BODY { font-family:Arial, Helvetica, sans-serif;font-size:12px;
}John, Francesco, list

        I'd like to thank you both for your posts of today - which, to me,
focus on the vital aspects of Peircean semiosis - namely, the
function of it as a logical pragmaticism.

        1] John wrote: "  But Peirce's logic was constant while his 
  terminology was changing.  Peirce put far more emphasis on mapping 
  logic to and from perception and action than anyone else.  But his 
  terminology was idiosyncratic.  His logic is the foundation for 
  relating his terminology to any versions in use today"

        I fully agree - Peirce changed his terms frequently and my view is
that the focus should not be to insist on a specific singular meaning
of a term, but to analyze the function of that term in the whole
system: that logic-of-pragmaticism. And by the way- I understand
logic as the foundation of all life, from the physico-chemical to the
biological to the human conceptual. So - logical processes and
pragmaticism are not human endeavours but are universal actions; that
is, they are all 'relations of reason' [see John's 5.448 quotations
below].

        2] With regard to my concern about a retreat into Platonic idealism,
this was based in the JAS concept of the 'genuine Sign' which is fully
general - about which Francesco has also queried. 

        3] And - making our ideas clear, to me, isn't based on insisting on
terms with singular definitive meanings that are not open to
interpretation but are instead authoritative as almost necessary
laws, but on interpretation - and this includes examining the logical
relations within the semiosic interaction - which action is always
triadic. Quite frankly, I think one can use different terms for these
semiosic relations; certainly, I think we can examine the works of
various researchers in physics, biology and cognition - and even
though they use different terms - I think we might see that they are
all talking about the same issues - those logical semiosic relations
that exist in the world.

        4]I acknowledge that my interest is in exploring the power of
Peircean semiosis to explain what is going on in the actual world -
in physics, chemistry, biology, economics and societies - and yes, I
claim that semiosis does function in all these realms. Because the
universe is logical.  As Peirce said - 

        "  It seems a strange thing, when one comes to ponder over it, that
a sign 
  should leave its interpreter to supply a part of its meaning; but
the 
  explanation of the phenomenon lies in the fact that the entire
universe 
 — not merely the universe of existents, but all that wider
universe, 
  embracing the universe of existents as a part, the universe which
we are 
  all accustomed to refer to as "the truth" — that all this
universe is 
  perfused with signs, if it is not composed exclusively of signs"
[5.448 #1]

        And by 'sign', I understand not the term but the process, the
triadic process of logical relations.

        Edwina
 On Fri 07/09/18 10:39 AM , John F Sowa s...@bestweb.net sent:
 Francesco, Edwina, and Jon AS, 
 FB 
 > "Subject and Object are the same thing except for trifling
distinctions" (EP 2:494) 
 Yes!  And they're the same as the "arguments" of relations by 
 logicians today.  This quotation and the others cited by Francesco 
 confirm the point I was trying to make:  From age 12 to 74, Peirce 
 was a logician.  Every version of logic that he used or invented 
 had a precise mapping to his algebra of 1885, to his later EGs, 
 and to the most widely used logics today. 
 Peirce was also a professional lexicographer.  Note his letter 
 to the editor of the Century Dictionary, Benjamin E. Smith, who 
 had also been one of his students at Johns Hopkins: 
 > The task of classifying all the words of language, or what's the 
 > same thing, all the ideas that seek expression, is the most 
 > stupendous of logical tasks. Anybody but the most accomplished 
 > logician must break down in it utterly; and even for the strongest

 > man, it is the severest possible tax on the logical equipment and 
 > faculty. 
 Implication:  Over the years, Peirce had described his logics and 
 the versions designed by other logicians in various ways.  He also 
 explored other versions in his Gamma graphs, 3-valued logic, modal 
 logics, and metalanguage.  But his first-order logic was equivalent 
 to the core (Alpha + Beta) of existential graphs, and to "classical 
 first-order logic" today.  For the history, see "Peirce the
logician" 
 by Hilary Putnam:  http://jfsowa.com/peirce/putnam.htm [1] 
 When trying to relate different terminologies by Peirce and others, 
 always ask how or whether they could be mapped to FOL.  If they 
 can't, then ask what extensions or variations would be needed. 
 ET 
 > I'm trying to emphasize... that Peircean semiotics is not 
 > expressed simply in language and/or logic, but in its pragmatic 
 > application to material life. 
 >  
 > My concern is that much of the focus of our examination of Peirce 
 > is often on terminology, on which term he used for..___. Since 
 > Peirce often changed these terms, then, to me, they are not the 
 > vital ground of Peircean semiosis and even sidesteps the
fundamental 
 > nature of Peircean semiotics - which is its pragmaticism.  
 I completely agree.  But Peirce's logic was constant while his 
 terminology was changing.  Peirce put far more emphasis on mapping 
 logic to and from perception and action than anyone else.  But his 
 terminology was idiosyncratic.  His logic is the foundation for 
 relating his terminology to any versions in use today. 
 That foundation is key to bringing Peirce into the 21st century. 
 Logicians, philosophers, and computer scientists today will never 
 study Peirce unless we can show exactly how his writings relate 
 to what they're doing now and what they still need to do. 
 JAS 
 > my own purpose in focusing so much on Peirce's concepts and 
 > terminology in logic as semeiotic is not for its own sake, but 
 > primarily for the purpose of making our ideas clear. 
 Yes. That was Peirce's motivation throughout his career.  And logic 
 was always his primary tool, as he said explicitly in 1877. 
 JAS 
 > Peirce defined pragmatism as "no attempt to determine any truth 
 > of things," but rather "merely a method of ascertaining the
meanings 
 > of hard words and of abstract concepts" (CP 5.464, EP 2:400;
1907). 
 Yes.  And remember his comment to Benjamin Smith. 
 JAS 
 > no one on the List is advocating "Platonic idealism." 
 > Why keep bringing it up? 
 I was citing Peirce's "three universes":  possibility, actuality, 
 and the necessitated.  Mathematical entities are "real possibles" 
 in Peirce's terms.  For an analysis of Peirce's ideas about these 
 issues, I recommend an article by Susan Haack: 

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/247935387_Peirce_and_Logicism_Notes_Towards_an_Exposition_1993
[2] 
 On page 9, she wrote 
 > at CP 4.118 (1893) Peirce speaks of "the Platonic world of pure 
 > forms with which mathematics is always dealing," and in the 
 > prospectus for his 12-volume _Principles of Philosophy_ (c. 1893) 
 > he entitles the third volume, _Plato's World: an Elucidation of 
 > the Ideas of Modern Mathematics_.  But at 4.161 (c. 1897) we
read... 
 > 
 > If this is Platonism, it is Platonism of a very distinctively 
 > Peircean stripe. 
 Edwina 
 > I think one can get trapped in the isolation of words and should 
 > instead, consider their function in the actual world. 
 Yes.  But Peirce claimed that math and logic, formal and informal, 
 are the foundation for all the sciences and all the ways of thinking

 and acting in the world.  (See his 1903 classification.) 
 William James could not fully understand Peirce because he did 
 not know logic.   WJ was never able to understand Peirce's 
 logic and his distinction between pragmatism and pragmaticism. 
 In the excerpts below, note that nearly every sentence uses logical 
 terminology.  (This excerpt happens to be something I was recently 
 reading, but you can find many more examples in all his writings.) 
 John 
 ___________________________________________________________________ 
 5.448.  Perhaps a more scientific pair of definitions would be that 
 anything is general in so far as the principle of excluded middle
does 
 not apply to it and is vague in so far as the principle of
contradiction 
 does not apply to it.†1 Thus, although it is true that "Any
proposition 
 you please, once you have determined its identity, is either true or

 false"; yet so long as it remains indeterminate and so without
identity, 
 it need neither be true that any proposition you please is true, nor

 that any proposition you please is false.  So likewise, while it is 
 false that "A proposition whose identity I have determined is both
true 
 and false," yet until it is determinate, it may be true that a 
 proposition is true and that a proposition is false.†P1 
 †P1 These remarks require supplementation.  Determination, in
general, 
 is not defined at all; and the attempt at defining the determination
of 
 a subject with respect to a character only covers (or seems only to 
 cover) explicit propositional determination.  The incidental remark 
 [447] to the effect that words whose meaning should be determinate
would 
 leave "no latitude of interpretation" is more satisfactory, since
the 
 context makes it plain that there must be no such latitude either
for 
 the interpreter or for the utterer.  The explicitness of the words
would 
 leave the utterer no room for explanations of his meaning.  This 
 definition has the advantage of being applicable to a command, to a 
 purpose, to a medieval substantial form; in short to anything
capable of 
 indeterminacy.  (That everything indeterminate is of the nature of a

 sign can be proved inductively by imagining and analyzing instances
of 
 the surdest description.  Thus, the indetermination of an event
which 
 should happen by pure chance without cause, /sua sponte/, as the
Romans 
 mythologically said, /spontanément /in French (as if what was done
of 
 one's own motion were sure to be irrational), does not belong to the

 event — say, an explosion — /per se/, or as explosion.  Neither
is it by 
 virtue of any real relation:  it is by virtue of a relation of
reason. 
 Now what is true by virtue of a relation of reason is
representative, 
 that is, is of the nature of a sign.  A similar consideration
applies to 
 the indiscriminate shots and blows of a Kentucky free fight.)  Even
a 
 future event can only be determinate in so far as it is a
consequent. 
 Now the concept of a consequent is a logical concept.  It is derived

 from the concept of the conclusion of an argument.  But an argument
is a 
 sign of the truth of its conclusion; its conclusion is the rational 
 interpretation of the sign.  This is in the spirit of the Kantian 
 doctrine that metaphysical concepts are logical concepts applied 
 somewhat differently from their logical application.  The
difference, 
 however, is not really as great as Kant represents it to be, and as
he 
 was obliged to represent it to be, owing to his mistaking the
logical 
 and metaphysical correspondents in almost every case.  Another
advantage 
 of this definition is that it saves us from the blunder of thinking
that 
 a sign is indeterminate simply because there is much to which it
makes 
 no reference; that, for example, to say, "C.S.  Peirce wrote this 
 article," is indeterminate because it does not say what the color of
the 
 ink used was, who made the ink, how old the father of the ink-maker 
 [was] when his son was born, nor what the aspect of the planets was
when 
 that father was born.  By making the definition turn upon the 
 interpretation, all that is cut off.  [Cf. 3.93.] 
 At the same time, it is tolerably evident that the definition, as it

 stands, is not sufficiently explicit, and further, that at the
present 
 stage of our inquiry cannot be made altogether satisfactory.  For
what 
 is the interpretation alluded to?  To answer that convincingly would
be 
 either to establish or to refute the doctrine of pragmaticism. 
Still 
 some explanations may be made.  Every sign has a single object,
though 
 this single object may be a single set or a single continuum of
objects. 
 No general description can identify an object.  But the common sense
of 
 the interpreter of the sign will assure him that the object must be
one 
 of a limited collection of objects.  Suppose, for example, two 
 Englishmen to meet in a continental railway carriage.  The total
number 
 of subjects of which there is any appreciable probability that one
will 
 speak to the other perhaps does not exceed a million; and each will
have 
 perhaps half that million not far below the surface of
consciousness, so 
 that each unit of it is ready to suggest itself.  If one mentions 
 Charles the Second, the other need not consider what possible
Charles 
 the Second is meant.  It is no doubt the English Charles Second. 
 Charles the Second of England was quite a different man on different

 days; and it might be said that without further specification the 
 subject is not identified.  But the two Englishmen have no purpose
of 
 splitting hairs in their talk; and the latitude of interpretation
which 
 constitutes the indeterminacy of a sign must be understood as a
latitude 
 which might affect the achievement of a purpose.  For two signs
whose 
 meanings are for all possible purposes equivalent are absolutely 
 equivalent.  This, to be sure, is rank pragmaticism; for a purpose
is an 
 affection of action. 
 What has been said of subjects is as true of predicates.  Suppose
the 
 chat of our pair of Englishmen had fallen upon the color of Charles
II's 
 hair.  Now that colors are seen quite differently by different
retinas 
 is known.  That the chromatic sense is much more varied than it is 
 positively known to be is quite likely.  It is very unlikely that
either 
 of the travelers is trained to observe colors or is a master of
their 
 nomenclature.  But if one says that Charles II had dark auburn hair,
the 
 other will understand him quite precisely enough for all their
possible 
 purposes; and it will be a determinate predication. 
 The October remarks [i.e. those in the above paper] made the proper 
 distinction between the two kinds of indeterminacy, viz.: 
 indefiniteness and generality, of which the former consists in the 
 sign's not sufficiently expressing itself to allow of an indubitable

 determinate interpretation, while the [latter] turns over to the 
 interpreter the right to complete the determination as he please. 
It 
 seems a strange thing, when one comes to ponder over it, that a sign

 should leave its interpreter to supply a part of its meaning; but
the 
 explanation of the phenomenon lies in the fact that the entire
universe 
 — not merely the universe of existents, but all that wider
universe, 
 embracing the universe of existents as a part, the universe which we
are 
 all accustomed to refer to as "the truth" — that all this universe
is 
 perfused with signs, if it is not composed exclusively of signs. 
Let us 
 note this in passing as having a bearing upon the question of 
 pragmaticism.  [Cf. 4.539.] 
 The October remarks, with a view to brevity, omitted to mention that

 both indefiniteness and generality might primarily affect either the

 logical breadth or the logical depth of the sign to which it
belongs. 
 It now becomes pertinent to notice this.  When we speak of the
depth, or 
 signification, of a sign we are resorting to hypostatic abstraction,

 that process whereby we regard a thought as a thing, make an 
 interpretant sign the object of a sign.  It has been a butt of
ridicule 
 since Molière's dying week, and the depth of a writer on philosophy
can 
 conveniently be sounded by his disposition to make fun of the basis
of 
 voluntary inhibition, which is the chief characteristic of mankind. 
For 
 cautious thinkers will not be in haste to deride a kind of thinking
that 
 is evidently founded upon observation — namely, upon observation
of a 
 sign.  At any rate, whenever we speak of a predicate we are
representing 
 a thought as a thing, as a substantia, since the concepts of
substance 
 and subject are one, its concomitants only being different in the
two 
 cases.  It is needful to remark this in the present connexion,
because, 
 were it not for hypostatic abstraction, there could be no generality
of 
 a predicate, since a sign which should make its interpreter its
deputy 
 to determine its signification at his pleasure would not signify 
 anything, unless nothing be its significate. — From "Basis of 
 Pragmaticism," 1906, following somewhat after 554. 


Links:
------
[1]
http://webmail.primus.ca/parse.php?redirect=http%3A%2F%2Fjfsowa.com%2Fpeirce%2Fputnam.htm
[2]
http://webmail.primus.ca/parse.php?redirect=https%3A%2F%2Fwww.researchgate.net%2Fpublication%2F247935387_Peirce_and_Logicism_Notes_Towards_an_Exposition_1993
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to