At 02:01 AM 7/13/2008, Chris Benham wrote:
Forest,
"The voter ranks all she wants to and the remaining candidates are ranked (later, i.e. below) by the voter's favorite or perhaps, as Steve Eppley has suggested, by the voter's specified public ranking.

Since IRV satisfies LNH, what's the harm in this?".

The harm is that voter's votes are used to help candidates that the voters may not wish to help. It offends the principle that the voter should be fully in control of his/her vote. Giving some voters (candidates) the power to fully control their own vote and also to complete the rankings of some of the truncators offends the principle that as far as possible all voters
should have equal power.

First of all, if we are talking about elections of representatives of some kind, the voter isn't going to be "in full control of his/her vote" no matter what. At the point of the election, or later, when the representative casts votes, individual control is lost.

The equal power issue is spurious. The voting power is in the hands of those who cast ballots, originally, and they may choose to delegate that power or not. More about this below. The original "candidate proxy" or "Asset Voting" proposal was actually an STV proposal by Lewis Carroll, aka Charles Dodgson, in 1994.

"In Australia, where (in single winner elections) most of the voters copy candidate cards, this would save
them a lot of bother."

In Australia the only significant "bother" stems from compulsory full strict ranking (for the vote to be counted as valid). How many or few voters choose to exercise their right to not follow their favourite's
ranking advice is no argument for removing that right.

Compulsory full ranking, Dodgson noted, was a problem for voters who may not be sufficiently informed to understand how to rank *all* candidates. Obviously, full ranking only works when candidate count is limited, and even then donkey voting seems to be fairly common. It would be interesting to see statistics on straight sequence voting (which wouldn't be visible in Australian results because of Robson Rotation, one would have to look at actual ballots or true ballot images.)

> And what do you have in mind as "Australia's worst problems
> with their version of IRV"?

"It has degenerated into a defacto second rate version of Asset Voting."
To the extent that that is true it can (and should) be fixed by simply allowing truncation.

That is done in Queensland and NSW, it's called "Optional Preferential Voting," but, of course, in that there is no remedy for ballot exhaustion.

Dodgson was studying the problem of ballot exhaustion, and hit upon the idea of allowing voters to vote for one.



> Why do you want to "stop" IRV? Do you agree with Kathy Dopp
> that IRV is worse than FPP?

"I would stop IRV if we could get a better method in its place.

If we cannot stop IRV, why not search for acceptable tweaks that would improve it?"

The short answer is because IRV isn't really amenable to "tweaks". In terms of positive criterion compliances it isn't dominated by any other method, and has both good and quite bad properties (averaging in my judgement to a "good" method). "Tweaks" generally muck up its good properties without enough compensation in terms of fixing or patching up its
bad properties.

Problem is that the "good" property, Later No Harm, is actually a *terrible* property, see Woodall's original paper that coined the term.

However, for proportional representation, there is, in fact, a very simple tweak that is what Dodgson invented. He noted that many voters, not being specialists in politics, wouldn't have sufficient knowledge to rank all candidates, and therefore, if truncation were allowed, would indeed truncate and would therefore be at risk of having their ballot exhausted and thus their vote wasted. Why not allow voters to vote for one only, with that one then being able to recast those votes, if exhausted, in order to create quotas for election? I'm not sure that he specified it, I don't have a copy of his full pamphlet yet, but I'd assume that if one ranked more than one, but the ballot were exhausted, the first preference would get the vote for reassignment (but there are other ways to do it, I'm sure, and I haven't considered all the contingencies). It's a simple tweak, but it turns STV into Asset Voting, with voter control over transfers possible, to the extent that the voter exercises the right. And then fallback to deliberative reassignment of exhausted votes, based on the candidate the voter most trusts, the first preference.

There are other possible tweaks: for example, allow multiple votes in each rank. This is similar to Bucklin, it makes each round an Approval election. Voters don't have to do it, so they have the choice of whether or not to vote to avoid Later No Harm. If it's an Asset election, then, and the ballot is exhausted, the vote is fractionally distributed, as in Fractional Approval Asset Voting, my old proposal. (Which is really ordinary Asset but with a simple ballot, unlike the original Warren Smith Asset that allowed votes in the range of 0-1, any set of fractions such that all votes add up to one full vote. With FAAV, I'd expect, most voters would simply vote for one, there really isn't, in my view, a lot of value gained by splitting up the vote, but it is also harmless to do so, and allows voters the flexibility, plus it removes on possible reason for considering a ballot spoiled.)

I think Smith (or Shwartz),IRV is quite a good Condorcet method. It completely fixes the failure of Condorcet while being more complicated (to explain and at least sometimes to count) than plain IRV, and a Mutual Dominant Third candidate can't be successfully buried. But it fails Later-no-Harm and Later-no-Help, is vulnerable to Burying strategy, fails mono-add-top, and keeps IRV's failure of mono-raise and (related) vulnerability to
Pushover strategy.

Once again, LNH compliance is a mark against a method, in my view, and apparently in the view of at least one of Woodall's referees. It's the kind of thing that sounds good, until the implications for democratic process are considered. It treats signaling a possible compromise as a weakness. Only compromise if you are going to die otherwise, would be the equivalent. In order to avoid "betraying" a favorite by making it possible for our total vote to help someone else to win, we choose a method, if we insist on LNH, that kills the candidate, instead of leaving the matter open for a broader determination. That eliminated candidate, my favorite, might have won if not for the LNH compliance of the method.

Further, LNH cannot be satisfied by any method that requires a majority, unless the majority is artificially created, either by eliminations *of votes* or by requiring full ranking, which amounts to coerced votes.

"It is better than FPP in some ways and worse in others, especially in complexity."

With separate paper ballots for each race, I don't accept that IRV is all that "complex".
I think that you have somewhat dodged my question.

It is far harder to audit. That's what the election security experts think. Sure, that can be overcome, but why is it worth the effort? There are better, easier to count forms of preferential voting.

What is missing with much of this is that IRV, in nonpartisan elections, almost always mimics plurality. Even in partisan elections, it tends to do this strongly, but "comeback" elections become more common.

"Do you think that Asset Voting is worse than FPP?"
No, on balance.

We don't really know, since we have only theory. Asset hasn't been tried in political contexts. But Asset is a form of proxy voting, which has been used for centuries where property is involved.


"Just to clarify, I think that Condorcet Methods and Range, though better than IRV, share this complexity
defect with IRV to some degree.  I have suggested the same tweak for them.

In fact, that is the essence of DYN, wihich is simply carrying this tweak to its logical conclusion in the case of Range, which is the only one of the three (Range, Condorcet, and IRV) that satisfies the FBC."

I find your DYN method less offensive than your "IRV tweak" suggestion because it is an "opt in" system and to the extent that voters don't opt in it is just plain Approval (a not-too-bad method).

Right. In fact, take Approval and require a majority for election, you have an *excellent* method, better than Plurality with majority required. (Simply because it avoids runoffs some of the time. Same thing with Bucklin, which is really a ranked Approval, especially if multiple votes are allowed in all rounds, unlike in the original form (Duluth is what I have in mind), where multiple votes were only allowed in third rank.

The irony in the U.S. is that, in nonpartisan elections in jurisdictions where a majority has been required (or else there was a top-two runoff), IRV is replacing this, with utterly spurious arguments based on the false analogy between IRV and real runoff. What is probably the most sophisticated election method in use in the U.S. is being replaced with a less democratic method.

In real practice, IRV in nonpartisan elections here is reproducing, closely, the results of Plurality while pretending to gain a majority. There have been some thirty or so IRV elections here, and there have been nine "instant runoffs." In seven of the nine, no majority of votes cast was found. I perhaps one additional one of those, there would have been a majority found if counting had not been discontinued because the false majority of IRV had been found. In *none* of the nine was the winner any different from the first round plurality result. On the other hand, in the real runoff elections I studied, one out of three resulted in a "comeback," where the runner-up in the first round ended up winning. In a series of federal primary elections, I think it was in Texas, FairVote found 29% "comebacks."

IRV is changing election results, it does not "simulate" real runoffs, and the reasons are pretty clear: real runoffs give the voters a new look at a reduced field, plus there will be differential turnout, which tests preference strength, probably pushing results toward what sincere Range would produce.

Further, there is a little-known fact about *some* runoff elections in the U.S.: write-in votes may be allowed, thus providing a safety valve for the situation, fairly unusual *in nonpartisan elections* that a Condorcet winner (from underlying preferences) isn't in the runoff. In Long Beach, California, there was an election where the mayor won as a write-in. This was an incumbent, and had been prohibited from being on the ballot by term limit laws, which did not prohibit her election, which would have been unconstitutional, but it prohibited her being placed on the ballot. So she ran as a write-in. She was the leader in the primary, but did not gain a majority. In the runoff, there was only one candidate on the ballot, the runner-up. Again, with write-in votes, she won that by a plurality, which was all that was required. (There was another write-in with significant votes in the runoff.)

Top-two runoff with write-ins allowed is much more sophisticated than any single-round system. Robert's Rules of Order prefers repeated balloting with a majority required, and no eliminations, and if a majority continued to be required, it would *be*, in reality, what Robert's Rules recommends, since candidates aren't actually eliminated, there is only the "suggestion" of which candidates are on the ballot.

Voting systems theorists have, as far as I can tell, mostly ignored all this, and voting systems that aren't deterministic with a single ballot aren't even considered voting systems by many theorists, just as Arrow dismissed cardinal ratings as not being a real voting method since it didn't completely rank and, allegedly, there was no "meaning" to the ratings. (Hint, Arrow: the "ratings" are votes, fractional votes. That's what they "mean." Weight placed on an election possibility. These ratings might be "related" to voter utilities, but that isn't what they "mean" because there is no fixed relationship.)

What we consider "election methods" are shortcuts for basic democratic process, which restricts itself to single questions which can be answered Yes or No, with the questions themselves being designed by a series of questions all of that kind. From my point of view, good election methods are simply a way of making democratic process more efficient without sacrificing the democratic value of majority approval of any result. Good methods will also reveal possible improvements over mere majority approval, and all of this *requires* that Later-No-Harm be unsatisfied. The simplest such reform is Approval Voting, which is a very small tweak to Plurality. Range is likewise pretty simple and easy to count, particularly if the resolution is low. To be what I call "Majority Rule compliant," Range must have a specified Approval cutoff, probably an absolute one (such as midrange or above, or simply above midrange). Likewise ranked methods would need an Approval cutoff, mere ranking is not enough.

All voting methods which require completion of the election in a single round are not Majority Rule compliant, with the possible exception that full ranking is required, and any ranking above bottom is considered approval, which coerces votes, and if votes can be coerced, Plurality satisfies it. (You will vote for Our Supreme Leader or we will discard your ballot as obviously containing an error. Remember, Saddam Hussein was re-elected in an election where nobody voted against him. As far as we know.)

I'm always amused by the argument that the last-round majority of IRV is a true majority, because, with this logic, we could always find unanimity for the IRV winner: just carry the elimination one step further.
----
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to