeleton of a set that can be constructed of the formal 
relations between these colors.  He calls the immediate interpretant the 
percipuum.  When he lays out what the percipuum is, it turns out that this 
interpretant is quite rich in its relation to past and future anticipated 
feelings--all of which are ordered in terms of such things are relative 
intensity, time, being spread in space, etc.

 

What then, is the character of the relation between the qualisign (the quality 
of the feeling of yellow) and the immediate object (the vague awareness of the 
yellow chair with the green cushion as a percept)?  Jon suggest that this 
relationship is not one of iconicity.  Such a term does not apply because this 
is an internal relation.  I suspect that this language of internal relation may 
prove to be quite helpful, because it is a general way of describing an 
important distinction between kinds of relations.  In "On a New List of 
Categories," Peirce draws on the scholastic distinction between relations of 
equiparance and disquiparance.  The former can fruitfully be thought of as 
internal relations of similarity.  How does this help us understand the opening 
moves in NDTR?  Peirce later found it necessary to modify the account of what 
relations of equiparance consist in:  

 

In my paper of 1867, I committed the error of identifying those relations 
constituted by non-relative characters with relations of equiparance, that is, 
with necessarily mutual relations, and the dynamical relations with relations 
of disquiparance, or possibly non-mutual relations. Subsequently, falling out 
of one error into another, I identified the two classes respectively with 
relations of reason and relations in re. (CP 1.567)

 

My hunch is that Peirce's examination genuinely triadic sign relations in NDTR 
is guided by his evolving understanding of what is necessary for establishing 
the kinds of ordered relations between the vague qualities of feelings in our 
percepts that are necessary for making comparisons between such things as the 
hue of a yellow chair and the hue of a green pillow.  In fact, I think he is 
attributing to the qualisign the features that are necessary to explain how 
such comparisons are possible (e.g., in the relatively uncontrolled inferences 
that give rise to our perceptual judgments).

 

GF: There is no vagueness in a percept; it’s a singular. So I don’t see how the 
concept of qualisign can serve the purpose you suggest here. I think the 
qualisign is simply a necessary result of Peirce’s introduction of the 
trichotomy of signs based on the sign’s mode of being in itself. It has to be 
First in that trichotomy.

 

--Jeff

 

Jeffrey Downard

Associate Professor

Department of Philosophy

Northern Arizona University

(o) 928 523-8354

-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to