RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-11 Thread Rick Garnett
Dear colleagues,

Like Eugene, I think there is (as always) a lot to what Alan says.  Still, with 
respect to the specific question whether judicial predictions or observations 
of political divisiveness along religious lines should be used to identify 
those practices and policies that are unconstitutional -- i.e., that violate 
the Establishment Clause -- my view is that they should play no role.  

To say this is not to deny that one good reason for prohibiting -- for taking 
off the table of ordinary politics -- religious establishments is to avoid 
such divisiveness (although divisiveness can just be a word we use for 
disagreement, which seems unavoidable and not necessarily undesirable).  In 
that article that Tom kindly mentioned, I tried to make the case that the 
Establishment Clause should not be seen as an invitation to the Court to play a 
managerial role with respect to the tone of our political discourse.  Its 
contributions, instead, should be more indirect -- it enforces our political, 
politics-constraining disestablishment decision, but does not, in the course of 
enforcing that decision, use feared or observed divisiveness to distinguish 
what we disallowed from what we left allowable.

Regards,

Rick
   
Richard W. Garnett
Professor of Law  Concurrent Professor of Political Science
Director, Program on Church, State  Society
Notre Dame Law School
P.O. Box 780
Notre Dame, IN  46556-0780

574-631-6981 (office)
574-631-4197 (fax)

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Tuesday, June 10, 2014 5:28 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Divisiveness

   I think there’s much to what Alan says, but I think the 
relationship between national and local politics is complex.  For instance, 
while choosing U.S. Supreme Court Justices is a matter for national politics, 
many groups that organize to influence that will also have local chapters and 
allies, which will get involved in state-level politics, and sometimes even in 
local politics; the anti-abortion movement is one example.  Moreover, one may 
influence national politics by working through state or local-level politics, 
for instance by pressuring the state legislature, a city council, or a school 
board to take symbolic action protesting against federal constitutional 
decisions, for instance relating to religious symbolism and the like.  My sense 
is that McCreary County indeed stemmed from local-level political activity 
aimed at symbolically protesting the Court’s Establishment Clause decisions.

   Again, this doesn’t tell us what the right answer is under the 
Establishment Clause, or under other clauses.  Perhaps an answer that leads to 
some extra political mobilization along religious lines is nonetheless correct. 
 But it does suggest that using the supposed divisiveness of a decision as a 
criterion for determining whether the decision is right, or determining what 
rule to adopt, would not be a good idea.

   Eugene

Alan Brownstein writes:


Eugene is certainly correct that sometimes a constitutional decision intended 
to take an issue off of the table of political deliberation and avoid 
political/religious divisions will have counterproductive consequences. I tend 
to see this as an unavoidable cost of deciding constitutional cases at least in 
part on some understanding of social reality and some prediction of how the 
decision will influence human behavior. Courts will make mistakes in this 
regard -- and they will make mistakes in many areas of constitutional law that 
extend far beyond the religion clauses.



If we focus on the religion clauses, however, I think constitutional decisions 
do mitigate political/religious divisions in many cases. For example, they 
certainly influence the level of decision making at which political/religious 
mobilization occurs.  Choosing new supreme court justices is a matter of 
national politics, not local politics.



There is one sense in which political/religious divisions may reduced if 
church-state issues are returned to the table of political deliberation. 
Subjecting religious exercise and the promotion of religion to political 
control reduces religious integration. More people will choose to live in 
communities in which they are the majority or a very well represented minority. 
In religiously homogenous communities, there is less need to mobilize along 
religious lines. I think there are other serious problems with this kind of 
fragmented, dis-integrated society along religious lines. But in many 
communities, the absence of minorities will reduce political/religious disputes.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Alan Brownstein
Eugene is certainly correct that sometimes a constitutional decision intended 
to take an issue off of the table of political deliberation and avoid 
political/religious divisions will have counterproductive consequences. I tend 
to see this as an unavoidable cost of deciding constitutional cases at least in 
part on some understanding of social reality and some prediction of how the 
decision will influence human behavior. Courts will make mistakes in this 
regard -- and they will make mistakes in many areas of constitutional law that 
extend far beyond the religion clauses.



If we focus on the religion clauses, however, I think constitutional decisions 
do mitigate political/religious divisions in many cases. For example, they 
certainly influence the level of decision making at which political/religious 
mobilization occurs.  Choosing new supreme court justices is a matter of 
national politics, not local politics.



There is one sense in which political/religious divisions may reduced if 
church-state issues are returned to the table of political deliberation. 
Subjecting religious exercise and the promotion of religion to political 
control reduces religious integration. More people will choose to live in 
communities in which they are the majority or a very well represented minority. 
In religiously homogenous communities, there is less need to mobilize along 
religious lines. I think there are other serious problems with this kind of 
fragmented, dis-integrated society along religious lines. But in many 
communities, the absence of minorities will reduce political/religious disputes.



Alan


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Monday, June 09, 2014 8:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Divisiveness


   I appreciate Alan's attempt to cabin the divisiveness concept, 
but I wonder whether it works.  Nothing is beyond the scope of political 
decision-making -- there is always the possibility of constitutional amendment, 
and, more importantly, so long as various decisions involve the contested 
interpretation of constitutional language, there is the possibility of using 
political processes to select Justices who will take a different view of the 
matter.  Indeed, my sense is that some of the most prominent political 
divisions along religious lines have come with regard to decisions that aimed 
to take things off the table, but have failed to do so.  Roe v. Wade is the 
classic example, though in some measure the various government speech 
decisions, from the school prayer case onwards, have had that effect as well.



Now it may well be that other decisions have indeed settled matters in 
considerable measure, and thus diminished religious groups’ political 
mobilization as religious groups.  But my guess is that it’s often not easy to 
predict which creates more mobilization of religious groups as religious 
groups: a particular executive or legislative policy decision, or a Supreme 
Court decision reversing that policy decision.



   Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 7:37 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: RE: Divisiveness



 If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision than 
 Eugene

 is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a decision was

 one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the sense that 
 if

 government could promote religion (or interfere with religion) religious 
 groups

 would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as religious 
 groups

 in order to make sure that it was their faith that the government promoted and

 that it was not their faith that was subject to government interference. 
 Placing a

 church-state issue beyond the scope of political decision-making by 
 subjecting it

 to constitutional constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of

 political/religious divisions.



 There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.



 Alan Brownstein
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Jon,

I think you don't understand, or are ignoring, the point of view of the Hobby 
Lobby parties. They don't object to employees buying what the Hobby Lobby 
parties consider to be abortifacient drugs. I don't think they monitor what 
their employees do with wages or would take any action against employees who 
buy or use such drugs. They object to being required themselves to take an 
action specifically related to abortion -- buying insurance that specifically 
covers the drugs. You might object to buying a gun for an employee, even though 
the recipient would be the one who uses it. You might, if you were a pacifist, 
object to being drafted to serve as an army medic or supply clerk, even though 
you would not be killing anyone but merely be advancing the army's operations. 

I understand that some people object to this characterization, but it doesn't 
move the discussion forward to just assume that it isn't the position taken by 
the objectors in Hobby Lobby.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law

Sent from my iPad

 On Jun 9, 2014, at 2:35 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:
 
 There is some authority for not preferring religion over non-religion.
 I do not think religious people should get exemptions reasons not
 connected to the practice of their religion (church services, prayer,
 lighting candles, sacrificing chickens etc.) To me many requests sound
 like I think it is wrong for religious reasons and therefore other
 people should not engage in that behavior.  E.g. I will not pay my taxes
 because taxes pay for killing people.  No one is asking the owners of
 Hobby Lobby to engage in activities that they believe offend their
 religion; they are seeking not to pay employees in such a way that
 certain contraceptives would be covered.  The decision to use or not use
 the contraceptives is the employees'.  One difficulty is that the courts
 are loath to inquire into to the closeness of the connection of the
 claim to the religious belief.  But without limits exemptions will
 become legion.
 
 Exemptions usually involve some unfairness.  That would be mitigated if
 religious exemptions were limited to the actual practice of religion
 rather than attempts to impose beliefs on others through refusing to
 comply with general laws. Smith is a good example and, as we know, does
 not stop you from sacrificing chickens because people in the community
 are offended.  Take it outside the church or home and give exemptions to
 general laws and that will create problems if the exemptions become wide
 enough to make it seem that religious folks have general privileges in
 society that secular folks do not.  Cf. Affirmative action.
 
 I noted previously Scalia's citation (in during oral argument) of the
 overwhelming majority extending the VRA as evidence that the law was not
 carefully considered. During RFRA's passage and thereafter I focused on
 conservatives articulating the issue as one in which the Supreme Court
 disrespected religion, and those on the other side of the spectrum
 articulated the Smith decision as having disrespected constitutional
 rights.  From discussion about Scalia with lawyers and non-lawyers, I
 cannot help thinking that a dislike of Scalia contributed to one side's
 support of RFRA.
 
Jon
 
 
 On 2014-06-09 17:00, Steven Jamar wrote:
 “nones”?
 Huh.  I knew that was a thing, but didn’t really expect to see it
 here.
 
 Steve
 
 On Jun 9, 2014, at 4:49 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu
 wrote:
 
 I agree with Alan's statement below, stated better than I did.  I
 would add that we now do/should include the nones within the system.
 
  Jon
 
 On 2014-06-08 22:36, Alan Brownstein wrote:
 If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive
 decision
 than Eugene is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was
 whether a decision was one that provoked political divisions along
 religious lines in the sense that if government could promote
 religion
 (or interfere with religion) religious groups would have an
 additional
 incentive to organize and mobilize as religious groups in order to
 make sure that it was their faith that the government promoted and
 that it was not their faith that was subject to government
 interference. Placing a church-state issue beyond the scope of
 political decision-making by subjecting it to constitutional
 constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of
 political/religious divisions.
 
 There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.
 
 Alan Brownstein
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
 [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:54 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Divisiveness
 
   I agree very much with Tom 

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread K Chen
 statute has experienced sympathetic interpretations and hostile
 interpretations, and it takes a lot of consistent appellate decisions to
 generate consistently sympathetic (or, not legitimate but nearly as likely)
 consistently hostile interpretations. And with RFRA, there just aren’t
 enough cases to generate such a body of appellate decisions.* Hobby
 Lobby* will the Court’s second opinion interpreting the Act in its 21
 years of existence.





 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Hillel Y. Levin
 *Sent:* Monday, June 09, 2014 12:59 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Divisiveness



 Chip:



 I am in total agreement of your analysis, except that I think there is a
 third way. That would be for legislatures to consider religious exemptions
 when they enact individual laws (as they did before Smith, and after as
 well). The results would still be inconsistent over time ((1) sometimes the
 legislature will grant an exception; sometimes it won't; and (2) courts
 will still have to resolve disputes on the margins), but at least they
 would have a majoritarian pedigree on the whole.



 We tolerate all kinds of legislative inconsistency because we understand
 that political interests change over time, issues that seem similar may
 appear different at the time of enactment, lobbying groups gain and lose
 power, the legislators themselves change over time, and so on. We don't
 demand consistency of legislators the same way we do of courts. Legislators
 are allowed to be inconsistent (within some broad due process/equality
 boundaries, I suppose).



 We could still quibble about the role of courts in this system. They'll
 still have to resolve some kinds of disputes, no doubt. Which side should
 they err on? Should their guiding principle be to force majoritarian
 engagement? Reverse the burden of legislative inertia? Etc. But at least we
 would have legislative guidance beyond do good stuff when it comes to
 legislative exceptions, which is what RFRA yields. This abdication of
 policy-making responsibility by legislators is indefensible.



 Eugene can correct me if I'm mistaken, but I think his proposed
 common-law approach to religious exceptions points in this direction.













 On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 12:43 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 It's a very old lesson.  Legislators support vague delegations aimed at
 some general good (clean air, workplace safety, endangered species), and
 claim political credit for doing so.  Then they (or their successors) sit
 back and criticize agencies and courts that have to apply those vague
 standards to specific facts.  Choices made from outside the veil of
 ignorance are inevitably much more difficult than those made from behind it.



 But I am making a further point.  The context of religious exemptions --
 because of all the variations among faiths (beliefs and practices) and all
 the variations among regulatory or other government contexts in which
 conflicts may arise, is uniquely vulnerable to the problem of
 irreconcilable inconsistency over time.  We can have a regime of no
 exemptions under these kind of general standards, or a regime of ad hoc, we
 know it when we see it, all things considered, interest-balancing
 exemptions (that is, a regime that will appear lawless when scrutinized
 over time).  I don't think there is any other choice.  RFRA represents the
 latter choice, but (especially in a case made prominent by its culture war
 salience) the judicial outcome will inevitably be seen as an act of bad
 faith by the losers (whichever side that is).



 On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 12:29 PM, Hillel Y. Levin hillelle...@gmail.com
 wrote:

 What's ironic to me is that the same legislators (I.e. All of them) who
 attack the courts for overreaching and making policy-decisions chose to
 bestow immense policy-making power on those same courts through RFRA.
 There's a legislative process lesson in there somewhere.



 On Monday, June 9, 2014, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 It is worth recalling that federal RFRA itself was anything but divisive.
  Au contraire.  It passed with overwhelming support from both parties, and
 wide support among civil rights and civil liberties groups (with Hobby
 Lobby under advisement, some of these groups are now running from RFRA like
 it was the plague).



 The problem now is not divisiveness, per se.  Like any controversial
 Supreme Court decision, some will hate it and others will love it.
  Inevitably, these folks will be divided by their disagreement.



 The problem is legitimacy.  Free exercise standards, pre-Smith, were
 incredibly plastic -- sometimes you got Yoder, Thomas, or Frazee, and
 sometimes you got Goldman, O'Lone, Lyng, and Smith

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
We've been over this before, of course, but as long as we're filling out the 
facts ... they are required to pay a $2,000-per-employee assessment if they 
drop health insurance, on top of being forced to choose an option that would 
either cause them significant competitive disadvantage or necessitate their 
raising wages. Even if we regard the wage increases and insurance premiums as a 
wash, the $2000/employee assessment is surely a government dissuasion.

In response to Art's question, I'm assuming the IRS ruling simply means the 
employer cannot make up for dropping health insurance with tax-free payments to 
employees, but rather must increase taxable wages. That dramatizes why, in 
practical terms, increasing wages enough to offset the tax consequences may be 
a burdensome option indeed. But quite apart from that, it seems to me clear 
that the $2,000/employee assessment is a substantial burden (even denominated 
as a tax, it can affect and be designed to affect behavior, as NFIB v. Sebelius 
recognizes).

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Arthur Spitzer [artspit...@gmail.com]
Sent: Tuesday, June 10, 2014 12:33 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Divisiveness

Marty-

Like you, I had thought that the law doesn't require HL to offer an employee 
health insurance plan at all, and that that was an escape hatch from its 
claimed religious problem. But from a recent news article it looks like 
employers no longer have that option, as a realistic matter:

http://www.nytimes.com/2014/05/26/us/irs-bars-employers-from-dumping-workers-into-health-exchanges.html?_r=0

WASHINGTON — Many employers had thought they could shift health costs to the 
government by sending their employees to a health insurance exchange with a 
tax-free contribution of cash to help pay premiums, but the Obama 
administration has squelched the idea in a new ruling. Such arrangements do not 
satisfy the health care 
lawhttp://topics.nytimes.com/top/news/health/diseasesconditionsandhealthtopics/health_insurance_and_managed_care/health_care_reform/index.html?inline=nyt-classifier,
 the administration said, and employers may be subject to a tax penalty of $100 
a day — or $36,500 a year — for each employee who goes into the individual 
marketplace.

The ruling this month, by the Internal Revenue 
Servicehttp://topics.nytimes.com/top/reference/timestopics/organizations/i/internal_revenue_service/index.html?inline=nyt-org,
 blocks any wholesale move by employers to dump employees into the exchanges.

Am I missing something?

Art Spitzer



Warning: this message is subject to monitoring by the NSA.



On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 1:05 PM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
I agree with Mark's correction that the complaint of the Greens is not that 
their employees' use of contraceptive burdens their religion.

But it's also not that they have to buy insurance that specifically covers the 
drugs.  For thing, the law doesn't require HL to offer an employee health 
insurance plan at all.  For another, the Greens aren't shareholders, and 
therefore aren't buying anything.  Hobby Lobby, Inc. --as opposed to the 
Greens-- is contracting for an insurance plan -- but of course that plan is not 
made available to their employees gratis; it is a part of their compensation 
package, provided in exchange for their labor, just like wages.

The nature of the way in which the Greens are alleged to be required to act in 
violation of any religious obligations, therefore, is not at all obvious.


On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 12:55 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
Jon,

I think you don't understand, or are ignoring, the point of view of the Hobby 
Lobby parties. They don't object to employees buying what the Hobby Lobby 
parties consider to be abortifacient drugs. I don't think they monitor what 
their employees do with wages or would take any action against employees who 
buy or use such drugs. They object to being required themselves to take an 
action specifically related to abortion -- buying insurance that specifically 
covers the drugs. You might object to buying a gun for an employee, even though 
the recipient would be the one who uses it. You might, if you were a pacifist, 
object to being drafted to serve as an army medic or supply clerk, even though 
you would not be killing anyone but merely

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Marty Lederman
My understanding is that that IRS reg is not about the option of declining
to offer a plan at all -- something that I'd think the statute guarantees
and that the executive cannot change -- but instead about whether certain
employer-employee arrangements for health care costs are excludable from
income.  The IRS Notice is here:

http://www.irs.gov/pub/irs-drop/n-13-54.pdf

For the life of me, I don't understand much of it, and would be grateful if
any of you can translate it into English.




On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 1:33 PM, Arthur Spitzer artspit...@gmail.com
wrote:

 Marty-

 Like you, I had thought that the law doesn't require HL to offer an
 employee health insurance plan at all, and that that was an escape hatch
 from its claimed religious problem. But from a recent news article it looks
 like employers no longer have that option, as a realistic matter:


 http://www.nytimes.com/2014/05/26/us/irs-bars-employers-from-dumping-workers-into-health-exchanges.html?_r=0

 WASHINGTON — Many employers had thought they could shift health costs to
 the government by sending their employees to a health insurance exchange
 with a tax-free contribution of cash to help pay premiums, but the Obama
 administration has squelched the idea in a new ruling. Such arrangements do
 not satisfy the health care law
 http://topics.nytimes.com/top/news/health/diseasesconditionsandhealthtopics/health_insurance_and_managed_care/health_care_reform/index.html?inline=nyt-classifier,
 the administration said, and employers may be subject to a tax penalty of
 $100 a day — or $36,500 a year — for each employee who goes into the
 individual marketplace.

 The ruling this month, by the Internal Revenue Service
 http://topics.nytimes.com/top/reference/timestopics/organizations/i/internal_revenue_service/index.html?inline=nyt-org,
 blocks any wholesale move by employers to dump employees into the exchanges.
 Am I missing something?

 Art Spitzer



 *Warning*
 *: this message is subject to monitoring by the NSA.*


 On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 1:05 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
 wrote:

 I agree with Mark's correction that the complaint of the Greens is not
 that their employees' use of contraceptive burdens their religion.

 But it's also not that they have to buy insurance that specifically
 covers the drugs.  For thing, the law doesn't require HL to offer an
 employee health insurance plan at all.  For another, the Greens aren't
 shareholders, and therefore aren't buying anything.  Hobby Lobby, Inc.
 --as opposed to the Greens-- is contracting for an insurance plan -- but of
 course that plan is not made available to their employees gratis; it is a
 part of their compensation package, provided in exchange for their labor,
 just like wages.

 The nature of the way in which the Greens are alleged to be required to
 act in violation of any religious obligations, therefore, is not at all
 obvious.


 On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 12:55 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Jon,

 I think you don't understand, or are ignoring, the point of view of the
 Hobby Lobby parties. They don't object to employees buying what the Hobby
 Lobby parties consider to be abortifacient drugs. I don't think they
 monitor what their employees do with wages or would take any action against
 employees who buy or use such drugs. They object to being required
 themselves to take an action specifically related to abortion -- buying
 insurance that specifically covers the drugs. You might object to buying a
 gun for an employee, even though the recipient would be the one who uses
 it. You might, if you were a pacifist, object to being drafted to serve as
 an army medic or supply clerk, even though you would not be killing anyone
 but merely be advancing the army's operations.

 I understand that some people object to this characterization, but it
 doesn't move the discussion forward to just assume that it isn't the
 position taken by the objectors in Hobby Lobby.

 Mark

 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law

 Sent from my iPad

  On Jun 9, 2014, at 2:35 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu
 wrote:
 
  There is some authority for not preferring religion over non-religion.
  I do not think religious people should get exemptions reasons not
  connected to the practice of their religion (church services, prayer,
  lighting candles, sacrificing chickens etc.) To me many requests sound
  like I think it is wrong for religious reasons and therefore other
  people should not engage in that behavior.  E.g. I will not pay my
 taxes
  because taxes pay for killing people.  No one is asking the owners of
  Hobby Lobby to engage in activities that they believe offend their
  religion; they are seeking not to pay employees in such a way that
  certain contraceptives would be covered.  The decision to use or not
 use
  the contraceptives is the employees'.  One difficulty is that the
 courts
  are loath to inquire into to the 

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Marty Lederman
I didn't say that the Greens are not potentially burden as company
directors -- indeed, that's exactly what I've argued the case is about,
rather than being about corporate free exercise or shareholder rights:

http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/hobby-lobby-part-v-whose-religious.html


On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 2:17 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 The just like wages characterization is highly contested and, at least
 if pushed to its logical conclusion,  unsustainable. As to the shareholder
 issue, almost everyone these days owns property through trusts; anyone who
 has substantial assets and wants to avoid probate will do so. So it's not
 surprising that the Greens are not personally shareholders but rather
 trustees of the trusts that hold the shares (if I understand the facts
 correctly). Their rights are implicated as beneficial owners and as
 controlling persons, by way of their being trustees of their family trust
 and also officers and directors who personally take actions on behalf of
 the corporation. As for them not being required to provide the coverage
 they object to, because they can just leave their employees out in the
 Obamacare cold, and pay a fine, there is a strong argument that the law
 still creates a substantial burden. I think we've discussed that issue at
 length.

 Mark

 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law


 Sent from my iPad

 On Jun 10, 2014, at 10:09 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
 wrote:

 I agree with Mark's correction that the complaint of the Greens is not
 that their employees' use of contraceptive burdens their religion.

 But it's also not that they have to buy insurance that specifically
 covers the drugs.  For thing, the law doesn't require HL to offer an
 employee health insurance plan at all.  For another, the Greens aren't
 shareholders, and therefore aren't buying anything.  Hobby Lobby, Inc.
 --as opposed to the Greens-- is contracting for an insurance plan -- but of
 course that plan is not made available to their employees gratis; it is a
 part of their compensation package, provided in exchange for their labor,
 just like wages.

 The nature of the way in which the Greens are alleged to be required to
 act in violation of any religious obligations, therefore, is not at all
 obvious.


 On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 12:55 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Jon,

 I think you don't understand, or are ignoring, the point of view of the
 Hobby Lobby parties. They don't object to employees buying what the Hobby
 Lobby parties consider to be abortifacient drugs. I don't think they
 monitor what their employees do with wages or would take any action against
 employees who buy or use such drugs. They object to being required
 themselves to take an action specifically related to abortion -- buying
 insurance that specifically covers the drugs. You might object to buying a
 gun for an employee, even though the recipient would be the one who uses
 it. You might, if you were a pacifist, object to being drafted to serve as
 an army medic or supply clerk, even though you would not be killing anyone
 but merely be advancing the army's operations.

 I understand that some people object to this characterization, but it
 doesn't move the discussion forward to just assume that it isn't the
 position taken by the objectors in Hobby Lobby.

 Mark

 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law

 Sent from my iPad

  On Jun 9, 2014, at 2:35 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu
 wrote:
 
  There is some authority for not preferring religion over non-religion.
  I do not think religious people should get exemptions reasons not
  connected to the practice of their religion (church services, prayer,
  lighting candles, sacrificing chickens etc.) To me many requests sound
  like I think it is wrong for religious reasons and therefore other
  people should not engage in that behavior.  E.g. I will not pay my taxes
  because taxes pay for killing people.  No one is asking the owners of
  Hobby Lobby to engage in activities that they believe offend their
  religion; they are seeking not to pay employees in such a way that
  certain contraceptives would be covered.  The decision to use or not use
  the contraceptives is the employees'.  One difficulty is that the courts
  are loath to inquire into to the closeness of the connection of the
  claim to the religious belief.  But without limits exemptions will
  become legion.
 
  Exemptions usually involve some unfairness.  That would be mitigated if
  religious exemptions were limited to the actual practice of religion
  rather than attempts to impose beliefs on others through refusing to
  comply with general laws. Smith is a good example and, as we know, does
  not stop you from sacrificing chickens because people in the community
  are offended.  Take it outside the church or home and give exemptions to
  general laws and that will create 

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Marty Lederman
Well, as long as we're filling out the facts, it begs the question to
assume that taking this option would cause any particular employer
significant competitive disadvantage.  Perhaps it would and perhaps it
wouldn't.  A recent report (
http://images.politico.com/global/2014/04/30/health_care_4-29_3.html)
concludes that most employers would be much better off choosing this
option.  (I don't vouch for the specifics of the report -- but it surely
demonstrates that one can't merely assume harm in these cases.)

Hobby Lobby, et al., have not alleged remotely enough facts to demonstrate
that it would make them worse off.

Nor does it necessitate raising wages.  Many employers would, of course,
do so, since the health insurance plan was a substitute for wages in the
first instance.  But the law doesn't require that; there's certainly no way
to know how much any particular employer would be compelled to wage wages;
and, most importantly, as noted above, many if not most employers will be
financially better off even if they do so.

Tom also writes that the $2000/employee assessment is surely a government
dissuasion.  Well, compared to $0, sure it is.  But the question is
whether the law *as a whole* -- including the incentives to drop plans,
such as the availability of government-subsidized plans -- not only
dissuades a particular employer from dropping their plan, but actually
imposes *substantial pressure* on an employer to offer the plan
notwithstanding that to do so would allegedly violate the religious tenets
of some individuals operating the company.  And, as noted above, for many
employers, the more economically profitable option may be to drop the
health plan, even apart from any religious motivations.  Accordingly, it
would take some doing for HL to demonstrate that it is substantially
pressured by the law to offer a plan with contraception insurance.


On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 1:53 PM, Berg, Thomas C. tcb...@stthomas.edu
wrote:

  We've been over this before, of course, but as long as we're filling out
 the facts ... they are required to pay a $2,000-per-employee assessment if
 they drop health insurance, on top of being forced to choose an option that
 would either cause them significant competitive disadvantage or necessitate
 their raising wages. Even if we regard the wage increases and insurance
 premiums as a wash, the $2000/employee assessment is surely a government
 dissuasion.

 In response to Art's question, I'm assuming the IRS ruling simply means
 the employer cannot make up for dropping health insurance with tax-free
 payments to employees, but rather must increase taxable wages. That
 dramatizes why, in practical terms, increasing wages enough to offset the
 tax consequences may be a burdensome option indeed. But quite apart from
 that, it seems to me clear that the $2,000/employee assessment is a
 substantial burden (even denominated as a tax, it can affect and be
 designed to affect behavior, as NFIB v. Sebelius recognizes).

 -

 Thomas C. Berg

 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy

 University of St. Thomas School of Law

 MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue

 Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015

 Phone: 651 962 4918

 Fax: 651 962 4881

 E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edu

 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564

 Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


 
 --
 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Arthur Spitzer [
 artspit...@gmail.com]
 *Sent:* Tuesday, June 10, 2014 12:33 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Divisiveness

   Marty-

  Like you, I had thought that the law doesn't require HL to offer an
 employee health insurance plan at all, and that that was an escape hatch
 from its claimed religious problem. But from a recent news article it looks
 like employers no longer have that option, as a realistic matter:


 http://www.nytimes.com/2014/05/26/us/irs-bars-employers-from-dumping-workers-into-health-exchanges.html?_r=0

 WASHINGTON — Many employers had thought they could shift health costs to
 the government by sending their employees to a health insurance exchange
 with a tax-free contribution of cash to help pay premiums, but the Obama
 administration has squelched the idea in a new ruling. Such arrangements do
 not satisfy the health care law
 http://topics.nytimes.com/top/news/health/diseasesconditionsandhealthtopics/health_insurance_and_managed_care/health_care_reform/index.html?inline=nyt-classifier,
 the administration said, and employers may be subject to a tax penalty of
 $100 a day — or $36,500 a year — for each employee who goes into the
 individual marketplace.

 The ruling this month, by the Internal Revenue Service
 http://topics.nytimes.com/top/reference/timestopics/organizations/i/internal_revenue_service/index.html

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Scarberry, Mark
But are they the beneficial owners of the shares as beneficiaries of the trust?

Sent from my iPad

On Jun 10, 2014, at 11:32 AM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

I didn't say that the Greens are not potentially burden as company directors -- 
indeed, that's exactly what I've argued the case is about, rather than being 
about corporate free exercise or shareholder rights:

http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/hobby-lobby-part-v-whose-religious.html


On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 2:17 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
The just like wages characterization is highly contested and, at least if 
pushed to its logical conclusion,  unsustainable. As to the shareholder issue, 
almost everyone these days owns property through trusts; anyone who has 
substantial assets and wants to avoid probate will do so. So it's not 
surprising that the Greens are not personally shareholders but rather trustees 
of the trusts that hold the shares (if I understand the facts correctly). Their 
rights are implicated as beneficial owners and as controlling persons, by way 
of their being trustees of their family trust and also officers and directors 
who personally take actions on behalf of the corporation. As for them not being 
required to provide the coverage they object to, because they can just leave 
their employees out in the Obamacare cold, and pay a fine, there is a strong 
argument that the law still creates a substantial burden. I think we've 
discussed that issue at length.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law


Sent from my iPad

On Jun 10, 2014, at 10:09 AM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

I agree with Mark's correction that the complaint of the Greens is not that 
their employees' use of contraceptive burdens their religion.

But it's also not that they have to buy insurance that specifically covers the 
drugs.  For thing, the law doesn't require HL to offer an employee health 
insurance plan at all.  For another, the Greens aren't shareholders, and 
therefore aren't buying anything.  Hobby Lobby, Inc. --as opposed to the 
Greens-- is contracting for an insurance plan -- but of course that plan is not 
made available to their employees gratis; it is a part of their compensation 
package, provided in exchange for their labor, just like wages.

The nature of the way in which the Greens are alleged to be required to act in 
violation of any religious obligations, therefore, is not at all obvious.


On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 12:55 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
Jon,

I think you don't understand, or are ignoring, the point of view of the Hobby 
Lobby parties. They don't object to employees buying what the Hobby Lobby 
parties consider to be abortifacient drugs. I don't think they monitor what 
their employees do with wages or would take any action against employees who 
buy or use such drugs. They object to being required themselves to take an 
action specifically related to abortion -- buying insurance that specifically 
covers the drugs. You might object to buying a gun for an employee, even though 
the recipient would be the one who uses it. You might, if you were a pacifist, 
object to being drafted to serve as an army medic or supply clerk, even though 
you would not be killing anyone but merely be advancing the army's operations.

I understand that some people object to this characterization, but it doesn't 
move the discussion forward to just assume that it isn't the position taken by 
the objectors in Hobby Lobby.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law

Sent from my iPad

 On Jun 9, 2014, at 2:35 PM, mallamud 
 malla...@camden.rutgers.edumailto:malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:

 There is some authority for not preferring religion over non-religion.
 I do not think religious people should get exemptions reasons not
 connected to the practice of their religion (church services, prayer,
 lighting candles, sacrificing chickens etc.) To me many requests sound
 like I think it is wrong for religious reasons and therefore other
 people should not engage in that behavior.  E.g. I will not pay my taxes
 because taxes pay for killing people.  No one is asking the owners of
 Hobby Lobby to engage in activities that they believe offend their
 religion; they are seeking not to pay employees in such a way that
 certain contraceptives would be covered.  The decision to use or not use
 the contraceptives is the employees'.  One difficulty is that the courts
 are loath to inquire into to the closeness of the connection of the
 claim to the religious belief.  But without limits exemptions will
 become legion.

 Exemptions usually involve some unfairness.  That would be mitigated if
 religious exemptions were limited to the actual practice of religion
 rather than attempts to 

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   I think there's much to what Alan says, but I think the 
relationship between national and local politics is complex.  For instance, 
while choosing U.S. Supreme Court Justices is a matter for national politics, 
many groups that organize to influence that will also have local chapters and 
allies, which will get involved in state-level politics, and sometimes even in 
local politics; the anti-abortion movement is one example.  Moreover, one may 
influence national politics by working through state or local-level politics, 
for instance by pressuring the state legislature, a city council, or a school 
board to take symbolic action protesting against federal constitutional 
decisions, for instance relating to religious symbolism and the like.  My sense 
is that McCreary County indeed stemmed from local-level political activity 
aimed at symbolically protesting the Court's Establishment Clause decisions.

   Again, this doesn't tell us what the right answer is under the 
Establishment Clause, or under other clauses.  Perhaps an answer that leads to 
some extra political mobilization along religious lines is nonetheless correct. 
 But it does suggest that using the supposed divisiveness of a decision as a 
criterion for determining whether the decision is right, or determining what 
rule to adopt, would not be a good idea.

   Eugene

Alan Brownstein writes:


Eugene is certainly correct that sometimes a constitutional decision intended 
to take an issue off of the table of political deliberation and avoid 
political/religious divisions will have counterproductive consequences. I tend 
to see this as an unavoidable cost of deciding constitutional cases at least in 
part on some understanding of social reality and some prediction of how the 
decision will influence human behavior. Courts will make mistakes in this 
regard -- and they will make mistakes in many areas of constitutional law that 
extend far beyond the religion clauses.



If we focus on the religion clauses, however, I think constitutional decisions 
do mitigate political/religious divisions in many cases. For example, they 
certainly influence the level of decision making at which political/religious 
mobilization occurs.  Choosing new supreme court justices is a matter of 
national politics, not local politics.



There is one sense in which political/religious divisions may reduced if 
church-state issues are returned to the table of political deliberation. 
Subjecting religious exercise and the promotion of religion to political 
control reduces religious integration. More people will choose to live in 
communities in which they are the majority or a very well represented minority. 
In religiously homogenous communities, there is less need to mobilize along 
religious lines. I think there are other serious problems with this kind of 
fragmented, dis-integrated society along religious lines. But in many 
communities, the absence of minorities will reduce political/religious disputes.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Daniel J. Greenwood
Even if the Greens are shareholders or beneficiaries of a trust that holds the 
shares, they aren’t buying anything.  The funds used to purchase the insurance 
belong either to the corporation or its employees, depending on whether one is 
thinking about the moment before or after the employment contract (assuming 
that employment is at will, and subject to renegotiation at any moment, either 
view is plausible).   Similarly, if the corporation fails to purchase the 
insurance, the corporation, not the Greens, will be required to pay an 
assessment to partially offset the exchange subsidies.

The corporation’s money is not the Greens’ money.  Corporate funds do not 
belong to shareholders, let alone beneficiaries of a trust that owns shares (if 
they are the trust’s beneficiaries).  To act otherwise is a gross violation of 
ordinary corporate law – basically, theft.   Shareholders have no claim to 
corporate assets unless the directors properly declare a dividend or dissolve 
the firm, and directors may take either of those actions only in furtherance of 
the corporation’s interests and after assuring that other, more senior, 
claimants to corporate assets (such as the employees and the IRS) have had 
their claims met.

Surely Freedom of  Religion does not extend to protecting religiously motivated 
expropriation.  (And if it does, we can expect some interesting revelations in 
the near future.)

The issue here is the rights of the corporation, not its directors or 
shareholders or beneficiaries of a trust holding shares.   The human beings 
have too attenuated a claim on the corporation’s assets for their rights to be 
at issue when it spends, or is compelled to spend, money.

From: Marty Lederman [mailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
Sent: Tuesday, June 10, 2014 1:05 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Divisiveness

I agree with Mark's correction that the complaint of the Greens is not that 
their employees' use of contraceptive burdens their religion.
But it's also not that they have to buy insurance that specifically covers the 
drugs.  For thing, the law doesn't require HL to offer an employee health 
insurance plan at all.  For another, the Greens aren't shareholders, and 
therefore aren't buying anything.  Hobby Lobby, Inc. --as opposed to the 
Greens-- is contracting for an insurance plan -- but of course that plan is not 
made available to their employees gratis; it is a part of their compensation 
package, provided in exchange for their labor, just like wages.
The nature of the way in which the Greens are alleged to be required to act in 
violation of any religious obligations, therefore, is not at all obvious.

On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 12:55 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
Jon,

I think you don't understand, or are ignoring, the point of view of the Hobby 
Lobby parties. They don't object to employees buying what the Hobby Lobby 
parties consider to be abortifacient drugs. I don't think they monitor what 
their employees do with wages or would take any action against employees who 
buy or use such drugs. They object to being required themselves to take an 
action specifically related to abortion -- buying insurance that specifically 
covers the drugs. You might object to buying a gun for an employee, even though 
the recipient would be the one who uses it. You might, if you were a pacifist, 
object to being drafted to serve as an army medic or supply clerk, even though 
you would not be killing anyone but merely be advancing the army's operations.

I understand that some people object to this characterization, but it doesn't 
move the discussion forward to just assume that it isn't the position taken by 
the objectors in Hobby Lobby.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law

Sent from my iPad

 On Jun 9, 2014, at 2:35 PM, mallamud 
 malla...@camden.rutgers.edumailto:malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:

 There is some authority for not preferring religion over non-religion.
 I do not think religious people should get exemptions reasons not
 connected to the practice of their religion (church services, prayer,
 lighting candles, sacrificing chickens etc.) To me many requests sound
 like I think it is wrong for religious reasons and therefore other
 people should not engage in that behavior.  E.g. I will not pay my taxes
 because taxes pay for killing people.  No one is asking the owners of
 Hobby Lobby to engage in activities that they believe offend their
 religion; they are seeking not to pay employees in such a way that
 certain contraceptives would be covered.  The decision to use or not use
 the contraceptives is the employees'.  One difficulty is that the courts
 are loath to inquire into to the closeness of the connection of the
 claim to the religious belief.  But without limits exemptions will
 become legion.

 Exemptions usually involve some unfairness.  That would be mitigated

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-10 Thread Marty Lederman
Can't stress this too often, apparently, since it doesn't seem to take
hold:

The alleged burden here is *not *about the expenditure of money; it's about
the choices.

See
http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/02/hobby-lobby-part-viii-hobby-lobbys.html


On Tue, Jun 10, 2014 at 9:40 PM, Daniel J. Greenwood 
daniel.greenw...@hofstra.edu wrote:

  Even if the Greens are shareholders or beneficiaries of a trust that
 holds the shares, they aren’t buying anything.  The funds used to purchase
 the insurance belong either to the corporation or its employees, depending
 on whether one is thinking about the moment before or after the employment
 contract (assuming that employment is at will, and subject to renegotiation
 at any moment, either view is plausible).   Similarly, if the corporation
 fails to purchase the insurance, the corporation, not the Greens, will be
 required to pay an assessment to partially offset the exchange subsidies.



 The corporation’s money is not the Greens’ money.  Corporate funds do not
 belong to shareholders, let alone beneficiaries of a trust that owns shares
 (if they are the trust’s beneficiaries).  To act otherwise is a gross
 violation of ordinary corporate law – basically, theft.   Shareholders have
 no claim to corporate assets unless the directors properly declare a
 dividend or dissolve the firm, and directors may take either of those
 actions only in furtherance of the corporation’s interests and after
 assuring that other, more senior, claimants to corporate assets (such as
 the employees and the IRS) have had their claims met.



 Surely Freedom of  Religion does not extend to protecting religiously
 motivated expropriation.  (And if it does, we can expect some interesting
 revelations in the near future.)



 The issue here is the rights of the corporation, not its directors or
 shareholders or beneficiaries of a trust holding shares.   The human beings
 have too attenuated a claim on the corporation’s assets for their rights to
 be at issue when it spends, or is compelled to spend, money.



 *From:* Marty Lederman [mailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
 *Sent:* Tuesday, June 10, 2014 1:05 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Divisiveness



 I agree with Mark's correction that the complaint of the Greens is not
 that their employees' use of contraceptive burdens their religion.

 But it's also not that they have to buy insurance that specifically
 covers the drugs.  For thing, the law doesn't require HL to offer an
 employee health insurance plan at all.  For another, the Greens aren't
 shareholders, and therefore aren't buying anything.  Hobby Lobby, Inc.
 --as opposed to the Greens-- is contracting for an insurance plan -- but of
 course that plan is not made available to their employees gratis; it is a
 part of their compensation package, provided in exchange for their labor,
 just like wages.

 The nature of the way in which the Greens are alleged to be required to
 act in violation of any religious obligations, therefore, is not at all
 obvious.



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   I appreciate Alan's attempt to cabin the divisiveness concept, 
but I wonder whether it works.  Nothing is beyond the scope of political 
decision-making -- there is always the possibility of constitutional amendment, 
and, more importantly, so long as various decisions involve the contested 
interpretation of constitutional language, there is the possibility of using 
political processes to select Justices who will take a different view of the 
matter.  Indeed, my sense is that some of the most prominent political 
divisions along religious lines have come with regard to decisions that aimed 
to take things off the table, but have failed to do so.  Roe v. Wade is the 
classic example, though in some measure the various government speech 
decisions, from the school prayer case onwards, have had that effect as well.



Now it may well be that other decisions have indeed settled matters in 
considerable measure, and thus diminished religious groups' political 
mobilization as religious groups.  But my guess is that it's often not easy to 
predict which creates more mobilization of religious groups as religious 
groups: a particular executive or legislative policy decision, or a Supreme 
Court decision reversing that policy decision.



   Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 7:37 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: RE: Divisiveness



 If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision than 
 Eugene

 is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a decision was

 one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the sense that 
 if

 government could promote religion (or interfere with religion) religious 
 groups

 would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as religious 
 groups

 in order to make sure that it was their faith that the government promoted and

 that it was not their faith that was subject to government interference. 
 Placing a

 church-state issue beyond the scope of political decision-making by 
 subjecting it

 to constitutional constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of

 political/religious divisions.



 There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.



 Alan Brownstein
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Ira Lupu
It is worth recalling that federal RFRA itself was anything but divisive.
 Au contraire.  It passed with overwhelming support from both parties, and
wide support among civil rights and civil liberties groups (with Hobby
Lobby under advisement, some of these groups are now running from RFRA like
it was the plague).

The problem now is not divisiveness, per se.  Like any controversial
Supreme Court decision, some will hate it and others will love it.
 Inevitably, these folks will be divided by their disagreement.

The problem is legitimacy.  Free exercise standards, pre-Smith, were
incredibly plastic -- sometimes you got Yoder, Thomas, or Frazee, and
sometimes you got Goldman, O'Lone, Lyng, and Smith itself (O'Connor's
concurrence).  RFRA codifies the regime of Sherbert-Yoder, but that has
proven in the lower courts to be equally plastic at every turn.  What is a
substantial burden, a compelling interest, a less restrictive means?  Does
RFRA restore U.S. v Lee, including its dictum about commercial actors
accepting relevant regulatory regimes?  Does it restore Braunfeld v. Brown?
 (See the Kagan -- Clement colloquy at oral argument about what RFRA
restores.)

The fussing over state RFRA's recently has reflected the same massive
uncertainty over what they will be held to protect -- wedding vendor
refusal to serve same sex couples?  Employer refusal to provide spousal
benefits to same sex spouses of employees?  Let's just leave it to the
courts (in these cases, state courts) is not reassuring to anyone.

What I fear is that, whatever the outcome in Hobby Lobby, the losers will
never believe that they lost based on any legal principle that will be
applied consistently over time.  Accordingly, they will believe that they
lost only on culture war politics. Religious exemptions present many deep
problems, including judicial appraisal of the religious significance of
particular acts, but this problem of inconsistency (and therefore
illegitimacy) over time seems particularly severe.


On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 11:10 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

I appreciate Alan's attempt to cabin the divisiveness
 concept, but I wonder whether it works.  Nothing is beyond the scope of
 political decision-making -- there is always the possibility of
 constitutional amendment, and, more importantly, so long as various
 decisions involve the contested interpretation of constitutional language,
 there is the possibility of using political processes to select Justices
 who will take a different view of the matter.  Indeed, my sense is that
 some of the most prominent political divisions along religious lines have
 come with regard to decisions that aimed to take things off the table, but
 have failed to do so.  Roe v. Wade is the classic example, though in some
 measure the various government speech decisions, from the school prayer
 case onwards, have had that effect as well.



 Now it may well be that other decisions have indeed settled matters in
 considerable measure, and thus diminished religious groups’ political
 mobilization as religious groups.  But my guess is that it’s often not easy
 to predict which creates more mobilization of religious groups as religious
 groups: a particular executive or legislative policy decision, or a Supreme
 Court decision reversing that policy decision.



Eugene



  -Original Message-

  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

  Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 7:37 PM

  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

  Subject: RE: Divisiveness

 

  If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision
 than Eugene

  is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a
 decision was

  one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the sense
 that if

  government could promote religion (or interfere with religion) religious
 groups

  would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as religious
 groups

  in order to make sure that it was their faith that the government
 promoted and

  that it was not their faith that was subject to government interference.
 Placing a

  church-state issue beyond the scope of political decision-making by
 subjecting it

  to constitutional constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these
 kinds of

  political/religious divisions.

 

  There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

 

  Alan Brownstein

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Ira Lupu
 policy decision, or a Supreme
 Court decision reversing that policy decision.



Eugene



  -Original Message-

  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

  Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 7:37 PM

  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

  Subject: RE: Divisiveness

 

  If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision
 than Eugene

  is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a
 decision was

  one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the
 sense that if

  government could promote religion (or interfere with religion)
 religious groups

  would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as
 religious groups

  in order to make sure that it was their faith that the government
 promoted and

  that it was not their faith that was subject to government
 interference. Placing a

  church-state issue beyond the scope of political decision-making by
 subjecting it

  to constitutional constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these
 kinds of

  political/religious divisions.

 

  There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

 

  Alan Brownstein

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




 --
 Ira C. Lupu
 F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
 George Washington University Law School
 2000 H St., NW
 Washington, DC 20052
 (202)994-7053
 Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government,
 Religious People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
 My SSRN papers are here:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg



 --
 Hillel Y. Levin
 Associate Professor
 University of Georgia
 School of Law
 120 Herty Dr.
 Athens, GA 30602
 (678) 641-7452
 hle...@uga.edu
 hillelle...@gmail.com
 SSRN Author Page:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




-- 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious
People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
 believe that they lost based on any legal principle that will be
 applied consistently over time.  Accordingly, they will believe that they
 lost only on culture war politics. Religious exemptions present many deep
 problems, including judicial appraisal of the religious significance of
 particular acts, but this problem of inconsistency (and therefore
 illegitimacy) over time seems particularly severe.


 On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 11:10 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 wrote:

I appreciate Alan's attempt to cabin the divisiveness
 concept, but I wonder whether it works.  Nothing is beyond the scope of
 political decision-making -- there is always the possibility of
 constitutional amendment, and, more importantly, so long as various
 decisions involve the contested interpretation of constitutional language,
 there is the possibility of using political processes to select Justices
 who will take a different view of the matter.  Indeed, my sense is that
 some of the most prominent political divisions along religious lines have
 come with regard to decisions that aimed to take things off the table, but
 have failed to do so.  Roe v. Wade is the classic example, though in some
 measure the various government speech decisions, from the school prayer
 case onwards, have had that effect as well.



 Now it may well be that other decisions have indeed settled matters in
 considerable measure, and thus diminished religious groups’ political
 mobilization as religious groups.  But my guess is that it’s often not easy
 to predict which creates more mobilization of religious groups as religious
 groups: a particular executive or legislative policy decision, or a Supreme
 Court decision reversing that policy decision.



Eugene



  -Original Message-

  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

  Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 7:37 PM

  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

  Subject: RE: Divisiveness

 

  If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision
 than Eugene

  is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a
 decision was

  one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the
 sense that if

  government could promote religion (or interfere with religion)
 religious groups

  would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as
 religious groups

  in order to make sure that it was their faith that the government
 promoted and

  that it was not their faith that was subject to government
 interference. Placing a

  church-state issue beyond the scope of political decision-making by
 subjecting it

  to constitutional constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these
 kinds of

  political/religious divisions.

 

  There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

 

  Alan Brownstein

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




 --
 Ira C. Lupu
 F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
 George Washington University Law School
 2000 H St., NW
 Washington, DC 20052
 (202)994-7053
 Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government,
 Religious People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
 My SSRN papers are here:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg



 --
 Hillel Y. Levin
 Associate Professor
 University of Georgia
 School of Law
 120 Herty Dr.
 Athens, GA 30602
 (678) 641-7452
 hle...@uga.edu
 hillelle...@gmail.com
 SSRN Author Page:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




 --
 Ira C. Lupu
 F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
 George Washington University Law School
 2000 H St., NW
 Washington, DC 20052
 (202)994-7053
 Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious
 People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
 My SSRN papers are here:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Ira Lupu
 of Sherbert-Yoder, but that has
 proven in the lower courts to be equally plastic at every turn.  What is a
 substantial burden, a compelling interest, a less restrictive means?  Does
 RFRA restore U.S. v Lee, including its dictum about commercial actors
 accepting relevant regulatory regimes?  Does it restore Braunfeld v. Brown?
  (See the Kagan -- Clement colloquy at oral argument about what RFRA
 restores.)

 The fussing over state RFRA's recently has reflected the same massive
 uncertainty over what they will be held to protect -- wedding vendor
 refusal to serve same sex couples?  Employer refusal to provide spousal
 benefits to same sex spouses of employees?  Let's just leave it to the
 courts (in these cases, state courts) is not reassuring to anyone.

 What I fear is that, whatever the outcome in Hobby Lobby, the losers
 will never believe that they lost based on any legal principle that will be
 applied consistently over time.  Accordingly, they will believe that they
 lost only on culture war politics. Religious exemptions present many deep
 problems, including judicial appraisal of the religious significance of
 particular acts, but this problem of inconsistency (and therefore
 illegitimacy) over time seems particularly severe.


 On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 11:10 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 wrote:

I appreciate Alan's attempt to cabin the divisiveness
 concept, but I wonder whether it works.  Nothing is beyond the scope of
 political decision-making -- there is always the possibility of
 constitutional amendment, and, more importantly, so long as various
 decisions involve the contested interpretation of constitutional language,
 there is the possibility of using political processes to select Justices
 who will take a different view of the matter.  Indeed, my sense is that
 some of the most prominent political divisions along religious lines have
 come with regard to decisions that aimed to take things off the table, but
 have failed to do so.  Roe v. Wade is the classic example, though in some
 measure the various government speech decisions, from the school prayer
 case onwards, have had that effect as well.



 Now it may well be that other decisions have indeed settled matters in
 considerable measure, and thus diminished religious groups’ political
 mobilization as religious groups.  But my guess is that it’s often not 
 easy
 to predict which creates more mobilization of religious groups as 
 religious
 groups: a particular executive or legislative policy decision, or a 
 Supreme
 Court decision reversing that policy decision.



Eugene



  -Original Message-

  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

  Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 7:37 PM

  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

  Subject: RE: Divisiveness

 

  If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive
 decision than Eugene

  is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a
 decision was

  one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the
 sense that if

  government could promote religion (or interfere with religion)
 religious groups

  would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as
 religious groups

  in order to make sure that it was their faith that the government
 promoted and

  that it was not their faith that was subject to government
 interference. Placing a

  church-state issue beyond the scope of political decision-making by
 subjecting it

  to constitutional constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these
 kinds of

  political/religious divisions.

 

  There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

 

  Alan Brownstein

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




 --
 Ira C. Lupu
 F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
 George Washington University Law School
 2000 H St., NW
 Washington, DC 20052
 (202)994-7053
 Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government,
 Religious People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
 My SSRN papers are here:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg



 --
 Hillel Y. Levin
 Associate Professor
 University of Georgia
 School of Law
 120 Herty Dr.
 Athens, GA 30602
 (678) 641-7452
 hle...@uga.edu
 hillelle...@gmail.com
 SSRN Author Page:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645


 ___
 To post, send

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   Just to clarify, I see jurisdiction-by-jurisdiction RFRAs as 
implementing what I call a “common-law model”: as with common law defenses, 
privileges, and the like, they (1) leave courts with the first call on whether 
to create an exemption, but (2) allow legislatures to modify or repeal those 
exemptions if they disapprove of the courts’ decisions.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin
Sent: Monday, June 09, 2014 9:59 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Divisiveness

Chip:

I am in total agreement of your analysis, except that I think there is a third 
way. That would be for legislatures to consider religious exemptions when they 
enact individual laws (as they did before Smith, and after as well). The 
results would still be inconsistent over time ((1) sometimes the legislature 
will grant an exception; sometimes it won't; and (2) courts will still have to 
resolve disputes on the margins), but at least they would have a majoritarian 
pedigree on the whole.

We tolerate all kinds of legislative inconsistency because we understand that 
political interests change over time, issues that seem similar may appear 
different at the time of enactment, lobbying groups gain and lose power, the 
legislators themselves change over time, and so on. We don't demand consistency 
of legislators the same way we do of courts. Legislators are allowed to be 
inconsistent (within some broad due process/equality boundaries, I suppose).

We could still quibble about the role of courts in this system. They'll still 
have to resolve some kinds of disputes, no doubt. Which side should they err 
on? Should their guiding principle be to force majoritarian engagement? Reverse 
the burden of legislative inertia? Etc. But at least we would have legislative 
guidance beyond do good stuff when it comes to legislative exceptions, which 
is what RFRA yields. This abdication of policy-making responsibility by 
legislators is indefensible.

Eugene can correct me if I'm mistaken, but I think his proposed common-law 
approach to religious exceptions points in this direction.






On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 12:43 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
It's a very old lesson.  Legislators support vague delegations aimed at some 
general good (clean air, workplace safety, endangered species), and claim 
political credit for doing so.  Then they (or their successors) sit back and 
criticize agencies and courts that have to apply those vague standards to 
specific facts.  Choices made from outside the veil of ignorance are inevitably 
much more difficult than those made from behind it.

But I am making a further point.  The context of religious exemptions -- 
because of all the variations among faiths (beliefs and practices) and all the 
variations among regulatory or other government contexts in which conflicts may 
arise, is uniquely vulnerable to the problem of irreconcilable inconsistency 
over time.  We can have a regime of no exemptions under these kind of general 
standards, or a regime of ad hoc, we know it when we see it, all things 
considered, interest-balancing exemptions (that is, a regime that will appear 
lawless when scrutinized over time).  I don't think there is any other choice.  
RFRA represents the latter choice, but (especially in a case made prominent by 
its culture war salience) the judicial outcome will inevitably be seen as an 
act of bad faith by the losers (whichever side that is).

On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 12:29 PM, Hillel Y. Levin 
hillelle...@gmail.commailto:hillelle...@gmail.com wrote:
What's ironic to me is that the same legislators (I.e. All of them) who attack 
the courts for overreaching and making policy-decisions chose to bestow immense 
policy-making power on those same courts through RFRA. There's a legislative 
process lesson in there somewhere.


On Monday, June 9, 2014, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
It is worth recalling that federal RFRA itself was anything but divisive.  Au 
contraire.  It passed with overwhelming support from both parties, and wide 
support among civil rights and civil liberties groups (with Hobby Lobby under 
advisement, some of these groups are now running from RFRA like it was the 
plague).

The problem now is not divisiveness, per se.  Like any controversial Supreme 
Court decision, some will hate it and others will love it.  Inevitably, these 
folks will be divided by their disagreement.

The problem is legitimacy.  Free exercise standards, pre-Smith, were incredibly 
plastic -- sometimes you got Yoder, Thomas, or Frazee, and sometimes you got 
Goldman, O'Lone, Lyng, and Smith itself (O'Connor's concurrence).  RFRA 
codifies the regime of Sherbert-Yoder, but that has proven in the lower courts 
to be equally plastic at every turn.  What is a substantial burden, a 
compelling interest

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
 may arise, is uniquely vulnerable to the problem of
 irreconcilable inconsistency over time.  We can have a regime of no
 exemptions under these kind of general standards, or a regime of ad hoc, we
 know it when we see it, all things considered, interest-balancing
 exemptions (that is, a regime that will appear lawless when scrutinized
 over time).  I don't think there is any other choice.  RFRA represents the
 latter choice, but (especially in a case made prominent by its culture war
 salience) the judicial outcome will inevitably be seen as an act of bad
 faith by the losers (whichever side that is).


 On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 12:29 PM, Hillel Y. Levin hillelle...@gmail.com
 wrote:

 What's ironic to me is that the same legislators (I.e. All of them) who
 attack the courts for overreaching and making policy-decisions chose to
 bestow immense policy-making power on those same courts through RFRA.
 There's a legislative process lesson in there somewhere.


 On Monday, June 9, 2014, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 It is worth recalling that federal RFRA itself was anything but
 divisive.  Au contraire.  It passed with overwhelming support from both
 parties, and wide support among civil rights and civil liberties groups
 (with Hobby Lobby under advisement, some of these groups are now running
 from RFRA like it was the plague).

 The problem now is not divisiveness, per se.  Like any controversial
 Supreme Court decision, some will hate it and others will love it.
  Inevitably, these folks will be divided by their disagreement.

 The problem is legitimacy.  Free exercise standards, pre-Smith, were
 incredibly plastic -- sometimes you got Yoder, Thomas, or Frazee, and
 sometimes you got Goldman, O'Lone, Lyng, and Smith itself (O'Connor's
 concurrence).  RFRA codifies the regime of Sherbert-Yoder, but that has
 proven in the lower courts to be equally plastic at every turn.  What is a
 substantial burden, a compelling interest, a less restrictive means?  Does
 RFRA restore U.S. v Lee, including its dictum about commercial actors
 accepting relevant regulatory regimes?  Does it restore Braunfeld v. 
 Brown?
  (See the Kagan -- Clement colloquy at oral argument about what RFRA
 restores.)

 The fussing over state RFRA's recently has reflected the same massive
 uncertainty over what they will be held to protect -- wedding vendor
 refusal to serve same sex couples?  Employer refusal to provide spousal
 benefits to same sex spouses of employees?  Let's just leave it to the
 courts (in these cases, state courts) is not reassuring to anyone.

 What I fear is that, whatever the outcome in Hobby Lobby, the losers
 will never believe that they lost based on any legal principle that will 
 be
 applied consistently over time.  Accordingly, they will believe that they
 lost only on culture war politics. Religious exemptions present many deep
 problems, including judicial appraisal of the religious significance of
 particular acts, but this problem of inconsistency (and therefore
 illegitimacy) over time seems particularly severe.


 On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 11:10 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 wrote:

I appreciate Alan's attempt to cabin the
 divisiveness concept, but I wonder whether it works.  Nothing is beyond
 the scope of political decision-making -- there is always the possibility
 of constitutional amendment, and, more importantly, so long as various
 decisions involve the contested interpretation of constitutional 
 language,
 there is the possibility of using political processes to select Justices
 who will take a different view of the matter.  Indeed, my sense is that
 some of the most prominent political divisions along religious lines have
 come with regard to decisions that aimed to take things off the table, 
 but
 have failed to do so.  Roe v. Wade is the classic example, though in some
 measure the various government speech decisions, from the school prayer
 case onwards, have had that effect as well.



 Now it may well be that other decisions have indeed settled matters
 in considerable measure, and thus diminished religious groups’ political
 mobilization as religious groups.  But my guess is that it’s often not 
 easy
 to predict which creates more mobilization of religious groups as 
 religious
 groups: a particular executive or legislative policy decision, or a 
 Supreme
 Court decision reversing that policy decision.



Eugene



  -Original Message-

  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

  Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 7:37 PM

  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

  Subject: RE: Divisiveness

 

  If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive
 decision than Eugene

  is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a
 decision was

  one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the
 sense that if

  government

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Douglas Laycock
It would take an empirical study of the cases under each statute to confirm 
Hillel’s intuition that the ADA cases are less more consistent than the RFRA 
cases. My intuition would be the opposite – that the cases are probably equally 
inconsistent at least in the beginning, and quite possibly permanently. And if 
the ADA cases have become more consistent over time, it is only because there 
are so many more of them. 

 

Both statutes leave individual applications to the courts because individual 
applications are far too varied for the legislature to deal with. And in the 
RFRA context, there is the additional problem that it is almost impossible for 
legislators to act on principal with respect to unpopular religions. Enacting a 
general standard, and not addressing individual applications, was treated as a 
matter of high principle in the discussions leading to RFRA.

 

The fundamental problem for both RFRA and the ADA is not just that they 
inevitably leave a range of discretion to judges, but also that some judges 
believe in the policy of the statute, and some do not. Each statute attempts to 
address the special needs of a minority group, and each imposes some costs on 
others. Those who are irritated or outraged by one of these statutes are rarely 
the same people who are irritated or outraged by the other. Each statute has 
experienced sympathetic interpretations and hostile interpretations, and it 
takes a lot of consistent appellate decisions to generate consistently 
sympathetic (or, not legitimate but nearly as likely) consistently hostile 
interpretations. And with RFRA, there just aren’t enough cases to generate such 
a body of appellate decisions. Hobby Lobby will the Court’s second opinion 
interpreting the Act in its 21 years of existence.

 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin
Sent: Monday, June 09, 2014 12:59 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Divisiveness

 

Chip:

 

I am in total agreement of your analysis, except that I think there is a third 
way. That would be for legislatures to consider religious exemptions when they 
enact individual laws (as they did before Smith, and after as well). The 
results would still be inconsistent over time ((1) sometimes the legislature 
will grant an exception; sometimes it won't; and (2) courts will still have to 
resolve disputes on the margins), but at least they would have a majoritarian 
pedigree on the whole.

 

We tolerate all kinds of legislative inconsistency because we understand that 
political interests change over time, issues that seem similar may appear 
different at the time of enactment, lobbying groups gain and lose power, the 
legislators themselves change over time, and so on. We don't demand consistency 
of legislators the same way we do of courts. Legislators are allowed to be 
inconsistent (within some broad due process/equality boundaries, I suppose).

 

We could still quibble about the role of courts in this system. They'll still 
have to resolve some kinds of disputes, no doubt. Which side should they err 
on? Should their guiding principle be to force majoritarian engagement? Reverse 
the burden of legislative inertia? Etc. But at least we would have legislative 
guidance beyond do good stuff when it comes to legislative exceptions, which 
is what RFRA yields. This abdication of policy-making responsibility by 
legislators is indefensible.

 

Eugene can correct me if I'm mistaken, but I think his proposed common-law 
approach to religious exceptions points in this direction.

 

 

 

 

 

 

On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 12:43 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu 
mailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu  wrote:

It's a very old lesson.  Legislators support vague delegations aimed at some 
general good (clean air, workplace safety, endangered species), and claim 
political credit for doing so.  Then they (or their successors) sit back and 
criticize agencies and courts that have to apply those vague standards to 
specific facts.  Choices made from outside the veil of ignorance are inevitably 
much more difficult than those made from behind it.

 

But I am making a further point.  The context of religious exemptions -- 
because of all the variations among faiths (beliefs and practices) and all the 
variations among regulatory or other government contexts in which conflicts may 
arise, is uniquely vulnerable to the problem of irreconcilable inconsistency 
over time.  We can have a regime of no exemptions under these kind of general 
standards, or a regime of ad hoc, we know it when we see it, all things 
considered, interest-balancing exemptions (that is, a regime that will appear 
lawless when scrutinized over time).  I don't think there is any other choice.  
RFRA

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Ira Lupu
The first SCOTUS opinion interpreting RFRA was O Centro (2006), which was
unanimous, demanding in its statutory application, and a resounding defeat
for the government.  O Centro surprised quite a few of us.
A student Note at 95 U. Va. L. Rev. 1281 (2009) argues that O Centro did
little to affect the ways in which the Courts of Appeals construed RFRA.
 My own research of decisions suggests that little has changed since 2009.
 Contraceptive mandate cases aside, RFRA claimants rarely win.  Of course,
a weakly construed RFRA is not necessarily an inconsistently applied RFRA.
 But if Hobby Lobby generates strong constructions of RFRA, and lower
courts go back to business as usual in RFRA cases not involving the
Affordable Care Act, the inference of lawless application of RFRA over time
will not be abated.


On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 2:09 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

 It would take an empirical study of the cases under each statute to
 confirm Hillel’s intuition that the ADA cases are less more consistent than
 the RFRA cases. My intuition would be the opposite – that the cases are
 probably equally inconsistent at least in the beginning, and quite possibly
 permanently. And if the ADA cases have become more consistent over time, it
 is only because there are so many more of them.



 Both statutes leave individual applications to the courts because
 individual applications are far too varied for the legislature to deal
 with. And in the RFRA context, there is the additional problem that it is
 almost impossible for legislators to act on principal with respect to
 unpopular religions. Enacting a general standard, and not addressing
 individual applications, was treated as a matter of high principle in the
 discussions leading to RFRA.



 The fundamental problem for both RFRA and the ADA is not just that they
 inevitably leave a range of discretion to judges, but also that some judges
 believe in the policy of the statute, and some do not. Each statute
 attempts to address the special needs of a minority group, and each imposes
 some costs on others. Those who are irritated or outraged by one of these
 statutes are rarely the same people who are irritated or outraged by the
 other. Each statute has experienced sympathetic interpretations and hostile
 interpretations, and it takes a lot of consistent appellate decisions to
 generate consistently sympathetic (or, not legitimate but nearly as likely)
 consistently hostile interpretations. And with RFRA, there just aren’t
 enough cases to generate such a body of appellate decisions.* Hobby Lobby*
 will the Court’s second opinion interpreting the Act in its 21 years of
 existence.





 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Hillel Y. Levin
 *Sent:* Monday, June 09, 2014 12:59 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Divisiveness



 Chip:



 I am in total agreement of your analysis, except that I think there is a
 third way. That would be for legislatures to consider religious exemptions
 when they enact individual laws (as they did before Smith, and after as
 well). The results would still be inconsistent over time ((1) sometimes the
 legislature will grant an exception; sometimes it won't; and (2) courts
 will still have to resolve disputes on the margins), but at least they
 would have a majoritarian pedigree on the whole.



 We tolerate all kinds of legislative inconsistency because we understand
 that political interests change over time, issues that seem similar may
 appear different at the time of enactment, lobbying groups gain and lose
 power, the legislators themselves change over time, and so on. We don't
 demand consistency of legislators the same way we do of courts. Legislators
 are allowed to be inconsistent (within some broad due process/equality
 boundaries, I suppose).



 We could still quibble about the role of courts in this system. They'll
 still have to resolve some kinds of disputes, no doubt. Which side should
 they err on? Should their guiding principle be to force majoritarian
 engagement? Reverse the burden of legislative inertia? Etc. But at least we
 would have legislative guidance beyond do good stuff when it comes to
 legislative exceptions, which is what RFRA yields. This abdication of
 policy-making responsibility by legislators is indefensible.



 Eugene can correct me if I'm mistaken, but I think his proposed common-law
 approach to religious exceptions points in this direction.













 On Mon, Jun 9, 2014 at 12:43 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 It's a very old lesson.  Legislators support vague delegations aimed at
 some general good (clean air, workplace safety, endangered species), and
 claim political credit for doing so

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread mallamud
I agree with Alan's statement below, stated better than I did.  I would 
add that we now do/should include the nones within the system.


   Jon

On 2014-06-08 22:36, Alan Brownstein wrote:

If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision
than Eugene is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was
whether a decision was one that provoked political divisions along
religious lines in the sense that if government could promote 
religion
(or interfere with religion) religious groups would have an 
additional

incentive to organize and mobilize as religious groups in order to
make sure that it was their faith that the government promoted and
that it was not their faith that was subject to government
interference. Placing a church-state issue beyond the scope of
political decision-making by subjecting it to constitutional
constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of
political/religious divisions.

There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

Alan Brownstein














From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
[vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:54 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Divisiveness

I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most
controversies, both sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be
labeled as divisive.  Government religious speech may be seen as
divisive, because it may alienate members of other religious 
groups;

but prohibitions on such speech, or litigation seeking such
prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A pro-Hobby-Lobby
decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision might be
divisive.  Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision
(or an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the
implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, as
Tom points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen
as divisive -- but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which
makes controversial judicially implemented religious accommodations
possible, can apparently be divisive, too.

Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally
here, and not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the
potential divisiveness of decisions they dislike on substantive
grounds, but don't even notice the divisiveness of decisions they
think are sound.  After all, if one thinks a decision is sound, it's
easy to view those who disagree as just unreasonable, so that their
feelings of alienation don't really count (since they deserved to
lose, and are now just being sore losers).

Of course,

Eugene

Tom Berg writes:

I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a 
ruling for Hobby
Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) 
substantively wrong.
One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being 
divisive
(undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate 
in the first
place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness 
should do

only very limited work in religion cases.)

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can
(rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can
(rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread Steven Jamar
“nones”? 
Huh.  I knew that was a thing, but didn’t really expect to see it here.

Steve

On Jun 9, 2014, at 4:49 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:

 I agree with Alan's statement below, stated better than I did.  I would add 
 that we now do/should include the nones within the system.
 
   Jon
 
 On 2014-06-08 22:36, Alan Brownstein wrote:
 If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision
 than Eugene is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was
 whether a decision was one that provoked political divisions along
 religious lines in the sense that if government could promote religion
 (or interfere with religion) religious groups would have an additional
 incentive to organize and mobilize as religious groups in order to
 make sure that it was their faith that the government promoted and
 that it was not their faith that was subject to government
 interference. Placing a church-state issue beyond the scope of
 political decision-making by subjecting it to constitutional
 constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of
 political/religious divisions.
 
 There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.
 
 Alan Brownstein
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
 [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:54 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Divisiveness
 
I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most
 controversies, both sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be
 labeled as divisive.  Government religious speech may be seen as
 divisive, because it may alienate members of other religious groups;
 but prohibitions on such speech, or litigation seeking such
 prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A pro-Hobby-Lobby
 decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision might be
 divisive.  Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision
 (or an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the
 implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, as
 Tom points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen
 as divisive -- but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which
 makes controversial judicially implemented religious accommodations
 possible, can apparently be divisive, too.
 
Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally
 here, and not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the
 potential divisiveness of decisions they dislike on substantive
 grounds, but don't even notice the divisiveness of decisions they
 think are sound.  After all, if one thinks a decision is sound, it's
 easy to view those who disagree as just unreasonable, so that their
 feelings of alienation don't really count (since they deserved to
 lose, and are now just being sore losers).
 
Of course,
 
Eugene
 
 Tom Berg writes:
 
 I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for 
 Hobby
 Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively 
 wrong.
 One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being 
 divisive
 (undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the 
 first
 place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should 
 do
 only very limited work in religion cases.)
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can
 (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can
 (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.


-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar  

Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-09 Thread mallamud
There is some authority for not preferring religion over non-religion.  
I do not think religious people should get exemptions reasons not 
connected to the practice of their religion (church services, prayer, 
lighting candles, sacrificing chickens etc.) To me many requests sound 
like I think it is wrong for religious reasons and therefore other 
people should not engage in that behavior.  E.g. I will not pay my taxes 
because taxes pay for killing people.  No one is asking the owners of 
Hobby Lobby to engage in activities that they believe offend their 
religion; they are seeking not to pay employees in such a way that 
certain contraceptives would be covered.  The decision to use or not use 
the contraceptives is the employees'.  One difficulty is that the courts 
are loath to inquire into to the closeness of the connection of the 
claim to the religious belief.  But without limits exemptions will 
become legion.


Exemptions usually involve some unfairness.  That would be mitigated if 
religious exemptions were limited to the actual practice of religion 
rather than attempts to impose beliefs on others through refusing to 
comply with general laws. Smith is a good example and, as we know, does 
not stop you from sacrificing chickens because people in the community 
are offended.  Take it outside the church or home and give exemptions to 
general laws and that will create problems if the exemptions become wide 
enough to make it seem that religious folks have general privileges in 
society that secular folks do not.  Cf. Affirmative action.


I noted previously Scalia's citation (in during oral argument) of the 
overwhelming majority extending the VRA as evidence that the law was not 
carefully considered. During RFRA's passage and thereafter I focused on 
conservatives articulating the issue as one in which the Supreme Court 
disrespected religion, and those on the other side of the spectrum 
articulated the Smith decision as having disrespected constitutional 
rights.  From discussion about Scalia with lawyers and non-lawyers, I 
cannot help thinking that a dislike of Scalia contributed to one side's 
support of RFRA.


   Jon


On 2014-06-09 17:00, Steven Jamar wrote:

“nones”?
Huh.  I knew that was a thing, but didn’t really expect to see it 
here.


Steve

On Jun 9, 2014, at 4:49 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu 
wrote:


I agree with Alan's statement below, stated better than I did.  I 
would add that we now do/should include the nones within the system.


  Jon

On 2014-06-08 22:36, Alan Brownstein wrote:
If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive 
decision

than Eugene is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was
whether a decision was one that provoked political divisions along
religious lines in the sense that if government could promote 
religion
(or interfere with religion) religious groups would have an 
additional

incentive to organize and mobilize as religious groups in order to
make sure that it was their faith that the government promoted and
that it was not their faith that was subject to government
interference. Placing a church-state issue beyond the scope of
political decision-making by subjecting it to constitutional
constraints avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of
political/religious divisions.

There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

Alan Brownstein














From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
[vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:54 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Divisiveness

   I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most
controversies, both sides are acting in ways that could plausibly 
be

labeled as divisive.  Government religious speech may be seen as
divisive, because it may alienate members of other religious 
groups;

but prohibitions on such speech, or litigation seeking such
prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A pro-Hobby-Lobby
decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision might 
be

divisive.  Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision
(or an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was 
the
implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, 
as
Tom points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be 
seen

as divisive -- but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which
makes controversial judicially implemented religious accommodations
possible, can apparently be divisive, too.

   Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally
here, and not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the
potential divisiveness of decisions they dislike on substantive
grounds, but don't even notice the divisiveness of decisions they
think are sound.  After all, if one 

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Whoops, hit enter too early -- please disregard the Of course,.

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:55 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Divisiveness
 
   I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most controversies, both
 sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be labeled as divisive.
 Government religious speech may be seen as divisive, because it may alienate
 members of other religious groups; but prohibitions on such speech, or 
 litigation
 seeking such prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A pro-Hobby-Lobby
 decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision might be 
 divisive.
 Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision (or an anti-Hobby-
 Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the implementation of the
 mandate without a broad religious exemption, as Tom points out.  The
 Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen as divisive -- but the RFRA
 regime, or the Sherbert regime, which makes controversial judicially
 implemented religious accommodations possible, can apparently be divisive,
 too.
 
   Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally here, and not
 with a focus on this list -- can easily see the potential divisiveness of 
 decisions
 they dislike on substantive grounds, but don't even notice the divisiveness of
 decisions they think are sound.  After all, if one thinks a decision is 
 sound, it's
 easy to view those who disagree as just unreasonable, so that their feelings 
 of
 alienation don't really count (since they deserved to lose, and are now just 
 being
 sore losers).
 
   Of course,
 
   Eugene
 
 Tom Berg writes:
 
  I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling
  for Hobby Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly)
 substantively wrong.
  One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being 
  divisive
  (undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in
  the first place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about
  divisiveness should do only very limited work in religion cases.)
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe,
 change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Divisiveness

2014-06-08 Thread mallamud
I am not suggesting that divisiveness should be a rule of decision.  
Rather the purpose of the religion clauses is to allow people with 
strong, differing views live together in reasonable harmony.  Thus in 
interpreting religious exemptions the Court needs to keep that principle 
in mind.  Perhaps the Hobby Lobby decision itself is not important, but 
it will set a precedent.  As far as I am concerned medical insurance 
provided by the employer is compensation and the employer should not be 
able to limit an employee's use of compensation. If the religious view 
that enabling someone else to get an abortion, or birth control that the 
employer, but not the medical profession, regards as abortion, then 
almost any arguably religious based claim must be upheld.  That, I 
suggest, would give people defining their own religious beliefs an 
exemption to interfere with the rights of others.  And a country where 
religious people, but not others, need not obey the general laws of the 
land is not the way to help the religious and the non-religious live 
together in reasonable peace.  So what I am talking about is not the 
consequences of any one decision, but of a general interpretation of 
religious exemptions.


I do realize that Congress has the right to enact federal law with 
exceptions, but as with conscientious objection, I do not think it is 
proper to treat non-religious people unequally.  I have never seen an 
argument that the due process clause limits the religion clauses 
although I have seen equal protection reasoning use in free speech 
cases.


Someone (maybe off-list) suggested that treating for-profit companies 
like non-profit groups and allowing them to put the cost of coverage on 
the insurance companies on the theory that there is no significant cost 
to the companies of covering contraception would solve the problem.  But 
as I understand it, the Little Sisters of the Poor will not certify that 
they have a religious objection to covering abortion because that 
certification would facilitate their employees in obtaining such 
services.


Finally, I realize that there are many other problems with other 
freedoms stemming from mandated health insurance coverage.  For example, 
should employers be allowed to refuse to hire smokers, or people who eat 
junk food, or who drink the Big Gulp at fast food places?  There was a 
case argued before the NY Court of Appeals last week about whether the 
Board of Health in New York City had the power to prohibit serving sodas 
in containers larger than a specified size.  But I realize this goes 
beyond the list. To avoid an inconsistency argument  in stating that 
employers should not control the use of compensation by employees based 
on the employers' religious views I mention this.  I know there might be 
competing considerations in other areas.  And I am not taking a position 
on them now.


   Jon

On 2014-06-08 19:54, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most controversies,
both sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be labeled as
divisive.  Government religious speech may be seen as divisive,
because it may alienate members of other religious groups; but
prohibitions on such speech, or litigation seeking such prohibition,
may be as divisive or more so.  A pro-Hobby-Lobby decision might be
divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision might be divisive.  
Indeed,

academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision (or an
anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the
implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, as
Tom points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen
as divisive -- but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which
makes controversial judicially implemented religious accommodations
possible, can apparently be divisive, too.

Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally here, and
not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the potential
divisiveness of decisions they dislike on substantive grounds, but
don't even notice the divisiveness of decisions they think are sound.
After all, if one thinks a decision is sound, it's easy to view those
who disagree as just unreasonable, so that their feelings of
alienation don't really count (since they deserved to lose, and are
now just being sore losers).

Of course,

Eugene

Tom Berg writes:

I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a 
ruling for Hobby
Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) 
substantively wrong.
One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being 
divisive
(undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate 
in the first
place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness 
should do

only very limited work in religion cases.)

___
To post, send message to 

RE: Divisiveness

2014-06-08 Thread Alan Brownstein
If divisive means that people will be upset by a substantive decision than 
Eugene is clearly correct. I have always thought the issue was whether a 
decision was one that provoked political divisions along religious lines in the 
sense that if government could promote religion (or interfere with religion) 
religious groups would have an additional incentive to organize and mobilize as 
religious groups in order to make sure that it was their faith that the 
government promoted and that it was not their faith that was subject to 
government interference. Placing a church-state issue beyond the scope of 
political decision-making by subjecting it to constitutional constraints 
avoided (or at least mitigated) these kinds of political/religious divisions. 

There is probably a better term for this concern than divisiveness.

Alan Brownstein














From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 08, 2014 4:54 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Divisiveness

I agree very much with Tom on this point.  In most controversies, both 
sides are acting in ways that could plausibly be labeled as divisive.  
Government religious speech may be seen as divisive, because it may alienate 
members of other religious groups; but prohibitions on such speech, or 
litigation seeking such prohibition, may be as divisive or more so.  A 
pro-Hobby-Lobby decision might be divisive, but an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision 
might be divisive.  Indeed, academic criticism of a pro-Hobby-Lobby decision 
(or an anti-Hobby-Lobby decision) might be divisive -- and so was the 
implementation of the mandate without a broad religious exemption, as Tom 
points out.  The Employment Division v. Smith regime can be seen as divisive -- 
but the RFRA regime, or the Sherbert regime, which makes controversial 
judicially implemented religious accommodations possible, can apparently be 
divisive, too.

Indeed, in my experience, most people -- I speak generally here, and 
not with a focus on this list -- can easily see the potential divisiveness of 
decisions they dislike on substantive grounds, but don't even notice the 
divisiveness of decisions they think are sound.  After all, if one thinks a 
decision is sound, it's easy to view those who disagree as just unreasonable, 
so that their feelings of alienation don't really count (since they deserved to 
lose, and are now just being sore losers).

Of course,

Eugene

Tom Berg writes:

 I get those arguments, but they don't really seem to rest on a ruling for 
 Hobby
 Lobby being divisive--they rest on it being (assertedly) substantively 
 wrong.
 One could just as easily charge the Obama administration with being divisive
 (undermining harmony, to use Jon's term) by adopting the mandate in the 
 first
 place. (See Rick Garnett's piece on why arguments about divisiveness should do
 only very limited work in religion cases.)
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Divisiveness as an Establishment Clause test

2009-03-29 Thread Christopher Lund
Got it.  And in addition to being speculative, maybe it's also
incommensurable in the sense that the sort of division created by the
no-religious-speech rule is different in kind than (and not easily
measured against) the sort of division that would be created by allowing
religious speech.  But I get what you're saying.  And maybe you're being
merciful to let me escape the divisiveness fight with a draw.
 
I guess I just think that it's sometimes easy to underestimate the
problems caused by governmental religious speech.  Perhaps Chief Justice
Burger in Marsh did that; I doubt he could have possibly foreseen the
various problems that having legislative prayer would create.  So, like
you, I guess I don't think divisiveness cuts only one way.  And, in part
for that reason, I too wouldn't make divisiveness the touchstone.
 
Best,
Chris
 
__
Christopher C. Lund
Assistant Professor of Law
Mississippi College School of Law
151 E. Griffith St.
Jackson, MS  39201
(601) 925-7141 (office)
(601) 925-7113 (fax)
Papers: http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=363402


 vol...@law.ucla.edu 3/28/2009 9:52 AM 

I'm not suggesting that avoiding religious divisiveness should be
the Establishment Clause test.  Rather, I was arguing against Chip's
suggestion that religious divisiveness ought to be the test, or perhaps
ought to be at least a justification for the no-religious-speech rule
(there are far more powerful and persuasive arguments against
permitting government to express religious sentiments, especially highly
sectarian ones.  First, there is the age-old problem of destructive
fights over whose sentiments will prevail.).  If there are other
arguments against certain government action, whether religious speech or
coercion of religious practice, that's just fine -- in fact, I might
well agree with some.  But divisiveness strikes me both as (1) extremely
speculative, and (2) often cutting in the opposite direction from the
way it has been asserted by some courts and commentators.

As to the empirical question of legislative prayer, my conjecture
is that an entirely nonjudicialized legislative prayer system -- as
opposed to the post-Marsh one, in which there are routine challenges
based on the theological content of the prayer or the way the prayer
program is administered -- would yield to fairly little friction, and
outrage only among a relatively few people who are deeply engaged in
the issue.  And certainly we see that outside legislative prayer, there
was a vast amount of outrage (and resulting divisiveness), in my view
addressed not just at the courts but also at those religious (or
nonreligious) groups that were seeking the change, with regard to the
Pledge decision, the school prayer decisions, and other decisions.  But
I agree that this is indeed highly tenuous speculation, which sounds
like good reason not to make divisiveness be the focus.

Eugene


Christopher Lund writes:

Professor Volokh's empirical statement might be true.  But what if it
is also true about coercion?  Perhaps division might be reduced if
government could coerce religiously.  I think the Innerchange litigation
was far more controversial than the program; maybe prisons should be
able to freely give prisoners benefits if they convert to Christianity. 
And allowing coercion may not mean jail time for anyone.  The same
political process that stops the more polarizing sort of endorsements
will also check the harsher forms of governmental coercion.  When
Professor Volokh asked, What if Establishment Clause has proven more
divisive than the problems it was supposed to solve? - what if that's
true for the Establishment Clause wholesale, and not just the
endorsement part of it?
 
As for the empirics, the counterfactual that Professor Volokh suggests
- what would our world be like if government could endorse religion? -
is obviously hard to run with the endorsement rule still in place.  But
we've run it with legislative prayer.  And I think it's been pretty bad
for religious liberty: Believers kept out of the rotation because of
their minority affiliations, listeners outraged by denominational
prayer, speakers outraged by being told not to pray in denominational
terms, elections decided on the basis of some legislative prayer issue. 
All of this, as Doug said, totally gratuitous to governance.  Of course,
maybe the situation would be worse if Marsh had been decided the other
way.  It's impossible to say for sure, but I think there is reason to
doubt that claim.  There would have been some hostility to the Supreme
Court, of course.  But it would have been directed mostly at the Court,
right?  And how much more additional hostility above
Engel/Schempp/Stone?  And wouldn't that hostility have tended to
diminish in the years that followed?  It's 25 years after Marsh, and in
terms of division, I sense that legislative prayer is only just getting
started.
 
Best,
Chris
 
__
Christopher C.