RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug, 

  

Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be 
different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care, etc. 
actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer money? Would 
saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a substantial burden even if 
the saving resulted a government mandate to provide health care that the 
employer found religiously objectionable? 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  


On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote: 
 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
 from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
 special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just 
 the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing 
 against conscience protections for medical providers. 
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
 the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
 The salary payments could have been used for anything. 
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the 
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is 
 highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling 
 interest in paying taxes. 
 
 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the 
 money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a 
 package of services that includes the services the employer believes to be 
 immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer 
 believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those 
 services and pays for those services, and these employers say they cannot in 
 conscience do those things. 
 
 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400 
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote: 
 Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state 
 can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle. 
 It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the 
 money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of 
 which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even 
 abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to 
 partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is 
 used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve 
 contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it 
 for that purpose. (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require 
 plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.) 
  
 Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of 
 salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial 
 burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be 
 overcome by a compelling government interest. For anyone who starts from 
 that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question. But I am not 
 aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the 
 payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows 
 that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of 
 salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful 
 in the eyes of the employer. 
  
 Thus the question here is whether the state ought to take at face value the 
 assertions of some employers that the moral obligation changes dramatically 
 when the money is used for partial subsidization of an insurance plan, 
 rather than for taxes or salaries. I actually think this is a complex 
 question, as to which I deeply appreciate the many thoughtful views others 
 have contributed to this thread. But whatever the merits of that 
 distinction, the case is a far cry from compelling the employer to kill 
 another human being. 
  
 On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 7:27 PM, Douglas Laycock 
 dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote: 
  
  

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in
virtually all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the
employer is prohibited from permitting its money to be used for
contraception, even as mediated by independent decisions of others; and if,
as the government alleges, in fact the actual cost to the employer of
providing the plan is *lower* because of the inclusions of contraception
(the use of which avoids much higher costs associated with pregnancy), then
in a very real sense the employers' dollars are not being used, even
remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  Seems to me that,
too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden claim, and not
because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of religious
obligations.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is
 arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer
 believes to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t
 matter whether it costs money or saves money.

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *b...@jmcenter.org
 *Sent:* Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Doug, 

   

 Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be
 different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care, etc.
 actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer money?
 Would saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a substantial
 burden even if the saving resulted a government mandate to provide health
 care that the employer found religiously objectionable? 

   

 Bob Ritter 

   

 Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

 A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

 Falls Church, VA 22042 

 703-533-0236 

   


 On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote:
  My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and
 exemption from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be
 nothing special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim
 than just the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice movement
 pushing against conscience protections for medical providers.
 
  As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays
 salary, and the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer
 considers immoral. The salary payments could have been used for anything.
 
  I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral,
 is highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's
 compelling interest in paying taxes.
 
  The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because
 the money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer
 buys a package of services that includes the services the employer believes
 to be immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the
 employer believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for
 those services and pays for those services, and these employers say they
 cannot in conscience do those things.
 
  On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
  Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
  Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the
 state
  can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in
 battle.
  It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of
 the
  money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some
 of
  which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or
 even
  abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
  partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
  used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
  contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use
 it
  for that purpose. (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to
 require
  plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)
  
  Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases
 of
  salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
  burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
  overcome by a compelling government interest. For anyone who starts
 from
  that view, the HHS would certainly raise a 

Re: Contraception and Conscience: A Symposium on Religious Liberty, Women's Health, and the HHS Rule on Provision of Birth Control Coverage for Employees

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
The videos of our conference are now posted, on a site where we have also
posted many of the most important resources (opinions, briefs, the Rule,
articles, blogposts, etc.) related to the debate.  Hope you find it
useful.  Please let me know if you have any reactions or suggestions of
sources to add to the page:

http://berkleycenter.georgetown.edu/essays/resources-and-background-on-contraception-and-conscience

Thanks,

Marty

On Fri, Sep 14, 2012 at 3:39 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.comwrote:

 Please excuse the plug.  I hope this is something that those of you in the
 D.C, environs and beyond might be interested in attending.  Thanks


  *Contraception and Conscience:  A Symposium on Religious Liberty,
 Women’s Health, and the HHS Rule on Provision of Birth Control Coverage for
 Employees *




 Georgetown University Law Center
 McDonough Hall
 Philip A. Hart Auditorium
 600 New Jersey Avenue, N.W.
 Washington, DC

 Friday, September 21, 2012
 9:00 a.m.-4:00 p.m.



 A conference examining the legal, theological, health, equality, and
 ethical issues relating to the recent Rule promulgated by the U.S.
 Department of Health and Human Services on “Coverage of Preventive Services
 Under the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act.”

 The symposium brings together legal, religious, and cultural scholars and
 practitioners for a day-long conversation about the increasingly
 contentious public debate surrounding the HHS Rule requiring employers to
 subsidize preventive health services for employees, the religious
 accommodations in the HHS rule, and the lawsuits filed by religious
 objectors challenging the rule.


 *Continental Breakfast—8:30-9:00
 *
 *Introduction—9:00-9:10
 *Dean William M. Treanor, Georgetown University Law Center
 *
 Panel One – 9:10-10:45
 *

 *The Legal Challenges to the HHS Contraception Rule*.  What is the nature
 of the HHS Rule and its religious accommodations?  What is the status of
 the more than two dozen lawsuits challenging the HHS Rule?  How are the
 courts likely to resolve the statutory and constitutional issues?  How do
 claims of religious conscience apply to institutional employers, including
 for-profit employers?  What are the relevant state interests—should the
 Rule be viewed as simply about enabling access to preventive health care,
 or also about ensuring equality in the workplace?  How do these cases
 reflect broader trends in the development of the law of religious liberty?
  How should HHS frame its promised additional religious accommodation?

 *Panelists
 *Martin Lederman, Georgetown University Law Center
 Louise Melling, American Civil Liberties Union
 Melissa Rogers,Wake Forest University Divinity School, Center for Religion
 and Public Affairs
 Robert Vischer, University of St. Thomas School of Law
 Lori Windham, Becket Fund for Religious Liberty


 *Panel Two – 11:00-12:45 *


 *What is the Burden on Religious Exercise*? Does the HHS Rule put
 religious employers to an untenable choice between obeying the law and
 honoring religious obligations, and if so, how?  Does it require
 individuals or entities to “cooperate with evil” in a manner that their
 faith forbids?  Does compliance with the law prevent them from “bearing
 witness” to their faith or create “scandal” by conveying endorsement of
 activities to which the employer morally objects?

 *Panelists
 *Lisa Sowle Cahill, Boston College
 Patrick Deneen, University of Notre Dame
 Cathleen Kaveny, University of Notre Dame
 Michael Kessler, Georgetown University
 John Langan, S.J., Georgetown University
 Robert Tuttle, George Washington University School of Law


 *Panel Three – 2:15-4:00 *


 *A Broader Focus*.  How and why did this particular issue engender such
 concern and controversy?  What are the historical antecedents?  What does
 it tell us about how religious communities and institutions (especially
 those involved in provision of education and social services) can and
 should navigate rapidly changing norms in the public square?   What are the
 implications of this debate for preventive health services?  For women’s
 equality in the workplace and elsewhere in public life?  What are the
 ethical implications for physicians and other health-care providers?

 *Panelists
 *Gregg Bloche, Georgetown University Law Center
 Tracy Fessenden, Arizona State University
 Eduardo Peñalver, Cornell University Law School
 Robin West, Georgetown University Law Center
 Robin Fretwell Wilson, Washington  Lee University School of Law


 *Please RSVP by September 19 to rs...@law.georgetown.edu
 *

 The conference is co-sponsored by the Georgetown University Law Center and
 the Berkley Center for Religion, Peace, and World Affairs at Georgetown
 University.  It is made possible through a grant from the Ford Foundation.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread hamilton02
The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.  


From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power. 
 That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.


On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:


The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.




Marci





 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.


On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:


The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

 

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

 


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


 

Doug, 


  

Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be 
different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care, etc. 
actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer money? Would 
saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a substantial burden even if 
the saving resulted a government mandate to provide health care that the 
employer found religiously objectionable? 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  


On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote: 
 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
 from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
 special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just 
 the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing 
 against conscience protections for medical providers. 
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
 the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
 The salary payments could have been used for anything. 
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the 
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is 
 highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling 
 interest in paying taxes. 
 
 The ACA looks different to those 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
Can I ask a quick question for people like Marci, Marty, and others who 
doubt the existence of a “substantial burden”?



What about United States v. Lee?  The Amish object to paying Social Security 
taxes.  The government makes them.  The decision to use the taxes for Social 
Security is the government’s, not the Amish.  The Amish say, “Well, we 
object to giving you money to pay for that.”  The Court says there’s a 
burden.  Isn’t this case just Lee again?  What am I missing?  (If I’ve 
missed earlier posts discussing this, I’m sorry.)



Best, Chris


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Scarberry, Mark
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546tel:434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Ira Lupu
Re: Chris Lund's question about Lee -- The Amish take care of their own who
are disabled or no longer able to work.  They didn't want to pay twice --
once for FICA contributions, and again in their own community.  And the
FICA contributions were earmarked for just that use.

Employers objecting to the ACA mandate are not concerned about paying
twice.  They want to be immune from even the appearance of support for
these services, even in a context where they can openly condemn the
services.  The religious entity employers (who can refuse to hire those who
use such services) don't even have to pay once.  They just want to be
entirely out of the causation loop between ACA  policies and the provision
of pregnancy prevention services.

Many taxpayers would like to be out of the causation loop between paying
taxes and financing causes they find deeply immoral -- the death penalty,
some or all wars, etc.  Of course, we can handle this on the compelling
interest side (need for uniformity), but the question of attenuation and
distance between the status (employer, taxpayer) and the conduct remains.
The question does not disappear because the claimant says so.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:35 AM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 Can I ask a quick question for people like Marci, Marty, and others who
 doubt the existence of a “substantial burden”?

 ** **

 What about *United States v. Lee*?  The Amish object to paying Social
 Security taxes.  The government makes them.  The decision to use the taxes
 for Social Security is the government’s, not the Amish.  The Amish say,
 “Well, we object to giving you money to pay for that.”  The Court says
 there’s a burden.  Isn’t this case just *Lee *again?  What am I missing?
 (If I’ve missed earlier posts discussing this, I’m sorry.)

 ** **

 Best, Chris

 ** **


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




-- 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Isn't that like saying, if it's OK for you to 'produc[e] the 
raw product necessary for the production of any kind of tank,' why is working 
on tank turrets any different??  Why isn't the answer much like that given in 
Thomas:  But Thomas' statements reveal no more than that he found work in the 
roll foundry sufficiently insulated from producing weapons of war.  We see, 
therefore, that Thomas drew a line, and it is not for us to say that the line 
he drew was an unreasonable one.?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection, enters 
into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in exchange for 
labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used for 
contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the employer 
considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be changed 
slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only wages (in 
effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance), but also access 
to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was getting at here was:  
If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why is the second any 
different?
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546tel:434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
I think Doug is right that it doesn't matter whether it costs money or
saves money.  The objection is any money going to the religiously
prohibited use.

 

You see this kind of argument in Establishment Clause cases.  The
government says to a taxpayer, You need to pay money to fund a religious
school.  The taxpayer says, I object to my money supporting the
religious functions of the school.  The government says, Well, you'd
have to pay for a public school anyway, and that would cost more.  So
you're just saving money this way.  

 

The government's logic here was rejected, and I think rightly, in Smith v.
Jefferson County Bd. of School Com'rs, 641 F.3d 197, 211 (6th Cir. 2011)
(A municipal taxpayer has standing to challenge any unconstitutional
appropriation or expenditure, regardless of whether more money would have
been spent had the government remained within constitutional bounds.
Taxpayer standing in this context will not turn on whether it was a
bargain to violate the Constitution.).

 

Best, 

Chris

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:03 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in
virtually all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the
employer is prohibited from permitting its money to be used for
contraception, even as mediated by independent decisions of others; and
if, as the government alleges, in fact the actual cost to the employer of
providing the plan is lower because of the inclusions of contraception
(the use of which avoids much higher costs associated with pregnancy),
then in a very real sense the employers' dollars are not being used, even
remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  Seems to me that,
too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden claim, and not
because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of religious
obligations.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer
believes to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't
matter whether it costs money or saves money.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:36 PM


To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug, 

  

Would your view -- expressed in the third paragraph of your post -- be
different if the HHS mandated contraceptive coverage, preventive care,
etc. actually saved the employer money rather than cost the employer
money? Would saving money (i.e., reduced insurance premium) be a
substantial burden even if the saving resulted a government mandate to
provide health care that the employer found religiously objectionable? 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  


On October 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote: 
 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and
exemption from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should
be nothing special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader
claim than just the ACA issue. And there are people in the pro-choice
movement pushing against conscience protections for medical providers. 
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays
salary, and the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer
considers immoral. The salary payments could have been used for anything. 
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the
government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral,
is highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's
compelling interest in paying taxes. 
 
 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because
the money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer
buys a package of services that includes the services the employer
believes to be immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills
that the employer believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer
contracts for those services and pays for those services, and these
employers say they cannot in conscience do those things. 
 
 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400 
 Marty Lederman 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Scarberry, Mark
And the point then, Marty, is that for centuries there has been a respectable 
mode of moral analysis in which the directness of involvement in an action is 
related to moral complicity. Buying an insurance policy that constitutes an 
agreement by the employer to subsidize a specific activity is a much more 
direct involvement than just paying wages that an employee may use in any way 
the employee chooses.

Mark



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection, enters 
into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in exchange for 
labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used for 
contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the employer 
considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be changed 
slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only wages (in 
effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance), but also access 
to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was getting at here was:  
If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why is the second any 
different?
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is 
arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer believes 
to be deeply immoral. From the believer's perspective, it doesn't matter 
whether it costs money or saves money.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546tel:434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Mark:  My point is that, as far as I know, for centuries *neither *case
has been considered impermissible cooperation with evil under the mode of
moral analysis you invoke (which I agree is respectable, indeed).  Of
course if the employer affirmatively *chose* to cover contraception, or had
a legal choice whether to accept a plan with it or without it, and chose
the former, that would be a form of *formal *cooperation with evil, which
is proscribed (assuming, as I am here for sake of argument, that
contraception is in fact evil from the employer's perspective).  But
absent such consent or choice, as here, the question is whether the
material cooperation is sufficiently proximate -- and my understanding is
that the proximity in these cases would be the same, and *not *sufficient
to raise the prospect of impermissible cooperation.

FWIW, Cathy Kaveny (copied here) offered a really fantastic summary of the
Catholic doctrine on this at the beginning of our second panel:

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=1J4rCsq732c



On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 11:15 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 And the point then, Marty, is that for centuries there has been a
 respectable mode of moral analysis in which the directness of involvement
 in an action is related to moral complicity. Buying an insurance policy
 that constitutes an agreement by the employer to subsidize a specific
 activity is a much more direct involvement than just paying wages that an
 employee may use in any way the employee chooses.

 ** **

 Mark

 ** **

 ** **

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection,
 enters into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in
 exchange for labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used
 for contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the
 employer considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be
 changed slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only
 wages (in effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance),
 but also access to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was
 getting at here was:  If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why
 is the second any different?

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the
 employer’s money mediated by independent decisions of others. It’s the
 requirement that the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions
 that the employer believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has
 claimed that he or she can withhold payment of wages because the employee
 might choose to use the money to obtain contraceptives or other services.
 

  

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM


 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  

 Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in
 virtually all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the
 employer is prohibited from permitting its money to be used for
 contraception, even as mediated by independent decisions of others; and if,
 as the government alleges, in fact the actual cost to the employer of
 providing the plan is *lower* because of the inclusions of contraception
 (the use of which avoids much higher costs associated with pregnancy), then
 in a very real sense the employers' dollars are not being used, even
 remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  Seems to me that,
 too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden claim, and not
 because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of religious
 obligations.

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote:

 The burden on religion in these cases is not the amount of money. It is
 arranging for, contracting for, and paying for services the employer
 believes to be deeply immoral. From the believer’s perspective, it doesn’t
 matter whether it costs money or saves money.

  

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Eugene has it exactly right.

On a related note, if, as some people have claimed, insurance premiums would be 
higher if contraceptive, sterilization etc. services were not covered (due to 
additional pregnancies), then it becomes perfectly obvious that the objection 
is not a disguised attempt to avoid costs. The analogy is imperfect, but it's 
like a taxpayer being allowed to check a box on a tax return that will cause 
the taxpayer to have to pay 10% extra in taxes, but will also cause the govt to 
segregate the taxpayer's payment (into a lockbox?) so that none of the money 
is traceable to payment for armaments. A taxpayer who checks the box certainly 
can't be accused of claiming a conscientious objection to war in order to save 
money.

(The analogy is imperfect for various reasons. For example, one who pays taxes 
is not being required to assent to the use of the taxes for any purpose. It 
also seems unlikely that insurance rates actually will be lower if 
contraception is covered. The main effect of the HHS requirement, insofar as it 
deals with contraception, may be that people switch from inexpensive birth 
control methods - e.g., generic pills that have been on the market for a long 
time - to more expensive kinds - e.g., the latest name brand version that is 
still under patent. The requirement, if I understand it correctly, requires 
coverage of all FDA approved contraceptives (without a copay and without a 
higher copay for nongeneric drugs. I wonder whether the pharmaceutical 
companies helped write it.)

Mark

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 8:07 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Isn't that like saying, if it's OK for you to 'produc[e] the 
raw product necessary for the production of any kind of tank,' why is working 
on tank turrets any different??  Why isn't the answer much like that given in 
Thomas:  But Thomas' statements reveal no more than that he found work in the 
roll foundry sufficiently insulated from producing weapons of war.  We see, 
therefore, that Thomas drew a line, and it is not for us to say that the line 
he drew was an unreasonable one.?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:49 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

That's the point, Mark.  The employer freely, and without objection, enters 
into an employment contract with the employee to pay wages in exchange for 
labor, knowing full well that some % of the wages will be used for 
contraception, abortion, and probably a bunch of other things the employer 
considers sinful.  Now, the state requires that the contract be changed 
slightly, so that in exchange for labor, the employee gets not only wages (in 
effect diminished because of the cost of the health insurance), but also access 
to a health insurance plan.  What I think the judge was getting at here was:  
If the first contract is morally unobjectionable, why is the second any 
different?
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:37 AM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
But it simply is not the case that the alleged burden is use of the employer's 
money mediated by independent decisions of others. It's the requirement that 
the employer enter into a contract that subsidizes actions that the employer 
believes to be immoral. No one, as far as I know, has claimed that he or she 
can withhold payment of wages because the employee might choose to use the 
money to obtain contraceptives or other services.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 7:03 AM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
Thanks, Chip.  A couple responses.

 

The way I read Lee, the burden was not that the Amish had to pay twice.
The burden was that they had to pay the government at all.  See, e.g.,
Lee, 455 U.S. at 257 (We therefore accept appellee's contention that both
payment and receipt of social security benefits is forbidden by the Amish
faith.  Because the payment of the taxes or receipt of benefits violates
Amish religious beliefs, compulsory participation in the social security
system interferes with their free exercise rights.).  True enough that
the Amish took care of their own.  But this seems like a background fact
necessary to explain (and tacitly validate) the Amish's religious beliefs;
it does not seem necessary to the finding of a burden.  Footnote 6 of the
opinion refers to another organization (Sai Baba) that the Court says does
not provide for their own members.  The Court mentions their views as a
reason to think that the Amish belief is bona fide; the Court does not
suggest that there would be no burden in that case.

 

But your post also led me down a logical trail that makes me think the
burden in the ACA case might be clearer than the burden in Lee.  The
Amish's religious objection in Lee starts with a Biblical requirement that
religious communities provide for their own members.  The government's
brief in Lee sensibly asks, Why is this a burden?  You can provide for
your own people, but still pay social security taxes.  (See U.S. Br. in
Lee, at 10-11.)  The Amish respond in their brief by saying, No, well,
also it's a sin to pay the taxes at all.  It's not clear to me this is
the most natural reading of the Biblical text.  But the Supreme Court
doesn't want to get into that.  So they (again citing Thomas) say, We
therefore accept appellee's contention that both payment and receipt of
social security benefits is forbidden by the Amish faith.  I think that
whole accept appellee's contention language is important-the Court may
not necessarily believe it, but will not investigate it further.

 

The Court in Lee thus goes to lengths to interpret the religious objection
as the kind of religious objection that the ACA plaintiffs raise: The
government is requiring us to pay money that will go toward things to
which we religiously object.  And the Court unanimously finds that to be a
burden.

 

Of course, none of this speaks to the sincerity or the compelling-interest
parts of it.  

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:59 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Re: Chris Lund's question about Lee -- The Amish take care of their own
who are disabled or no longer able to work.  They didn't want to pay twice
-- once for FICA contributions, and again in their own community.  And the
FICA contributions were earmarked for just that use.

Employers objecting to the ACA mandate are not concerned about paying
twice.  They want to be immune from even the appearance of support for
these services, even in a context where they can openly condemn the
services.  The religious entity employers (who can refuse to hire those
who use such services) don't even have to pay once.  They just want to be
entirely out of the causation loop between ACA  policies and the provision
of pregnancy prevention services.

Many taxpayers would like to be out of the causation loop between paying
taxes and financing causes they find deeply immoral -- the death penalty,
some or all wars, etc.  Of course, we can handle this on the compelling
interest side (need for uniformity), but the question of attenuation and
distance between the status (employer, taxpayer) and the conduct remains.
The question does not disappear because the claimant says so.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 10:35 AM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

Can I ask a quick question for people like Marci, Marty, and others who
doubt the existence of a substantial burden?

 

What about United States v. Lee?  The Amish object to paying Social
Security taxes.  The government makes them.  The decision to use the taxes
for Social Security is the government's, not the Amish.  The Amish say,
Well, we object to giving you money to pay for that.  The Court says
there's a burden.  Isn't this case just Lee again?  What am I missing?
(If I've missed earlier posts discussing this, I'm sorry.)

 

Best, Chris

 


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
wrongly) forward the 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
Chris, I respectfully disagree with the ipso facto view that a plaintiff is
substantially burdened when ever compelled to do something their religion
forbids. Burdened yes, substantially burdened maybe. This may sound cold, but
it's business. I would suggest to people who oppose the mandate to move on
but I know that isn't going to happen.

I believe that current mandate found the correct accommodation in balancing
the interests of employers and employees. Obviously, some disagree.

Not said in this discussion so far is that in the name of religion much ill is
done (including war and discrimination). In my view, broadening the
accommodation would add to the list. (I would see granting the accommodation to
O'Brien like granting a religious exemption to parents from seeking medical care
for their sick children.)

Bob Ritter


On October 2, 2012 at 1:05 PM Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 
  As for Chip and Bob Ritter’s point about the burden being “substantial,” I
 think that anytime a plaintiff is forced to do something their religion
 forbids, that is not just a burden but a substantial burden.  I think the
 Court made this clear by implication in Hernandez.  See Hernandez v.
 Commissioner, 490 U.S. 680, 699 (1989) (“We do, however, have doubts whether
 the alleged burden imposed by the deduction disallowance on the
 Scientologists' practices is a substantial one.  Neither the payment nor the
 receipt of taxes is forbidden by the Scientology faith generally, and
 Scientology does not proscribe the payment of taxes in connection with
 auditing or training sessions specifically.”).  This is not to say that the
 word “substantial” makes no difference.  It may be important in other kinds of
 cases like, say, Braunfeld—cases where the government makes the religious
 practice more onerous but does not forbid it.  (For another example, we could
 go back to my discussion with Marci about a prison that doesn’t force a Jew to
 eat non-Kosher food, but puts him on a Kosher diet that is significantly worse
 than that of other inmates.)
 
 
 
  I think Chip has rightly diagnosed the deep divide between the two groups.  I
 think there are merits and demerits to both sides.  But I think the Court has
 chosen the first position.  Subject to the sincerity inquiry, churches do
 indeed get to “self-declare” what their religious views are.  I know that
 sounds weird, but wouldn’t it be weirder if they didn’t?  Certainly this broad
 conception of “burden” will lead to outcomes like Lee: As the scope of the
 religious objection grows wider and wider, the government’s claim of a
 compelling interest becomes more and more persuasive.  Maybe the Court’s
 adoption of a broad sense of “burden” in cases like Lee helped lead to
 Employment Division v. Smith.  Gosh knows, it was part of Boerne.  See City of
 Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507, 535 (1997) (“It is a reality of the modern
 regulatory state that numerous state laws, such as the zoning regulations at
 issue here, impose a substantial burden on a large class of individuals.”)
  But it seems to me that this is the path we’re on.
 
 
 
  Best,
 
  Chris
 
 
 
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
  Sent: Tuesday, October 02, 2012 11:10 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
 
 
 
  The formal findings in RFRA reference Sherbert and Yoder, but not Thomas.
  Significant?
 
 
 
  Should Thomas even apply to artificial persons, like holding companies,
 corporations, and religious non-profits?  Shouldn't they be required to
 articulate with clarity and precision just how their religious exercise is
 burdened?
 
 
 
  I have not yet seen a reply to Bob Ritter's very good question about what
 work is being done by the word substantial in RFRA. It has to mean
 something.  Does it refer to material burdens (e.g., one must pay a fine of $X
 if one insists on compliance with one's own religious conscience)?  Or does it
 refer to the religious substantiality of the burden?
 
 
 
  The list appears to divide into two groups on this burden question.  One one
 side, the claimant gets to self-declare, and that triggers the strict scrutiny
 of RFRA.   That seems to wildly over-enforce religious freedom.  Consider the
 religiously idiosyncratic and libertarian employer who objects to FLSA, OSHA,
 Title VII, etc.
 
 
 
  On the other side, the government lawyers and courts get to second-guess and
 decide what someone's religion really requires, and what kind of burden on
 that is presumptively too great to force the claimant to endure.  That seems
 unconstitutional (see Hosanna-Tabor and other decisions on Establishment
 Clause limits on the state's resolving internal religious questions).
 
 
 
   Chip
 
 
 
  On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Scarberry, Mark
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
Marty, obviously worthy questions.  No answers, just some thoughts.

 

1.   I think I feel the same way you do.  Burden, sincerity, and
centrality all were used to restrict the scope of the compelling-interest
test.  The Court has junked centrality, and has limited inquiries on
sincerity.  All that is left is burden, and if we interpret it broadly,
then there's a risk of a taffy pull-every claim receives some
constitutional protection, which dilutes the compelling-interest test,
ultimately meaning that strong claims get treated much worse.  I don't
have an answer to this; I wish I did.  But I wonder if this fear is a bit
overblown.  We got rid of the centrality inquiry 20 years ago, and
rigorous inquiries into sincerity 30 years ago, and RFRA/state RFRAs seems
to work fine without them.  My sense is that-apart from prisons-the
weakest claims aren't brought, or don't find lawyers, or get dismissed on
doctrinally-unjustifiable-but-realistically-understandable grounds.  But I
do worry about the taffy pull.   What has alarmed me most about the HHS
litigation is the private employers.  I am sympathetic to the claims of
the Catholic Church (in all of its iterations); I am less sympathetic to
the private owner of a for-profit business wanting not to provide
contraception coverage.  Maybe I shouldn't feel this way, but I do.  And I
bet judges do too. 

 

2.   (I agree about the difficulties of Gillette.)  One thing: The
claimant's say-so of a religious burden.  A plaintiff's subjective views
of a burden are irrelevant-that's Lyng and Bowen.  But plaintiffs'
subjective views of their own religion are controlling-that's Thomas, and
Lee, and others.  There's a difference there, and the gap creates a real
check.  Yes, plaintiffs can create a burden by willing to plead whatever
religious beliefs necessary to get them there, but I'm not convinced they
would do that.  And I think sincerity is a legitimate attack there.

 

3.   I think this issue comes ultimately before the Court, but as a
sincerity issue not as a burden issue.  And to be clear, I don't think it
should be off the table.  At various times, quite maddeningly, the
Catholic Church has confused the issue of (1) whether they should be
required to provide contraception to their employees, with (2) whether
contraception should be provided at all (whether by other employers or the
government).  The first is a religious liberty claim, where I am
sympathetic to the Church; the second is a public policy claim, where I am
not.  That the Church has sometimes mixed the two together opens the door
to a doubt about sincerity: Maybe the Catholic Church just doesn't like
contraception generally, and this is just another tactic to minimize its
spread.  But I think a plausible reading of the Church's position is that
while they dislike contraception across-the-board, there are special
problems with them being forced to provide it.  

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 11:17 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Chris:  You and Marc raise absolutely valid points about doctrine during
the Sherbert/Yoder era:  The argument I'm suggesting (I'm not advocating
it yet -- merely thinking it through) is in at least some tension with the
sheet-metal/turrets portion of Thomas, and perhaps the burden discussion
in Lee (I can't recall offhand what the Amish theory was about why the
Social Security taxes violated their religion, but I assume it was
something akin to the cooperation with evil theory being floated here;
although as Chip suggests, it also involved some aspect of
double-payment).

So, simply in terms of what the right answer is or ought to be under RFRA,
the government will obviously have to contend with those cases, either by
suggesting (as someone here did) that perhaps RFRA did not incorporate
their burden analysis wholesale (I'm dubious, but haven't thought it
through), or that this case is distinguishable.

But I'm not simply asking what the right answer is under RFRA.  I'm
trying to address at least three other questions raised by these claims:

1.  Was Burger right on the turrets/sheet-metal point?  Should the courts
actually treat all religious claims of substantial burden uncritically,
without even asking whether and to what extent the claimant's own conduct
calls into question whether the burden is in fact substantial from the
claimant's own religious perspective?  If the courts do not differentiate
at all between the plausibility and strength of such claims, and treat all
alleged substantial burdens alike, is that a good thing for religious
liberty?  After all, it means that if the government were to voluntarily
give exemptions, or be compelled by the FEC/RFRA to do so, it would have
to cover a much, much wider class of 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

Derek L. Gaubatz
IMB General Counsel

Our vision is a multitude from every language, people, tribe and nation knowing 
and worshipping our Lord Jesus Christ.

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

Derek L. Gaubatz
IMB General Counsel

Our vision is a multitude from every language, people, tribe and nation knowing 
and worshipping our Lord Jesus Christ.

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and 

HHS Rule: What is at Stake?

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Thanks, Chris.  As to your discussion regarding what might be truly
bothering at least some critics of the HHS within the Church, over at
Mirror of Justice Rick G. links to this new post by one of our esteemed
Conference participants, Patrick Deenen, whose views on this certainly
differ considerably from mine (and from many of his co-panelists'):

http://www.firstthings.com/onthesquare/2012/10/president-obamarsquos-campaign-for-leviathan.


To Patrick's credit, at our conference he acknowledged during his panel's
discussion (hope I'm characterizing this fairly--I need to review the video
myself!) that the issue from the Church's perspective is not so much (or at
least not principally) impermissible forced cooperation with evil, but
something much more fundamental about the role of the state.  His new essay
gives a flavor of what he sees as one of the real concerns for at least
certain of the objectors to the HHS Rule.

Patrick writes that with the observation during the Democratic National
Convention that 'government is the only thing we all belong to', and the
actual underlying theme [of the Convention] that the State is needed to
ensure our individuated liberty, the Obama administration thus implicitly
and effectively endorsed the Hobbesian liberal ontology that there ought
exist only individuals and the state—all other competitors are to be
regarded as oppressors, and require an expansive and empowered government
for individual liberation.

Now, I happen to think that this leap is, to put it politely, not
intuitively obvious and more than a bit hyberbolic.  Does anyone seriously
think that statements or themes at a convention that the government is the
only thing we all belong to and the state is needed to ensure our
individuated liberty reveal that the Obama Administration endorses
elimination of all other social institutions (there ought to exist only
individuals and the state), every one of which is to be regarded as
oppressors?

But more to the point, Patrick argues that the HHS rule is a prime example
of the Leviathan state dangerously intruding into the internal operations
of voluntary, constitutive social organizations to which persons once owed
their primary allegiance --- including the family, the Church, and private
guilds.

The problem (well, one problem) with this argument is that the HHS rule
will not apply to virtually any organization of the type that Patrick
describes -- in particular, to any nonprofit organization that qualifies
for and exercises the title VII exemption allowing preferences for
co-religionists.  In *those *organizations, the employees know going in
that they are committing to be part of a religious community, and that they
might have to adjust their behaviors to reflect religious norms.  For that
reason, HHS does not apply its Rule to those organizations.  (I'm putting
to one side here the fact that there may be -- though I doubt it -- a few
organizations that hire only from within the Church but that would not
qualify for either of the HHS exemptions.  Because that's a hypothetical
situation unlikely to be encountered, I think it fair to reserve it here.)

The employees being protected by HHS here are *not *those who have
voluntarily joined such an organization constituitive of a cohesive
community challenging the orthodoxies of the state.  Instead, they are, for
the most part, non-Catholic employees who have been hired by Catholic
employers to process refractory and ceramic materials (*O'Brien*), or to
serve soup, or to sort the mail, or to take dictation, or to keep the
accounting books, etc.  These employees do not promise, and are not
expected, to follow Catholic precepts in their private lives.  And, perhaps
more to the point, well before the HHS Rule, the dreaded Leviathan state
had already imposed *countless *regulations on the employer for the purpose
of protecting those employees (wage and hour regs, antidiscrimnation norms,
OSHA, etc., etc.) -- regulations that are not typically applied to the
sorts of theoretical pre-state organizations to which Patrick refers.

Perhaps most importantly for purposes of this list, if this is really
what's driving the objection to the HHS Rule, then, *whatever* one thinks
of its merits, is it really the sort of objection that the state should
accommodate in the name of religious liberty?

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 12:41 PM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 Marty, obviously worthy questions.  No answers, just some thoughts.

 ** **

 **1.   **I think I feel the same way you do.  Burden, sincerity, and
 centrality all were used to restrict the scope of the compelling-interest
 test.  The Court has junked centrality, and has limited inquiries on
 sincerity.  All that is left is “burden,” and if we interpret it broadly,
 then there’s a risk of a taffy pull—every claim receives some
 constitutional protection, which dilutes the compelling-interest test,
 ultimately meaning that “strong” claims get treated much worse.  

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it’s merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I’m not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can’t use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power.  
That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman  
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock   wrote:

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
Dear Marci,

The substantial burden theory here is not new, it's merely another factual 
iteration of what the Supreme Court has previously recognized in cases like 
Yoder to be a substantial burden:   levying a financial penalty against an 
individual who refuses to violate his sincere religious beliefs (whatever those 
beliefs might be) is a per se substantial burden.As I noted earlier, the 
proper focus of whether there is a government imposed substantial burden  is an 
objective test that focuses on the action taken by the government, not the 
subjective feelings of the believer.   An objective substantial burden is an 
action by the government that coerces or tend to inhibit any religious 
exercise.   For example, Yoder makes clear that being fined for engaging in a 
particular act of religious exercise is objectively a substantial burden 
regardless of the particular nature of the religious exercise involved (e.g., 
wearing a yarmulke, sending kids to the public school, or being forced to 
purchase a product or service contrary to your beliefs).Objectively 
focusing on the nature of the action taken by the government avoids getting 
into a quagmire of analyzing the subjective nature about how the claimant feels 
about the government action.

I'm not smart enough to debate whether the religious claimants are channeling 
Nietzsche, but I suspect most of them are good people who simply wish the 
government would return things to the state of affairs that existed before it 
imposed the mandate.   That is, recognizing a religious accommodation to the 
mandate under RFRA merely returns things to the empirical world that existed 
pre- mandate: the non-believing employee still has the power to spend her money 
to purchase contraceptives and abortifacients or work for an employer who does 
cover them; she just can't use the machinery of the state to compel the 
believing employer to put up the money to pay for them.

Blessings,
Derek

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 10:22 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

The burden in these cases is a newly configured theory of burden, wherein the 
believer is attempting to alter a neutral, generally applicable system
so that nonbelievers will be deterred from engaging in practices the believer 
disapproves of.  It is no longer about the believer him or herself, but also 
about the power of the believer to affect non-believer's choices relative to 
the believer's religious world view.  The key problem here is the imposition of 
the employer's world view on the independent medical choices of the employee.  
No case has protected this kind of overreaching regarding conduct.

From a philosophical perspective, it is the classic Nietzschean will to power. 
 That doesn't mean the belief is not sincere, but rather that the asserted 
beliefs
no longer are solely about the practice of the individual but also about 
suppressing the practices of others.  The free exercise clause doesn't protect 
it.

On a different note, does anyone think that Title VII would permit a sexual 
harrassment, gender discrimination, or hostile work environment claim in the 
following scenario:

The employer is opposed to abortion on religious grounds, and posts 
anti-abortion signs in every woman's bathroom, which include a statement that
the employee who obtains an abortion will have problems.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman  
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wed, Oct 3, 2012 10:04 am
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Well, if the claim of a religious burden is -- as the plaintiffs in virtually 
all of these cases has alleged -- based upon the notion that the employer is 
prohibited from permitting its money to be used for contraception, even as 
mediated by independent decisions of others; and if, as the government alleges, 
in fact the actual cost to the employer of providing the plan is lower because 
of the inclusions of contraception (the use of which avoids much higher costs 
associated with pregnancy), then in a very real sense the employers' dollars 
are not being used, even remotely and indirectly, to subsidize contraception.  
Seems to me that, too, would significantly undermine the substantial burden 
claim, and not because of any governmental disagreement on the nature of 
religious obligations.
On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 9:55 AM, Douglas Laycock   wrote:

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
It cannot be the answer that the coverage is mandated. Whether the coverage can 
be mandated is the question. The employer signs a contract, and pays for a 
contract, that covers these services. But for the regulation, he could sign and 
pay for a very similar contract that does not cover these services. 

 

Re saving money: I’m going to tweak the facts to isolate the issue of cost 
saving. I’m going to make the religious objection one that everyone would 
share. I understand that  these hypothetical facts are extreme. The point is 
only to separate the issue of saving money from all the other issues.

 

Suppose the church runs an orphanage with 1000 children. It invites bids on a 
contract to feed the children for a year. It specifies the quantity and quality 
of food. It gets two bids. 

 

The first bid is $1.5 million.  The second bid is $1.3 million. The second 
bidder specifies that after the contract is awarded, it will take the 100 
oldest children, drive them to the nearest big city, and dump them on the 
street. There will be no need to feed them anymore. The church should not worry 
that it is paying for this immoral act, because it isn’t paying – it is 
actually paying less instead of more. But of course the church would think 
itself morally responsible if it signed that contract.

 

From the church’s perspective, if contraception saves money, it will do so by 
preventing children from being born. Most of us think that contraception is 
good thing. But if you think it an evil thing, the fact that it saves money 
does not make it morally acceptable to contract for it, or to pay for a 
package that includes it.

 

 

 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: b...@jmcenter.org [mailto:b...@jmcenter.org] 
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 1:23 PM
To: Douglas Laycock
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug, thank you for responding but I still don't comprehend your point. (By the 
way, you slipped the money back into the argument.) 

  

Since the coverage is mandated and operative clauses are likely boilerplate 
(thus no or virtually no arranging and contracting: for the contraceptive, 
etc. coverage) and under the scenario I presented that the employer is charged 
nothing additional, I suspect that what is left is merely that an employer 
maybe upset that his or her employees have an opportunity to participated in 
the mandated services. Much to attenuated for me to call the mandate a 
substantial burden on the employer's free exercise of religion. 

  

Bob Ritter 

  

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

Falls Church, VA 22042 

703-533-0236 

  

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: HHS Rule: What is at Stake?

2012-10-03 Thread Christopher Lund
Marty,

 

If the Catholic Church's view is really the same as Patrick Deenen's-if
the Catholic Church's real objection is that HHS moves us to a
Leviathan-like state and they have religious objections to that-then I
agree its First Amendment claim fails.  Then this really does become a
case like Lyng or Bowen.  The Catholic Church can object if they are
coerced by the government in doing things against their religious will,
but they have no First Amendment claim to control the government's
behavior. 

 

A problem is going to be that there are a lot of people in the Catholic
Church.  Some will have a religious objection specifically to the
government-imposed role for the Catholic Church, some will just have a
religious objection to the whole act (maybe like Patrick Deenen), and some
will have no religious objection at all.  I guess everything depends on
who the plaintiff is.  And in the case of an organizational plaintiff, it
depends on the people vested with authority for the organization.  

 

You seem to equate (1) religious organizations where the employees know
going in that they are committing to be part of a religious community, and
that they might have to adjust their behaviors to reflect religious norms
and (2) religious organizations that qualif[y] for and exercis[e] the
title VII exemption allowing preferences for co-religionists.  I think I
agree that (1) makes sense in deciding on the breadth of any religious
exception.  My question is why (1) and (2) are the same.  Why can't there
be organizations that have an important religious mission, but don't hire
exclusively in the faith?  I think a lot of religious social-justice
organizations work that way.  And church schools.  This was a big deal in
Hosanna-Tabor.  The fact that the church school hired non-Lutherans was
evidence to the Sixth Circuit that the church school wasn't serious about
its religious mission.  That seems to me (and it seemed to the Court) to
be a mistake.

 

Best, Chris

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 2:28 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: HHS Rule: What is at Stake?

 

Thanks, Chris.  As to your discussion regarding what might be truly
bothering at least some critics of the HHS within the Church, over at
Mirror of Justice Rick G. links to this new post by one of our esteemed
Conference participants, Patrick Deenen, whose views on this certainly
differ considerably from mine (and from many of his co-panelists'):

http://www.firstthings.com/onthesquare/2012/10/president-obamarsquos-campa
ign-for-leviathan.  

To Patrick's credit, at our conference he acknowledged during his panel's
discussion (hope I'm characterizing this fairly--I need to review the
video myself!) that the issue from the Church's perspective is not so much
(or at least not principally) impermissible forced cooperation with evil,
but something much more fundamental about the role of the state.  His new
essay gives a flavor of what he sees as one of the real concerns for at
least certain of the objectors to the HHS Rule.

Patrick writes that with the observation during the Democratic National
Convention that 'government is the only thing we all belong to', and the
actual underlying theme [of the Convention] that the State is needed to
ensure our individuated liberty, the Obama administration thus
implicitly and effectively endorsed the Hobbesian liberal ontology that
there ought exist only individuals and the state-all other competitors are
to be regarded as oppressors, and require an expansive and empowered
government for individual liberation.

Now, I happen to think that this leap is, to put it politely, not
intuitively obvious and more than a bit hyberbolic.  Does anyone seriously
think that statements or themes at a convention that the government is
the only thing we all belong to and the state is needed to ensure our
individuated liberty reveal that the Obama Administration endorses
elimination of all other social institutions (there ought to exist only
individuals and the state), every one of which is to be regarded as
oppressors?

But more to the point, Patrick argues that the HHS rule is a prime example
of the Leviathan state dangerously intruding into the internal
operations of voluntary, constitutive social organizations to which
persons once owed their primary allegiance --- including the family, the
Church, and private guilds. 

The problem (well, one problem) with this argument is that the HHS rule
will not apply to virtually any organization of the type that Patrick
describes -- in particular, to any nonprofit organization that qualifies
for and exercises the title VII exemption allowing preferences for
co-religionists.  In those organizations, the employees know going in that
they are committing to be part of a religious community, and that they
might have to adjust their behaviors to reflect religious 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the
church will have *chosen* to save the $200,000 by having the kids dumped.
That would be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal cooperation with
evil.

But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite -- because
the employer can still make the payment to the government instead of
offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for purposes of Catholic
(and most other) moral reasoning, because now we're asking the question *not
* of whether your *volitional choice* was impermissible (as in your hypo),
but instead whether your proximity to the evil, in and of itself, is so
great that your cooperation is immoral *even though you were
well-intentioned*.

You're right, of course, that the fact that coverage is legally mandated
can't categorically eliminate the prospect of a substantial burden, because
in that case there'd never be a valid RFRA claim.  So, for example, a
religion might teach that *certain *action is immoral, even if done under
duress -- indeed, even if done under threat of criminal sanction.  In such
a case, a state law requiring the conduct surely imposes a substantial
burden on religious exercise, at least if the person in question otherwise
is committed to abiding by that norm.

But in most cases, including this one, the fact of legal compulsion does
radically alter the moral calculus, because it eliminates the principal
thing that made the conduct in your hypo wrongful, namely, the *choice* to
sacrifice the kids for $200,000 savings.

Suppose, for example, that in City A, taxi drivers have complete discretion
which fares to accept, and a taxi driver who believes that prostitution is
immoral chooses to prefer fares going to so-called houses of ill-repute,
because they much more remunerative (because of distance, clientele,
whatever).  That choice would be a violation of the norm against formal
cooperation with evil.

City B, however, has decided to treat cab drivers as common carriers --
they must accept all fares, no matter the destination.  Our same cab
driver, thinking that prostitution is unlawful, but now working in City B,
abides by the law, picks up all fares without discrimination . . . and
occasionally finds himself being asked to drop the passenger at a so-called
house of ill-repute, a request that (like all others) he honors.  In this
case, he has performed exactly the same act as he did in City A, but this
time, he has not violated religious tenets.

Seems to be that in most material respects, the HHS Rule is more like my
taxi driver in City B -- or the taxpayer in any jurisdiction -- than like
your hypo of a Church that would gladly leave kids on the street in order
to save a few bucks.



On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 3:04 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 It cannot be the answer that the coverage is mandated. Whether the
 coverage can be mandated is the question. The employer signs a contract,
 and pays for a contract, that covers these services. But for the
 regulation, he could sign and pay for a very similar contract that does not
 cover these services. 

 ** **

 Re saving money: I’m going to tweak the facts to isolate the issue of cost
 saving. I’m going to make the religious objection one that everyone would
 share. I understand that  these hypothetical facts are extreme. The point
 is only to separate the issue of saving money from all the other issues.**
 **

 ** **

 Suppose the church runs an orphanage with 1000 children. It invites bids
 on a contract to feed the children for a year. It specifies the quantity
 and quality of food. It gets two bids. 

 ** **

 The first bid is $1.5 million.  The second bid is $1.3 million. The second
 bidder specifies that after the contract is awarded, it will take the 100
 oldest children, drive them to the nearest big city, and dump them on the
 street. There will be no need to feed them anymore. The church should not
 worry that it is paying for this immoral act, because it isn’t paying – it
 is actually paying less instead of more. But of course the church would
 think itself morally responsible if it signed that contract.

 ** **

 From the church’s perspective, if contraception saves money, it will do so
 by preventing children from being born. Most of us think that contraception
 is good thing. But if you think it an evil thing, the fact that it saves
 money does not make it morally acceptable to contract for it, or to pay for
 a package that includes it.

 ** **

 ** **

 ** **

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* b...@jmcenter.org [mailto:b...@jmcenter.org]
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Alan Brownstein
A couple of quick thoughts regarding your points, Chris.


1.   If we are talking about existing laws such as RFRA or other laws that 
require strict scrutiny review, there may be a dilution problem (although like 
you I have seen strict scrutiny diluted in state RFRA cases and in RLUIPA cases 
without any evidence that this has crossed over to other areas of law.) Also, 
because courts often do not really apply strict scrutiny in RFRA and RLUIPA 
cases, notwithstanding the clear language of the statutes, the insistence that 
courts rigorously enforce a substantial burden threshold seems harder to 
justify. In any case, from a more abstract perspective, we can re-think both 
the standard of review and the substantial burden threshold. That's at least 
the focus of my posts.


2.   When you talk about plaintiff's creating a burden that sounds like 
religious beliefs have clear parameters governed by logical rules. I'm 
certainly not a theologian, but for a lot of individuals, religious beliefs and 
duties are relational and they are evolving in the sense that individuals don't 
always think about what their religion requires in hypothetical situations.  
Relational beliefs and duties are rarely logical. (Certainly, my relationships 
with people who are important to me aren't logical.) As for evolving 
understandings,  it seems just as plausible to say that a religious individual 
confronted with a new question or situation realizes that a government mandate 
burdens his or her faith than it is to say that they create a burden to get 
their claim adjudicated on the merits. Outside of the prison context, I have 
seen very few free exercise or RFRA claims where plaintiffs are asserting sham 
beliefs to benefit unfairly from religious liberty legislation. (List members 
can correct me if I'm wrong about this.)



3.I can't summarize the position of the Catholic Church on 
contraceptive mandate laws at the national level or in other states. But in 
California, when the Women's Contraceptive Equity Act (the state forerunner of 
the HHS regulations) was debated in the legislature, the Catholic Conference 
took a neutral position on the law but strongly insisted on a religious 
exemption for Catholic Charities and other Catholic non-profits (which it did 
not receive.)

Alan

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 9:41 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Marty, obviously worthy questions.  No answers, just some thoughts.


1.   I think I feel the same way you do.  Burden, sincerity, and centrality 
all were used to restrict the scope of the compelling-interest test.  The Court 
has junked centrality, and has limited inquiries on sincerity.  All that is 
left is burden, and if we interpret it broadly, then there's a risk of a 
taffy pull-every claim receives some constitutional protection, which dilutes 
the compelling-interest test, ultimately meaning that strong claims get 
treated much worse.  I don't have an answer to this; I wish I did.  But I 
wonder if this fear is a bit overblown.  We got rid of the centrality inquiry 
20 years ago, and rigorous inquiries into sincerity 30 years ago, and 
RFRA/state RFRAs seems to work fine without them.  My sense is that-apart from 
prisons-the weakest claims aren't brought, or don't find lawyers, or get 
dismissed on doctrinally-unjustifiable-but-realistically-understandable 
grounds.  But I do worry about the taffy pull.   What has alarmed me most about 
the HHS litigation is the private employers.  I am sympathetic to the claims of 
the Catholic Church (in all of its iterations); I am less sympathetic to the 
private owner of a for-profit business wanting not to provide contraception 
coverage.  Maybe I shouldn't feel this way, but I do.  And I bet judges do too.


2.   (I agree about the difficulties of Gillette.)  One thing: The 
claimant's say-so of a religious burden.  A plaintiff's subjective views of a 
burden are irrelevant-that's Lyng and Bowen.  But plaintiffs' subjective views 
of their own religion are controlling-that's Thomas, and Lee, and others.  
There's a difference there, and the gap creates a real check.  Yes, plaintiffs 
can create a burden by willing to plead whatever religious beliefs necessary 
to get them there, but I'm not convinced they would do that.  And I think 
sincerity is a legitimate attack there.



3.   I think this issue comes ultimately before the Court, but as a 
sincerity issue not as a burden issue.  And to be clear, I don't think it 
should be off the table.  At various times, quite maddeningly, the Catholic 
Church has confused the issue of (1) whether they should be required to provide 
contraception to their employees, with (2) whether contraception should be 
provided at 

Re: HHS Rule: What is at Stake?

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Sorry if I was unclear, Chris.  I agree wholeheartedly that organizations
that that don’t hire exclusively in the faith can have an important
religious mission.  And that mission might even include asking its
employees -- of all faiths and no faith -- to act in certain ways while
performing their jobs.  But those organizations, unlike those who take
advantage of the title VII exemption, do not typically assume that they can
regulate what their employees do *outside* the workplace -- in particular,
they cannot insist that their employees, particularly those of other
faiths, comply with the employer's religious tenets.  And so if the
burden here is that it will be harder for the employer to establish an
organization full of employees who abide by Catholic tenets w/r/t
contraceptive use -- to establish the sort of constitutive community of
which Deneen writes (if I'm understanding him correctly), then the HHS Rule
is the least of it:  Title VII and other laws already prevent the employer
from insisting upon such religious uniformity among its employees.  By
contrast, if the employer is one that is legally entitled to insist upon
such employee religious conformity outside the workplace, and exercises
that right, then the HHS Rule will almost certainly not apply to that
employer.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 3:22 PM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 Marty,

 ** **

 If the Catholic Church’s view is really the same as Patrick Deenen’s—if
 the Catholic Church’s real objection is that HHS moves us to a
 Leviathan-like state and they have religious objections to that—then I
 agree its First Amendment claim fails.  Then this really does become a case
 like *Lyng* or *Bowen*.  The Catholic Church can object if they are
 coerced by the government in doing things against their religious will, but
 they have no First Amendment claim to control the government’s behavior. *
 ***

 ** **

 A problem is going to be that there are a lot of people in the Catholic
 Church.  Some will have a religious objection specifically to the
 government-imposed role for the Catholic Church, some will just have a
 religious objection to the whole act (maybe like Patrick Deenen), and some
 will have no religious objection at all.  I guess everything depends on who
 the plaintiff is.  And in the case of an organizational plaintiff, it
 depends on the people vested with authority for the organization.  

 ** **

 You seem to equate (1) religious organizations where “the employees know
 going in that they are committing to be part of a religious community, and
 that they might have to adjust their behaviors to reflect religious norms”
 and (2) religious organizations “that qualif[y] for and exercis[e] the
 title VII exemption allowing preferences for co-religionists.”  I think I
 agree that (1) makes sense in deciding on the breadth of any religious
 exception.  My question is why (1) and (2) are the same.  Why can’t there
 be organizations that have an important religious mission, but don’t hire
 exclusively in the faith?  I think a lot of religious social-justice
 organizations work that way.  And church schools.  This was a big deal in
 *Hosanna-Tabor*.  The fact that the church school hired non-Lutherans was
 evidence to the Sixth Circuit that the church school wasn’t serious about
 its religious mission.  That seems to me (and it seemed to the Court) to be
 a mistake.

 ** **

 Best, Chris

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 2:28 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* HHS Rule: What is at Stake?

 ** **

 Thanks, Chris.  As to your discussion regarding what might be truly
 bothering at least some critics of the HHS within the Church, over at
 Mirror of Justice Rick G. links to this new post by one of our esteemed
 Conference participants, Patrick Deenen, whose views on this certainly
 differ considerably from mine (and from many of his co-panelists'):


 http://www.firstthings.com/onthesquare/2012/10/president-obamarsquos-campaign-for-leviathan.


 To Patrick's credit, at our conference he acknowledged during his panel's
 discussion (hope I'm characterizing this fairly--I need to review the video
 myself!) that the issue from the Church's perspective is not so much (or at
 least not principally) impermissible forced cooperation with evil, but
 something much more fundamental about the role of the state.  His new essay
 gives a flavor of what he sees as one of the real concerns for at least
 certain of the objectors to the HHS Rule.

 Patrick writes that with the observation during the Democratic National
 Convention that 'government is the only thing we all belong to', and the
 actual underlying theme [of the Convention] that the State is needed to
 ensure our individuated liberty, the Obama administration thus implicitly
 and effectively endorsed the Hobbesian 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
Well, Marty's response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn't
take away the claim.

 

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
would take away the church's choice - but the church would not feel at all
exonerated.

 

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not.
And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations
of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims
are never filed because people with religious objections go along when their
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the
government.

 

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in
that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause
abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other position. With
respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to
believe they take the rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so
stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and to some conservative
Catholics, and they are saying that following orders cannot justify them in
paying for a policy that will provide these drugs. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the church
will have chosen to save the $200,000 by having the kids dumped.  That would
be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal cooperation with evil.

But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite -- because
the employer can still make the payment to the government instead of
offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for purposes of Catholic
(and most other) moral reasoning, because now we're asking the question not
of whether your volitional choice was impermissible (as in your hypo), but
instead whether your proximity to the evil, in and of itself, is so great
that your cooperation is immoral even though you were well-intentioned.

You're right, of course, that the fact that coverage is legally mandated
can't categorically eliminate the prospect of a substantial burden, because
in that case there'd never be a valid RFRA claim.  So, for example, a
religion might teach that certain action is immoral, even if done under
duress -- indeed, even if done under threat of criminal sanction.  In such a
case, a state law requiring the conduct surely imposes a substantial burden
on religious exercise, at least if the person in question otherwise is
committed to abiding by that norm.  

But in most cases, including this one, the fact of legal compulsion does
radically alter the moral calculus, because it eliminates the principal
thing that made the conduct in your hypo wrongful, namely, the choice to
sacrifice the kids for $200,000 savings.

Suppose, for example, that in City A, taxi drivers have complete discretion
which fares to accept, and a taxi driver who believes that prostitution is
immoral chooses to prefer fares going to so-called houses of ill-repute,
because they much more remunerative (because of distance, clientele,
whatever).  That choice would be a violation of the norm against formal
cooperation with evil.

City B, however, has decided to treat cab drivers as common carriers -- they
must accept all fares, no matter the destination.  Our same cab driver,
thinking that prostitution is unlawful, but now working in City B, abides by
the law, picks up all fares without discrimination . . . and occasionally
finds himself being asked to drop the passenger at a so-called house of
ill-repute, a request that (like all others) he honors.  In this case, he
has performed exactly the same act as he did in City A, but this time, he
has not violated religious tenets.

Seems to be that in most material respects, the HHS Rule is more like my
taxi driver in City B -- or the taxpayer in any jurisdiction -- than like
your hypo of a Church that would gladly leave kids on the street in order to
save a few bucks.




On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 3:04 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

It cannot be the answer that the coverage is mandated. Whether the coverage
can be 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Doug:  Is it actually the case that the bishops say these rules are too
important to them for a following orders defense to provide moral
justification?  That is to say, have the bishops, or any other Catholic
authority, actually articulated the view that a Catholic employer will
engage in forbidden proximate material cooperation with evil if it complies
with the HHS Rule?  And if so, have they provided any explanation of why
that is the case here and not, e.g., in the cases of paying taxes and
salaries, or in the case of my hypothetical common carrier taxi driver
who takes a woman to a clinic for an abortion?

I'm not saying there have been no such statements -- I simply haven't heard
them, and would be very grateful to be pointed to any such statement.

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:46 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 Well, Marty’s response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn’t
 take away the claim.

 ** **

 Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
 notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
 orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
 would take away the church’s choice – but the church would not feel at all
 exonerated.

 ** **

 Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do
 not. And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify
 violations of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of
 RFRA claims are never filed because people with religious objections go
 along when their objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult
 fight with the government.

 ** **

 The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following
 orders defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing
 implausible in that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe
 sometimes cause abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other
 position. With respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are
 finding it hard to believe they take the rule so seriously, because we
 think the rule is so stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and
 to some conservative Catholics, and they are saying that following orders
 cannot justify them in paying for a policy that will provide these drugs.
 

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Cc:* M Cathleen Kaveny
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the
 church will have *chosen* to save the $200,000 by having the kids
 dumped.  That would be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal
 cooperation with evil.

 But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite --
 because the employer can still make the payment to the government instead
 of offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
 it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
 unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for purposes of Catholic
 (and most other) moral reasoning, because now we're asking the question *
 not* of whether your *volitional choice* was impermissible (as in your
 hypo), but instead whether your proximity to the evil, in and of itself, is
 so great that your cooperation is immoral *even though you were
 well-intentioned*.

 You're right, of course, that the fact that coverage is legally mandated
 can't categorically eliminate the prospect of a substantial burden, because
 in that case there'd never be a valid RFRA claim.  So, for example, a
 religion might teach that *certain *action is immoral, even if done under
 duress -- indeed, even if done under threat of criminal sanction.  In such
 a case, a state law requiring the conduct surely imposes a substantial
 burden on religious exercise, at least if the person in question otherwise
 is committed to abiding by that norm.

 But in most cases, including this one, the fact of legal compulsion does
 radically alter the moral calculus, because it eliminates the principal
 thing that made the conduct in your hypo wrongful, namely, the *choice*to 
 sacrifice the kids for $200,000 savings.

 Suppose, for example, that in City A, taxi drivers have complete
 discretion which fares to accept, and a taxi driver who believes that
 prostitution is immoral chooses to prefer fares going to so-called houses
 of ill-repute, because they much more remunerative (because of distance,
 clientele, whatever).  That choice would be a violation of the 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
I did not mean to say that the bishops are saying that no Catholic employer
can comply. I don't know what they are saying about that. Quite possibly
nothing. But they are saying loud and clear that the Catholic institutions
for which they are responsible cannot comply, and they are saying that in
the face of government coercion. They are obviously saying that government
coercion does not justify them in complying.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 4:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Doug:  Is it actually the case that the bishops say these rules are too
important to them for a following orders defense to provide moral
justification?  That is to say, have the bishops, or any other Catholic
authority, actually articulated the view that a Catholic employer will
engage in forbidden proximate material cooperation with evil if it complies
with the HHS Rule?  And if so, have they provided any explanation of why
that is the case here and not, e.g., in the cases of paying taxes and
salaries, or in the case of my hypothetical common carrier taxi driver who
takes a woman to a clinic for an abortion?

I'm not saying there have been no such statements -- I simply haven't heard
them, and would be very grateful to be pointed to any such statement. 

On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:46 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

Well, Marty's response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn't
take away the claim.

 

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
would take away the church's choice - but the church would not feel at all
exonerated.

 

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not.
And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations
of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims
are never filed because people with religious objections go along when their
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the
government.

 

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in
that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause
abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other position. With
respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to
believe they take the rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so
stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and to some conservative
Catholics, and they are saying that following orders cannot justify them in
paying for a policy that will provide these drugs. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM


To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the church
will have chosen to save the $200,000 by having the kids dumped.  That would
be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal cooperation with evil.

But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite -- because
the employer can still make the payment to the government instead of
offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for purposes of Catholic
(and most other) moral reasoning, because now we're asking the question not
of whether your volitional choice was impermissible (as in your hypo), but
instead whether your proximity to the evil, in and of itself, is so great
that your cooperation is immoral even though you were well-intentioned.

You're right, of course, that the fact that coverage is legally mandated
can't categorically eliminate the prospect of a substantial burden, because
in that case there'd never be a valid RFRA claim.  So, for example, a
religion might teach that certain action is immoral, even if done under
duress -- indeed, even if done under threat of criminal sanction.  In such a
case, a state law requiring the 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Loud -- I agree.  Clear?  Not so much.  Have they said that such
institutions cannot comply?  Indeed, I'm not even sure they've instructed
such institutions that they must make the alternative payment to the
government if they are not exempted.  Again, I genuinely don't know --
perhaps the Bishops have said just that, in which case it would be very
useful to be referred to whatever they've said.



On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:59 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 I did not mean to say that the bishops are saying that no Catholic
 employer can comply. I don’t know what they are saying about that. Quite
 possibly nothing. But they are saying loud and clear that the Catholic
 institutions for which they are responsible cannot comply, and they are
 saying that in the face of government coercion. They are obviously saying
 that government coercion does not justify them in complying.

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 4:57 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Cc:* M Cathleen Kaveny
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Doug:  Is it actually the case that the bishops say these rules are too
 important to them for a following orders defense to provide moral
 justification?  That is to say, have the bishops, or any other Catholic
 authority, actually articulated the view that a Catholic employer will
 engage in forbidden proximate material cooperation with evil if it complies
 with the HHS Rule?  And if so, have they provided any explanation of why
 that is the case here and not, e.g., in the cases of paying taxes and
 salaries, or in the case of my hypothetical common carrier taxi driver
 who takes a woman to a clinic for an abortion?

 I'm not saying there have been no such statements -- I simply haven't
 heard them, and would be very grateful to be pointed to any such statement.
 

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 4:46 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote:

 Well, Marty’s response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn’t
 take away the claim.

  

 Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty
 notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the
 orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it
 would take away the church’s choice – but the church would not feel at all
 exonerated.

  

 Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do
 not. And I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify
 violations of minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of
 RFRA claims are never filed because people with religious objections go
 along when their objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult
 fight with the government.

  

 The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following
 orders defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing
 implausible in that claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe
 sometimes cause abortions, I would be astonished if they took any other
 position. With respect to ordinary contraception, I think many of us are
 finding it hard to believe they take the rule so seriously, because we
 think the rule is so stupid. But it is very important to the bishops, and
 to some conservative Catholics, and they are saying that following orders
 cannot justify them in paying for a policy that will provide these drugs.
 

  

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

  

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM


 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 *Cc:* M Cathleen Kaveny
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

  

 If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the
 church will have *chosen* to save the $200,000 by having the kids
 dumped.  That would be a form of (presumptively prohibited) formal
 cooperation with evil.

 But here, the state has eliminated the choice.  (Well, not quite --
 because the employer can still make the payment to the government instead
 of offering the insurance plan.  But let's assume for sake of argument that
 it's a flat requirement, or that the level of payment make noncompliance
 unrealistic.)  And that makes a huge difference for 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Alan Brownstein
To follow up on Doug's point, in some cases whether a religious person is 
relieved of an obligation because of duress might depend on the kind and 
magnitude of the duress. Obligations may be excused if compliance places the 
individual's life at risk, for example. Under Marty's analysis, would this mean 
that the greater the punishment imposed by the state in requiring someone to 
violate their religious obligations, the less likely it will be that this 
requirement constitutes a substantial burden on religion? The greater the 
duress - the less choice the religious individual has to refuse to comply - 
therefore the weaker the claim to a substantial burden on religion.

Alan

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 1:46 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Cc: 'M Cathleen Kaveny'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, Marty's response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn't take 
away the claim.

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty 
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the 
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it would 
take away the church's choice - but the church would not feel at all exonerated.

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not. And 
I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations of 
minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims are 
never filed because people with religious objections go along when their 
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the 
government.

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders 
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in that 
claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause abortions, I 
would be astonished if they took any other position. With respect to ordinary 
contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to believe they take the 
rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so stupid. But it is very 
important to the bishops, and to some conservative Catholics, and they are 
saying that following orders cannot justify them in paying for a policy that 
will provide these drugs.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-03 Thread Sanford Levinson
I really don't understand Mark's argument here:  If one accepts a (strong 
version of) Romans 13:1 re the legitimacy of magistrates and therefore feels 
impelled to obey them (as Scalia has suggested he does), then why is it a 
burden at all, since by definition what the magistrate (appointed by God, 
even if one can't quite undersatnd why) is a legitimate authority.  We're not 
talking about authoritarian personalities with a psychological predisposition 
to follow authority, but, rather religions that have strong belief in obeying 
the authorities (presumably because of a theology that derives from Romans 
13:1.)  It's tricker if we're talking about a belief that one should obey 
rather than avoid civil strife.  But isn't avoiding civil strife generally 
desirable.  Of course, the argument is that there shouldn't be such strife 
because the rest of us should tolerate the disobedience.  But doesn't that 
depend on the specifics of what is being disobeyed?

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark [mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 4:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: 'M Cathleen Kaveny'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

A “following orders” defense disadvantages religions that have strong belief in 
obeying the authorities, or that balance the need to avoid civil strife against 
the need to follow religious precepts. I don’t think the successful coercion of 
religious people should cut against their right to free exercise. Coercion is 
not freedom. If you send your kids to a public school that has Bible readings 
and prayers, because you can’t afford private school, and because there are 
mandatory education laws, does the successful coercion eliminate the invasion 
of religious freedom? If your kids tell your kids to go ahead and recite the 
pledge because otherwise they will be punished, do you and they forfeit your 
First Amendment claim? (Of course, any other approach is circular; if you are 
willing to suffer the consequences, then you don’t have to suffer the 
consequences, because (or assuming) your religious freedom claim succeeds.)

Do people have to be willing to go to jail or to pay large fines in order to 
have religious freedom claims? We may test sincerity, but we don’t require 
heroism.

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
Malibu, CA 90263
(310)506-4667

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 1:46 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Cc: 'M Cathleen Kaveny'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Well, Marty’s response at least seems to agree that saving money doesn’t take 
away the claim.

Does following government orders take away the claim? If it did, as Marty 
notes, there could never be a RFRA claim. If the government funded the 
orphanage, and ordered the church to take the cheaper food contract, it would 
take away the church’s choice – but the church would not feel at all exonerated.

Some people feel exonerated by a following orders defense, and some do not. And 
I suspect many people feel that following orders can justify violations of 
minor rules, but cannot justify serious wrongdoing. Lots of RFRA claims are 
never filed because people with religious objections go along when their 
objections are not strong enough to motivate a difficult fight with the 
government.

The bishops say these rules are too important to them for a following orders 
defense to provide moral justification. And I find nothing implausible in that 
claim. With respect to the drugs that they believe sometimes cause abortions, I 
would be astonished if they took any other position. With respect to ordinary 
contraception, I think many of us are finding it hard to believe they take the 
rule so seriously, because we think the rule is so stupid. But it is very 
important to the bishops, and to some conservative Catholics, and they are 
saying that following orders cannot justify them in paying for a policy that 
will provide these drugs.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, October 03, 2012 3:26 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: M Cathleen Kaveny
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

If I understand the Catholic doctrine, Doug, in your hypothetical the church 
will have chosen to save the $200,000 by having the kids