Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-23 Thread Russell Standish

On Fri, Dec 21, 2007 at 01:08:38PM +0100, Günther Greindl wrote:
 
 Hi Russell,
 
 Russell Standish wrote:
 
  In your first case, the number (1,1,1,1...) is not a natural number,
  since it is infinite. In the second case, (0,0,0,...) is a natural
  number, but is also on the list (at infinity).
 
 Why is (1,1,1,...) not in the list but (0,0,0,...) in the list at 
 infinity? This seems very arbitrary to me.

Quentin replied correctly on the first point. On the second point, the
list is assumed to contain all natural numbers. If that is true, the
0, which maps to the sequence (0,0,0...) must lie at infinity on the
list. If you don't accept this, then the enumeration given is not an
enumeration of the naturals, since 0 is then not on the list. Either
way falsifies the argument.

 
 I am becoming more and more an ultra-finitist. Arguments with infinity 
 seem to be very based on the assumptions you make (about platonia or 
 whatever)
 
 Regards,
 Günther
 
 
 -- 
 Günther Greindl
 Department of Philosophy of Science
 University of Vienna
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 http://www.univie.ac.at/Wissenschaftstheorie/
 
 Blog: http://dao.complexitystudies.org/
 Site: http://www.complexitystudies.org
 
 
-- 


A/Prof Russell Standish  Phone 0425 253119 (mobile)
Mathematics  
UNSW SYDNEY 2052 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Australiahttp://www.hpcoders.com.au


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-21 Thread Günther Greindl

Hi,

 Because zero even repeated an infinity of time is zero and is a natural 
 number. (1,1,1,...) can't be a natural number because it is not finite and a 
 natural number is finite. If it was a natural number, then N would not have a 
 total ordering.

Ok agreed: I was caught up in viewing it simply as an indexing scheme, 
but viewed constructively I of course agree. My error.

 I am becoming more and more an ultra-finitist. Arguments with infinity
 seem to be very based on the assumptions you make (about platonia or
 whatever)
 
 Finite and infinite concepts are dual concepts you can't leave one without 
 leaving the other.

Could you elaborate some more on this?

Regards,
Günther


-- 
Günther Greindl
Department of Philosophy of Science
University of Vienna
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://www.univie.ac.at/Wissenschaftstheorie/

Blog: http://dao.complexitystudies.org/
Site: http://www.complexitystudies.org

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-21 Thread Quentin Anciaux

Hi,

Le Friday 21 December 2007 13:08:38 Günther Greindl, vous avez écrit :
 Hi Russell,

 Russell Standish wrote:
  In your first case, the number (1,1,1,1...) is not a natural number,
  since it is infinite. In the second case, (0,0,0,...) is a natural
  number, but is also on the list (at infinity).

 Why is (1,1,1,...) not in the list but (0,0,0,...) in the list at
 infinity? This seems very arbitrary to me.

Because zero even repeated an infinity of time is zero and is a natural 
number. (1,1,1,...) can't be a natural number because it is not finite and a 
natural number is finite. If it was a natural number, then N would not have a 
total ordering.

 I am becoming more and more an ultra-finitist. Arguments with infinity
 seem to be very based on the assumptions you make (about platonia or
 whatever)

Finite and infinite concepts are dual concepts you can't leave one without 
leaving the other.

 Regards,
 Günther


Regards,
Quentin Anciaux

-- 
All those moments will be lost in time, like tears in rain.

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-21 Thread Günther Greindl

Hi Russell,

Russell Standish wrote:

 In your first case, the number (1,1,1,1...) is not a natural number,
 since it is infinite. In the second case, (0,0,0,...) is a natural
 number, but is also on the list (at infinity).

Why is (1,1,1,...) not in the list but (0,0,0,...) in the list at 
infinity? This seems very arbitrary to me.

I am becoming more and more an ultra-finitist. Arguments with infinity 
seem to be very based on the assumptions you make (about platonia or 
whatever)

Regards,
Günther


-- 
Günther Greindl
Department of Philosophy of Science
University of Vienna
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://www.univie.ac.at/Wissenschaftstheorie/

Blog: http://dao.complexitystudies.org/
Site: http://www.complexitystudies.org

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-20 Thread Bruno Marchal


Le 19-déc.-07, à 21:09, Barry Brent a écrit :


 Excellent, Bruno,  Thanks!

Well thanks. I will send a next diagonalization post and some 
references next week,

Best,

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-19 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi Barry,


Le 18-déc.-07, à 18:52, Barry Brent a écrit :


 Bruno--

 Ahh, my amateur status is nakedly exposed. I'm going to expose my
 confusion even further now.


That is the courageous attitude of the authentic scientists.
I like amateur because they have less prejudices, they have inner
motivations, and rarely follow authoritative arguments.



 Never heard of a universal language.  I thought I was familiar with
 Church's thesis, but apparently no.


As I said a while ago, coming back from an international meeting on
computability (in Siena, where my Plotinus' paper has been accepted), I
got the feeling that few people really grasp Church Thesis, including 
some
experts.
My Brussels thesis has been criticized  for being too much pedagogical
on Church thesis, but each time people try to debunk my work, soon
enough I realize they have a problem with Godel or Church, never (yet) 
with
my contribution.
The worst is that most people *feel* at ease with CT but apparently are 
not.
I take as an honor to explain this too you, I *do* appreciate your work 
in
Number Theory, as far as I understand it. Possible links could emerge.
(You make me discover also the nice paper on prime percolation by 
Vardi:
I love percolation. Not just because I am an amateur of good coffe, but 
because
exact percolation problem have led to the Temperley Lieb 
algebra/category; which
makes links between knot theory, combinators/lambda-calculus, quantum
computations, and eventually number theory, if not the number 24 
itself).



 I thought it was the claim that
 two or three or four concepts (including recursive function and
 computable function) were extensionally equivalent.  I have heard of
 the lambda calculus, but I don't know what it is, or what its
 connection is with Church's thesis.  I have a rough guess, based on
 what you're saying.  I'm surprised.  I imagine that the claim of
 existence of a universal language must be made in the context of a
 theory of languages?  Never heard of that theory.


This happens because the expression theory of languages is used in
the context of non universal languages, like in the Chomsky hierarchy 
of
languages for example. Universal languages and machines appears in
what is called computability theory or recursion theory.







 Well, if I  imagine such a theory, it must involve both syntax and
 semantics, yes?  Semantics connects a language to a world, right?
 (The experts are cringing, I'm sure)  Can one language encompass
 all possible worlds?  Can't we imagine worlds, the structures of
 which are so dissonant, that their languages could never be
 consistently subsumed under some single larger (universal)
 language?  (More cringing, no doubt)  Or, is it that when we
 restrict the worlds in question to some suitable realm--say, numbers--
 all these things work out?  (Cringes redoubled!)  I can imagine other
 ways out.  Maybe we're concerned with just one world, suitably
 described.  Maybe structural inconsistencies of possible worlds are
 no more an impediment to being expressible in one language than
 logical inconsistencies?  (But how do we know?)


We have to distinguish logic and computability. In logic we will have
language in which sentences are to be interpreted in some world/model.
But in computability we can go very far by just interpreting them in 
some
procedural way. The expressions in computer language are really basic
instruction like in the coffee-bar machine. Eventually we can describe 
them
all in term of NAND gates, delay and electrical current.
A computing language is then universal if all computable functions 
(from N
to N, or from finite things coded in N to finite things coded in N) can 
be
computed by following a finite set of instructions in the language.




 What about cardinality? From your remarks, I imagine that the number
 of elementary symbols in any language, including the universal
 language, is supposed to be finite,


Yes.



 so that the set of algorithms is
 countable?


Yes. And so are the computable functions.




 If there are lots of worlds and languages, I wonder how
 people make that work.


Because all the languages or machines which have been
invented for computing (computable) functions from N to N, have
been shown equivalent, and that the closure of the set of computable
functions by those machines, for the (transcendental) diagonalization
procedure, give a powerful argument that those language/machine
are universal.
Careful: they are universal with respect to the class of computable
functions. They are not universal with respect to the propositions they
can express or prove. A universal language/machine is not a theory.
Most universal language don't even have a way to assert propositions,
just some sort of commands (cf the coffee-bar instructions as example).





 Is such a language going to be adequate for
 expressing propositions about all possible worlds?  How do we know?


In computing, well ... like in Number theory, 

Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-19 Thread Barry Brent

Excellent, Bruno,  Thanks!

Barry

On Dec 19, 2007, at 7:57 AM, Bruno Marchal wrote:


 Hi Barry,


 Le 18-déc.-07, à 18:52, Barry Brent a écrit :


 Bruno--

 Ahh, my amateur status is nakedly exposed. I'm going to expose my
 confusion even further now.


 That is the courageous attitude of the authentic scientists.
 I like amateur because they have less prejudices, they have inner
 motivations, and rarely follow authoritative arguments.



 Never heard of a universal language.  I thought I was familiar with
 Church's thesis, but apparently no.


 As I said a while ago, coming back from an international meeting on
 computability (in Siena, where my Plotinus' paper has been  
 accepted), I
 got the feeling that few people really grasp Church Thesis, including
 some
 experts.
 My Brussels thesis has been criticized  for being too much  
 pedagogical
 on Church thesis, but each time people try to debunk my work, soon
 enough I realize they have a problem with Godel or Church, never (yet)
 with
 my contribution.
 The worst is that most people *feel* at ease with CT but apparently  
 are
 not.
 I take as an honor to explain this too you, I *do* appreciate your  
 work
 in
 Number Theory, as far as I understand it. Possible links could emerge.
 (You make me discover also the nice paper on prime percolation by
 Vardi:
 I love percolation. Not just because I am an amateur of good coffe,  
 but
 because
 exact percolation problem have led to the Temperley Lieb
 algebra/category; which
 makes links between knot theory, combinators/lambda-calculus, quantum
 computations, and eventually number theory, if not the number 24
 itself).



 I thought it was the claim that
 two or three or four concepts (including recursive function and
 computable function) were extensionally equivalent.  I have heard of
 the lambda calculus, but I don't know what it is, or what its
 connection is with Church's thesis.  I have a rough guess, based on
 what you're saying.  I'm surprised.  I imagine that the claim of
 existence of a universal language must be made in the context of a
 theory of languages?  Never heard of that theory.


 This happens because the expression theory of languages is used in
 the context of non universal languages, like in the Chomsky  
 hierarchy
 of
 languages for example. Universal languages and machines appears in
 what is called computability theory or recursion theory.







 Well, if I  imagine such a theory, it must involve both syntax and
 semantics, yes?  Semantics connects a language to a world, right?
 (The experts are cringing, I'm sure)  Can one language encompass
 all possible worlds?  Can't we imagine worlds, the structures of
 which are so dissonant, that their languages could never be
 consistently subsumed under some single larger (universal)
 language?  (More cringing, no doubt)  Or, is it that when we
 restrict the worlds in question to some suitable realm--say,  
 numbers--
 all these things work out?  (Cringes redoubled!)  I can imagine other
 ways out.  Maybe we're concerned with just one world, suitably
 described.  Maybe structural inconsistencies of possible worlds are
 no more an impediment to being expressible in one language than
 logical inconsistencies?  (But how do we know?)


 We have to distinguish logic and computability. In logic we will have
 language in which sentences are to be interpreted in some world/model.
 But in computability we can go very far by just interpreting them in
 some
 procedural way. The expressions in computer language are really basic
 instruction like in the coffee-bar machine. Eventually we can describe
 them
 all in term of NAND gates, delay and electrical current.
 A computing language is then universal if all computable functions
 (from N
 to N, or from finite things coded in N to finite things coded in N)  
 can
 be
 computed by following a finite set of instructions in the language.




 What about cardinality? From your remarks, I imagine that the number
 of elementary symbols in any language, including the universal
 language, is supposed to be finite,


 Yes.



 so that the set of algorithms is
 countable?


 Yes. And so are the computable functions.




 If there are lots of worlds and languages, I wonder how
 people make that work.


 Because all the languages or machines which have been
 invented for computing (computable) functions from N to N, have
 been shown equivalent, and that the closure of the set of computable
 functions by those machines, for the (transcendental) diagonalization
 procedure, give a powerful argument that those language/machine
 are universal.
 Careful: they are universal with respect to the class of computable
 functions. They are not universal with respect to the propositions  
 they
 can express or prove. A universal language/machine is not a theory.
 Most universal language don't even have a way to assert propositions,
 just some sort of commands (cf the coffee-bar instructions as  
 example).





 

Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-18 Thread Bruno Marchal


Le 17-déc.-07, à 19:04, meekerdb (Brent Meeker) wrote:


 Bruno wrote:
 Exercise:
 What is wrong with the following argument. (I recall that by 
 definition
 a function from N to N is defined on all natural numbers).

 (false) theorem: the set of computable functions from N to N is not
 enumerable.
 (erroneous) proof: let us suppose (by absurdum) that the set of
 computable functions from N to N is enumerable. Thus there exist an
 enumeration f_1, f_2, f_3, ... f_i,  of the computable functions
 from N to N. But then I can define the following computable function 
 g,
 from N to N, by:

 g(n) = f_n(n) + 1

 g is computable: to compute it just search in the enumeration the
 function f_n, which is computable, and then apply it on n, and then 
 add 1.
 But then g has to be in that enumeration f_i of the computable 
 function.
 Thus there is a k such that g = f_k. In particular g(k) = f_k(k). But
 g(k) = f_k(k) + 1, by definition of g. Thus f_k(k) = f_k(k)+1. And the
 f_i are computable functions, so f_k(k) is a well defined number, 
 which
 I can subtract on the left and the right side of f_k(k) = f_k(k)+1,
 giving 0 = 1. Contradiction. So the set of computable functions from N
 to N is not enumerable.

 What is wrong? We know that the set of computable function has to be
 enumerable, because computable means we can describe how to compute
 the function in a finite expression in some language, and the set of 
 all
 finite expressions has been shown enumerable. So what happens?

 If you tried to compute g(k) and g was in the list, i.e. some f_k, 
 then when
 you searched a for g, when you came to f_k it would start with the
 prescription ...just search in the enumeration... and you would be 
 in a
 infinite loop.



This is a bit fuzzy, but then the exercise was a bit fuzzy too, so I can
considered this as correct. More below.




Barry Brent wrote:

 Brent, I don't think this is enough.  There may be a different
 algorithm for f_k that escapes your infinite loop.  If this
 alternative algoritm doesn't exist, I think you need to show that it
 doesn't exist.

 I suspect that the error in Bruno's erroneous proof has to do with
 formal languages.  Say a function f is computable with regard to a
 formal language L when there exists an algorithm written in L  to
 compute f. The f_n are computable with regard to some particular
 formal language.  Functions computable with regard to one language
 may or may not be computable with regard to another language.  (If
 this is false, Bruno needs to prove it's false.)  Thus when Bruno
 argues that the set of computable functions is enumerable, he must
 mean for any fixed language L, the functions computable with regard
 to L is enumerable.  Now the procedure Bruno described for computing
 g is not written in a formal language--it's written in English.  The
 fact that this English language description is finite doesn't prove
 that g is computable with regard to L, ie, doesn't prove that  g is
 one of the f_n.

 I'm an amateur at this--this solution is really just a question for
 Bruno...


 Barry  (Barry Brent, not Brent Meeker!)


Now, if this comment was correct, it would mean that universal languages
or universal machines would not exist!

Actually, I can also take this remark as a correct conclusion, but only 
by
considering a restricted notion of universal machines or language.

Barry, are you actually denying Church Thesis (which says that an 
universal
language exists, indeed LAMBDA-CALCULUS is one!) ?

Barry Brent, Brent Meeker, you are both correct, individually, but you 
cannot
be both correct simultaneously, so what?

I let you and others think a bit more, for the fun of it, for the 
importance of
being 100% clear on this before proceeding, and because I have not the
time to say more today.

Don't worry, even the biggest one like Godel, Kleene, Church ... all 
have been
wrong on this at some moment. It *is* a bit subtle. But all the 
possibility of my
work, or more generally, the very consistency of comp relies on that 
subtlety.

Only after a good understanding on this, will I be able to come back on 
less
technical explanation. If I explain things non technically to soon I 
will have
the feeling to take you in a boat (we say in French), meaning roughly 
to be
dishonest.

It is worth to take the time, and to play a bit with the idea, right?

Bruno



PS I know also, for having explained this years ago in the list that 
some in the
list does understand what happen here, but I encourage them to go 
through
the reasoning again, because I am not sure they did understand the 
*impact*
of this  It is one thing to understand a proposition, and another 
thing to get
the importance, relatively to the TOE search of what is really going on 
here ...
In particular, when the ASSA people invoke Kolmogorov complexity 
notions,
they do rely on Church Thesis  The key post is a key for 
everybody, I mean
for both ASSA and RSSA type of TOE researchers.


Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-18 Thread Barry Brent

Bruno--

Ahh, my amateur status is nakedly exposed. I'm going to expose my  
confusion even further now.

Never heard of a universal language.  I thought I was familiar with  
Church's thesis, but apparently no.  I thought it was the claim that  
two or three or four concepts (including recursive function and  
computable function) were extensionally equivalent.  I have heard of  
the lambda calculus, but I don't know what it is, or what its  
connection is with Church's thesis.  I have a rough guess, based on  
what you're saying.  I'm surprised.  I imagine that the claim of  
existence of a universal language must be made in the context of a  
theory of languages?  Never heard of that theory.

Well, if I  imagine such a theory, it must involve both syntax and  
semantics, yes?  Semantics connects a language to a world, right?   
(The experts are cringing, I'm sure)  Can one language encompass  
all possible worlds?  Can't we imagine worlds, the structures of  
which are so dissonant, that their languages could never be  
consistently subsumed under some single larger (universal)  
language?  (More cringing, no doubt)  Or, is it that when we  
restrict the worlds in question to some suitable realm--say, numbers-- 
all these things work out?  (Cringes redoubled!)  I can imagine other  
ways out.  Maybe we're concerned with just one world, suitably  
described.  Maybe structural inconsistencies of possible worlds are  
no more an impediment to being expressible in one language than  
logical inconsistencies?  (But how do we know?)

What about cardinality? From your remarks, I imagine that the number  
of elementary symbols in any language, including the universal  
language, is supposed to be finite, so that the set of algorithms is  
countable? If there are lots of worlds and languages, I wonder how  
people make that work.  Is such a language going to be adequate for  
expressing propositions about all possible worlds?  How do we know?

My poor excuse is, I've only been on this list a little while, and I  
made my (sketchy) acquaintance with these ideas a very long time  
ago.  Sorry if I'm way off topic.  Tell me to go look it up  
somewhere, or stop wasting time, if you want to...

Barry Brent

On Dec 18, 2007, at 8:49 AM, Bruno Marchal wrote:



 Le 17-déc.-07, à 19:04, meekerdb (Brent Meeker) wrote:


 Bruno wrote:
 Exercise:
 What is wrong with the following argument. (I recall that by
 definition
 a function from N to N is defined on all natural numbers).

 (false) theorem: the set of computable functions from N to N is not
 enumerable.
 (erroneous) proof: let us suppose (by absurdum) that the set of
 computable functions from N to N is enumerable. Thus there exist an
 enumeration f_1, f_2, f_3, ... f_i,  of the computable functions
 from N to N. But then I can define the following computable function
 g,
 from N to N, by:

 g(n) = f_n(n) + 1

 g is computable: to compute it just search in the enumeration the
 function f_n, which is computable, and then apply it on n, and then
 add 1.
 But then g has to be in that enumeration f_i of the computable
 function.
 Thus there is a k such that g = f_k. In particular g(k) = f_k(k).  
 But
 g(k) = f_k(k) + 1, by definition of g. Thus f_k(k) = f_k(k)+1.  
 And the
 f_i are computable functions, so f_k(k) is a well defined number,
 which
 I can subtract on the left and the right side of f_k(k) = f_k(k)+1,
 giving 0 = 1. Contradiction. So the set of computable functions  
 from N
 to N is not enumerable.

 What is wrong? We know that the set of computable function has to be
 enumerable, because computable means we can describe how to  
 compute
 the function in a finite expression in some language, and the set of
 all
 finite expressions has been shown enumerable. So what happens?

 If you tried to compute g(k) and g was in the list, i.e. some f_k,
 then when
 you searched a for g, when you came to f_k it would start with the
 prescription ...just search in the enumeration... and you would be
 in a
 infinite loop.



 This is a bit fuzzy, but then the exercise was a bit fuzzy too, so  
 I can
 considered this as correct. More below.




 Barry Brent wrote:

 Brent, I don't think this is enough.  There may be a different
 algorithm for f_k that escapes your infinite loop.  If this
 alternative algoritm doesn't exist, I think you need to show that it
 doesn't exist.

 I suspect that the error in Bruno's erroneous proof has to do with
 formal languages.  Say a function f is computable with regard to a
 formal language L when there exists an algorithm written in L  to
 compute f. The f_n are computable with regard to some particular
 formal language.  Functions computable with regard to one language
 may or may not be computable with regard to another language.  (If
 this is false, Bruno needs to prove it's false.)  Thus when Bruno
 argues that the set of computable functions is enumerable, he must
 mean for any fixed language L, the functions 

Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-17 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi Daniel,

I agree with Barry, but apaprently you have still a problem, so I 
comment your posts.


Le 16-déc.-07, à 10:49, Daniel Grubbs a écrit :

  Hi Folks,

  I joined this list a while ago but I haven't really kept up.  Anyway, 
 I saw the reference to Cantor's Diagonal and thought perhaps someone 
 could help me.

  Consider the set of positive integers: {1,2,3,...}, but rather than 
 write them in this standard notation we'll use what I'll call 'prime 
 notation'. 



OK. That is often used to compare the purely additive and the purely 
multiplicative structures of the natural numbers. Of course the number 
0 is banished in the multiplicative structure (so you have to handle 0 
manualy, but that does not change the enumeration question, ok).




 Here, the number m may be written as
 m = n1,n2,n3,n4,...

 1 = 0,0,0,0,0,...
  2 = 1,0,0,0,0,...
  3 = 0,1,0,0,0,...
  4 = 2,0,0,0,0,...
  5 = 0,0,1,0,0,...
  ...
  28 = 2,0,0,1,0,0,0,...
  ...

 D = 1,1,1,1,1,...


  I can see that one may complain that D is clearly infinite and 
 therefore should not be in the set, ...


Yes. D does not describe a natural number.



 ... but consider the following...

  Let's take the original set and reorder it by exchanging the places 
 of the i'th prime number with that of the number in the i'th 
 position.  (i.e. First switch the number 2 with the number 1 to move 
 it to the first position. Then switch 3 with the number -- now 1 -- in 
 the 2nd position. Then 5 with the 1 which is now in the 3rd position. 
 Etc...) Because we are just trading the positions of the numbers, all 
 the same numbers will be in the set afterwards.

  The set is now:
 2  = 1,0,0,0,0,...
  3  = 0,1,0,0,0,...
  5  = 0,0,1,0,0,...
  7  = 0,0,0,1,0,...
  11= 0,0,0,0,1,...
  ...


What does ... mean here? It seems to me you are just enumerating the 
prime numbers. At which step will you put the numbers 1, 4, 6, etc.
If you do have a way to add, in the limit,  those numbers in the set, 
then you are just constructing an order type (ordinal) bigger than 
omega on the set of positive integers. But such constructive) ordinal 
are all enumerable.

You could have said directly: let us consider the following order: it 
is the usual order except that we decide that all even numbers are 
bigger than the odd numbers, so we have the order:

1, 3, 5, 7, 9,   2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 

This is an example of order type OMEGA+OMEGA

So what? We can easily enumerate it by zigzagging between the even and 
odd numbers.




 D = 0,0,0,0,...


  I would suggest that the diagonal method does not find a number which 
 is different from all the members of a set, but rather finds a number 
 which is infinitely far out in the ordered set.


Like I say. Your construction put a bigger, but still enumerable, order 
on N. Actually we have already used diagonalization for building 
constructive ordinal, or order type on the set of computable growing 
functions. But those produce enumerable sets.



  If anyone can find where I've gone wrong, please let me know.


Cantor showed that ALL tentative enumeration of some set S fails. This 
is what makes that set S non enumerable. You are just showing that the 
diagonal method can also work on some precise enumeration on N. This 
does not make N non enumerable, it makes only your precise enumeration 
incomplete (or extendible in the constructive ordinal, but that does 
not change anything).
A set is non enumerable if ALL attempts to enumerate it fail, not if 
some particular attempt fails. That is why we do a proof by a reductio 
ad absurdo.

In you next post you say (to Barry):


  Let me see if I am clear about Cantor's  method.  Given a set S, and 
 some enumeration of that set


Well S is fixed. It is the set we want to show being NOT enumerable. 
Then you take not some enumeration, but ANY enumeration.


 (i.e., a no one-one onto map from Z^+ to S) we can use the 
 diagonalization  method to find an D which is a valid element of S but 
 is different from any particular indexed element in the enumeration.


... is different from any particular indexed element, for any arbitrary 
enumeration. You have to be sure that the diagonal will work whatever 
enumeration is proposed.


  Cantor's argument then goes on to say (and here is where I disagree 
 with it) that therefore D is not included in the enumeration and the 
 enumeration is incomplete.

  I, on the other hand, would posit that the enumeration may include 
 elements whose index is not well defined.


H In Cantor's proof of the non enumerability of 2^N (the set of 
infinite binary sequences), the indexes are all perfectly well defined 
even if it is in Platonia or in the mind of God, so your remark does 
not apply.

But now, curiously enough, a remark similar to your's can be done about 
the proof that the (total) computable functions from N to N are not 
*computably* enumerable.
In that case, if we assume Church thesis, and thus the existence of a 
universal 

Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-16 Thread Barry Brent

Hi.

Bruno could do this better, but I like the practice.

I guess you're trying to demonstrate that the form of Cantor's  
argument is invalid, by displaying an example in which it produces an  
absurd result.

Start with a set S you want to show is not enumerable.  (ie, there is  
no one-one onto map from Z^+ to S).  The form of the diagonalization  
argument is as follows: give me any, repeat, any, particular  
candidate for an enumeration of S.   This should be a map from Z^+  
into S.  (If it isn't such a map, it isn't an enumeration.)   I will  
show you an element D of S that your candidate enumeration omits.   
(That is, I will show you that your candidate is not onto.)  Hence, S  
is not denumerable.

In your first attempt, your D is not an element of your S (= Z^+).   
So your first attempt doesn't fit the form of the diagonalization  
argument on this account.  More fundamentally, it also fails to fit  
the form of Cantor's argument because you haven't tried to debunk  
*any* candidate enumeration, but a particular one.

In your second attempt, if I understand you, you start with a map  
from the primes (all of them!) and then (your work suggests, but I  
think you'd need more details--what's the image of 4, for example?)  
from the rest of Z^+, into S = Z^+ again.   This example doesn't  
invalidate Cantor's argument either.  Again, you debunk a particular  
candidate enumeration, not any and all candidate enumerations.  So  
you don't arrive at the absurdity you seem to be after, even if you  
fill in the details I mentioned.

Barry

On Dec 16, 2007, at 3:49 AM, Daniel Grubbs wrote:

 Hi Folks,

 I joined this list a while ago but I haven't really kept up.   
 Anyway, I saw the reference to Cantor's Diagonal and thought  
 perhaps someone could help me.

 Consider the set of positive integers: {1,2,3,...}, but rather than  
 write them in this standard notation we'll use what I'll call  
 'prime notation'.  Here, the number m may be written as
 m = n1,n2,n3,n4,...
 where ni is the number of times the i'th prime number is a factor  
 of m. Thus:
 1 = 0,0,0,0,0,...
 2 = 1,0,0,0,0,...
 3 = 0,1,0,0,0,...
 4 = 2,0,0,0,0,...
 5 = 0,0,1,0,0,...
 ...
 28 = 2,0,0,1,0,0,0,...
 ...
 If we now apply the diagonal method to this ordered set, we get the  
 number:
 D = 1,1,1,1,1,...
 Has this just shown that the set of positive integers is not  
 denumerable?

 I can see that one may complain that D is clearly infinite and  
 therefore should not be in the set, but consider the following...

 Let's take the original set and reorder it by exchanging the places  
 of the i'th prime number with that of the number in the i'th  
 position.  (i.e. First switch the number 2 with the number 1 to  
 move it to the first position. Then switch 3 with the number -- now  
 1 -- in the 2nd position. Then 5 with the 1 which is now in the 3rd  
 position. Etc...) Because we are just trading the positions of the  
 numbers, all the same numbers will be in the set afterwards.

 The set is now:
 2  = 1,0,0,0,0,...
 3  = 0,1,0,0,0,...
 5  = 0,0,1,0,0,...
 7  = 0,0,0,1,0,...
 11= 0,0,0,0,1,...
 ...
 Now instead of adding 1 to each 'digit' of the diagonal, subtract  
 1.  This will ensure that the diagonal number is different from  
 each of the numbers in the set. Thus,
 D = 0,0,0,0,...
 But this is the number 1 which we know was in the set to begin  
 with.  What happened to it?

 I would suggest that the diagonal method does not find a number  
 which is different from all the members of a set, but rather finds  
 a number which is infinitely far out in the ordered set.

 If anyone can find where I've gone wrong, please let me know.

 Dan Grubbs

 

Dr. Barry Brent
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://home.earthlink.net/~barryb0/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-16 Thread Russell Standish

On Sun, Dec 16, 2007 at 04:49:34AM -0500, Daniel Grubbs wrote:

Cantor's argument only works by finding a number that satisfies the
criteria for inclusion in the list, yet is nowhere to be found in the
list.

In your first case, the number (1,1,1,1...) is not a natural number,
since it is infinite. In the second case, (0,0,0,...) is a natural
number, but is also on the list (at infinity).

Therefore Cantor's argument doesn't work in these cases.

Cheers

-- 


A/Prof Russell Standish  Phone 0425 253119 (mobile)
Mathematics  
UNSW SYDNEY 2052 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Australiahttp://www.hpcoders.com.au


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-16 Thread Daniel Grubbs





Hi Barry,

Let me see if I am clear about Cantor's method. Given a set S, and
some enumeration of that set (i.e., a no one-one onto map from Z^+ to
S) we can use the diagonalization method to find an D which is a valid
element of S but is different from any particular indexed element in
the enumeration.

Cantor's argument then goes on to say (and here is where I disagree
with it) that therefore D is not included in the enumeration and the
enumeration is incomplete.

I, on the other hand, would posit that the enumeration may include
elements whose index is not well defined. For example, 1 or 4 in my
second example. They were in the enumeration prior to its being
shuffled, and always had a definite position during the process. They
must still be in there, with definite positions, despite the fact that
their indices are now infinite and ill-defined.

If the diagonalization process does not produce the proffered result in
this case (i,e., it does not prove that the element D is not included
in the enumeration) then it does not prove it in any case. The number
D found with this method may actually be in the enumeration, but with
an ill-defined index.

Dan

Barry Brent wrote:

  Hi.

Bruno could do this better, but I like the practice.

I guess you're trying to demonstrate that the form of Cantor's  
argument is invalid, by displaying an example in which it produces an  
absurd result.

Start with a set S you want to show is not enumerable.  (ie, there is  
no one-one onto map from Z^+ to S).  The form of the diagonalization  
argument is as follows: give me any, repeat, any, particular  
candidate for an enumeration of S.   This should be a map from Z^+  
into S.  (If it isn't such a map, it isn't an enumeration.)   I will  
show you an element D of S that your candidate enumeration omits.   
(That is, I will show you that your candidate is not onto.)  Hence, S  
is not denumerable.

In your first attempt, your D is not an element of your S (= Z^+).   
So your first attempt doesn't fit the form of the diagonalization  
argument on this account.  More fundamentally, it also fails to fit  
the form of Cantor's argument because you haven't tried to debunk  
*any* candidate enumeration, but a particular one.

In your second attempt, if I understand you, you start with a map  
from the primes (all of them!) and then (your work suggests, but I  
think you'd need more details--what's the image of 4, for example?)  
from the rest of Z^+, into S = Z^+ again.   This example doesn't  
invalidate Cantor's argument either.  Again, you debunk a particular  
candidate enumeration, not any and all candidate enumerations.  So  
you don't arrive at the absurdity you seem to be after, even if you  
fill in the details I mentioned.

Barry

On Dec 16, 2007, at 3:49 AM, Daniel Grubbs wrote:

  
  
Hi Folks,

I joined this list a while ago but I haven't really kept up.   
Anyway, I saw the reference to Cantor's Diagonal and thought  
perhaps someone could help me.

Consider the set of positive integers: {1,2,3,...}, but rather than  
write them in this standard notation we'll use what I'll call  
'prime notation'.  Here, the number m may be written as
m = n1,n2,n3,n4,...
where ni is the number of times the i'th prime number is a factor  
of m. Thus:
1 = 0,0,0,0,0,...
2 = 1,0,0,0,0,...
3 = 0,1,0,0,0,...
4 = 2,0,0,0,0,...
5 = 0,0,1,0,0,...
...
28 = 2,0,0,1,0,0,0,...
...
If we now apply the diagonal method to this ordered set, we get the  
number:
D = 1,1,1,1,1,...
Has this just shown that the set of positive integers is not  
denumerable?

I can see that one may complain that D is clearly infinite and  
therefore should not be in the set, but consider the following...

Let's take the original set and reorder it by exchanging the places  
of the i'th prime number with that of the number in the i'th  
position.  (i.e. First switch the number 2 with the number 1 to  
move it to the first position. Then switch 3 with the number -- now  
1 -- in the 2nd position. Then 5 with the 1 which is now in the 3rd  
position. Etc...) Because we are just trading the positions of the  
numbers, all the same numbers will be in the set afterwards.

The set is now:
2  = 1,0,0,0,0,...
3  = 0,1,0,0,0,...
5  = 0,0,1,0,0,...
7  = 0,0,0,1,0,...
11= 0,0,0,0,1,...
...
Now instead of adding 1 to each 'digit' of the diagonal, subtract  
1.  This will ensure that the diagonal number is different from  
each of the numbers in the set. Thus,
D = 0,0,0,0,...
But this is the number 1 which we know was in the set to begin  
with.  What happened to it?

I would suggest that the diagonal method does not find a number  
which is different from all the members of a set, but rather finds  
a number which is infinitely far out in the ordered set.

If anyone can find where I've gone wrong, please let me know.

Dan Grubbs


  
  
Dr. Barry Brent
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://home.earthlink.net/~barryb0/






  



--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~

Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-16 Thread Barry Brent

Hi Dan,

Let me take your statements a few at a time.

 Let me see if I am clear about Cantor's  method.  Given a set S,  
 and some enumeration of that set (i.e., a no one-one onto map from  
 Z^+ to S) we can use the diagonalization  method to find an D  
 which is a valid element of S but is different from any particular  
 indexed element in the enumeration.

Not given a set S and *some* enumeration... but given a set S and  
*any candidate for an enumeration*...  The idea is to show that no  
candidate for an enumeration succeeds, hence the set S has no  
enumeration, hence the set S is not enumerable.

  we can use the diagonalization  method to find an D which is a  
 valid element of S but is different from any particular indexed  
 element in the enumeration.

Yes.

 Cantor's argument then goes on to say (and here is where I  
 disagree with it) that therefore D is not included in the  
 enumeration and the enumeration is incomplete.

Yes, except for your disagreement with it

One step of Cantor's argument is to show, for a given candidate  
enumeration of S, that some D in S is different from every single  
enumerated member of S.  If you can't show this for some particular  
candidate enumeration, you haven't done a Cantor diagonalization  
argument that encompasses the candidate enumeration.  To do a  
successful Cantor diagonalization argument, you must show that some D  
in S is different from every single enumerated member of S, for each  
candidate enumeration of S.  The value of D will typically depend on  
the candidate.

 I, on the other hand, would posit that the enumeration may include  
 elements whose index is not well defined. For example, 1 or 4 in   
 my second example.  They were in the enumeration prior to its  
 being shuffled, and always had a definite position during the  
 process.  They must still be in there, with definite positions,  
 despite the fact that their indices are now infinite and ill-defined.

I don't need to parse this shuffling enumeration to say that what  
you're doing is not an instance of Cantor's argument.  Any instance  
of Cantor's argument will debunk, not just one candidate shuffling  
enumeration, to take your example, but each and every candidate  
enumeration.  And you haven't even debunked the shuffling  
enumeration.  In fact you're arguing that it's valid (it seems to me.)

 If the diagonalization process does not produce the proffered  
 result in this case (i,e., it does not prove that the element D is  
 not included in the enumeration) then it does not prove it in any  
 case.  The number D found with this method may actually be in the  
 enumeration, but with an ill-defined index.

A defender of the validity of the form of Cantor's argument doesn't  
*want* to use it to prove that Z^+ has no enumeration. To do so would  
be to fall into the paradox you're trying to construct.  So it's  
perfectly fine if the diagonalization process does not produce the  
proffered result in this case.

Barry

On Dec 16, 2007, at 9:09 PM, Daniel Grubbs wrote:

 Hi Barry,

 Let me see if I am clear about Cantor's  method.  Given a set S,  
 and some enumeration of that set (i.e., a no one-one onto map from  
 Z^+ to S) we can use the diagonalization  method to find an D which  
 is a valid element of S but is different from any particular  
 indexed element in the enumeration.

 Cantor's argument then goes on to say (and here is where I disagree  
 with it) that therefore D is not included in the enumeration and  
 the enumeration is incomplete.

 I, on the other hand, would posit that the enumeration may include  
 elements whose index is not well defined. For example, 1 or 4 in   
 my second example.  They were in the enumeration prior to its being  
 shuffled, and always had a definite position during the process.   
 They must still be in there, with definite positions, despite the  
 fact that their indices are now infinite and ill-defined.

 If the diagonalization process does not produce the proffered  
 result in this case (i,e., it does not prove that the element D is  
 not included in the enumeration) then it does not prove it in any  
 case.  The number D found with this method may actually be in the  
 enumeration, but with an ill-defined index.

 Dan



Dr. Barry Brent
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://home.earthlink.net/~barryb0/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-04 Thread Bruno Marchal


Le 03-déc.-07, à 16:56, David Nyman a écrit :


 On Nov 20, 4:40 pm, Bruno Marchal [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not
 enumerable.

 All right?

 OK.  I have to try to catch up now, because I've had to be away longer
 than I expected, but I'm clear on this diagonal argument.

OK. I hope you have done the exercise  below, which consists to show 
that N^N is also not enumerable. It is the same reasoning, of course.
(Of course it is also a consequence of the non enumerability of 2^N, 
because 2^N is included in N^N, but in the exercise I was asking for a 
direct diagonal argument).
You can look at the solution:
http://www.mail-archive.com/everything-list@eskimo.com/msg14063.html

I will send the key post asap. It is written, but I am currently 
hesitating to add more explanations, but sometimes when I do that, I 
introduce just more confusion. I guess I will send some part so that 
you have something to think about (of 'course I don't doubt you have 
many things to think about ...).

Bruno

===


 Hi,

 David, are you still there? This is a key post, with respect to the
 Church Thesis thread.

 So let us see that indeed there is no bijection between N and 2^N =
 2X2X2X2X2X2X... = {0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X... = the set of infinite
 binary sequences.

 Suppose that there is a bijection between N and the set of infinite
 binary sequences. Well, it will look like that, where again 
 represents the ropes:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 My sheep are the natural numbers, and my neighbor's sheep are the
 infinite binary sequences (the function from N to 2, the elements of
 the infinite cartesian product 2X2X2X2X2X2X... ).
 My flock of sheep is the *set* of natural numbers, and my neighbor's
 flock of sheep is the *set* of all infinite binary sequences.

 Now, if this:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 is really a bijection, it means that all the numbers 1 and 0 appearing
 on the right are well determined (perhaps in Platonia, or in God's
 mind, ...).

 But then the diagonal sequence, going from the left up to right down,
 and build from the list of binary sequences above:

 1 0 0 1 0 0 ...

 is also completely well determined (in Platonia or in the mind of a
 God).

 But then the complementary sequence (with the 0 and 1 permuted) is 
 also
 well defined, in Platonia or in the mind of God(s)

 0 1 1 0 1 1 ...

 But this infinite sequence cannot be in the list, above. The God in
 question has to ackonwledge that.
 The complementary sequence is clearly different
 -from the 0th sequence (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ..., because it differs at
 the first (better the 0th)  entry.
 -from the 1th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the second (better the 1th)  entry.
 -from the 2th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the third (better the 2th)  entry.
 and so one.
 So, we see that as far as we consider the bijection above well
 determined (by God, for example), then we can say to that God that the
 bijection misses one of the neighbor sheep, indeed the sheep
 constituted by the infinite binary sequence complementary to the
 diagonal sequence cannot be in the list, and that sequence is also 
 well
 determined (given that the whole table is).

 But this means that this bijection fails. Now the reasoning did not
 depend at all on the choice of any particular bijection-candidate.  
 Any
 conceivable bijection will lead to a well determined infinite table of
 binary numbers. And this will determine the diagonal sequence and then
 the complementary diagonal sequence, and this one cannot be in the
 list, because it contradicts all sequences in the list when they cross
 the diagonal (do the drawing on paper).

 Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not
 enumerable.

 All right?

   Next I will do again that proof, but with notations instead of
 drawing, and I will show more explicitly how the contradiction arise.

 Exercice-training: show similarly that N^N, the set of functions from 
 N
 to N, is not enumerable.

 Bruno

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
 

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, 

Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-12-03 Thread David Nyman

On Nov 20, 4:40 pm, Bruno Marchal [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not
 enumerable.

 All right?

OK.  I have to try to catch up now, because I've had to be away longer
than I expected, but I'm clear on this diagonal argument.

David

 Hi,

 David, are you still there? This is a key post, with respect to the
 Church Thesis thread.

 So let us see that indeed there is no bijection between N and 2^N =
 2X2X2X2X2X2X... = {0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X... = the set of infinite
 binary sequences.

 Suppose that there is a bijection between N and the set of infinite
 binary sequences. Well, it will look like that, where again 
 represents the ropes:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 My sheep are the natural numbers, and my neighbor's sheep are the
 infinite binary sequences (the function from N to 2, the elements of
 the infinite cartesian product 2X2X2X2X2X2X... ).
 My flock of sheep is the *set* of natural numbers, and my neighbor's
 flock of sheep is the *set* of all infinite binary sequences.

 Now, if this:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 is really a bijection, it means that all the numbers 1 and 0 appearing
 on the right are well determined (perhaps in Platonia, or in God's
 mind, ...).

 But then the diagonal sequence, going from the left up to right down,
 and build from the list of binary sequences above:

 1 0 0 1 0 0 ...

 is also completely well determined (in Platonia or in the mind of a
 God).

 But then the complementary sequence (with the 0 and 1 permuted) is also
 well defined, in Platonia or in the mind of God(s)

 0 1 1 0 1 1 ...

 But this infinite sequence cannot be in the list, above. The God in
 question has to ackonwledge that.
 The complementary sequence is clearly different
 -from the 0th sequence (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ..., because it differs at
 the first (better the 0th)  entry.
 -from the 1th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the second (better the 1th)  entry.
 -from the 2th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the third (better the 2th)  entry.
 and so one.
 So, we see that as far as we consider the bijection above well
 determined (by God, for example), then we can say to that God that the
 bijection misses one of the neighbor sheep, indeed the sheep
 constituted by the infinite binary sequence complementary to the
 diagonal sequence cannot be in the list, and that sequence is also well
 determined (given that the whole table is).

 But this means that this bijection fails. Now the reasoning did not
 depend at all on the choice of any particular bijection-candidate.  Any
 conceivable bijection will lead to a well determined infinite table of
 binary numbers. And this will determine the diagonal sequence and then
 the complementary diagonal sequence, and this one cannot be in the
 list, because it contradicts all sequences in the list when they cross
 the diagonal (do the drawing on paper).

 Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not
 enumerable.

 All right?

   Next I will do again that proof, but with notations instead of
 drawing, and I will show more explicitly how the contradiction arise.

 Exercice-training: show similarly that N^N, the set of functions from N
 to N, is not enumerable.

 Bruno

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: elaboration Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-22 Thread Bruno Marchal


Le 22-nov.-07, à 07:19, Barry Brent a écrit :


 The reason it isn't a bijection (of a denumerable set with the set of
 binary sequences):  the  pre-image (the left side of your map) isn't
 a set--you've imposed an ordering.  Sets, qua sets, don't have
 orderings.  Orderings are extra.  (I'm not a specialist on this stuff
 but I think Bruno, for example, will back me up.)  It must be the
 case that you won't let us identify the left side, for example, with
 {omega, 0, 1, 2, ... }, will you? For if you did, it would fall under
 Cantor's argument.


I agree.
Presently, I prefer not talking too much on the ordinals, because it 
could be confusing for many.  More later ...

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-22 Thread Bruno Marchal

Le 21-nov.-07, à 17:33, Torgny Tholerus a écrit :

  What do you think of this proof?:

  Let us have the bijection:

  0  {0,0,0,0,0,0,0,...}
  1  {1,0,0,0,0,0,0,...}
  2  {0,1,0,0,0,0,0,...}
  3  {1,1,0,0,0,0,0,...}
  4  {0,0,1,0,0,0,0,...}
  5  {1,0,1,0,0,0,0,...}
  6  {0,1,1,0,0,0,0,...}
  7  {1,1,1,0,0,0,0,...}
  8  {0,0,0,1,0,0,0,...}
  ...
  omega --- {1,1,1,1,1,1,1,...}

  What do we get if we apply Cantor's Diagonal to this?


Note also that in general, we start from what we want to prove, and 
then do the math. Your idea of transfinite (ordinal) diagonalisation is 
cute though, but I have currently no idea where this could lead. BTW, 
it is also funny that such a transfinite idea is proposed by an 
ultrafinistist!

I guess you have seen that {(0,0,0,0,0,0,0,...), (1,0,0,0,0,0,0,...), 
... does clearly not enumerate the infinite sequences (you don't have 
to use the diagonal for showing that. It is also better to use 
parentheses instead of accolades, given that the binary sequences are 
ordered (notation detail).

Bruno

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-21 Thread Bruno Marchal


Le 20-nov.-07, à 17:47, David Nyman a écrit :


 On 20/11/2007, Bruno Marchal [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 David, are you still there? This is a key post, with respect to the
 Church Thesis thread.

 Sorry Bruno, do forgive me - we seem destined to be out of synch at
 the moment.  I'm afraid I'm too distracted this week to respond
 adequately - back on-line next week at the latest.


Take it easy. It is the main advantage of electronical conversation, 
unlike the phone, we can answer at the best moment. But I appreciate 
you tell me.

See you next week.

Bruno

PS I'm afraid I have not the time to comment the last posts today, 
except for elementary question perhaps, but I will have more time soon 
(probably or hopefully tomorrow).






 David

 Hi,

 David, are you still there? This is a key post, with respect to the
 Church Thesis thread.

 So let us see that indeed there is no bijection between N and 2^N =
 2X2X2X2X2X2X... = {0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X... = the set of infinite
 binary sequences.

 Suppose that there is a bijection between N and the set of infinite
 binary sequences. Well, it will look like that, where again 
 represents the ropes:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 My sheep are the natural numbers, and my neighbor's sheep are the
 infinite binary sequences (the function from N to 2, the elements of
 the infinite cartesian product 2X2X2X2X2X2X... ).
 My flock of sheep is the *set* of natural numbers, and my neighbor's
 flock of sheep is the *set* of all infinite binary sequences.

 Now, if this:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 is really a bijection, it means that all the numbers 1 and 0 appearing
 on the right are well determined (perhaps in Platonia, or in God's
 mind, ...).

 But then the diagonal sequence, going from the left up to right down,
 and build from the list of binary sequences above:

 1 0 0 1 0 0 ...

 is also completely well determined (in Platonia or in the mind of a
 God).

 But then the complementary sequence (with the 0 and 1 permuted) is 
 also
 well defined, in Platonia or in the mind of God(s)

 0 1 1 0 1 1 ...

 But this infinite sequence cannot be in the list, above. The God in
 question has to ackonwledge that.
 The complementary sequence is clearly different
 -from the 0th sequence (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ..., because it differs at
 the first (better the 0th)  entry.
 -from the 1th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the second (better the 1th)  entry.
 -from the 2th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the third (better the 2th)  entry.
 and so one.
 So, we see that as far as we consider the bijection above well
 determined (by God, for example), then we can say to that God that the
 bijection misses one of the neighbor sheep, indeed the sheep
 constituted by the infinite binary sequence complementary to the
 diagonal sequence cannot be in the list, and that sequence is also 
 well
 determined (given that the whole table is).

 But this means that this bijection fails. Now the reasoning did not
 depend at all on the choice of any particular bijection-candidate.  
 Any
 conceivable bijection will lead to a well determined infinite table of
 binary numbers. And this will determine the diagonal sequence and then
 the complementary diagonal sequence, and this one cannot be in the
 list, because it contradicts all sequences in the list when they cross
 the diagonal (do the drawing on paper).

 Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not
 enumerable.

 All right?

   Next I will do again that proof, but with notations instead of
 drawing, and I will show more explicitly how the contradiction arise.


 Exercice-training: show similarly that N^N, the set of functions from 
 N
 to N, is not enumerable.

 Bruno

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




 

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-21 Thread Bruno Marchal


Le 20-nov.-07, à 23:39, Barry Brent wrote :


 You're saying that, just because you can *write down* the missing
 sequence (at the beginning, middle or anywhere else in the list), it
 follows that there *is* no missing sequence.  Looks pretty wrong to me.

   Cantor's proof disqualifies any candidate enumeration.  You respond
 by saying, well, here's another candidate!  But Cantor's procedure
 disqualified *any*, repeat *any* candidate enumeration.

 Barry Brent


Torgny, I do agree with Barry. Any bijection leads to a contradiction, 
even in some effective way, and that is enough (for a classical 
logician).
But look what you write:

 On Nov 20, 2007, at 11:42 AM, Torgny Tholerus wrote:



 An ultrafinitist comment to this:
 ==
 You can add this complementary sequence to the end of the list.
 That will make you have a list with this complementary sequence
 included.

 But then you can make a new complementary sequence, that is not
 inluded.  But you can then add this new sequence to the end of the
 extended list, and then you have a bijection with this new sequence
 also.  And if you try to make another new sequence, I will add that
 sequence too, and this I will do an infinite number of times.


How could an ultrafinitist refute an argument by saying ... and this I 
will do an infinite number of times. ?




 So
 you will not be able to prove that there is no bijection...


Actually no. If you do what you described omega times, you will just 
end up with a set which can still be put in 1-1 correspondence with N 
(as shown in preceding posts on bijections)
To refute Cantor, here, you should do what you described a very big 
infinity of times, indeed an non enumerable infinity of times. But then 
you have to assume the existence of a non enumerable set at the start. 
OK?

Bruno
http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




 ==
 What is wrong with this conclusion?

 -- 
 Torgny



 Dr. Barry Brent
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 http://home.earthlink.net/~barryb0/




 



--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-21 Thread Bruno Marchal

Le 21-nov.-07, à 08:49, Torgny Tholerus a écrit :




  meekerdb skrev:Torgny Tholerus wrote:


 An ultrafinitist comment to this:
 ==
 You can add this complementary sequence to the end of the list.  That
 will make you have a list with this complementary sequence included.

 But then you can make a new complementary sequence, that is not
 inluded.  But you can then add this new sequence to the end of the
 extended list, and then you have a bijection with this new sequence
 also.  And if you try to make another new sequence, I will add that
 sequence too, and this I will do an infinite number of times.  So you
 will not be able to prove that there is no bijection...
 ==
 What is wrong with this conclusion?

 You'd have to insert the new sequence in the beginning, as there is no
 end of the list.



  Why can't you add something to the end of the list?  In an earlier 
 message Bruno wrote:

  Now omega+1 is the set of all ordinal strictly lesser than omega+1, 
 with the convention above. This gives {0, 1, 2, 3, ... omega} = {0, 1, 
 2, 3, 4, {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, }}.

  In this sentence he added omega to the end of the list of natural 
 numbers...




Adding something to the end or to the middle or to the beginning of an 
infinite  list, does not change the cardinality of that list. And in 
Cantor proof, we are interested only in the cardinality notion.

Adding something to the beginning or to the end of a infinite ORDERED 
list, well, it does not change the cardinal of the set involved, but it 
obviosuly produce different order on those sets, and this can give 
different ordinal, which denote type of order (isomorphic order).

The ordered set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} has the same cardinality that the 
ordered set {1, 2, 3, 4, ... 0} (where by definition 0 is bigger than 
all natural numbers). But they both denote different ordinal, omega, 
and omega+1 respectively. Note that {1, 0, 2, 3, 4, ...} is a different 
order than {0, 1, 2, 3, ...}, but both order here are isomorphic, and 
correspond to the same ordinal (omega).

That is why 1+omega = omega, and omega+1 is different from omega. 
Adding one object in front of a list does not change the type of the 
order. Adding an element at the end of an infinite list does change the 
type of the order. {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} has no bigger element, but {1, 2, 
3, ... 0} has a bigger element. So, you cannot by simple relabelling of 
the elements get the same type of order (and thus they correspond to 
different ordinals).

OK?  (this stuff will not be used for Church Thesis, unless we go very 
far ...later).


Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-21 Thread Torgny Tholerus





Bruno Marchal skrev:

  
Le 20-nov.-07,  23:39, Barry Brent wrote :

  
  
You're saying that, just because you can *write down* the missing
sequence (at the beginning, middle or anywhere else in the list), it
follows that there *is* no missing sequence.  Looks pretty wrong to me.

  Cantor's proof disqualifies any candidate enumeration.  You respond
by saying, "well, here's another candidate!"  But Cantor's procedure
disqualified *any*, repeat *any* candidate enumeration.

Barry Brent

  
  

Torgny, I do agree with Barry. Any bijection leads to a contradiction, 
even in some effective way, and that is enough (for a classical 
logician).
  


What do you think of this "proof"?:

Let us have the bijection:

0  {0,0,0,0,0,0,0,...}
1  {1,0,0,0,0,0,0,...}
2  {0,1,0,0,0,0,0,...}
3  {1,1,0,0,0,0,0,...}
4  {0,0,1,0,0,0,0,...}
5  {1,0,1,0,0,0,0,...}
6  {0,1,1,0,0,0,0,...}
7  {1,1,1,0,0,0,0,...}
8  {0,0,0,1,0,0,0,...}
...
omega --- {1,1,1,1,1,1,1,...}

What do we get if we apply Cantor's Diagonal to this?

-- 
Torgny

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups Everything List group.  To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]  To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]  For more options, visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en  -~--~~~~--~~--~--~---






elaboration Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-21 Thread Barry Brent

The reason it isn't a bijection (of a denumerable set with the set of  
binary sequences):  the  pre-image (the left side of your map) isn't  
a set--you've imposed an ordering.  Sets, qua sets, don't have  
orderings.  Orderings are extra.  (I'm not a specialist on this stuff  
but I think Bruno, for example, will back me up.)  It must be the  
case that you won't let us identify the left side, for example, with  
{omega, 0, 1, 2, ... }, will you? For if you did, it would fall under  
Cantor's argument.

Barry

On Nov 21, 2007, at 10:33 AM, Torgny Tholerus wrote:

 Bruno Marchal skrev:
 Le 20-nov.-07, à 23:39, Barry Brent wrote :
 You're saying that, just because you can *write down* the missing  
 sequence (at the beginning, middle or anywhere else in the list),  
 it follows that there *is* no missing sequence. Looks pretty  
 wrong to me. Cantor's proof disqualifies any candidate  
 enumeration. You respond by saying, well, here's another  
 candidate! But Cantor's procedure disqualified *any*, repeat  
 *any* candidate enumeration. Barry Brent
 Torgny, I do agree with Barry. Any bijection leads to a  
 contradiction, even in some effective way, and that is enough (for  
 a classical logician).

 What do you think of this proof?:

 Let us have the bijection:

 0  {0,0,0,0,0,0,0,...}
 1  {1,0,0,0,0,0,0,...}
 2  {0,1,0,0,0,0,0,...}
 3  {1,1,0,0,0,0,0,...}
 4  {0,0,1,0,0,0,0,...}
 5  {1,0,1,0,0,0,0,...}
 6  {0,1,1,0,0,0,0,...}
 7  {1,1,1,0,0,0,0,...}
 8  {0,0,0,1,0,0,0,...}
 ...
 omega --- {1,1,1,1,1,1,1,...}

 What do we get if we apply Cantor's Diagonal to this?

 -- 
 Torgny

 

Dr. Barry Brent
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://home.earthlink.net/~barryb0/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-20 Thread David Nyman

On 20/11/2007, Bruno Marchal [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 David, are you still there? This is a key post, with respect to the
 Church Thesis thread.

Sorry Bruno, do forgive me - we seem destined to be out of synch at
the moment.  I'm afraid I'm too distracted this week to respond
adequately - back on-line next week at the latest.

David

 Hi,

 David, are you still there? This is a key post, with respect to the
 Church Thesis thread.

 So let us see that indeed there is no bijection between N and 2^N =
 2X2X2X2X2X2X... = {0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X{0,1}X... = the set of infinite
 binary sequences.

 Suppose that there is a bijection between N and the set of infinite
 binary sequences. Well, it will look like that, where again 
 represents the ropes:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 My sheep are the natural numbers, and my neighbor's sheep are the
 infinite binary sequences (the function from N to 2, the elements of
 the infinite cartesian product 2X2X2X2X2X2X... ).
 My flock of sheep is the *set* of natural numbers, and my neighbor's
 flock of sheep is the *set* of all infinite binary sequences.

 Now, if this:

 0  -- (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ...
 1 --  (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...
 2 --- (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...
 3 --- (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
 4 --- (0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, ...
 5 (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...
 ...

 is really a bijection, it means that all the numbers 1 and 0 appearing
 on the right are well determined (perhaps in Platonia, or in God's
 mind, ...).

 But then the diagonal sequence, going from the left up to right down,
 and build from the list of binary sequences above:

 1 0 0 1 0 0 ...

 is also completely well determined (in Platonia or in the mind of a
 God).

 But then the complementary sequence (with the 0 and 1 permuted) is also
 well defined, in Platonia or in the mind of God(s)

 0 1 1 0 1 1 ...

 But this infinite sequence cannot be in the list, above. The God in
 question has to ackonwledge that.
 The complementary sequence is clearly different
 -from the 0th sequence (1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ..., because it differs at
 the first (better the 0th)  entry.
 -from the 1th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the second (better the 1th)  entry.
 -from the 2th sequence (0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ...  because it differs at
 the third (better the 2th)  entry.
 and so one.
 So, we see that as far as we consider the bijection above well
 determined (by God, for example), then we can say to that God that the
 bijection misses one of the neighbor sheep, indeed the sheep
 constituted by the infinite binary sequence complementary to the
 diagonal sequence cannot be in the list, and that sequence is also well
 determined (given that the whole table is).

 But this means that this bijection fails. Now the reasoning did not
 depend at all on the choice of any particular bijection-candidate.  Any
 conceivable bijection will lead to a well determined infinite table of
 binary numbers. And this will determine the diagonal sequence and then
 the complementary diagonal sequence, and this one cannot be in the
 list, because it contradicts all sequences in the list when they cross
 the diagonal (do the drawing on paper).

 Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not
 enumerable.

 All right?

   Next I will do again that proof, but with notations instead of
 drawing, and I will show more explicitly how the contradiction arise.


 Exercice-training: show similarly that N^N, the set of functions from N
 to N, is not enumerable.

 Bruno

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/

 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-20 Thread Torgny Tholerus





Bruno Marchal skrev:
But then the complementary sequence (with the 0 and 1
permuted) is
also well defined, in Platonia or in the mind of God(s)
  
  
  0 1 1 0
  1 1 ...
  
  
But this infinite sequence cannot be in the list, above.
The "God" in question has to ackonwledge that. 
The complementary sequence is clearly different 
-from the 0th sequence (1, 0, 0,
1, 1, 1, 0 ..., because it differs at the first (better the 0th) entry.
  
-from the 1th sequence (0, 0, 0,
1, 1, 0, 1 ... because it differs at the second (better the 1th) entry.
  
-from the 2th sequence (0, 0, 0,
1, 1, 0, 1 ... because it differs at the third (better the 2th) entry.
  
and so one.
  
So, we see that as far as we consider the bijection above well
determined (by God, for example), then we can say to that God that the
bijection misses one of the neighbor sheep, indeed the "sheep"
constituted by the infinite binary sequence complementary to the
diagonal sequence cannot be in the list, and that sequence is also
well determined (given that the whole table is).
  
  
But this means that this bijection fails. Now the reasoning did not
depend at all on the choice of any particular bijection-candidate. Any
conceivable bijection will lead to a well determined infinite
table of binary numbers. And this will determine the diagonal sequence
and then the complementary diagonal sequence, and this one cannot be
in the list, because it contradicts all sequences in the list when
they cross the diagonal (do the drawing on paper).
  
  
Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not
enumerable.
  
  
All right?
  


An ultrafinitist comment to this:
==
You can add this complementary sequence to the end of the list. That
will make you have a list with this complementary sequence included.

But then you can make a new complementary sequence, that is not
inluded. But you can then add this new sequence to the end of the
extended list, and then you have a bijection with this new sequence
also. And if you try to make another new sequence, I will add that
sequence too, and this I will do an infinite number of times. So you
will not be able to prove that there is no bijection...
==
What is wrong with this conclusion?

-- 
Torgny

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups Everything List group.  To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]  To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]  For more options, visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en  -~--~~~~--~~--~--~---






Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-20 Thread meekerdb

Torgny Tholerus wrote:
 Bruno Marchal skrev:
 But then the complementary sequence (with the 0 and 1 permuted) is 
 also well defined, in Platonia or in the mind of God(s)

 *0* *1* *1* *0* *1* *1* ...

 But *this* infinite sequence cannot be in the list, above. The God 
 in question has to ackonwledge that.
 The complementary sequence is clearly different
 -from the 0th sequence (*_1_*, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0 ..., because it 
 differs at the first (better the 0th) entry.
 -from the 1th sequence (0, *_0_*, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1 ... because it 
 differs at the second (better the 1th) entry.
 -from the 2th sequence (0, 0, *_0_*, 1, 1, 0, 1 ... because it 
 differs at the third (better the 2th) entry.
 and so one.
 So, we see that as far as we consider the bijection above well 
 determined (by God, for example), then we can say to that God that 
 the bijection misses one of the neighbor sheep, indeed the sheep 
 constituted by the infinite binary sequence complementary to the 
 diagonal sequence cannot be in the list, and that sequence is also 
 well determined (given that the whole table is).

 But this means that this bijection fails. Now the reasoning did not 
 depend at all on the choice of any particular bijection-candidate. 
 Any conceivable bijection will lead to a well determined infinite 
 table of binary numbers. And this will determine the diagonal 
 sequence and then the complementary diagonal sequence, and this one 
 cannot be in the list, because it contradicts all sequences in the 
 list when they cross the diagonal (do the drawing on paper).

 Conclusion: 2^N, the set of infinite binary sequences, is not 
 enumerable.

 All right?

 An ultrafinitist comment to this:
 ==
 You can add this complementary sequence to the end of the list.  That 
 will make you have a list with this complementary sequence included.

 But then you can make a new complementary sequence, that is not 
 inluded.  But you can then add this new sequence to the end of the 
 extended list, and then you have a bijection with this new sequence 
 also.  And if you try to make another new sequence, I will add that 
 sequence too, and this I will do an infinite number of times.  So you 
 will not be able to prove that there is no bijection...
 ==
 What is wrong with this conclusion?

You'd have to insert the new sequence in the beginning, as there is no 
end of the list.

Brent Meeker

 -- 
 Torgny

 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: Cantor's Diagonal

2007-11-20 Thread Torgny Tholerus





meekerdb skrev:

  Torgny Tholerus wrote:
  
  
An ultrafinitist comment to this:
==
You can add this complementary sequence to the end of the list.  That 
will make you have a list with this complementary sequence included.

But then you can make a new complementary sequence, that is not 
inluded.  But you can then add this new sequence to the end of the 
extended list, and then you have a bijection with this new sequence 
also.  And if you try to make another new sequence, I will add that 
sequence too, and this I will do an infinite number of times.  So you 
will not be able to prove that there is no bijection...
==
What is wrong with this conclusion?

  
  
You'd have to insert the new sequence in the beginning, as there is no 
"end of the list".

  


Why can't you add something to the end of the list? In an earlier
message Bruno wrote:

"Now omega+1 is the set of all ordinal strictly lesser than omega+1,
with the convention above. This gives {0, 1, 2, 3, ... omega} = {0, 1,
2, 3, 4, {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, }}."

In this sentence he added omega to the end of the list of natural
numbers...

-- 
Torgny

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups Everything List group.  To post to this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]  To unsubscribe from this group, send email to [EMAIL PROTECTED]  For more options, visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en  -~--~~~~--~~--~--~---