http://www.westonaprice.org/healthissues/ethicsmeat.html

The Ethics of Eating Meat: A Radical View

By Charles Eisenstein

Most vegetarians I know are not primarily motivated by nutrition. 
Although they argue strenuously for the health benefits of a 
vegetarian diet, many see good health as a reward for the purity and 
virtue of a vegetarian diet, or as an added bonus. In my experience, 
a far more potent motivator among vegetarians-ranging from idealistic 
college students, to social and environmental activists, to adherents 
of Eastern spiritual traditions like Buddhism and Yoga-is the moral 
or ethical case for not eating meat.

Enunciated with great authority by such spiritual luminaries as 
Mahatma Gandhi, and by environmental crusaders such as Frances Moore 
Lappe, the moral case against eating meat seems at first glance to be 
overpowering. As a meat eater who cares deeply about living in 
harmony with the environment, and as an honest person trying to 
eliminate hypocrisy in the way I live, I feel compelled to take these 
arguments seriously.

A typical argument goes like this: In order to feed modern society's 
enormous appetite for meat, animals endure unimaginable suffering in 
conditions of extreme filth, crowding and confinement. Chickens are 
packed twenty to a cage, hogs are kept in concrete stalls so narrow 
they can never turn around.

Arguing for the Environment

The cruelty is appalling, but no less so than the environmental 
effects. Meat animals are fed anywhere from five to fifteen pounds of 
vegetable protein for each pound of meat produced-an unconscionable 
practice in a world where many go hungry. Whereas one-sixth an acre 
of land can feed a vegetarian for a year, over three acres are 
required to provide the grain needed to raise a year's worth of meat 
for the average meat-eater.

All too often, so the argument goes, those acres consist of clear-cut 
rain forests. The toll on water resources is equally grim: the meat 
industry accounts for half of US water consumption-2500 gallons per 
pound of beef, compared to 25 gallons per pound of wheat. Polluting 
fossil fuels are another major input into meat production. As for the 
output, 1.6 million tons of livestock manure pollutes our drinking 
water. And let's not forget the residues of antibiotics and synthetic 
hormones that are increasingly showing up in municipal water supplies.
Even without considering the question of taking life (I'll get to 
that later), the above facts alone make it clear that it is immoral 
to aid and abet this system by eating meat.

Factory or Farm?

I will not contest any of the above statistics, except to say that 
they only describe the meat industry as it exists today. They 
constitute a compelling argument against the meat industry, not 
meat-eating. For in fact, there are other ways of raising animals for 
food, ways that make livestock an environmental asset rather than a 
liability, and in which animals do not lead lives of suffering. 
Consider, for example, a traditional mixed farm combining a variety 
of crops, pasture land and orchards. Here, manure is not a pollutant 
or a waste product; it is a valuable resource contributing to soil 
fertility. Instead of taking grain away from the starving millions, 
pastured animals actually generate food calories from land unsuited 
to tillage. When animals are used to do work-pulling plows, eating 
bugs and turning compost-they reduce fossil fuel consumption and the 
temptation to use pesticides. Nor do animals living outdoors require 
a huge input of water for sanitation.

In a farm that is not just a production facility but an ecology, 
livestock has a beneficial role to play. The cycles, connections and 
relationships among crops, trees, insects, manure, birds, soil, water 
and people on a living farm form an intricate web, "organic" in its 
original sense, a thing of beauty not easily lumped into the same 
category as a 5000-animal concrete hog factory. Any natural 
environment is home to animals and plants, and it seems reasonable 
that an agriculture that seeks to be as close as possible to nature 
would incorporate both. Indeed, on a purely horticultural farm, wild 
animals can be a big problem, and artificial measures are required to 
keep them out. Nice rows of lettuce and carrots are an irresistible 
buffet for rabbits, woodchucks and deer, which can decimate whole 
fields overnight. Vegetable farmers must rely on electric fences, 
traps, sprays, and-more than most people realize-guns and traps to 
protect their crops. If the farmer refrains from killing, raising 
vegetables at a profitable yield requires holding the land in a 
highly artificial state, cordoned off from nature.

Yes, one might argue, but the idyllic farms of yesteryear are 
insufficient to meet the huge demand of our meat-addicted society. 
Even if you eat only organically raised meat, you are not being moral 
unless your consumption level is consistent with all of Earth's six 
billion people sharing your diet.

Production and Productivity

Such an argument rests on the unwarranted assumption that our current 
meat industry seeks to maximize production. Actually it seeks to 
maximize profit, which means maximizing not "production" but 
"productivity"-units per dollar. In dollar terms it is more efficient 
to have a thousand cows in a high-density feedlot, eating corn 
monocultured on a chemically-dependent 5,000-acre farm, than it is to 
have fifty cows grazing on each of twenty 250-acre family farms. It 
is more efficient in dollar terms, and probably more efficient in 
terms of human labor too. Fewer farmers are needed, and in a society 
that belittles farming, that is considered a good thing. But in terms 
of beef per acre (or per unit of water, fossil fuel, or other natural 
capital) it is not more efficient.

In an ideal world, meat would be just as plentiful perhaps, but it 
would be much more expensive. That is as it should be. Traditional 
societies understood that meat is a special food; they revered it as 
one of nature's highest gifts. To the extent that our society 
translates high value into high price, meat should be expensive. The 
prevailing prices for meat (and other food) are extraordinarily low 
relative to total consumer spending, both by historical standards and 
in comparison to other countries. Ridiculously cheap food 
impoverishes farmers, demeans food itself, and makes less "efficient" 
modes of production uneconomical. If food, and meat in particular, 
were more expensive then perhaps we wouldn't waste so much-another 
factor to consider in evaluating whether current meat consumption is 
sustainable.

Moral Imperative

So far I have addressed issues of cruel conditions and environmental 
sustainability, important moral motivations for vegetarianism, to be 
sure. But vegetarianism existed before the days of factory farming, 
and it was inspired by a simple, primal conviction that killing is 
wrong. It is just plain wrong to take another animal's life 
unnecessarily; it is bloody, brutal, and barbaric.

Of course, plants are alive too, and most vegetarian diets involve 
the killing of plants. (The exception is the fruit-only "fruitarian" 
diet.) Most people don't accept that killing an animal is the same as 
killing a plant though, and few would argue that animals are not a 
more highly organized form of life, with greater sentience and 
greater capacity for suffering. Compassion extends more readily to 
animals that cry out in fear and pain, though personally, I do feel 
sorry for garden weeds as I pull them out by the roots. Nonetheless, 
the argument "plants are alive too" is unlikely to satisfy the moral 
impulse behind vegetarianism.

It should also be noted that mechanized vegetable farming involves 
massive killing of soil organisms, insects, rodents and birds. Again, 
this does not address the central vegetarian motivation, because this 
killing is incidental and can in principle be minimized. The soil 
itself, the earth itself, may, for all we know, be a sentient being, 
and surely an agricultural system, even if plant-based, that kills 
soil, kills rivers, and kills the land, is as morally reprehensible 
as any meat-oriented system, but again this does not address the 
essential issue of intent: Isn't it wrong to kill a sentient being 
unnecessarily?

One might also question whether this killing is truly unnecessary. 
Although the nutritional establishment looks favorably on 
vegetarianism, a significant minority of researchers vigorously 
dispute its health claims. An evaluation of this debate is beyond the 
scope of this article, but after many years of dedicated 
self-experimentation, I am convinced that meat is quite "necessary" 
for me to enjoy health, strength and energy. Does my good health 
outweigh another being's right to life? This question leads us back 
to the central issue of killing. It is time to drop all unstated 
assumptions and meet this issue head-on.

The Central Question

Let's start with a very naïve and provocative question: "What, 
exactly, is wrong about killing?" And for that matter, "What is so 
bad about dying?"

It is impossible to fully address the moral implications of eating 
meat without thinking about the significance of life and death. 
Otherwise one is in danger of hypocrisy, stemming from our separation 
from the fact of death behind each piece of meat we eat. The physical 
and social distance from slaughterhouse to dinner table insulates us 
from the fear and pain the animals feel as they are led to the 
slaughter, and turns a dead animal into just "a piece of meat." Such 
distance is a luxury our ancestors did not have: in ancient hunting 
and farming societies, killing was up close and personal, and it was 
impossible to ignore the fact that this was recently a living, 
breathing animal.

Our insulation from the fact of death extends far beyond the food 
industry. Accumulating worldly treasures-wealth, status, beauty, 
expertise, reputation-we ignore the truth that they are impermanent, 
and therefore, in the end, worthless. "You can't take it with you," 
the saying goes, yet the American system, fixated on worldly 
acquisition, depends on the pretense that we can, and that these 
things have real value. Often only a close brush with death helps 
people realize what's really important. The reality of death reveals 
as arrant folly the goals and values of conventional modern life, 
both collective and individual.

It is no wonder, then, that our society, unprecedented in its wealth, 
has also developed a fear of death equally unprecedented in history. 
Both on a personal and institutional level, prolonging and securing 
life has become more important than how that life is lived. This is 
most obvious in our medical system, of course, in which death is 
considered the ultimate "negative outcome," to which even prolonged 
agony is preferable. I see the same kind of thinking in Penn State 
students, who choose to suffer the "prolonged agony" of studying 
subjects they hate, in order to get a job they don't really love, in 
order to have financial "security." They are afraid to live right, 
afraid to claim their birthright, which is to do joyful and exciting 
work. The same fear underlies our society's lunatic obsession with 
"safety." The whole American program now is to insulate oneself as 
much as possible from death-to achieve "security." It comes down to 
the ego trying to make permanent what can never be permanent.

Modern Dualism

Digging deeper, the root of this fear, I think, lies in our culture's 
dualistic separation of body and soul, matter and spirit, man and 
nature. The scientific legacy of Newton and Descartes holds that we 
are finite, separate beings; that life and its events are accidental; 
that the workings of life and the universe may be wholly explained in 
terms of objective laws applied to inanimate, elemental parts; and 
therefore, that meaning is a delusion and God a projection of our 
wishful thinking. If materiality is all there is, and if life is 
without real purpose, then of course death is the ultimate calamity.

Curiously, the religious legacy of Newton and Descartes is not all 
that different. When religion abdicated the explanation of "how the 
world works"-cosmology-to physics, it retreated to the realm of the 
non-worldly. Spirit became the opposite of matter, something elevated 
and separate. It did not matter too much what you did in the world of 
matter, it was unimportant, so long as your (immaterial) "soul" were 
saved. Under a dualistic view of spirituality, living right as a 
being of flesh and blood, in the world of matter, becomes less 
important. Human life becomes a temporary excursion, an 
inconsequential distraction from the eternal life of the spirit.

Other cultures, more ancient and wiser cultures, did not see it like 
this. They believed in a sacred world, of matter infused with spirit. 
Animism, we call it, the belief that all things are possessed of a 
soul. Even this definition betrays our dualistic presumptions. 
Perhaps a better definition would be that all things are soul. If all 
things are soul, then life in the flesh, in the material world, is 
sacred. These cultures also believed in fate, the futility of trying 
to live past one's time. To live rightly in the time allotted is then 
a matter of paramount importance, and life a sacred journey.

When death itself, rather than a life wrongly lived, is the ultimate 
calamity, it is easy to see why an ethical person would choose 
vegetarianism. To deprive a creature of life is the ultimate crime, 
especially in the context of a society that values safety over fun 
and security over the inherent risk of creativity. When meaning is a 
delusion, then ego-the self's internal representation of itself in 
relation to not-self-is all there is. Death is never right, part of a 
larger harmony, a larger purpose, a divine tapestry, because there is 
no divine tapestry; the universe is impersonal, mechanical and 
soulless.

Obsolete Science

Fortunately, the science of Newton and Descartes is now obsolete. Its 
pillars of reductionism and objectivity are crumbling under the 
weight of 20th century discoveries in quantum mechanics, 
thermodynamics and nonlinear systems, in which order arises out of 
chaos, simplicity out of complexity, and beauty out of nowhere and 
everywhere; in which all things are connected; and in which there is 
something about the whole that cannot be fully understood in terms of 
its parts. Be warned, my views would not be accepted by most 
professional scientists, but I think there is much in modern science 
pointing to an ensouled world, in which consciousness, order and 
cosmic purpose are written into the fabric of reality.

In an animistic and holistic world view, the moral question to ask 
oneself about food is not "Was there killing?" but rather, "Is this 
food taken in rightness and harmony?" The cow is a soul, yes, and so 
is the land and the ecosystem, and the planet. Did that cow lead the 
life a cow ought to lead? Is the way it was raised beautiful, or ugly 
(according to my current understanding)? Allying intuition and 
factual knowledge, I ask whether eating this food contributes to that 
tiny shred of the divine tapestry that I can see.

Divine Tapestry

There is a time to live and a time to die. That is the way of nature. 
If you think about it, prolonged suffering is rare in nature. Our 
meat industry profits from the prolonged suffering of animals, people 
and the Earth, but that is not the only way. When a cow lives the 
life a cow ought to live, when its life and death are consistent with 
a beautiful world, then for me there is no ethical dilemma in killing 
that cow for food. Of course there is pain and fear when the cow is 
taken to the slaughter (and when the robin pulls up the worm, and 
when the wolves down the caribou, and when the hand uproots the 
weed), and that makes me sad. There is much to be sad about in life, 
but underneath the sadness is a joy that is dependent not on avoiding 
pain and maximizing pleasure, but on living rightly and well.

It would indeed be hypocritical of me to apply this to a cow and not 
to myself. To live with integrity as a killer of animals and plants, 
it is necessary for me in my own life to live rightly and well, even 
and especially when such decisions seem to jeopardize my comfort, 
security, and rational self-interest, even if, someday, to live 
rightly is to risk death. Not just for animals, but for me too, there 
is a time to live and a time to die. I'm saying: What is good enough 
for any living creature is good enough for me. Eating meat need not 
be an act of arrogant species-ism, but consistent with a humble 
submission to the tides of life and death.

If this sounds radical or unattainable, consider that all those 
calculations of what is "in my interest" and what will benefit me and 
what I can "afford" grow tiresome. When we live rightly, decision by 
decision, the heart sings even when the rational mind disagrees and 
the ego protests. Besides, human wisdom is limited. Despite our 
machinations, we are ultimately unsuccessful at avoiding pain, loss 
and death. For animals, plants, and humans alike, there is more to 
life than not dying.

About the Author

Charles Eisenstein is a stay-at-home dad living in central 
Pennsylvania. He teaches part-time at Penn State. His book, The Yoga 
of Eating, may be purchased from New Trends Publishing, 
http://www.newtrendspublishing.com/YOGA/

_______________________________________________
Biofuel mailing list
Biofuel@sustainablelists.org
http://sustainablelists.org/mailman/listinfo/biofuel_sustainablelists.org

Biofuel at Journey to Forever:
http://journeytoforever.org/biofuel.html

Search the combined Biofuel and Biofuels-biz list archives (50,000 messages):
http://www.mail-archive.com/biofuel@sustainablelists.org/

Reply via email to