Dear Jerry, List:

You ask two questions. First, what is Anselm's ontological argument.
Thankfully, that is easy to answer. It is short, and I append it to this
email at the end.

Your second question is why "you are imposing the question on us, which
includes me [Jerry Rhee]?

First. let me clarify for the record: I am not from Missouri, and only used
that phrase assuming everyone is familiar with it, in order to get to the
"show me" part. Further, I do not know whether everyone in Missouri has
heard of Anselm's ontological argument, though I assume not.

However, I would expect (silly me!) that anyone with a Ph.D. would have
heard of it, since it is pretty nearly the most famous argument about God's
existence in the history of philosophy, and would be expected to be brought
up in any introductory, or history of, philosophy course or in any
conversation or study anytime anyone questions whether God exists.

Further, since we are talking about Peirce's "Neglected Argument for the
Reality of God," Anselm's argument would naturally come to mind as soon as
anyone inquires into why Peirce thought his argument had been "neglected."
In other words, the very title of Peirce's paper points to other arguments
for God's existence in the context of which he is placing his. But it is
worth noting that Peirce did not claim that he had a *new* argument, but
suggests by his title that it may have arisen before and was merely
"neglected." So he was bringing a long neglected argument back into view.
At least I take that to be one possible interpretation of the suggestion in
his title.(On the other hand, I take Peirce's title to imply that he felt
his argument had been neglected because it was so simple!!!! that no one
thought to dignify it previously. Silly me.)

Since the original questions that commenced this chain include "How exactly
is "this theory of thinking" *logically *connected with "the hypothesis of
God's reality"? I assumed that that was to be one of the major questions
dealt with in the discussion, which Jon thought to begin by asking his four
questions.

Now, the ontological argument has evoked a stupendous literature in
philosophy and logic, because it seems to prove the existence of God by
a purely logical and non-empirical method. That is why it is called
ontological, i.e., the argument proceeds only from being (onto=being).
Philosophers agree that Anselm makes at least two different arguments in
chapters II and III, though some philosophers find three and even four
separate arguments. Many logicians have wrestled with it, and some
logicians see it as a "modal" argument.

The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy gives a very brief and readable
description of Anselm's ontological argument: Be sure  to read sections 1,
2a, 3, and 4.

http://www.iep.utm.edu/ont-arg/

I hope that you will agree, after reading the brief account in the link
above that Anselm is quite relevant to placing Peirce's "neglected"
argument into context. The connection is that both Anselm and Peirce seek
to prove God's existence purely from a thought process.

Now, if you want to read a different take on Anselm's understanding of what
is meant by "existence," I invite you to read my article entitled "Anselm
on Nothing," *in the International Philosophical Quarterly*, Volume 48,
Issue 3, September 2008, pages 305-320, which you may read on line here:

https://www.academia.edu/13891780/Anselm_on_Nothing

For this second link, it must be borne in mind that Anselm wrote two tracts
relating to God's existence (or being), and the first link deals with his
second work, the *Proslogion*, where his famous ontological argument is
found (appended below), while the second link (my article) deals mostly
with Anselm's arguments in his first work, the *Monologion.* (Understand,
too, that my views though increasingly cited are nevertheless minority.)

Understand too that Peirce's works were constantly on my mind throughout
writing "Anselm on Nothing," and that I planned to write a second article
on Peirce and Anselm, but was largely discouraged from doing so by the
realization that Peirceans would disagree with just about everything a
simple person like me would say about Peirce's thought---which is why I was
so excited when Jon posted his questions that began this chain.For example,
I thought the example I gave of simple firstness, secondness, and thirdness
was safe, but I received a private email from an observer of this list that
such is not the case:

Echoing others, the Firstness-Secondness-Thirdness ordering in your example
is too linear. It should be Firstness-Thirdness-Secondness. That is, some
shock meets your habitual conditioning which determines the reaction. How
else could we have different reactions?

So, I need a lot of enlightenment, which is why I appreciate this forum so
much.

In any event, appended below are Chapters II, III, and IV of the
*Proslogion, *which contains Anselm's famous ontological argument;


Ben
Chapter II

Therefore, O Lord, who grantest to faith understanding, grant unto me that,
so far as Thou knowest it to be expedient for me, I may understand that
Thou art, as we believe; and also that Thou art what we believe Thee to be.
And of a truth we believe that Thou art somewhat than which no greater can
be conceived. Is there then nothing real that can be thus described? for
the fool hath said in his heart, There is no God. Yet surely even that fool
himself when he hears me speak of somewhat than which nothing greater can
be conceived under stands what he hears, and what he understands is in his
understanding, even if he do not under stand that it really exists. It is
one thing for a thing to be in the understanding, and another to understand
that the thing really exists. For when a painter considers the work which
he is to make, he has it indeed in his understanding; but he doth not yet
understand that really to exist which as yet he has not made. But when he
has painted his picture, then he both has the picture in his understanding,
and also under stands it really to exist. Thus even the fool is certain
that something exists, at least in his understanding, than which nothing
greater can be conceived; because, when he hears this mentioned, he
understands it, and whatsoever is understood, exists in the understanding.
And surely that than which no greater can be conceived cannot exist only in
the understanding. For if it exist indeed in the understanding only, it can
be thought to exist also in reality; and real existence is more than
existence in the under standing only. If then that than which no greater
can be conceived exists in the understanding only, then that than which no
greater can be conceived is something a greater than which can be
conceived: but this is impossible. There fore it is certain that something
than which no greater can be conceived exists both in the under standing
and also in reality.
Chapter II

Not only does this something than which no greater can be conceived exist,
but it exists in so true a sense that it cannot even be conceived not to
exist. For it is possible to form the conception of an object whose
non-existence shall be inconceivable; and such an object is of necessity
greater than any object whose existence is conceivable: wherefore if that
than which no greater can be conceived can be conceived not to exist; it
follows that that than which no greater can be conceived is not that than
which no greater can be conceived [for there can be thought a greater than
it, namely, an object whose non-existence shall be inconceivable]; and this
brings us to a contradiction. And thus it is proved that that thing than
which no greater can be conceived exists in so true a sense, that it cannot
even be conceived not to exist: and this thing art Thou, O Lord our God!
And so Thou, O Lord my God, existest in so true a sense that Thou canst not
even be conceived not to exist. And this is as is fitting. For if any mind
could conceive aught better than Thee, then the creature would be ascending
above the Creator, and judging the Creator; which is a supposition very
absurd. Thou therefore dost exist in a truer sense than all else beside
Thee, and art more real than all else beside Thee; because whatsoever else
existeth, existeth in a less true sense than Thou, and therefore is less
real than Thou. Why then said the fool in his heart, There is no God, when
it is so plain to a rational mind that Thou art more real than any thing
else? Why, except that he is a fool indeed?
Chapter IV

But how came the fool to say in his heart that which he could not conceive?
or how came he to be able not to conceive that which yet he said in his
heart? For it may be thought that to conceive and to say in one’s heart are
one and the same thing. If it is true—nay, because it is true, that he
conceived it, because he said it in his heart; and also true that he did
not say it in his heart because he could not conceive it; it follows that
there are two senses in which something may be understood to be conceived
or said in the heart. For in one sense we are said to have a conception of
something, when we have a conception of the word that signifies it; and in
another sense, when we understand what the thing really is. In the former
sense then we may say that God is conceived not to exist: but in the
latter, He cannot by any means be conceived not to exist. For no man that
understandeth what fire and water mean, can conceive that fire is really
water; though he may have this conception, as far as the words go. Thus in
like manner no man that understandeth what God is can conceive that God
does not exist; although he may say these words [that God does not exist]
either with no meaning at all, or with some other meaning than that which
they properly bear. For God is that than which no greater can be conceived.
He who well under standeth what this is, certainly understandeth it to be
such as cannot even be conceived not to exist. Whosoever therefore
understandeth in this way that God exists, cannot conceive that he does not
exist. Thanks be to Thee, O good Lord, thanks be to Thee! because that
which heretofore I believed by Thy grace, I now by Thine illumination thus
understand, so that, even though I should not wish to believe in Thine
existence, I cannot but understand that Thou dost exist.







*Ben Novak <http://bennovak.net>*
5129 Taylor Drive, Ave Maria, FL 34142
Telephone: (814) 808-5702

*"All art is mortal, **not merely the individual artifacts, but the arts
themselves.* *One day the last portrait of Rembrandt* *and the last bar of
Mozart will have ceased to be—**though possibly a colored canvas and a
sheet of notes may remain—**because the last eye and the last ear
accessible to their message **will have gone." *Oswald Spengler

On Tue, Sep 13, 2016 at 5:11 PM, Jerry Rhee <jerryr...@gmail.com> wrote:

> Ben,
>
> What is Anselm's ontological argument, for it is my opinion that someone
> from Missouri is expected to know it.
>
> If I, being from Missouri, is not expected to know about Anselm's
> ontological argument, then why are you imposing the question on us, which
> includes me?
>
> Best,
> Jerry R
>
> On Tue, Sep 13, 2016 at 3:05 PM, Ben Novak <trevriz...@gmail.com> wrote:
>
>> Dear Jon Alan Schmidt:
>>
>> I would like to go back to the point that this chain of emails began. Jon
>> Alan Schmidt asked about something he found Peirce had said in the *Neglected
>> Argument*, which had been omitted in the version published in the *Essential
>> Peirce*:
>>
>>
>> CSP:  Among the many pertinent considerations which have been crowded out
>> of this article, I may just mention that it could have been shown that the
>> hypothesis of God's Reality is logically not so isolated a conclusion as it
>> may seem.  On the contrary, it is connected so with a theory of the nature
>> of thinking that if this be proved so is that.  Now there is no such
>> difficulty in tracing experiential consequences of this theory of thinking
>> as there are in attempting directly to trace out other consequences of
>> God's reality.
>>
>>
>> Jon said that raised "a few interesting questions," namely:
>>
>>    1. To what specifically was Peirce referring here as "a theory of the
>>    nature of thinking"--the three stages of a "complete inquiry" and their
>>    "logical validity," as laid out in sections III and IV of the paper, or
>>    something else?
>>    2. How exactly is "this theory of thinking" *logically *connected
>>    with "the hypothesis of God's reality"?
>>    3. What would be some "experiential consequences of this theory of
>>    thinking" that we could, with comparatively little difficulty, deductively
>>    trace and inductively test?
>>    4. What exactly would it mean to "prove" Peirce's "theory of the
>>    nature of thinking," such that "the hypothesis of God's reality" would
>>    thereby also be "proved"?
>>
>> I have some tentative thoughts about these matters, including a couple of
>> ideas that I found in the secondary literature, but would appreciate seeing
>> what others have to say initially.
>>
>> So, let me respond.
>>
>> I thought I understood firstness, secondness, and thirdness when  our
>> discussion began. This is the example I had in mind.  I am a student
>> sitting in a class listening to an interesting lecture, when suddenly an
>> explosion occurs. It could be a firecracker under behind the professor's
>> desk, or a truck wreck on the street right outside the classroom windows.
>> The sound of true explosion, whatever it is, is  sudden, unexpected, and
>> immediate.  The sound or other shock waves hitting my body constitute
>> firstness--I feel them. Secondness is what my body does in reaction, which
>> is to  immediately and involuntarily, raise my head, flinch, and commence
>> other bodily reactions to the explosion waves reaching me. Thirdness occurs
>> next, when my mind begins to wonder what just happened. All this  can
>> happen in far less than the blink of an eye.  Peirce's analysis of it by
>> breaking it down in this way was thought to be a fertile way of beginning
>> to understand thinking, or to begin a theory of thinking.
>>
>> Please correct me again, Jon, if that is not an elementary example of
>> firstness, etc.
>>
>> However, I soon got lost in the subsequent discussion of these, where
>> thirdness became intertwined with secondness and firstness, and so on, in
>> the subsequent emails.  I do  not doubt that all of you are correct that
>> Peirce did take this rudimentary example to far heights of thinking which I
>> may just be constitutionally unable to rise to. But my reading of Peirce
>> suggests that he was a very pragmatic person who appreciated someone from
>> Missouri showing up and saying "show me." In any event, so much of the
>> subsequent discussion involved concepts going back and forth with no
>> examples that allowed them to be brought to earth for examination. At
>> least, that is what it seemed to me.
>>
>> So, is it possible to get back to the original question. Remember that
>> Peirce thought that all this became clear to him his daily walks through
>> the woods, and he wrote this essay suggesting that its thinking would be
>> available to anyone of ordinary intelligence who pondered the three
>> universes suggested on their own daily walks through the woods.
>>
>> So, let's go back to Jon's 2nd, 3rd, and 4th questions, because I think
>> he  is on to something:
>>
>>    1. How exactly is "this theory of thinking" *logically *connected
>>    with "the hypothesis of God's reality"?
>>    2. What would be some "experiential consequences of this theory of
>>    thinking" that we could, with comparatively little difficulty, deductively
>>    trace and inductively test?
>>    3. What exactly would it mean to "prove" Peirce's "theory of the
>>    nature of thinking," such that "the hypothesis of God's reality" would
>>    thereby also be "proved"?
>>
>> In response, some raised the ontological argument of St. Anselm. But the
>> raising of it was not followed through. Here is my question (which I hope
>> "nests" all three of Jon's questions):
>>
>> What would Anselm's ontological argument look like if it were restated in
>> Peirce's terms? In other words, could Anselm have discovered the same
>> argument as Peirce? Would this give us any insight into the theory of
>> thinking? Peirce says that we could, with comparatively little difficulty,
>> deductively and inductively test such a theory of thinking. Someone from
>> Missouri might say, "Show me."
>>
>> Ben Novak
>>
>>
>>
>>
>> *Ben Novak <http://bennovak.net>*
>> 5129 Taylor Drive, Ave Maria, FL 34142
>> Telephone: (814) 808-5702
>>
>> *"All art is mortal, **not merely the individual artifacts, but the arts
>> themselves.* *One day the last portrait of Rembrandt* *and the last bar
>> of Mozart will have ceased to be—**though possibly a colored canvas and
>> a sheet of notes may remain—**because the last eye and the last ear
>> accessible to their message **will have gone." *Oswald Spengler
>>
>> On Tue, Sep 13, 2016 at 12:34 PM, Clark Goble <cl...@lextek.com> wrote:
>>
>>>
>>> On 9/13/2016 3:29 AM, John Collier wrote:
>>>
>>> I used Peirce’s ideas fairly prominently in my philosophy of science
>>> courses in the 1980s and 90s. I also used his work to cast light on Kuhnian
>>> issues both in my classes and in my doctoral dissertation. Although the
>>> last was accepted enthusiastically, I continually got grumblings about how
>>>  was not teaching the Standard View properly.
>>>
>>> Maybe things have improved, with more naturalistic approaches becoming
>>> more prevalent, but the culture wars really made a mess of trying to bring
>>> in Peircean ideas because the view that science was a mere social construct
>>> seemed to be supported by naïve interpretations of Peirce. So I found
>>> myself apparently fighting myself at some times.
>>>
>>>
>>> Yes, the culture wars (which are still with us) are rather annoying. Not
>>> just because of how they try to make science into something we can control
>>> and thereby reject but because of how often they just read philosophers so
>>> badly. Lots of figures who make more careful subtle distinctions about
>>> science’s social aspects are appropriated for tasks they’d be aghast at.
>>> (Kuhn is the classic example although it’s not hard to find others)
>>>
>>>
>>> -----------------------------
>>> PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON
>>> PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to
>>> peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to
>>> PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the line "UNSubscribe
>>> PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at
>>> http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .
>>>
>>>
>>>
>>>
>>>
>>>
>>
>>
>> -----------------------------
>> PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON
>> PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to
>> peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L
>> but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the
>> BODY of the message. More at http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce
>> -l/peirce-l.htm .
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to