Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-19 Thread Bruno Marchal
Title: Re: modal logic and possible
worlds


George Levy wrote:



I have been following the latest
very scholarly exchange involving different logical models in relation
to the MWI, however I fail to see how it relates to my own perception
of the world and my own consciousness unless I think according to
those formal systems which I think is unlikely.

Using different logical models to
describe possible worlds is interesting but isn't it true that if the
problem of consciousness (as an observer, and definer, for
these worlds) is to be addressed, then the only logic that
matters is the one in my, or in your, own head? Of all these logical
models which one is the right one? Are all of them
right?



One thing is sure. Those modal logics are right for the
consistent machines.
This is essentially what Godel (followed by Lob, ...)
proves.
The rest is a matter of definition.
Can we find those logic by pure introspection? The S4 first
person: yes (it
happens all the time from Heraclite to toposes
...
The G and G* logics? Not at all, they formalize by construction
the most
counter-intuitive feature of the computationalist
hypothesis.



When Copernicus formulated the
heliocentric system, he didn't go around saying that a new
logic had to be used to explain the central position of the sun. He
simply used a physical model. People just had to accept the new
paradigm that the Earth moves even though they do not feel
the Earth move. Can't we just accept the fact that the world - and our
consciousness - split or merge even though we
do not feel them split and merge? It
seems to me that if we define a good physical model, then classical
probability could do the job of formulating the decision theory
desired by Wei.


I think all the problem relies in the question what is a
physical model?
Even what is a physical reality? Does that
exists in some absolute sense?
With the comp hyp, that's doubtful, as I am used to argue.
I think this is coherent with your relativism, as we concluded
before,
independently of comp!

Bruno



Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-19 Thread Bruno Marchal

Wei Dai wrote:
Thank you for the explanation on S4, IL, and CL. I'm interested in
more details, but rather than bombarding you with endless questions, can
you suggest a book on this topic? Something that talks about
what you just did, but in more detail?



BM:
Try perhaps the book by Van Dalen at Springer Verlag. It is good for
CL and IL.
For modal logic there is the excellent book by Chellas.
CHELLAS Brian F., Modal Logic an introduction, Cambridge University
Press 1980. But Boolos 1979 or 1993 introduces well both modal
logic and provability theory (the G, G* logics).



WD:
Unfortunately I'm still not able to understand much of your second post
yesterday. I continue to hope you will put all of your ideas into English
in an organized form, whether as a paper or a book. Why don't you
translate your Ph.D. thesis into English, expand it into a book, and
publish it? (Like Nick Bostrom did with his thesis, except it was already
in English.)


BM:
My PhD Thesis presupposes ALL the logical and computer-science stuff
and presupposes the physicist motivations. So a translation of
my thesis would not help more than my english paper (CCQ) and probably
less than our conversation on the net.
Perhaps I should translate my brussels thesis/technical report. It is
more self-contained (yet not completely) but then it makes 800 pages, and
my experience is that people reading it loose the track or the line of the
reasoning.
I am hoping making some technical progress to be able to write some
intermediate presentation.
In any case, thank you very much for what I take as encouragement.

Bruno




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-17 Thread jamikes



Dear George, 
I was missing your input lately, I like this 
one a lot. 
2 remarks:
1./ Logic in 'your', 'my', or anyody else's 
mind may be different. Does it allow to
restrict it from being "any"? Any may be right 
in their own rite. We may not like 'some'.
2./ The world just HAD to accept Copernicus 
and his conclusions
But was Copernicus right? (Partially: yes, of 
course).
(A step forward does not make it a complete 
novelty. Important and salutable, but
also debatable - especially when even newer 
ideas coincide).
Thanks for the words of reason.
John MIkes

  - Original Message - 
  From: 
  George Levy 
  
  To: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  Sent: Friday, August 16, 2002 7:39 
  PM
  Subject: Re: modal logic and possible 
  worlds
  I have been following the latest very scholarly exchange 
  involving different logical models in relation to the MWI, however I fail to 
  see how it relates to my own perception of the world and my own consciousness 
  unless I think according to those formal systems which I think is 
  unlikely.Using different logical models to describe possible worlds is 
  interesting but isn't it true that if the problem of consciousness (as an 
  observer, and definer, for these worlds) is to be addressed, 
  then the only logic that matters is the one in my, or in your, own head? 
  Of all these logical models which one is the "right" one? Are all of them 
  "right?"When Copernicus formulated the heliocentric system, he didn't 
  go around saying that a "new" logic had to be used to explain the central 
  position of the sun. He simply used a physical model. People just had to 
  accept the new paradigm that the Earth "moves" even though they do not feel 
  the Earth move. Can't we just accept the fact that the world - and our 
  consciousness - "split" or "merge" even though we do not feel them "split" and 
  "merge?" It seems to me that if we define a good physical model, then 
  classical probability could do the job of formulating the decision theory 
  desired by Wei.George


Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-17 Thread Wei Dai

Thank you for the explanation on S4, IL, and CL. I'm interested in 
more details, but rather than bombarding you with endless questions, can 
you suggest a book on this topic? Something that talks about 
what you just did, but in more detail?

Unfortunately I'm still not able to understand much of your second post
yesterday. I continue to hope you will put all of your ideas into English
in an organized form, whether as a paper or a book. Why don't you
translate your Ph.D. thesis into English, expand it into a book, and
publish it? (Like Nick Bostrom did with his thesis, except it was already
in English.)




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-17 Thread George Levy



jamikes wrote:
007f01c24609$8a1cfa00$5e76d03f@default">
  
  
   
  I was missing your input lately
  
Yes, I am very busy preparing for a patent bar. But I still read the list.
I don't have too much time to dig deep into the references so I can't comment
intelligently when the going gets too technical. 
  007f01c24609$8a1cfa00$5e76d03f@default">
 
2 remarks:
1./ Logic in 'your', 'my', or anyody
else's  mind may be different. Does it allow to
restrict it from being "any"? Any may
be right  in their own rite. We may not like 'some'.

The arbitrariness of "my," "your" or anybody's own mind point to the need
for the relativistic approach which I have been advocating. The frame of
reference here is the logical system residing in the observer's mind. It
may not be the type of formal system which has been discussed in the list.
There may be a need to develop some kind of "fuzzy" logical system for human
mental processes corresponding to the formal systems already in existence.
As far as I know Fuzzy Logic has not been developped to the same extent as
the branches of logic that have been discussed in the list.

In any case, a totally different approach involves using physical models,
just like Copernicus and Einstein did. An interesting conjecture is that
the "physical model" approach and the "logical model" approach will converge
or even will be proven to be equivalent. 
007f01c24609$8a1cfa00$5e76d03f@default">
  2./ The world just HAD to accept
Copernicus  and his conclusions
  But was Copernicus right? (Partially:
yes, of  course).
  (A step forward does not make it
a complete  novelty. Important and salutable, but
  also debatable - especially when
even newer  ideas coincide).
  
I agree with you here. I have been somewhat imprecise.
  
George
  007f01c24609$8a1cfa00$5e76d03f@default">

  
- Original Message - 
  
From:George
Levy
  
  
To:
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
  
  
Sent: Friday, August 16, 2002 7:39PM
  
Subject: Re: modal logic and possibleworlds
  
  
I have been following the latest very scholarly exchangeinvolving different
logical models in relation to the MWI, however I fail tosee how it relates
to my own perception of the world and my own consciousnessunless I think
according to those formal systems which I think isunlikely.
  
Using different logical models to describe possible worlds isinteresting
but isn't it true that if the problem of consciousness (as anobserver,
  and definer, for these worlds) is to be addressed,then
the only logic that matters is the one in my, or in your, own head?Of
all these logical models which one is the "right" one? Are all of them  
 "right?"
  
When Copernicus formulated the heliocentric system, he didn'tgo around
saying that a "new" logic had to be used to explain the centralposition
of the sun. He simply used a physical model. People just had toaccept
the new paradigm that the Earth "moves" even though they do not feelthe
Earth move. Can't we just accept the fact that the world - and ourconsciousness
- "split" or "merge" even though we do not feel them "split" and"merge?"
It seems to me that if we define a good physical model, thenclassical
probability could do the job of formulating the decision theorydesired
by Wei.
  
George
  
  
  
  
  
  


Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-17 Thread Tim May


On Saturday, August 17, 2002, at 08:06  PM, George Levy wrote:
 The arbitrariness of my, your or anybody's own mind point to the 
 need for the relativistic approach which I have been advocating. The 
 frame of reference here is the logical system residing in the 
 observer's mind. It may not be the type of  formal system which has 
 been discussed in the list. There may be a need to develop some kind of 
 fuzzy logical system for human mental processes corresponding to the 
 formal systems already in existence. As far as I know Fuzzy Logic has 
 not been developped to the same extent as the branches of  logic that 
 have been discussed in the list.

Well, count me as skeptical that the hype about fuzzy set theory and 
fuzzy logic has ever, or will ever, live up to some of the claims made 
by Bart Kosko, Lofti Zadeh, and others. Most of what passes for fuzzy 
logic just looks like ordinary Bayesian probability.

Here's a comment from Saunders Mac Lane in his book Mathematics: Form 
and Function, 1986:

Not all outside influences are really fruitful. For example, one 
engineer came up with the notion of a _fuzzy_ set--a set X where a 
statement x elementof X of membership may be neither true nor false but 
lies somewhere in between, say between 0 and 1. It was hoped that this 
ingenious notion would lead to all sorts of fruitful applications, to 
fuzzy automata, fuzzy decision theory and elsewhere. However, as yet 
most of the intended applications turn out to be just extensive 
exercises, not actually applicable; there has been a spate of such 
exercises. (. pp 439-40).

While maybe Mac Lane is a little too snippily dismissive, here we are 
more than 15 years later and what do we have? Fuzzy rice cookers which 
look like nothing more than rice cookers with various algorithms Newton 
could have calculated, fuzzy-logic elevators which are simply 
implementing similar acceleration algorithms, and not much else. 
Certainly fuzzy logic has not been significantly in the foundations of 
mathematics. Logicians have not been using fuzzy sets and fuzzy logic in 
any significant way, judging by the books and articles I've seen.

I agree that formal logic is not easily applied to minds. Logicians 
would agree. A mind is weighing large numbers of inputs, far beyond what 
would normally fill an entire page of First Order Logic 
equationssurvival has made the ability to reason with uncertainty (a 
better core concept that calling it fuzzy logic, in my opinion) a 
survival trait. Those minds which can find solutions in the midst of 
noise and uncertainty tend to reproduce more than those minds which are 
paralyzed or too slow in reaching survival-enhancing conclusions.

What we have talked about here in this sub-thread on _modal logic and 
possible worlds_ is an idealization of logic, just a snapshot or facet 
of things, in much the same way a line or a plane is a facet of the 
world around us (and understandable at some level by birds and reptiles 
even).

--Tim May
(.sig for Everything list background)
Corralitos, CA. Born in 1951. Retired from Intel in 1986.
Current main interest: category and topos theory, math, quantum reality, 
cosmology.
Background: physics, Intel, crypto, Cypherpunks




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-16 Thread Bruno Marchal

At 10:29 -0700 13/08/2002, Wei Dai wrote:

Does it mean anything that S4 and intuitionistic propositional 
calculus (= 0-order intutionistic logic, right?) ...


Right.



 have the same kind of models, or is
it just a coincidence? I guess Tim is saying that it does mean something,
but I don't understand what.




I almost missed this fair question. It is not a coincidence.
I choose S4 for not frightening Tim with irreflexive or non
transitive accessibility relation :-).


Kripke knew a 1933 result(*) by Godel according to which, (with IL
standing for Intuitionist logic):

   Theorem: S4 proves T(A) if and only if IL proves A

where T is a function from the propositional language to the modal
propositional logic given by

  T(A) = A if A is a propositional letter = A belongs to {p, q, r ...}
  T(-A) = []-T(A)
  T(A-B) = [](T(A) - T(B)

Kripke first discovered his semantics for general normal modal logic.
By Godel 1933 this provides him (and us!) the S4 possible world
semantics of IL.
Note that Beth developed a more awkward but similar semantics before.

The world of the S4 models (= of the IL) models are sometimes
interpreted as *state of knowledge*. This fit well with the fact
that the S4 logic in my thesis describes a pure first person knower.
(But I get S4Grz, its antisymmetrical extension, good for subjective
irreversible time).

The following remarks may help.


S4, which is a *classical* extension of CL
(Classical Logic), is capable of simulating IL. This is not an argument
that CL is better, for Godel (again) found that IL can simulate CL:
basically IL proves (- - A) when CL proves A. It's a key of IL that
IL does not prove (- - A) - A.   (but IL proves A - (- - A))

Like CL admits an algebraic semantics in term of Boolean Algebra, ...

parenthesis:
(where the propositions A, B, C ... are interpreted by subsets of
a set W, the and by intersection, the or by union, the - by the
complementary, the constant f by the empty set and the constant t by
the whole set W. You can even (in our modal context interpret the element
of W as worlds verifying the formula, for example a tautology being
true in all world you see a tautology, like the constant t, is 
interpreted by W). For example [A union -A] = W, i.e the exclude
middle principle is universally valid, in CL.
end of parenthesis

... IL admits a topological interpretation, where the propositions
are interpreted by open sets in a topological space. The and by
intersection, the or by union, the not by ... the interior of
the complementary. For exemple take as topological space the real
line. Interpret A by the open set (-infinity 0) then -A is (O infinity)
you see [A union -A] does not give the whole space, and this
shows the exclude middle is not universally valid, in IL.

Quantum Logic (QL) like IL, is a syntactically weaker logic than CL.
(And thus IL and QL are semantically richer). Algebraic semantics
for QL is given by the lattice of subspace of vector spaces (or Hilbert
spaces).

A good shape to remember is the following drawing (Arrows from bottom
to up = syntactically extend:


   S4 B
\/
 \  /
  CL
 / \
/   \
  IL QL

S4 gives a classical representation of IL, and B gives (thanks to
Goldblatt result) classical representation of QL.


(*) Godel was so famous that he did'nt need no more to prove his
affirmation/conjecture. It is a two pages paper without proof.
  The Godel's result will be proved by McKinsey and Tarski in 1948.


Bruno




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-16 Thread Bruno Marchal

At 10:11 -0700 14/08/2002, Wei Dai wrote:
Let me generalize my question then. Is it true that for any modal logic
that has a semantics, any sentence in that logic has a corresponding
sentence in non-modal quantificational logic with the same meaning?


It depends of the semantics. It depends of the order of quantification.
It depends what you want to do.


At 10:11 -0700 14/08/2002, Wei Dai wrote:
Before the invention of possible world semantics, people had to reason
about modalities on a purely syntactical basis. Are there still modal
logics for which no semantics is known?


There are the modal logics of your servitor :-)

Z, Z1, Z*, Z1* and X, X1, X*, X1*

Those are well-defined modal logics. It is easy to prove them even
decidable. I have partial soundness theorem for Z and Z1. No
completeness! None of those logics have not even been axiomatized.
(Open problems!).

Remember the high constraint due to the fact that I interview
sounds universal machines. The mother box corresponds to the
Goedelian beweisbar  predicate. If we interpret the propositional
letters p, q, r ... by arithmetical sentences, and []p is interpreted by
beweisbar(godel-number-of(p)) then a natural question, which curiously did
not appear in Godel 1933, is: which modal logic, if any, does the beweisbar
box obey?
Thanks to the work of Lob, Magari, Boolos, Solovay and others we know
such a logic exists and it is G. Here is a presentation of G:


AXIOMS:  [](p - q) - ([]p - []q)
  []([]p - p) - []p
  []p - [][]p (this one can been shown redundant)

RULES:p p-q   p
  ,---
 q []p

A class of Kripke frames (there exists others!) is set of finite,
irreflexive, transitive frames.

Actually G gives the part of that logic which remains provable by the
machine itself. Solovay showed much more: the following *non normal*
(indeed: NON necessetation rules) logic gives the whole propositional
logic, including what is true but such that the machine cannot prove:


AXIOMS:  All theorems of G
  []p - p

RULES:p p-q
  
 q

In particular G* minus G gives the set of all 0-order modal propositions
corresponding to true unprovable (by the sound machines), but bettable
self-referential sentences.

G* has no Kripke semantics, but it can be shown G* has some natural
semantics in term of sequences of Kripke models.

All the logics defined in my work are defined syntactically *from* G and G*,
so that it is non trivial at all to find semantics. Roughly speaking
the knower is defined by ([]p  p), the observer/bet-ter by []p  p,
the observer/better-embedded-in-UD*-with-comp-true is []p  p with p
interpretation restricted on \Sigma_1 sentences (if they are true there
are provable). The sensible observer = []p  p  p , with p \Sigma_1)




At 10:11 -0700 14/08/2002, Wei Dai wrote:
We know that in general syntactical formulas and rules are not powerful
enough to always let us reason without meaning, because the set of
mathematical truths that are derivable syntactically from a fixed set of
axioms is just a subset of all mathematical truths.


Yes but self-transforming theories or machine/brains can learn
to makes bets and change themselves. That never gives the whole truth,
a priori, but can help a machine to progress or just survive.


At 10:11 -0700 14/08/2002, Wei Dai wrote:
The rest can only be
obtained by considering the semantic consequences of the axioms. I think
the point of syntax is just to give us a way to obtain at least some of
the truths through syntactical manipulation - a way to grab the
low-hanging fruit.

Yes. And it is a point of the brain/body too.

Bruno








Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-16 Thread George Levy



I have been following the latest very scholarly exchange involving different
logical models in relation to the MWI, however I fail to see how it relates
to my own perception of the world and my own consciousness unless I think
according to those formal systems which I think is unlikely.

 Using different logical models to describe possible worlds is interesting 
but isn't it true that if the problem of consciousness (as an observer, 
and definer, for these worlds) is to be addressed, then the only logic
that matters is the one in my, or in your, own head? Of all these logical
models which one is the "right" one? Are all of them "right?"

When Copernicus formulated the heliocentric system, he didn't go around saying
that a "new" logic had to be used to explain the central position of the
sun. He simply used a physical model. People just had to accept the new paradigm
that the Earth "moves" even though they do not feel the Earth move. Can't
we just accept the fact that the world - and our consciousness - "split"
or "merge" even though we do not feel them "split" and "merge?" It seems
to me that if we define a good physical model, then classical probability
could do the job of formulating the decision theory desired by Wei.

George





Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-14 Thread Bruno Marchal


Wei Dai wrote:


Thanks for your answers. They are very helpful.


Y're welcome. I want just add something.


Your general question was Why using modal logic when
quantifying on worlds is enough. My basic answer was
that Kripke's possible world semantics works only on a
subset of the possible modal logics.
You can do modal logics without semantics. In fact modal
logic appeared because of apparent existence of modalities.
The main one is possible and necessary. But others
occurred like permitted and obligatory; provable and
consistent, believable and imaginable, etc.
The fundamental motivation of a logician is to give purely
syntactical formula and rules for manipulating formula so that
we can reason and communicating reasoning *without* any
meaning. The traditional joke is that a logician does not
want understand what he talk about!
When you do that you fall automatically on the following sort
of problem:

Take a formal theory like S4, again:
(I suppose a language with the usual logical symbol
including the propositional constant f and t, + the [])


AXIOMS:   axioms of classical propositional logic
   [](p - q) - ([]p - []q)
   []p - p
   []p - [][]p

RULES:p p-q   p
  ,---
 q []p


This gives at once an infinity of formula: those derivable
from the axioms by using finitely many times the rules.

I recall that -p is an abbreviation for (p-f), and p is
an abbreviation for -[]-p.

The question is: is the formula []p - []p derivable in S4?
Now that question is not so hard and you can solve it *syntactically*.
Just find a pathway from the axioms to the formula by using the
rules of inference. (That is: just prove []p - []p in S4).
But I can say this because I know the solution!
Now logician want not only prove theorems in their system, they
want also know if the system is consistent, that is, if the system
does not prove f, and question like that.
For example, and this is a *very* difficult exercise, try to prove
that S4 does *not* prove the formula p - []p.

Before the rise of semantics such question was almost not answerable
in general. You cannot solve them by searching all the proofs
because you have an infinity of proofs.

Something like Kripke semantics makes such an exercise very easy,
once you have soundness and completeness metatheorem relating your
logic (here S4) with the semantics.

Now it not very difficult to prove such completeness and soundness
theorem for system as simple as S4 (see also ref in the archive
below). I give you only the two main metatheorems we can use here.

I recall that a Kripke frame is just a set (of worlds) with some
binary relation among them (the accessibility relation).
A model is a frame with, for each world w, a function from L in {0,1}.
L = our set of propositional letters {p, q, r, ...}.
(That is: a model assigns truth to the proposition in each world).
I recall also that classical logic is verify in each world, that is:
if p is true in world w and q is true in world w, then p-q is
true in world w, etc. Now the S4/Kripke-semantics soundness
and completeness (SC) metatheorem is:

   SC theorem: S4 proves A if and only if A is true in any
   world of any model based on a reflexive and transitive frame.

Now, if p - []p was derivable in S4 it would follow from
the SC metatheorem that p - []p would be true in any world
of any model based on a reflexive and transitive frame.

So, to prove that p - []p is not a theorem of S4 it is
enough to find a model based on a reflexive and transitive frame
in which  p - []p is false in some world.

Let us build that counterexample. For having p - []p false
in a world w1, by classical logic, you need a world with p true
in it, and []p false in it, i.e. -[]p true in it.
But -[]p is equivalent with []-p, so it is enough to join
a unique world w2 with -p true in it.
Our counterexample is:
   The frame = {w1, w2}
   The accessibility relation R is given by w1Rw1, w2Rw2, w1Rw2
  (if you prefer: R = {(w1 w1) (w2 w2) (w1 w2)}
   The model is given by making p true in w1, and false in w2.
R being reflexive and transitive, and p - []p being false at
w1, p - []p has been shown not derivable in S4.


Another use of Kripke CS result is to show that S4, for example,
is decidable (and then write a theorem prover for S4). This is easy
if you succeed in refining the completeness part of the CS theorem
above with finite frame instead of any frame. In that case
you know that if a counterexample exist you can find it.

But Kripke semantics is useless with a non normal
logic, for example a modal logic without the necessitation rule.
Chellas excellent book has a chapter on Scott-Montague semantics
(also known as minimal model) which can be used in the same
way for weaker modal logic. The Scott-Montague semantics gives
topological or quasi-topological structure on the set of worlds.
In Kripke []p is true at world w if p is true at all worlds x such
that wRx. In Scott-Montague 

Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-14 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi Tim, just some quick comments.

On Tue, Aug 13, 2002 at 10:08:50AM -0700, Tim May wrote:
   * Because toposes are essentially mathematical universes in which
  various bits and pieces of mathematics can be assumed. A topos in which
  Euclid's Fifth Postulate is true, and many in which it is not. A topos
  where all functions are differentiable. A topos in which the Axiom of
  Choice is assumed--and ones where it is not assumed. In other words, as
  all of the major thinkers have realized over the past 30 years, topos
  theory is the natural theory of possible worlds.


Frankly I think you exaggerate :)
I could be very long on this even without mentioning my thesis.
But I want to be short, and in my thesis, toposes could only be used
for first person semantics (and even this is still an exaggeration).
Toposes are just (enlarged) S4 model, or (classical) model for
intuitionist logic.


At 11:15 -0700 13/08/2002, Tim May wrote:
Worlds _are_ propositions.

This can be misleading. In modal context we have a duality: we can
define world by set of propositions (the proposition true in the world),
and we can define dually proposition by set of worlds (the world in
which p is true).


At 15:51 -0700 13/08/2002, Tim May wrote:
(You might also want to take a look at the paper by Guts, a Russian, 
on a Topos-Theoretic Model of the Deutsch Multiverse. Available at 
the usual xxx.lanl.gov site.)


Thank you very much for this interesting reference (and the reference
therein, including a Russian website on Everett!).


At 15:51 -0700 13/08/2002, Tim May wrote:
As far as the math of nonstandard logic goes, I think the most 
interesting application within our lifetimes will come with AI.


I agree. Perhaps Wei Dai should look at the non monotonic logics and
to the logics of relevance. Especially if he want escape the problem
of omniscience.


At 21:29 -0700 13/08/2002, Tim May wrote:
Nor do I take Schmidhuber's all running programs notion very
seriously. Interesting ideas to play with, and to use some tools on. [...]
At 21:29 -0700 13/08/2002, Tim May wrote:
Lack of even the slightest piece of evidence for all possible 
mathematical universes actually exist and/or the all runnable 
computer programs.'

I also don't believe there are gods or other supernatural beings, 
for the same reason.

If and when I see an experiment that points to there being other 
universes which have tangible existence, then I'll start to believe.


Then I urge you to read my thesis (which results, btw, has been published
about ten years before Tegmark and Schmidhuber and which results goes far
away beyond, ... :)

Why. Because even *without experiment*, but with just a small amount
of platonism in arithmetic and computationalism in the cognitive science,
you will understand that the
many computations are unavoidable, and that the physical laws
necessarily emerges from simple elementary relation between integers ...
I am more skeptical than you, I don't believe in a *physical* universe.
Actually I show that with comp physics cannot be fundamental, but must
emerge from numbers and numbers as seen by numbers ... Physicalism
and materialism is *just incompatible* with mechanism.

Perhaps read just my Computation, Consciousness and the Quantum loadable
from my URL below. I will say more in a post which I am writing
to you and where I make a comment on Yetter's Functorial Knot theory.

Bruno
-- 
http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-14 Thread Wei Dai

On Wed, Aug 14, 2002 at 04:38:45PM +0200, Bruno Marchal wrote:
 Your general question was Why using modal logic when
 quantifying on worlds is enough. My basic answer was
 that Kripke's possible world semantics works only on a
 subset of the possible modal logics.

Let me generalize my question then. Is it true that for any modal logic
that has a semantics, any sentence in that logic has a corresponding
sentence in non-modal quantificational logic with the same meaning? In
other words, are there any modal sentences whose meaning cannot be
expressed by quantifying directly on the appropriate objects?

 You can do modal logics without semantics. In fact modal
 logic appeared because of apparent existence of modalities.
 The main one is possible and necessary. But others
 occurred like permitted and obligatory; provable and
 consistent, believable and imaginable, etc.
 The fundamental motivation of a logician is to give purely
 syntactical formula and rules for manipulating formula so that
 we can reason and communicating reasoning *without* any
 meaning. The traditional joke is that a logician does not
 want understand what he talk about!

Before the invention of possible world semantics, people had to reason
about modalities on a purely syntactical basis. Are there still modal
logics for which no semantics is known?

We know that in general syntactical formulas and rules are not powerful
enough to always let us reason without meaning, because the set of
mathematical truths that are derivable syntactically from a fixed set of
axioms is just a subset of all mathematical truths. The rest can only be
obtained by considering the semantic consequences of the axioms. I think
the point of syntax is just to give us a way to obtain at least some of
the truths through syntactical manipulation - a way to grab the
low-hanging fruit.




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Russell Standish

Bruno probably does, but I'll put my spin on it. Each distinguishable
world is a description*, which is a conjunction of propositions I
have green eyes _and_ I live in Sydney _and_ the twin towers were
destroyed by airliners on 11/9/2002 _and_ ..., and as such is a
proposition. I'm not completely convinced that one can simply apply
modal logic to the set of all descriptions in this way, but it does
have some plausibility.

Cheers

* This is the case in the Schmidhuber and Tegmark ensembles, but not
so obviously true of Deutsch's Multiverse.

Wei Dai wrote:
 
 
 Now I'm lost again. Again A is a world not a proposition so what would A
 or not-A mean even if A and B are comparable?
 
 If anyone else understand the point Tim is making please help me out...
 




A/Prof Russell Standish  Director
High Performance Computing Support Unit, Phone 9385 6967, 8308 3119 (mobile)
UNSW SYDNEY 2052 Fax   9385 6965, 0425 253119 ()
Australia[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Room 2075, Red Centrehttp://parallel.hpc.unsw.edu.au/rks
International prefix  +612, Interstate prefix 02





Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Bruno Marchal

Wei Dai wrote:

According to possible world semantics, it's necessary that P means that
P is true in all worlds accessible from this one. Different modal logics
correspond to different restrictions on the accessibility relation. Before
the invention of possible world semantics, people argued about which modal
logic is the correct one, but now philosophers realize that different
notions of accessibility (and the corresponding notions of modality) are
useful at different times, so there is no single correct modal logic.

That's my one paragraph summary of possible world semantics. Please
correct me if I'm wrong, or read these articles if you're not familiar
with this topic:

http://www.xrefer.com/entry.jsp?xrefid=552831
http://www.xrefer.com/entry.jsp?xrefid=553229

My questions is, why not just quantify over the possible worlds and refer
to the accessibility relation directly? This way you can talk about
multiple accessibility relations simultaneously, and you don't have to
introduce new logical symbols (i.e. the box and the diamond). Is
modality just a syntactic shorthand now?




BM:
Each time you can reduce a theory in another you can considered it
as a syntactic shorthand. In fact you could just as well throw all
math in the basket keeping numbers, right at the start.
It reminds me early programmers saying that FORTRAN was just a toy
language for those stupid guy unable to manage binary code.

Of course your question is not *that* stupid, for sure, :-)

The first answer I would give is that Kripke Possible world semantics
just works for a portion of the possible modal logics. (Sometimes
called the classical normal modal logics). So, if modal logician
would have defined the modal logic by the accessibility relations,
they would have missed the whole forest.
Just in my thesis, among G, G*, S4Grz, Z, X, Z*, X*, Z1, Z1*, X1, X1*,
only G and S4Grz have Kripke semantics. (Z, X, Z1, X1 have Scott-
Montague semantics, the others ... are more difficult...).
Note that in first order logic, the quantifier For all and it exists
are sort of modal connector and are used in your sense: the variable x
denoting a sort of abtract world).
But even for modal logic with possible world semantics, it is
important (for a logician) to distinguish 0-order and first-order
complexity, and this in a a priori, non semantical way.
Also first order modal logic, would be syntactically awkward if
everything was done by quantifying on the worlds.
Last answer: if you take a simple modal logic like S4, that is:

AXIOMS:   [](p - q) - ([]p - []q)
   []p - p
   []p - [][]p

RULES:p p-q   p
  ,---
 q []p

You can define the accessibility relation in a first order formula.
The accessibility relation, indeed, is just a transtive and reflexive
relation, making the frame of world a partially ordered set (the
model of intutionnistic propositional calculus).
But take the famous G Lob formula: []([]p-p)-[]p, there is *no*
semantics for it describable by a first order formula. The frame is
an inverse of a well founded set. This means that to continue your
semantical use of modal logic in a synctatical well defined way, you should
use second order logic. Here, the fact that there is a simple modal
formula making all the heavy work for you is *very* nice. It really
simplify things a lot.

To sum up, my main answer is that
Kripke semantics has been invented to handle
better some--not all--modalities (invented by Aristotle!).
Modalities has not been invented for shortand description of Kripke
worlds. It is the other way round. In the real life (like in comp!)
Kripke semantics can only be used exceptionally.

Bruno




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Tim May


On Monday, August 12, 2002, at 11:41  PM, Russell Standish wrote:

 Bruno probably does, but I'll put my spin on it. Each distinguishable
 world is a description*, which is a conjunction of propositions I
 have green eyes _and_ I live in Sydney _and_ the twin towers were
 destroyed by airliners on 11/9/2002 _and_ ..., and as such is a
 proposition. I'm not completely convinced that one can simply apply
 modal logic to the set of all descriptions in this way, but it does
 have some plausibility.


I think small. Attempting to reason about entire worlds with huge 
amounts of state (put various ways: long description, high logical 
depth, high algorithmic complexity, big) is not useful...to me.

So I use A and B for two possible worlds. The outcome of a coin 
toss, for example. The click of a geiger counter or not. Schrodinger's 
cat alive, or dead. These states are, as Russell notes, propositions. Or 
sets of propositions (or huge sets of propositions, for entire worlds).

I prefer at this time to ignore the implied complexity of an entire 
world and just call them A and B. Two outcomes, two branches in the 
MWI sense, two possible worlds, two points in a lattice, two points in a 
pre-ordered set (see below), two points in a partially-ordered set 
(poset, see below).

I picked WWIII happens this year (or doesn't) to illustrate the 
general point that modal logic applies, that classical logic cannot 
apply to find and implication from A to B or B to A, as they represent 
contradictory to each other worlds. I didn't mean it to imply that modal 
logic is going to somehow tell us how likely such a world is, or what 
life might be like in either of those worlds, etc. I just wanted to make 
A and B more tangible to MWI sorts of folks.

(Goldblatt, in his book Topoi, uses Fermat's last theorem is true or 
false as the two contradictory possible worlds. At the time he wrote 
his book, 1979, the truth or falsity of FLT was unknown. These were two 
possible worlds, visualizable by mathematicians and others, each having 
a kind of tangible reality. In fact, something that was shown to be 
equivalent to FLT was the Taniyama-Shimura Conjecture about some 
curious relationships between elliptic functions and modular forms. And 
for many years before Taniyama was proved, papers would start with this 
perfect example of modal logic: Assuming Taniyama-Shimura is true, 
then People _believed_ T-S was probably true, but it hadn't been 
proved formally until Andrew Wiles did so, thus proving Fermat's Last 
Theorem as almost a trivial afternote.)

A series of moments or events is drawn as a graph, with vertices linked 
with edges, with some events clearly coming after others, because they 
are causally-dependent on earlier events. But also some events 
_independent_ of other events, with no known (and perhaps no _possible_ 
causal relationship, e.g., events outside each other's light cones, 
i.e., spacelike intervals).

This graph, this set of vertices and edges, is a per-ordered set. More 
than just a set, any category with the property that between any two 
objects p and q there is AT MOST one arrow p -- q is said to be 
pre-ordered. There are lots of examples of this: the integers (and the 
real numbers) are pre-ordered under the operation greater than or equal 
to or less than or equal to. Moments in time are pre-ordered. 
Containment of sets is pre-ordered.

Following Goldblatt, I'll call the arrow R. So the p -- q example 
above is written as pRq.

Here are some properties of pre-orders:

1. Reflexive: for every p, pRp.

Example: For every p, p implies p.

Example: For every real number, that real number is less than or equal 
(LTE) to itself. And also greater than or equal (GTE) to itself.

Example: For every event, that event occurs before or at the same time 
as that event.

(Here I'm using time, because time is the most interesting pre-order for 
our discussion of worlds, MWI, causality, etc.)

Example: Every set contains itself (where containment is contains or is 
equal to). (This may say like a tautological definition. Draw pictures 
of sets as blobs. The motivation for this example will become clearer 
with later properties.)

2. Transitive: Whenever pRq and qRs, then pRs.

Example: If p implies q and q implies s, then p implies s.

Example: if p is less than or equal (LTE)  to q and q is LTE  to s, then 
p is LTE to s.

Example: if event A happens before (or at the same time as) event B and 
event B happens before (or at the same times as) event C, then even A 
happens before (or at the same time as) event C.

Example: (short version--you know the drill by now): If A contains B and 
B contains C, then A contains C.

Discussion: These are all simple points to make. Obvious even. But they 
tell us some important things about the ontological structure of many 
familiar things. I encourage anyone not familiar with these ideas to 
think about the points and think about how many things around us are 
pre-ordered.

Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Tim May


On Tuesday, August 13, 2002, at 10:08  AM, Tim May wrote:
 This graph, this set of vertices and edges, is a per-ordered set. 
 More than just a set, any category with the property that between any 
 two objects p and q there is AT MOST one arrow p -- q is said to 
 be pre-ordered.

I meant to type pre-ordered in the first line above.

I don't normally worry overmuch about minor typos, especially when I 
used the correct spelling right after the typo, but I wouldn't want 
anyone thinking there's some kind of per-ordered set!

--Tim May




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Tim May


On Monday, August 12, 2002, at 11:18  PM, Wei Dai wrote:

 Tim, I'm afraid I still don't understand you.

 On Mon, Aug 12, 2002 at 06:00:26PM -0700, Tim May wrote:
 It is possible that WWIII will happen before the end of this year. In
 one possible world, A, many things are one way...burned, melted,
 destroyed, etc. In another possible world, B, things are dramatically
 different.

 Ok, but what about my point that you can state this by explicit
 quantification over possible worlds rather than using modal operators?
 I.e., There exist a world accessible from this one where WWIII happens
 before the end of this year. instead of It is possible that WWIII will
 happen before the end of this year.?

That is indeed saying just the same thing (though the language is 
slightly different).

The important part of modal logic is not in the accessible from this 
one or it is possible language.

Rather, the forking paths (a la Borges) picture that is described by 
posets and lattices.


 There can be no implication from one world to the other. That is, we
 can't say A implies B or B implies A.

 What does that have to do with my question? Anyway A and B are supposed 
 to
 be worlds here, not propositions, so of course you can't say A implies
 B. I don't know what point you're trying to make here.

Worlds _are_ propositions. And the causal operator (time) is the same 
as implication.

With some important caveats that I can't easily explain without drawing 
a picture. In conventional logic, implication is fully-contained or 
defined from some event A (or perhaps some combination of events A, B, 
C, etc., all causally contributing to a later event).

There are two interesting cases to consider where implication does not 
follow so easily from A:

1. Possible worlds. The event A forks down two (or more) possible paths. 
A future where war occurs, a future where war does not. A future where 
Fermat's Last Theorem is proved to be true. A future where it is not. A 
future of heads, a future of tails.

2. Quantum mechanics. Schrodinger's cat.

(It was Einstein and Podolsky's belief that classical logic must apply 
that led to their belief that there _must_ be some other cause, some 
hidden variable, that makes the outcome follow classical logic. Bohm, 
too. But we know from Bell's Theorem and the Kochen-Specker no-go 
theorems that, basically, these hidden variables are not extant.)

(By the way, the book Interpreting the Quantum World, by Jeffrey Bub, 
has an interesting section on how modal logic applies to QM.)

Bruno is much more of a logician than I am, but the various terms of 
logic, lattices, and set theory are analogous (probably a very efficient 
category theory metaview, but I don't yet know it).

1 is True
0 is False
lattice infimum or Boolean meet, ^ , is conjunction (AND)
lattice supremum or Boolean join, v , is disjunction (OR)
lattice or Boolean orthocomplement is negation (NOT)

(Understanding this is not essential to my arguments here...I just 
wanted to make the point that there are mappings between the languages 
of logic, set theory, and lattices. In a deep sense, they are all the 
same thing. Definitions do matter, of course, but e-mail is not a great 
place to lay out long lists of definitions!)



 This branching future is exactly what I was talking about a week or so
 ago in terms of partially ordered sets. If the order relationship is
 occurs before or at the same time as, which is equivalent to less
 than or equal to, A and B cannot be linearly ordered. In fact, since
 both A and B are completely different states, neither can be said to be
 a predecessor or parent of the other. In fact, A and B are not
 comparable.

 I'm with you so far in this paragraph.

 We cannot say A or not-A.

 Now I'm lost again. Again A is a world not a proposition so what 
 would A
 or not-A mean even if A and B are comparable?

The two forks in the road are given the same truth value weighting in 
this possible worlds approach.

We have _assumed_ A in this fork I described, so not-A is certainly 
not necessarily the other path. In fact, the meaningful interpretation 
of not-A in the complement sense is that which precedes A, that is, 
the events leading up to A in this world.

I realize this sounds confusing. Draw a picture. Just have three points 
in it, arranged in a triangle:

A   B

   \   /

   X

Time is in the upward direction. The points/events/states X, A, B form a 
poset. One arrow between any two points. Pre-ordering (reflexive, 
transitive) and partial-ordering (reflexive, transitive, antisymmetric).

We cannot, however, say X implies A because X has given rise to _both_ 
A and B.

Besides the possible worlds situation, where we assume X could give 
rise to either of these events, there is also the distinct possibility 
that this will be the only logic we ever know for quantum mechanics. The 
situation X gives rise to either the cat being dead or alive at the time 
we make the measurement, 

Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Wei Dai

Tim, I think I'm starting to understand what you're saying. However, it
still seems that anything you can do with intuitionistic logic, toposes,
etc., can also be done with classical logic and set theory. (I'm not
confident about this, but see my previous post in reponse to Bruno.) Maybe
it's not as convenient or natural in some cases (similar to how modal
logic can be more convenient than explicitly quantifying over possible
worlds even when they are equivalent), but if one is not already familiar
with intuitionistic logic and category theory, is it really worth the
trouble to learn them?

For example, posets can certainly be studied and understood using 
classical logic. How much does intuitionistic logic buy you here?




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Tim May


On Tuesday, August 13, 2002, at 02:34  PM, Wei Dai wrote:

 Tim, I think I'm starting to understand what you're saying. However, it
 still seems that anything you can do with intuitionistic logic, toposes,
 etc., can also be done with classical logic and set theory. (I'm not
 confident about this, but see my previous post in reponse to Bruno.) 
 Maybe
 it's not as convenient or natural in some cases (similar to how modal
 logic can be more convenient than explicitly quantifying over possible
 worlds even when they are equivalent), but if one is not already 
 familiar
 with intuitionistic logic and category theory, is it really worth the
 trouble to learn them?

I don't know. One learns a field for various reasons. Clearly a lot of 
people think classical logic with the right exceptions and terminology 
serves them well. A lot of others, though not as many, think program 
semantics and possible worlds semantics are best understood in the 
natural logic of time-varying sets and topos theory.  I'm in the 
latter category (no pun intended).

I also don't know what your goals are, despite reading many of your 
posts. If, for example, you are looking for tools to understand a 
possible multiverse, or how multiverses in general might be constructed, 
I'm not at all sure any such tools have ever existed or _will_ ever 
exist, except insofar as tools for understanding toposes, lattices, etc. 
exist.

This is quite different from understanding, say, general relativity, 
where the tools of differential geometry and exterior calculus are 
immediately useful for understanding and for calculations.

The MWI/Tegmark/Egan stuff is very far out on the fringes, as we know, 
and there is unlikely to be anything one can do calculations of. Still, 
it seems likely that a _lot_ of mathematics is needed...a lot more math 
than physics, almost certainly.

Modal logic seems to me to be _exactly_ the right logic for talking 
about possible states of existence, for talking about possible worlds, 
for talking about branching universes. So the issue is not But can't I 
find a way to do everything in ordinary logic? but is, rather, to think 
in terms of modal logic offering a more efficient basis (in the 
conceptual vector space), a basis with a smaller semantic gap between 
the formalism and the hypothesized world.

(You might also want to take a look at the paper by Guts, a Russian, on 
a Topos-Theoretic Model of the Deutsch Multiverse. Available at the 
usual xxx.lanl.gov site.)

 For example, posets can certainly be studied and understood using
 classical logic. How much does intuitionistic logic buy you here?

Posets can certainly be studied with classical logic. However, posets 
fail the law of trichotomy, that two things when compared by some 
ordering result in one of three outcomes: A is less than B, A is greater 
than B, or A is equal to B. This is the common sense comparison of 
objects, one with a linear or total order. However, posets are 
partially-ordered precisely because they don't follow the law of 
trichotomy.

Is one more natural than the other? More common? More useful?

I have my own beliefs at this point.

A book I strongly recommend, though it is difficult, is Paul Taylor's 
Practical Foundations of Mathematics. 1999. (I buy many books not to 
read straight through, but to consult, to draw insights and inspirations 
from, and to let me know what I need to learn more of. This is one of 
those books. The first 175 pages, which I've been reading from, is 
making more and more sensethe terms become familiar, I see 
connections with other areas, and by a process akin to analytic 
continuation the ensemble of ideas becomes more and more natural. 
Beyond these pages, though, it's mostly incomprehensible.)

I recommend this book for the broad insights I am gaining from it, but 
not as any kind of manual for tinkering with multiverses! (insert silly 
smiley as one sees fit)

My conclusion from  Tegmark's paper, which dovetailed with Egan's 
treatment of all topologies models in Distress, was that to make 
progress a lot of math needs to be learned. Which is my current approach.

These are not my only inspirations. Indeed, I came to join this list 
after becoming fascinated (again, after a nearly 28-year absence) in 
topology, algebra, and the physics of time and cosmology.

Seen this way, category and topos theory are worth studying for their 
own sake. I don't think it is likely that every conceivable universe 
with consistent laws of mathematics has actual existence (to nutshell 
my understanding of Tegmark's theory) is actually true (whatever that 
means). Nor do I take Schmidhuber's all running programs notion very 
seriously. Interesting ideas to play with, and to use some tools on.

Strangely, then, I view these notions as places to apply the math I'm 
learning to. And I'm thinking small, in terms of simple systems. A paper 
I have mentioned a couple of times is directly in line with this 
approach: Fotini 

Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Wei Dai

On Tue, Aug 13, 2002 at 10:08:50AM -0700, Tim May wrote:
 * Because toposes are essentially mathematical universes in which 
 various bits and pieces of mathematics can be assumed. A topos in which 
 Euclid's Fifth Postulate is true, and many in which it is not. A topos 
 where all functions are differentiable. A topos in which the Axiom of 
 Choice is assumed--and ones where it is not assumed. In other words, as 
 all of the major thinkers have realized over the past 30 years, topos 
 theory is the natural theory of possible worlds.

How does this compare to the situation in classical logic, where you can
have theories (and corresponding models) that assume Euclid's Fifth
Postulate as an axiom and theories that don't?




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Tim May


On Tuesday, August 13, 2002, at 06:16  PM, Wei Dai wrote:

 On Tue, Aug 13, 2002 at 10:08:50AM -0700, Tim May wrote:
 * Because toposes are essentially mathematical universes in which
 various bits and pieces of mathematics can be assumed. A topos in which
 Euclid's Fifth Postulate is true, and many in which it is not. A topos
 where all functions are differentiable. A topos in which the Axiom of
 Choice is assumed--and ones where it is not assumed. In other words, as
 all of the major thinkers have realized over the past 30 years, topos
 theory is the natural theory of possible worlds.

 How does this compare to the situation in classical logic, where you can
 have theories (and corresponding models) that assume Euclid's Fifth
 Postulate as an axiom and theories that don't?

Because such a dichotomy (and theories that don't) means the logic is 
ipso facto modal. The very form tells us that a modal (and hence 
intuitionist) assumption is at work: If it were the case that the 
parallel postulate were valid, then... and Suppose the parallel 
postulate is not true, then...


If the Fifth Postulate is independent of the others, then within the 
framework of the other postulates one may have one branch where the 
Fifth holds (Euclidean Geometry) and another branch where it doesn't 
hold (all of the various non-Euclidean geometries).

Now this turns out to be a not very important example, as various 
geometries with various geodesics on curved surfaces are sort of 
mundane. And the details were mostly worked out a hundred years ago, 
starting with Gauss, Bolyai, Lobachevsky, Riemann, and continuing to 
Levi-Cevita, Ricci, and Cartan. The fact that by the mid-19th century we 
could _see_ clear examples of geometries which did not obey the 
parallel postulate, e.g., triangles drawn largely enough on a sphere, 
great circles, figures drawn on saddle surfaces and trumpet surfaces, 
etc., meant that most people didn't think much about the modal aspects. 
But they are certainly there.

(I believe it's possible to cast differential geometry, including the 
parallel postulate or its negation, in topos terms. Anders Kock has done 
this with what he calls synthetic differential geometry, but I haven't 
read his papers (circa 1970-80), so i don't know if he discusses the 
parallel postulate explicitly.)


Both category theory and topos theory have been used to prove some 
important theorems (e.g., the Weyl Conjecture about a certain form of 
the Riemann zeta function, and the Cohen forcing proof of the 
independence of the Continuum Hypothesis from the Zermelo-Frenkel 
logical system), but it is misleading to think that either will give 
different results from conventional mathematics. It is not as if 
Fermat's Last Theorem is true in conventional logic or in conventional 
set theory but false in intuitionist logic or category theory.

I'm going to have to slow down in my writing. You ask a lot of short 
questions, but these short questions need long answers. Or, perhaps, I 
feel the need to make a lot of explanations of terminology and 
motivations. I'll have to tune the length of my responses to the length 
of your questions, I think!

--Tim May
(.sig for Everything list background)
Corralitos, CA. Born in 1951. Retired from Intel in 1986.
Current main interest: category and topos theory, math, quantum reality, 
cosmology.
Background: physics, Intel, crypto, Cypherpunks




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Wei Dai

On Tue, Aug 13, 2002 at 03:51:49PM -0700, Tim May wrote:
 I also don't know what your goals are, despite reading many of your 
 posts. If, for example, you are looking for tools to understand a 
 possible multiverse, or how multiverses in general might be constructed, 
 I'm not at all sure any such tools have ever existed or _will_ ever 
 exist, except insofar as tools for understanding toposes, lattices, etc. 
 exist.

I think the theory of everything is a multiverse theory. So I want to
understand the implications that following from the idea that multiple
universes exist. These include philosophical, practical, and scientific
implications. Right now I really want to know the answers to these 
questions:

1. What do probabilities mean? 2. How should one reason and make
decisions? 3. What is the structure of the multiverse? Which class of
universes does it contain? For example does it contain non-computable 
universes?

1 and 2 are philosophical questions, but clearly very practically 
relevant. For 3, I'm only interested in the coarsest level of detail for 
now. It needs to be answered because the answer makes a difference for 
question 2.

 The MWI/Tegmark/Egan stuff is very far out on the fringes, as we know, 
 and there is unlikely to be anything one can do calculations of. Still, 
 it seems likely that a _lot_ of mathematics is needed...a lot more math 
 than physics, almost certainly.

I think there are a lot of philosophical and practical questions that 
can be answered without detailed investigation into the fine structure of 
the multiverse. Certainly understanding the fine structure, including the 
structure of all of the universes that it contains, requires a lot of math 
(in fact it requires ALL of math if Tegmark is correct), but I'll leave 
that to the future.

 Modal logic seems to me to be _exactly_ the right logic for talking 
 about possible states of existence, for talking about possible worlds, 
 for talking about branching universes. So the issue is not But can't I 
 find a way to do everything in ordinary logic? but is, rather, to think 
 in terms of modal logic offering a more efficient basis (in the 
 conceptual vector space), a basis with a smaller semantic gap between 
 the formalism and the hypothesized world.

I don't know. When I hear a modal sentence, I have to interpret it in 
terms of possible worlds. It seems easier to just talk directly about 
possible worlds. I haven't seen where the efficiency comes from. I'm sure 
it is more efficient for some purposes, but I'm not convinced that it is 
for mine.

 Seen this way, category and topos theory are worth studying for their
 own sake. I don't think it is likely that every conceivable universe
 with consistent laws of mathematics has actual existence (to nutshell
 my understanding of Tegmark's theory) is actually true (whatever that 
 means). Nor do I take Schmidhuber's all running programs notion very
 seriously. Interesting ideas to play with, and to use some tools on.

Well why don't you take these ideas seriously?




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-13 Thread Tim May


On Tuesday, August 13, 2002, at 08:47  PM, Wei Dai wrote:
 Seen this way, category and topos theory are worth studying for their
 own sake. I don't think it is likely that every conceivable universe
 with consistent laws of mathematics has actual existence (to nutshell
 my understanding of Tegmark's theory) is actually true (whatever that
 means). Nor do I take Schmidhuber's all running programs notion very
 seriously. Interesting ideas to play with, and to use some tools on.

 Well why don't you take these ideas seriously?

Lack of even the slightest piece of evidence for all possible 
mathematical universes actually exist and/or the all runnable computer 
programs.'

I also don't believe there are gods or other supernatural beings, for 
the same reason.

If and when I see an experiment that points to there being other 
universes which have tangible existence, then I'll start to believe.



--Tim May
That the said Constitution shall never be construed to authorize 
Congress to infringe the just liberty of the press or the rights of 
conscience; or to prevent the people of the United States who are 
peaceable citizens from keeping their own arms. --Samuel Adams




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-12 Thread Tim May


On Monday, August 12, 2002, at 12:07  PM, Wei Dai wrote:

 According to possible world semantics, it's necessary that P means 
 that
 P is true in all worlds accessible from this one. Different modal logics
 correspond to different restrictions on the accessibility relation. 
 Before
 the invention of possible world semantics, people argued about which 
 modal
 logic is the correct one, but now philosophers realize that different
 notions of accessibility (and the corresponding notions of modality) are
 useful at different times, so there is no single correct modal logic.

 That's my one paragraph summary of possible world semantics. Please
 correct me if I'm wrong, or read these articles if you're not familiar
 with this topic:

 http://www.xrefer.com/entry.jsp?xrefid=552831
 http://www.xrefer.com/entry.jsp?xrefid=553229

 My questions is, why not just quantify over the possible worlds and 
 refer
 to the accessibility relation directly? This way you can talk about
 multiple accessibility relations simultaneously, and you don't have to
 introduce new logical symbols (i.e. the box and the diamond). Is
 modality just a syntactic shorthand now?

Modal logic is a lot more than syntactic shorthand.

Consider this example, phrased in MWI terms.

It is possible that WWIII will happen before the end of this year. In 
one possible world, A, many things are one way...burned, melted, 
destroyed, etc. In another possible world, B, things are dramatically 
different.

There can be no implication from one world to the other. That is, we 
can't say A implies B or B implies A.

This branching future is exactly what I was talking about a week or so 
ago in terms of partially ordered sets. If the order relationship is 
occurs before or at the same time as, which is equivalent to less 
than or equal to, A and B cannot be linearly ordered. In fact, since 
both A and B are completely different states, neither can be said to be 
a predecessor or parent of the other. In fact, A and B are not 
comparable. We cannot say A or not-A.

We have thus left the world of classical logic and are in the world of 
non-classical, or intuitionistic, or Heyting logic.

Posets are not just a different syntactic shorthand from 
linearly-ordered sets.

Branching worlds, aka possible worlds, aka MWI (when QM is involved) is 
a more accurate way of talking about time and successions of events than 
is attempting to force time into a strait-jacket of linearly-ordered 
sets (chains).

Besides the topos work of Saul Kripke, Vaughan Pratt at Stanford has 
written a lot on concurrency, lattices, and posets.

Lee Smolin's book Three Roads to Quantum Gravity is very good at 
explaining how this relates to cosmology.

--Tim May
(.sig for Everything list background)
Corralitos, CA. Born in 1951. Retired from Intel in 1986.
Current main interest: category and topos theory, math, quantum reality, 
cosmology.
Background: physics, Intel, crypto, Cypherpunks




Re: modal logic and possible worlds

2002-08-12 Thread Wei Dai

Tim, I'm afraid I still don't understand you.

On Mon, Aug 12, 2002 at 06:00:26PM -0700, Tim May wrote:
 It is possible that WWIII will happen before the end of this year. In 
 one possible world, A, many things are one way...burned, melted, 
 destroyed, etc. In another possible world, B, things are dramatically 
 different.

Ok, but what about my point that you can state this by explicit 
quantification over possible worlds rather than using modal operators? 
I.e., There exist a world accessible from this one where WWIII happens 
before the end of this year. instead of It is possible that WWIII will 
happen before the end of this year.?

 There can be no implication from one world to the other. That is, we 
 can't say A implies B or B implies A.

What does that have to do with my question? Anyway A and B are supposed to
be worlds here, not propositions, so of course you can't say A implies
B. I don't know what point you're trying to make here.

 This branching future is exactly what I was talking about a week or so 
 ago in terms of partially ordered sets. If the order relationship is 
 occurs before or at the same time as, which is equivalent to less 
 than or equal to, A and B cannot be linearly ordered. In fact, since 
 both A and B are completely different states, neither can be said to be 
 a predecessor or parent of the other. In fact, A and B are not 
 comparable. 

I'm with you so far in this paragraph.

 We cannot say A or not-A.

Now I'm lost again. Again A is a world not a proposition so what would A
or not-A mean even if A and B are comparable?

If anyone else understand the point Tim is making please help me out...