Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Marci Hamilton
Richard's point is fair so let me provide some more context that perhaps would 
be helpful.   

Privileges are concoctions of positive law dealing w what information can be 
excluded in the judicial process.   The confessional privilege is no different 
than the attorney client privilege or the spousal  privilege on that score.  
Every faith invokes it or tries to to avoid disclosing legally damaging 
evidence in the judicial process.  The RCC and LDS are the most active in 
lobbying to expand it in the state legislatures.

  It is always invoked in clergy sex abuse cases and to avoid mandatory 
reporting of child sex abuse.  Courts have had to struggle w the distinction 
between counseling and confession for salvation purposes, because when laws are 
violated, the exclusion of relevant evidence is to be avoided.   The privilege, 
depending on the state, belongs to the confessor or confessee and always can be 
waived but how differs state to state.  It is routinely waived if the content 
is disclosed outside the one-on-one confession. 

It is also routinely invoked to conceal information that was obtained outside 
the confessional.   

It is my view that there should be an exception to it that parallels the 
attorney client exception for future crimes or fraud.   And that it should not 
be an exception to mandatory reporting of child sex abuse.   The privilege is a 
permissive accommodation that we have learned has a corrosive effect on 
children, families, churches, and society.   Under Smith it is not required and 
under a RFRA analysis it should not overcome the needs of the judicial process 
or  mandatory reporting laws.  

I offer these examples to contextualize the discussion.   It only matters when  
it is alleged a law has been broken so that  law should be the starting point 
for discourse.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 6, 2013, at 11:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu 
wrote:

 As I’ve said earlier, I’m sympathetic to Richard’s argument  inasmuch as 
 confession is in fact part of a complex (required) sacramental process.  But 
 the point is that (I think) that’s relatively unusual, certainly not present, 
 so far as I am aware, in Judaism, for example.  Am I correct in believing 
 that the ingestion of peyote was in fact a sacramental aspect of the Native 
 American church?
  
 sandy
  
 From: religionlaw-bounces+slevinson=law.utexas@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-bounces+slevinson=law.utexas@lists.ucla.edu] On 
 Behalf Of Richard Dougherty
 Sent: Friday, December 06, 2013 6:09 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 I will confess to not having read the state cases, or at least not most of 
 them.  But isn't the question whether the privilege is constitutionally 
 required?  (Perhaps the fact that it is referred to as a privilege muddies 
 the waters.)  If free exercise of religion includes receiving a sacrament, 
 then why is compelling violation of the privilege not a constitutional issue? 
  Indeed, I wonder why a recent discussion suggested stronger free speech 
 claims than free exercise claims; does the First Amendment make that 
 distinction?  I have no doubt courts have read it that way, but that's partly 
 why we get distortions of free exercise claims masquerading as free speech 
 claims.
  
 Richard Dougherty
 University of Dallas
  
 
 On Fri, Dec 6, 2013 at 1:17 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 With all due respect to this entire thread, how many people have actually 
 read the state cases involving the priest-penitent privilege?  There is a 
 level of abstraction
 to this discussion that indicates to me probably not.  As someone who has 
 actively been involved in arguing the issue in court in the last year, I'd 
 suggest that the law is
 more reticulated and specific. state-by-state, than the speculation going on 
 here.  It is state law, which means 50 states plus DC law, and it is a 
 privilege that is not constitutionally required,
 particularly when the issue is whether the religious confessor or confessee 
 engaged in illegal behavior. 
  
  
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Fri, Dec 6, 2013 10:06 am
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
 
 Again, I’m late—sorry about that.  But honestly people, it’s shocking how 
 many posts are written between the hours of 9 p.m. and 7 a.m.  Who can keep 
 up?
  
 So this may backtrack, but I’ve been thinking about the earlier posts in this 
 thread.  Say there are no secular analogies to the 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Douglas Laycock
I think the history of the privilege is that it was first protected for
Catholics, because of its sacramental nature and the very strong teaching,
and then extended to other faiths by analogy and to avoid what looked to
some like denominational discrimination. I'm pretty sure about that
chronology; I'm inferring the causation without having done the historical
work to verify it. 

 

The peyote service is the central act of worship in the Native American
Church; I don't know if they use the word sacrament. But Smith and Black
(the other plaintiff) were not members of the church; they were exploring. 

 

It is generally illusory to enact toleration, and say that religious
minorities can live among you, if you then prosecute them for acts essential
to their faith. The force of that point is weaker with respect to less
important religious practices, although I think it never goes to zero. 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Friday, December 06, 2013 11:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

 

As I've said earlier, I'm sympathetic to Richard's argument  inasmuch as
confession is in fact part of a complex (required) sacramental process.  But
the point is that (I think) that's relatively unusual, certainly not
present, so far as I am aware, in Judaism, for example.  Am I correct in
believing that the ingestion of peyote was in fact a sacramental aspect of
the Native American church?

 

sandy

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Richard Dougherty
I much appreciate Marci's comments.  From the point of view of the free
exercise of religion, the question for the believer, in my view, is what
the effect of the revelation of confidential information is on the soul of
the penitent, not what the legal consequences might be.  Obviously the
state has other concerns, but they need not clash, except at the margins
(though that's what really counts).  I agree that the fall-out of the abuse
crisis in the Catholic Church has seen some try to claim privilege where no
legitimate claim of privilege seems to be at stake.  The dangers of doing
so are multiple -- most importantly, more people are put at risk of future
abuse, but it also undermines legitimate claims of privilege, as those
entrusted with making judgments about its legitimacy find it harder to
distinguish the genuine from the spurious.  I'm not convinced that
discussions in diocesan chanceries about how to avoid losses in court are
part of the free exercise of religion.

The abuse crisis in contemporary America (not, of course, confined to the
Catholic Church) is painful for what it has done to so many who have
suffered, and it has been devastating for the Church.  Almost all of what I
have seen has nothing to do with Confession or free exercise of religion,
though, and here I support Marci's strong view of holding responsible those
who have enabled abusers; while this would likely prevent subsequent abuse
-- the most important consequence -- it would have the side effect of
calling Catholics to abide by their own beliefs.

Richard Dougherty
University of Dallas


On Sat, Dec 7, 2013 at 7:45 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

 Richard's point is fair so let me provide some more context that perhaps
 would be helpful.

 Privileges are concoctions of positive law dealing w what information can
 be excluded in the judicial process.   The confessional privilege is no
 different than the attorney client privilege or the spousal  privilege on
 that score.  Every faith invokes it or tries to to avoid disclosing legally
 damaging evidence in the judicial process.  The RCC and LDS are the most
 active in lobbying to expand it in the state legislatures.

   It is always invoked in clergy sex abuse cases and to avoid mandatory
 reporting of child sex abuse.  Courts have had to struggle w the
 distinction between counseling and confession for salvation purposes,
 because when laws are violated, the exclusion of relevant evidence is to be
 avoided.   The privilege, depending on the state, belongs to the confessor
 or confessee and always can be waived but how differs state to state.  It
 is routinely waived if the content is disclosed outside the one-on-one
 confession.

 It is also routinely invoked to conceal information that was obtained
 outside the confessional.

 It is my view that there should be an exception to it that parallels the
 attorney client exception for future crimes or fraud.   And that it should
 not be an exception to mandatory reporting of child sex abuse.   The
 privilege is a permissive accommodation that we have learned has a
 corrosive effect on children, families, churches, and society.   Under
 Smith it is not required and under a RFRA analysis it should not overcome
 the needs of the judicial process or  mandatory reporting laws.

 I offer these examples to contextualize the discussion.   It only matters
 when  it is alleged a law has been broken so that  law should be the
 starting point for discourse.

 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Marci Hamilton
In my view, there should be no privilege for criminal acts.  

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 7, 2013, at 12:12 PM, Richard Dougherty dou...@udallas.edu wrote:

 I much appreciate Marci's comments.  From the point of view of the free 
 exercise of religion, the question for the believer, in my view, is what the 
 effect of the revelation of confidential information is on the soul of the 
 penitent, not what the legal consequences might be.  Obviously the state has 
 other concerns, but they need not clash, except at the margins (though that's 
 what really counts).  I agree that the fall-out of the abuse crisis in the 
 Catholic Church has seen some try to claim privilege where no legitimate 
 claim of privilege seems to be at stake.  The dangers of doing so are 
 multiple -- most importantly, more people are put at risk of future abuse, 
 but it also undermines legitimate claims of privilege, as those entrusted 
 with making judgments about its legitimacy find it harder to distinguish the 
 genuine from the spurious.  I'm not convinced that discussions in diocesan 
 chanceries about how to avoid losses in court are part of the free exercise 
 of religion.
 
 The abuse crisis in contemporary America (not, of course, confined to the 
 Catholic Church) is painful for what it has done to so many who have 
 suffered, and it has been devastating for the Church.  Almost all of what I 
 have seen has nothing to do with Confession or free exercise of religion, 
 though, and here I support Marci's strong view of holding responsible those 
 who have enabled abusers; while this would likely prevent subsequent abuse -- 
 the most important consequence -- it would have the side effect of calling 
 Catholics to abide by their own beliefs.
 
 Richard Dougherty
 University of Dallas
 
 
 On Sat, Dec 7, 2013 at 7:45 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Richard's point is fair so let me provide some more context that perhaps 
 would be helpful.   
 
 Privileges are concoctions of positive law dealing w what information can be 
 excluded in the judicial process.   The confessional privilege is no 
 different than the attorney client privilege or the spousal  privilege on 
 that score.  Every faith invokes it or tries to to avoid disclosing legally 
 damaging evidence in the judicial process.  The RCC and LDS are the most 
 active in lobbying to expand it in the state legislatures.
 
   It is always invoked in clergy sex abuse cases and to avoid mandatory 
 reporting of child sex abuse.  Courts have had to struggle w the distinction 
 between counseling and confession for salvation purposes, because when laws 
 are violated, the exclusion of relevant evidence is to be avoided.   The 
 privilege, depending on the state, belongs to the confessor or confessee and 
 always can be waived but how differs state to state.  It is routinely waived 
 if the content is disclosed outside the one-on-one confession. 
 
 It is also routinely invoked to conceal information that was obtained 
 outside the confessional.   
 
 It is my view that there should be an exception to it that parallels the 
 attorney client exception for future crimes or fraud.   And that it should 
 not be an exception to mandatory reporting of child sex abuse.   The 
 privilege is a permissive accommodation that we have learned has a corrosive 
 effect on children, families, churches, and society.   Under Smith it is not 
 required and under a RFRA analysis it should not overcome the needs of the 
 judicial process or  mandatory reporting laws.  
 
 I offer these examples to contextualize the discussion.   It only matters 
 when  it is alleged a law has been broken so that  law should be the 
 starting point for discourse.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I am certainly drawn to  be protective of religious acts essential to their 
faith.  The problem, of course, comes with the radical pluralism of American 
religious life, and our (perhaps admirable) propensity to allow each individual 
more-or-less carte blanche (unless it involves smoking marijuana) as to what 
those essentials are.  And, of course, one still has to explain why claims of 
conscience that are essential to one's own notion living with integrity are 
not protected.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Saturday, December 07, 2013 10:53 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I think the history of the privilege is that it was first protected for 
Catholics, because of its sacramental nature and the very strong teaching, and 
then extended to other faiths by analogy and to avoid what looked to some like 
denominational discrimination. I'm pretty sure about that chronology; I'm 
inferring the causation without having done the historical work to verify it.

The peyote service is the central act of worship in the Native American Church; 
I don't know if they use the word sacrament. But Smith and Black (the other 
plaintiff) were not members of the church; they were exploring.

It is generally illusory to enact toleration, and say that religious minorities 
can live among you, if you then prosecute them for acts essential to their 
faith. The force of that point is weaker with respect to less important 
religious practices, although I think it never goes to zero.
Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Friday, December 06, 2013 11:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

As I've said earlier, I'm sympathetic to Richard's argument  inasmuch as 
confession is in fact part of a complex (required) sacramental process.  But 
the point is that (I think) that's relatively unusual, certainly not present, 
so far as I am aware, in Judaism, for example.  Am I correct in believing that 
the ingestion of peyote was in fact a sacramental aspect of the Native American 
church?

sandy

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Richard Foltin
BEGIN:VCALENDAR
METHOD:REQUEST
PRODID:AndroidEmail
VERSION:2.0
BEGIN:VEVENT
UID:c9fafb38-77b1-4e73-ac29-684411eed353
DTSTAMP:20131208T001712Z
DTSTART:20131208T003000Z
DTEND:20131208T013000Z
SUMMARY:RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
DESCRIPTION:When: 7:30pm – 8:30pm\, December 7\n--
	-\nI am certainly drawn to be protective of religious acts 
	“essential to their faith.” The problem\, of course\, comes with th
	e radical pluralism of American religious life\, and our (perhaps admir
	able) propensity to allow each individual more-or-less cart
X-MICROSOFT-CDO-ALLDAYEVENT:FALSE
ATTENDEE;ROLE=REQ-PARTICIPANT;PARTSTAT=NEEDS-ACTION;RSVP=TRUE;CN=SLevin
	s...@law.utexas.edu:MAILTO:slevin...@law.utexas.edu
ATTENDEE;ROLE=REQ-PARTICIPANT;PARTSTAT=NEEDS-ACTION;RSVP=TRUE;CN=religi
	on...@lists.ucla.edu:MAILTO:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
ORGANIZER:MAILTO:folt...@ajc.org
CLASS:PUBLIC
STATUS:CONFIRMED
TRANSP:OPAQUE
PRIORITY:5
SEQUENCE:0
BEGIN:VALARM
TRIGGER:-PT10M
ACTION:DISPLAY
DESCRIPTION:Reminder
END:VALARM
END:VEVENT
END:VCALENDAR
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Richard Foltin
Apologies to all for the invitation that my (not-so-)Smartphone somehow just 
sent to the listserve for a non-existent event.

Sent from my Verizon Wireless 4G LTE DROID


Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

I am certainly drawn to  be protective of religious acts “essential to their 
faith.”  The problem, of course, comes with the radical pluralism of American 
religious life, and our (perhaps admirable) propensity to allow each individual 
more-or-less carte blanche (unless it involves smoking marijuana) as to what 
those “essentials are.”  And, of course, one still has to explain why claims of 
conscience that are “essential to one’s own notion living with integrity” are 
not protected.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Saturday, December 07, 2013 10:53 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I think the history of the privilege is that it was first protected for 
Catholics, because of its sacramental nature and the very strong teaching, and 
then extended to other faiths by analogy and to avoid what looked to some like 
denominational discrimination. I’m pretty sure about that chronology; I’m 
inferring the causation without having done the historical work to verify it.

The peyote service is the central act of worship in the Native American Church; 
I don’t know if they use the word sacrament. But Smith and Black (the other 
plaintiff) were not members of the church; they were exploring.

It is generally illusory to enact toleration, and say that religious minorities 
can live among you, if you then prosecute them for acts essential to their 
faith. The force of that point is weaker with respect to less important 
religious practices, although I think it never goes to zero.
Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Friday, December 06, 2013 11:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

As I’ve said earlier, I’m sympathetic to Richard’s argument  inasmuch as 
confession is in fact part of a complex (required) sacramental process.  But 
the point is that (I think) that’s relatively unusual, certainly not present, 
so far as I am aware, in Judaism, for example.  Am I correct in believing that 
the ingestion of peyote was in fact a sacramental aspect of the Native American 
church?

sandy

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Canceled: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Richard Foltin
BEGIN:VCALENDAR
METHOD:CANCEL
PRODID:AndroidEmail
VERSION:2.0
BEGIN:VEVENT
UID:c9fafb38-77b1-4e73-ac29-684411eed353
DTSTAMP:20131208T003217Z
DTSTART:20131208T003000Z
DTEND:20131208T013000Z
SUMMARY:RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
DESCRIPTION:When: 7:30pm – 8:30pm\, December 7\n--
	-\nI am certainly drawn to be protective of religious acts 
	“essential to their faith.” The problem\, of course\, comes with th
	e radical pluralism of American religious life\, and our (perhaps admir
	able) propensity to allow each individual more-or-less cart
X-MICROSOFT-CDO-ALLDAYEVENT:FALSE
ATTENDEE;ROLE=REQ-PARTICIPANT;CN=slevin...@law.utexas.edu:MAILTO:SLevi
	n...@law.utexas.edu
ATTENDEE;ROLE=REQ-PARTICIPANT;CN=religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu:MAILTO:rel
	igion...@lists.ucla.edu
ORGANIZER:MAILTO:folt...@ajc.org
CLASS:PUBLIC
STATUS:CANCELLED
TRANSP:OPAQUE
PRIORITY:5
SEQUENCE:0
END:VEVENT
END:VCALENDAR
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-06 Thread Paul Horwitz



I don't have much of a dog in this fight, but let me add three things:
1) I appreciate Marci's response. It's clear the privilege has indeed been 
interpreted in a confined manner in many jurisdictions, even where the statute 
itself is fairly broad. Too confined, perhaps, in my view. But I take the law 
as it is for present purposes. 
2) I would treat the existence and scope of the privilege separately from the 
religious aspects of the privilege. I don't find convincing the idea that 
something about the privilege makes it uniquely troubling from the perspective 
of the realm of testimonial privileges generally. In identifying privileged 
communications, we start by asking, among other things, whether there are 
particular relationships which, in society's view, ought to be fostered and/or 
for which confidentiality is an important element. In doing so, we don't, in my 
view, start strictly from a position of liberal neutrality; rather, we begin 
with existing relationships in our actual society and at least take into 
account traditional reliance upon or approval of those relationships. (I 
appreciate, however, Sandy Levinson's interesting 1984 Duke Law Journal article 
on the subject.) From that perspective, and whether or not everyone can avail 
himself or herself of a particular relationship or privilege, I don't think 
it's per se unreasonable to include priest-penitent relationships among those 
that society values for various reasons. But any and every privilege, this one 
included, is subject to both reexamination on the question of whether it should 
exist, and reexamination on its scope and exceptions.  
3) I do, however, tend to agree more with Greg than with Eugene on the 
potential value and nature of the counseling that might be offered in a 
priest-communicant relationship. Many clergy are extensively trained in 
counseling, and although that counseling may have a spiritual component, it 
also includes all the other qualities, skills, and advice that are relevant to 
any person serving a counseling role. Of course there are going to be ministers 
who are lousy counselors, just as there are psychotherapists and doctors who 
are lousy counselors. But others--I think many--can and will give advice that 
is tailored not so much to a particular religious worldview but to the role of 
counselor in general. And I don't think it's far-fetched, at least from my 
personal experience, to think of such a person as serving a role to more people 
than just their own parishioners. Leaving aside potential converts or 
communicants, whose communications are analogous to communications by potential 
clients, in many smaller communities or neighborhoods a minister can serve an 
important role as a community leader and friend and counselor to its residents. 
Again, nothing in this paragraph prevents us from reexamining whether the 
privilege should exist at all, or whether it should be subject to particular 
reporting exceptions etc.   

From: vol...@law.ucla.edu
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Date: Thu, 5 Dec 2013 14:44:54 -0800
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I’m sure there are some such situations, perhaps even quite a 
few.  But I imagine there are quite a few situations where the priest would 
quite rightly not give me the advice that works for me given my philosophical 
worldview.  The benefit of the clergy-penitent privilege to the religious is 
that they can generally get such advice, tailored to the particular religious 
belief system they follow.  The irreligious, I think, don’t have that benefit, 
though they might get some second-best option for those situations where their 
worldview overlaps with a clergyman’s. Eugene  From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Sisk, Gregory C.
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 2:31 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties 
Actually, I think non-Catholics mostly would be pleasantly surprised, both on 
the receptivity of the priest-confessor and the wisdom of the response.  To be 
sure, there are some misdeeds that are shared in confession that are understood 
to be such solely from the perspective of the Catholic believer (e.g., failed 
to attend mass, took the Lord’s name in vain, etc.), but most of what is shared 
with a priest are the kinds of faults to which all of us are prone and which 
all (or nearly all) of us regard as faults.  And, following the confession, a 
good priest (which is to say, most priests) responds both in religious terms by 
pronouncing absolution and reconciliation with God, but also speaking about 
reconciliation with one’s neighbors and future personal growth.  Indeed, in my 
own experience – and I do not go to confession nearly as often as I should (one 
more thing to confess, I guess) – is that the priest usually engages me 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-06 Thread Christopher Lund
Again, I’m late—sorry about that.  But honestly people, it’s shocking how 
many posts are written between the hours of 9 p.m. and 7 a.m.  Who can keep 
up?



So this may backtrack, but I’ve been thinking about the earlier posts in 
this thread.  Say there are no secular analogies to the priest-penitent 
privilege.  Does that, in itself, justify the conclusion that it is 
favoritism for religion?



I don’t think so, or at least I’m not convinced of that right now.  Some 
people are religious; some people are not.  Some people feel a need to 
confess and receive absolution in return; others do not.  The 
priest-penitent privilege only helps those in the former group.  But that 
need not be favoritism.  Sure, it’s differential treatment, but it might be 
justified because the people aren’t similarly situated in the first place. 
(And here this ties in to Greg Sisk’s earlier posts.)



I think it helps that there are secular analogues, but I think it’s a 
mistake to require the secular analogues to match up perfectly with the 
religious one.  I think it’s a mistake because it denies the reasons why we 
want to accommodate religion in the first place: Religion is different than 
other human needs.  It may be analogous to them, but it’s never perfectly 
analogous; it inevitably differs in ways that require tailored treatment. 
The equality approach means that religious activities never get protection 
when there’s no exact secular parallel to them.  If there’s no exact secular 
parallel to confession—and of course there isn’t!—then confession doesn’t 
get protected.  More generally, I take this to be the central weakness of 
Smith (even for those who think Smith rightly decided).  It is also why—to 
pick up Sandy’s train of thought below—Widmar ends up turning into Bronx 
Household.



In Trammel, the Court goes through all the privileges in a sensible and 
attractive way.  The attorney-client privilege helps you secure legal help; 
the physician privilege helps you secure medical help; later on, the 
psychotherapist privilege will help you secure emotional help; the clergy 
privilege helps you secure spiritual help.  True enough that some don’t 
believe in spiritual help, because they think it’s bs.  But some think 
psychotherapy is bs.



If the priest-penitent privilege is conceptualized the way Sandy phrases 
it—as a “desire [of people] to unburden themselves to sympathetic 
 listeners”—then the priest-penitent privilege looks terribly 
underinclusive.  But that phrases the priest-penitent privilege at a high 
level of generality.  And at that level of generality, all the other 
privileges become terribly underinclusive as well.  The spousal privilege 
discriminates against the unmarried and against me if I confide in my best 
friend more than my wife.  The psychotherapist privilege discriminates 
against sympathetic mothers, fathers, siblings, and bartenders.  (This is 
one way Justice Scalia goes after the privilege in Redmond.)



There’s also the spectre of discrimination against religion arising if, say, 
psychotherapists got a privilege and clergy didn’t.  But I really think we 
might be better off not always thinking about this in terms of 
discrimination.  Religion seems sui generis, and unique things must be 
treated in unique ways.



Best,

Chris



From:  mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [ 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 5:17 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties



My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at 
least contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest 
would respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my 
own.  (There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular 
in secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren’t the norm.)



Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share. 
Secular people do not.



Eugene



From:  mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [ 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties



Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed 
for any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her 
professional capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that 
counsel need not 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-06 Thread hamilton02

With all due respect to this entire thread, how many people have actually read 
the state cases involving the priest-penitent privilege?  There is a level of 
abstraction
to this discussion that indicates to me probably not.  As someone who has 
actively been involved in arguing the issue in court in the last year, I'd 
suggest that the law is
more reticulated and specific. state-by-state, than the speculation going on 
here.  It is state law, which means 50 states plus DC law, and it is a 
privilege that is not constitutionally required,
particularly when the issue is whether the religious confessor or confessee 
engaged in illegal behavior.  




Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003 
(212) 790-0215 
http://sol-reform.com





-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Fri, Dec 6, 2013 10:06 am
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties



Again, I’m late—sorry about that.  But honestly people, it’s shocking how many 
posts are written between the hours of 9 p.m. and 7 a.m.  Who can keep up?
 
So this may backtrack, but I’ve been thinking about the earlier posts in this 
thread.  Say there are no secular analogies to the priest-penitent privilege.  
Does that, in itself, justify the conclusion that it is favoritism for 
religion?   
 
I don’t think so, or at least I’m not convinced of that right now.  Some people 
are religious; some people are not.  Some people feel a need to confess and 
receive absolution in return; others do not.  The priest-penitent privilege 
only helps those in the former group.  But that need not be favoritism.  Sure, 
it’s differential treatment, but it might be justified because the people 
aren’t similarly situated in the first place.  (And here this ties in to Greg 
Sisk’s earlier posts.)
 
I think it helps that there are secular analogues, but I think it’s a mistake 
to require the secular analogues to match up perfectly with the religious one.  
I think it’s a mistake because it denies the reasons why we want to accommodate 
religion in the first place: Religion is different than other human needs.  It 
may be analogous to them, but it’s never perfectly analogous; it inevitably 
differs in ways that require tailored treatment.  The equality approach means 
that religious activities never get protection when there’s no exact secular 
parallel to them.  If there’s no exact secular parallel to confession—and of 
course there isn’t!—then confession doesn’t get protected.  More generally, I 
take this to be the central weakness of Smith (even for those who think Smith 
rightly decided).  It is also why—to pick up Sandy’s train of thought 
below—Widmar ends up turning into Bronx Household.
 
In Trammel, the Court goes through all the privileges in a sensible and 
attractive way.  The attorney-client privilege helps you secure legal help; the 
physician privilege helps you secure medical help; later on, the 
psychotherapist privilege will help you secure emotional help; the clergy 
privilege helps you secure spiritual help.  True enough that some don’t believe 
in spiritual help, because they think it’s bs.  But some think psychotherapy is 
bs.  
 
If the priest-penitent privilege is conceptualized the way Sandy phrases it—as 
a “desire [of people] to unburden themselves to sympathetic listeners”—then the 
priest-penitent privilege looks terribly underinclusive.  But that phrases the 
priest-penitent privilege at a high level of generality.  And at that level of 
generality, all the other privileges become terribly underinclusive as well.  
The spousal privilege discriminates against the unmarried and against me if I 
confide in my best friend more than my wife.  The psychotherapist privilege 
discriminates against sympathetic mothers, fathers, siblings, and bartenders.  
(This is one way Justice Scalia goes after the privilege in Redmond.)  
 
There’s also the spectre of discrimination against religion arising if, say, 
psychotherapists got a privilege and clergy didn’t.  But I really think we 
might be better off not always thinking about this in terms of discrimination.  
Religion seems sui generis, and unique things must be treated in unique ways.
 
Best,
Chris
 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 5:17 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

 
My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at least 
contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest would 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-06 Thread Richard Dougherty
I will confess to not having read the state cases, or at least not most of
them.  But isn't the question *whether* the privilege is constitutionally
required?  (Perhaps the fact that it is referred to as a privilege muddies
the waters.)  If free exercise of religion includes receiving a sacrament,
then why is compelling violation of the privilege not a constitutional
issue?  Indeed, I wonder why a recent discussion suggested stronger free
speech claims than free exercise claims; does the First Amendment make that
distinction?  I have no doubt courts have read it that way, but that's
partly why we get distortions of free exercise claims masquerading as free
speech claims.

Richard Dougherty
University of Dallas


On Fri, Dec 6, 2013 at 1:17 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

 With all due respect to this entire thread, how many people have actually
 read the state cases involving the priest-penitent privilege?  There is a
 level of abstraction
 to this discussion that indicates to me probably not.  As someone who has
 actively been involved in arguing the issue in court in the last year, I'd
 suggest that the law is
 more reticulated and specific. state-by-state, than the speculation going
 on here.  It is state law, which means 50 states plus DC law, and it is a
 privilege that is not constitutionally required,
 particularly when the issue is whether the religious confessor or
 confessee engaged in illegal behavior.


  Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 http://sol-reform.com
  https://www.facebook.com/professormarciahamilton?fref=ts   
 https://twitter.com/marci_hamilton

   -Original Message-
 From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Fri, Dec 6, 2013 10:06 am
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

   Again, I’m late—sorry about that.  But honestly people, it’s shocking
 how many posts are written between the hours of 9 p.m. and 7 a.m.  Who can
 keep up?

 So this may backtrack, but I’ve been thinking about the earlier posts in
 this thread.  Say there are no secular analogies to the priest-penitent
 privilege.  Does that, in itself, justify the conclusion that it is
 favoritism for religion?


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-06 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
As I've said earlier, I'm sympathetic to Richard's argument  inasmuch as 
confession is in fact part of a complex (required) sacramental process.  But 
the point is that (I think) that's relatively unusual, certainly not present, 
so far as I am aware, in Judaism, for example.  Am I correct in believing that 
the ingestion of peyote was in fact a sacramental aspect of the Native American 
church?

sandy

From: religionlaw-bounces+slevinson=law.utexas@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-bounces+slevinson=law.utexas@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf 
Of Richard Dougherty
Sent: Friday, December 06, 2013 6:09 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I will confess to not having read the state cases, or at least not most of 
them.  But isn't the question whether the privilege is constitutionally 
required?  (Perhaps the fact that it is referred to as a privilege muddies the 
waters.)  If free exercise of religion includes receiving a sacrament, then why 
is compelling violation of the privilege not a constitutional issue?  Indeed, I 
wonder why a recent discussion suggested stronger free speech claims than free 
exercise claims; does the First Amendment make that distinction?  I have no 
doubt courts have read it that way, but that's partly why we get distortions of 
free exercise claims masquerading as free speech claims.

Richard Dougherty
University of Dallas

On Fri, Dec 6, 2013 at 1:17 PM, hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com 
wrote:
With all due respect to this entire thread, how many people have actually read 
the state cases involving the priest-penitent privilege?  There is a level of 
abstraction
to this discussion that indicates to me probably not.  As someone who has 
actively been involved in arguing the issue in court in the last year, I'd 
suggest that the law is
more reticulated and specific. state-by-state, than the speculation going on 
here.  It is state law, which means 50 states plus DC law, and it is a 
privilege that is not constitutionally required,
particularly when the issue is whether the religious confessor or confessee 
engaged in illegal behavior.


Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
http://sol-reform.comhttp://sol-reform.com/
[http://sol-reform.com/fb.png]https://www.facebook.com/professormarciahamilton?fref=ts
   [http://www.sol-reform.com/tw.png] https://twitter.com/marci_hamilton
-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edumailto:l...@wayne.edu
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Fri, Dec 6, 2013 10:06 am
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
Again, I'm late-sorry about that.  But honestly people, it's shocking how many 
posts are written between the hours of 9 p.m. and 7 a.m.  Who can keep up?

So this may backtrack, but I've been thinking about the earlier posts in this 
thread.  Say there are no secular analogies to the priest-penitent privilege.  
Does that, in itself, justify the conclusion that it is favoritism for religion?

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Paul Horwitz
Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed for 
any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her professional 
capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel need not 
necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just hair-splitting. 
It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women can seek medical 
care for pregnancy. 

 On Dec 4, 2013, at 10:56 PM, Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu 
 wrote:
 
 Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
 everyone.  What is distinctive about the “clergy-penitent privilege” is that 
 it protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
 religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to 
 unburden themselves to sympathetic listeners but can’t assume that it is 
 protected in the same way.  Aren’t we back to the conundra involving 
 “conscientious objection” and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court 
 could adopt Paul Tillich and say that secularists, too, have “ultimate 
 concerns” equivalent to religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar 
 move with regard to clergy privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger 
 (assuming, at least, one version of the facts in that case, which may or may 
 not be entirely correct) and Widmar v. Vincent on “equality” grounds, i.e., 
 those who are religious should not be selected out for worse treatment than 
 those who are secular.  If I can use a facility for meetings of my philosophy 
 club, then I think that others should be free to use the facility for 
 meetings of the “Good News Club.”  But it is telling that we’re talking about 
 a “privilege” that is denied to each and every secular person (unless they 
 can afford a shrink, though even there the privilege is significantly more 
 constrained than is the case with a priest), and “equality” arguments go by 
 the boards. 
  
 sandy
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
 Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 11:35 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third 
 parties; for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress as 
 do the mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech that 
 does not quite violate Brandenburg can incite violence. Further, the cost to 
 the public in protecting speech can be extraordinarily high. cities incurred 
 tens of thousands of dollars in police and other costs while trying to 
 maintain order during Operation Rescue protests. Criminal procedure rights 
 can make it more difficult to apprehend and punish people who commit crimes. 
 Property rights can make it more difficult to protect the environment. Rights 
 have always been expensive politcal goods.
  
 It is true that the Establishment Clause imposes some constitutional 
 constraints on the costs government may incur or impose on third parties in 
 protecting religious liberty. Arguing that free exercise rights or statutory 
 religious liberty rights should only be protected in situations in which 
 doing so imposes virtually no costs on either the public or third parties, 
 however, would treat religious liberty differently than almost all other 
 rights and dramatically undermine their utility for people attempting to 
 exercise such rights.
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edu]
 Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 5:53 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
 
 I think Marc’s point is solid and underappreciated.  Following up on it, does 
 anyone know of any literature that tries to think about “burdens on third 
 parties” across constitutional rights?  We accept such burdens as a matter of 
 course with defamation law, as Marc notes.  Yet we also accept them in other 
 contexts.  Guns would be one obvious example.  But also think of, for 
 example, busing during the Civil Rights Era.  White suburban families had to 
 accept busing of their kids to distant and sometimes difficult schools, 
 because desegregation was that important.  Or think about abortion: I think 
 the Court was right to hold spousal consent and notification laws 
 unconstitutional, but there are real issues of third-party harms there too.
  
 Best, Chris
  
  
  
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Marci Hamilton
It depends on the state actually. But generally the confession must be for 
spiritual/salvation purposes


Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 5, 2013, at 12:32 PM, Paul Horwitz phorw...@hotmail.com wrote:

 Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed 
 for any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her 
 professional capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel 
 need not necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just 
 hair-splitting. It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women 
 can seek medical care for pregnancy. 
 
 On Dec 4, 2013, at 10:56 PM, Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu 
 wrote:
 
 Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
 everyone.  What is distinctive about the “clergy-penitent privilege” is that 
 it protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
 religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to 
 unburden themselves to sympathetic listeners but can’t assume that it is 
 protected in the same way.  Aren’t we back to the conundra involving 
 “conscientious objection” and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court 
 could adopt Paul Tillich and say that secularists, too, have “ultimate 
 concerns” equivalent to religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar 
 move with regard to clergy privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger 
 (assuming, at least, one version of the facts in that case, which may or may 
 not be entirely correct) and Widmar v. Vincent on “equality” grounds, i.e., 
 those who are religious should not be selected out for worse treatment than 
 those who are secular.  If I can use a facility for meetings of my 
 philosophy club, then I think that others should be free to use the facility 
 for meetings of the “Good News Club.”  But it is telling that we’re talking 
 about a “privilege” that is denied to each and every secular person (unless 
 they can afford a shrink, though even there the privilege is significantly 
 more constrained than is the case with a priest), and “equality” arguments 
 go by the boards. 
  
 sandy
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
 Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 11:35 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third 
 parties; for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress 
 as do the mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech 
 that does not quite violate Brandenburg can incite violence. Further, the 
 cost to the public in protecting speech can be extraordinarily high. cities 
 incurred tens of thousands of dollars in police and other costs while trying 
 to maintain order during Operation Rescue protests. Criminal procedure 
 rights can make it more difficult to apprehend and punish people who commit 
 crimes. Property rights can make it more difficult to protect the 
 environment. Rights have always been expensive politcal goods.
  
 It is true that the Establishment Clause imposes some constitutional 
 constraints on the costs government may incur or impose on third parties in 
 protecting religious liberty. Arguing that free exercise rights or statutory 
 religious liberty rights should only be protected in situations in which 
 doing so imposes virtually no costs on either the public or third parties, 
 however, would treat religious liberty differently than almost all other 
 rights and dramatically undermine their utility for people attempting to 
 exercise such rights.
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Christopher Lund 
 [l...@wayne.edu]
 Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 5:53 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
 
 I think Marc’s point is solid and underappreciated.  Following up on it, 
 does anyone know of any literature that tries to think about “burdens on 
 third parties” across constitutional rights?  We accept such burdens as a 
 matter of course with defamation law, as Marc notes.  Yet we also accept 
 them in other contexts.  Guns would be one obvious example.  But also think 
 of, for example, busing during the Civil Rights Era.  White suburban 
 families had to accept busing of their kids to distant and sometimes 
 difficult schools, because desegregation was that important.  Or think about 
 abortion: I think the Court was right to hold spousal consent and 
 notification laws unconstitutional, but there are real issues of third-party 
 harms there too.
  
 Best, Chris
  
  
  
 ___
 To 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at least 
contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest would 
respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my own.  
(There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular in 
secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren’t the norm.)

Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share.  
Secular people do not.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed for 
any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her professional 
capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel need not 
necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just hair-splitting. 
It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women can seek medical 
care for pregnancy.

On Dec 4, 2013, at 10:56 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
everyone.  What is distinctive about the “clergy-penitent privilege” is that it 
protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to unburden 
themselves to sympathetic listeners but can’t assume that it is protected in 
the same way.  Aren’t we back to the conundra involving “conscientious 
objection” and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court could adopt Paul 
Tillich and say that secularists, too, have “ultimate concerns” equivalent to 
religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar move with regard to clergy 
privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger (assuming, at least, one 
version of the facts in that case, which may or may not be entirely correct) 
and Widmar v. Vincent on “equality” grounds, i.e., those who are religious 
should not be selected out for worse treatment than those who are secular.  If 
I can use a facility for meetings of my philosophy club, then I think that 
others should be free to use the facility for meetings of the “Good News Club.” 
 But it is telling that we’re talking about a “privilege” that is denied to 
each and every secular person (unless they can afford a shrink, though even 
there the privilege is significantly more constrained than is the case with a 
priest), and “equality” arguments go by the boards.

sandy

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 11:35 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties


Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third parties; 
for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress as do the 
mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech that does not 
quite violate Brandenburg can incite violence. Further, the cost to the public 
in protecting speech can be extraordinarily high. cities incurred tens of 
thousands of dollars in police and other costs while trying to maintain order 
during Operation Rescue protests. Criminal procedure rights can make it more 
difficult to apprehend and punish people who commit crimes. Property rights can 
make it more difficult to protect the environment. Rights have always been 
expensive politcal goods.



It is true that the Establishment Clause imposes some constitutional 
constraints on the costs government may incur or impose on third parties in 
protecting religious liberty. Arguing that free exercise rights or statutory 
religious liberty rights should only be protected in situations in which doing 
so imposes virtually no costs on either the public or third parties, however, 
would treat religious liberty differently than almost all other rights and 
dramatically undermine their utility for people attempting to exercise such 
rights.


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edumailto:l...@wayne.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 5:53 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
I think 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Sisk, Gregory C.
Actually, I think non-Catholics mostly would be pleasantly surprised, both on 
the receptivity of the priest-confessor and the wisdom of the response.  To be 
sure, there are some misdeeds that are shared in confession that are understood 
to be such solely from the perspective of the Catholic believer (e.g., failed 
to attend mass, took the Lord’s name in vain, etc.), but most of what is shared 
with a priest are the kinds of faults to which all of us are prone and which 
all (or nearly all) of us regard as faults.  And, following the confession, a 
good priest (which is to say, most priests) responds both in religious terms by 
pronouncing absolution and reconciliation with God, but also speaking about 
reconciliation with one’s neighbors and future personal growth.  Indeed, in my 
own experience – and I do not go to confession nearly as often as I should (one 
more thing to confess, I guess) – is that the priest usually engages me in a 
common-sense and real-world dialogue about why I have fallen short, what are 
the obstacles in my path, and what steps I should take to overcome those 
obstacles.  Penance may include prayer (the traditional, “say, ten ‘Our 
Father’s) but more and more often will include steps to compensate for harm to 
others, efforts to assist others in a similar situation, charitable activities, 
etc.

Gregory Sisk
Laghi Distinguished Chair in Law
University of St. Thomas School of Law (Minnesota)
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN  55403-2005
651-962-4923
gcs...@stthomas.edu
http://personal.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.htmlhttp://personal2.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.html
Publications:  http://ssrn.com/author=44545

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 4:17 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at least 
contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest would 
respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my own.  
(There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular in 
secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren’t the norm.)

Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share.  
Secular people do not.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed for 
any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her professional 
capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel need not 
necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just hair-splitting. 
It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women can seek medical 
care for pregnancy.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I’m sure there are some such situations, perhaps even quite a 
few.  But I imagine there are quite a few situations where the priest would 
quite rightly not give me the advice that works for me given my philosophical 
worldview.  The benefit of the clergy-penitent privilege to the religious is 
that they can generally get such advice, tailored to the particular religious 
belief system they follow.  The irreligious, I think, don’t have that benefit, 
though they might get some second-best option for those situations where their 
worldview overlaps with a clergyman’s.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sisk, Gregory C.
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 2:31 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Actually, I think non-Catholics mostly would be pleasantly surprised, both on 
the receptivity of the priest-confessor and the wisdom of the response.  To be 
sure, there are some misdeeds that are shared in confession that are understood 
to be such solely from the perspective of the Catholic believer (e.g., failed 
to attend mass, took the Lord’s name in vain, etc.), but most of what is shared 
with a priest are the kinds of faults to which all of us are prone and which 
all (or nearly all) of us regard as faults.  And, following the confession, a 
good priest (which is to say, most priests) responds both in religious terms by 
pronouncing absolution and reconciliation with God, but also speaking about 
reconciliation with one’s neighbors and future personal growth.  Indeed, in my 
own experience – and I do not go to confession nearly as often as I should (one 
more thing to confess, I guess) – is that the priest usually engages me in a 
common-sense and real-world dialogue about why I have fallen short, what are 
the obstacles in my path, and what steps I should take to overcome those 
obstacles.  Penance may include prayer (the traditional, “say, ten ‘Our 
Father’s) but more and more often will include steps to compensate for harm to 
others, efforts to assist others in a similar situation, charitable activities, 
etc.

Gregory Sisk
Laghi Distinguished Chair in Law
University of St. Thomas School of Law (Minnesota)
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN  55403-2005
651-962-4923
gcs...@stthomas.edumailto:gcs...@stthomas.edu
http://personal.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.htmlhttp://personal2.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.html
Publications:  http://ssrn.com/author=44545

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 4:17 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at least 
contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest would 
respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my own.  
(There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular in 
secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren’t the norm.)

Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share.  
Secular people do not.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed for 
any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her professional 
capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel need not 
necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just hair-splitting. 
It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women can seek medical 
care for pregnancy.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I have no doubt that Steve is accurately reporting his own experience, but I 
still don't see why it should add up to a confidentiality privilege.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:38 PM
To: Law Religion  Law List
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I disagree with Eugene on this - as a non-religious athiest, I have met many 
ministers and priests with whom I have had excellent conversations, some even 
confessional or at least very candid and have been given advice, even by 
priests, which was insightful and helpful and respectful of me.  They did not 
try to get me to do hail Marys or whatevers and did not speak to me in 
religious speech.  I have dealt with others whose only aim was indeed to 
convert me.

--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Director of International Programs, Institute for Intellectual Property and 
Social Justice http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/


The aim of education must be the training of independently acting and thinking 
individuals who, however, see in the service to the community their highest 
life achievement.



Albert Einstein




On Dec 5, 2013, at 5:16 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:


My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at least 
contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest would 
respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my own.  
(There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular in 
secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren't the norm.)

Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share.  
Secular people do not.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed for 
any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her professional 
capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel need not 
necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just hair-splitting. 
It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women can seek medical 
care for pregnancy.

On Dec 4, 2013, at 10:56 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
everyone.  What is distinctive about the clergy-penitent privilege is that it 
protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to unburden 
themselves to sympathetic listeners but can't assume that it is protected in 
the same way.  Aren't we back to the conundra involving conscientious 
objection and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court could adopt Paul 
Tillich and say that secularists, too, have ultimate concerns equivalent to 
religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar move with regard to clergy 
privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger (assuming, at least, one 
version of the facts in that case, which may or may not be entirely correct) 
and Widmar v. Vincent on equality grounds, i.e., those who are religious 
should not be selected out for worse treatment than those who are secular.  If 
I can use a facility for meetings of my philosophy club, then I think that 
others should be free to use the facility for meetings of the Good News Club. 
 But it is telling that we're talking about a privilege that is denied to 
each and every secular person (unless they can afford a shrink, though even 
there the privilege is significantly more constrained than is the case with a 
priest), and equality arguments go by the boards.

sandy

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 11:35 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third parties; 
for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress as do the 
mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech that does not 
quite violate 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Steven Jamar
Sandy and Marci,

I agree my conversations were not and should not have been privileged.  But it 
is not the case that non-believers cannot be helped by priests either in a 
priest/pentitent setting or less formally.  

Steve

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Director of International Programs, Institute for Intellectual Property and 
Social Justice http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/

“There are no wrong notes in jazz: only notes in the wrong places.”
Miles Davis

On Dec 5, 2013, at 5:44 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I’m sure there are some such situations, perhaps even quite a 
 few.  But I imagine there are quite a few situations where the priest would 
 quite rightly not give me the advice that works for me given my philosophical 
 worldview.  The benefit of the clergy-penitent privilege to the religious is 
 that they can generally get such advice, tailored to the particular religious 
 belief system they follow.  The irreligious, I think, don’t have that 
 benefit, though they might get some second-best option for those situations 
 where their worldview overlaps with a clergyman’s.
  
 Eugene
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf OfSisk, Gregory C.
 Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 2:31 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 Actually, I think non-Catholics mostly would be pleasantly surprised, both on 
 the receptivity of the priest-confessor and the wisdom of the response.  To 
 be sure, there are some misdeeds that are shared in confession that are 
 understood to be such solely from the perspective of the Catholic believer 
 (e.g., failed to attend mass, took the Lord’s name in vain, etc.), but most 
 of what is shared with a priest are the kinds of faults to which all of us 
 are prone and which all (or nearly all) of us regard as faults.  And, 
 following the confession, a good priest (which is to say, most priests) 
 responds both in religious terms by pronouncing absolution and reconciliation 
 with God, but also speaking about reconciliation with one’s neighbors and 
 future personal growth.  Indeed, in my own experience – and I do not go to 
 confession nearly as often as I should (one more thing to confess, I guess) – 
 is that the priest usually engages me in a common-sense and real-world 
 dialogue about why I have fallen short, what are the obstacles in my path, 
 and what steps I should take to overcome those obstacles.  Penance may 
 include prayer (the traditional, “say, ten ‘Our Father’s) but more and more 
 often will include steps to compensate for harm to others, efforts to assist 
 others in a similar situation, charitable activities, etc.
  
 Gregory Sisk
 Laghi Distinguished Chair in Law
 University of St. Thomas School of Law (Minnesota)
 MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN  55403-2005
 651-962-4923
 gcs...@stthomas.edu
 http://personal.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.html
 Publications:  http://ssrn.com/author=44545
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf OfVolokh, Eugene
 Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 4:17 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
 relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
 Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at 
 least contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest 
 would respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my 
 own.  (There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular 
 in secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren’t the norm.)
  
 Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
 confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share.  
 Secular people do not.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf OfPaul Horwitz
 Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed 
 for any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her 
 professional capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel 
 need not necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just 
 hair-splitting. It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women 
 can seek medical care for pregnancy. 
  
 
 ___
 To post, send message to 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread hamilton02
No question.  They can be helped just as believers might not be!   But that is 
separate from whether, as a legal matter, a privilege attaches.


Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003 
(212) 790-0215 
http://sol-reform.com





-Original Message-
From: Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com
To: Law Religion  Law List religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Thu, Dec 5, 2013 10:09 pm
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties


Sandy and Marci,


I agree my conversations were not and should not have been privileged.  But it 
is not the case that non-believers cannot be helped by priests either in a 
priest/pentitent setting or less formally.  


Steve



-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Director of International Programs, Institute for Intellectual Property and 
Social Justice http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/



“There are no wrong notes in jazz: only notes in the wrong places.”
Miles Davis


On Dec 5, 2013, at 5:44 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:



I’m sure there are some such situations, perhaps even quite a 
few.  But I imagine there are quite a few situations where the priest would 
quite rightly not give me the advice that works for me given my philosophical 
worldview.  The benefit of the clergy-penitent privilege to the religious is 
that they can generally get such advice, tailored to the particular religious 
belief system they follow.  The irreligious, I think, don’t have that benefit, 
though they might get some second-best option for those situations where their 
worldview overlaps with a clergyman’s.
 
Eugene
 
 


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf OfSisk, Gregory C.
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 2:31 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

 
Actually, I think non-Catholics mostly would be pleasantly surprised, both on 
the receptivity of the priest-confessor and the wisdom of the response.  To be 
sure, there are some misdeeds that are shared in confession that are understood 
to be such solely from the perspective of the Catholic believer (e.g., failed 
to attend mass, took the Lord’s name in vain, etc.), but most of what is shared 
with a priest are the kinds of faults to which all of us are prone and which 
all (or nearly all) of us regard as faults.  And, following the confession, a 
good priest (which is to say, most priests) responds both in religious terms by 
pronouncing absolution and reconciliation with God, but also speaking about 
reconciliation with one’s neighbors and future personal growth.  Indeed, in my 
own experience – and I do not go to confession nearly as often as I should (one 
more thing to confess, I guess) – is that the priest usually engages me in a 
common-sense and real-world dialogue about why I have fallen short, what are 
the obstacles in my path, and what steps I should take to overcome those 
obstacles.  Penance may include prayer (the traditional, “say, ten ‘Our 
Father’s) but more and more often will include steps to compensate for harm to 
others, efforts to assist others in a similar situation, charitable activities, 
etc.
 

Gregory Sisk
Laghi Distinguished Chair in Law
University of St. Thomas School of Law (Minnesota)
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN  55403-2005
651-962-4923
gcs...@stthomas.edu
http://personal.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.html
Publications:  http://ssrn.com/author=44545

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf OfVolokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 4:17 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

 
My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at least 
contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest would 
respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my own.  
(There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular in 
secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren’t the norm.)
 
Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share.  
Secular people do not.
 
Eugene
 


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf OfPaul Horwitz
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties


RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I’m genuinely curious:  Do we have any idea which denominations impose a duty 
on their clergy to preserve confidentiality?  Every Sunday I read in the Style 
section of the Times of couples who are married by someone who has been 
licensed by the Universal Church (I think it’s called) to perform weddings.   
Often, of course, the officiant is a close friend of one or both of the couple 
being married.  Would we/should we take seriously an internet declaration by 
the Universal Church that it requires its “clergy” to keep confidential 
whatever the bride(s), groom(s), members of the wedding party, etc., might have 
said in the run-up to tying the knot?

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 10:15 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I don’t know how it is in other states, but Cal. Evid Code 
1030-1034 absolutely covers any “communication made in confidence, in the 
presence of no third person so far as the penitent is aware, to a member of the 
clergy who, in the course of the discipline or practice of the clergy member's 
church, denomination, or organization, is authorized or accustomed to hear 
those communications and, under the discipline or tenets of his or her church, 
denomination, or organization, has a duty to keep those communications secret.” 
 So the question isn’t whether it’s “for salvation or other religious goal” as 
such; rather, it’s whether the clergy member “has a duty to keep those 
communications secret” under his religious denomination’s tenets.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 6:59 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Steve-- That may be true in your experience, but it doesn't make those 
discussions confessional for purposes of the clergy-penitent privilege.  It 
typically requires a showing that the
discussion was not counseling, therapy, or simply an exchange of information.  
Rather, it must be for salvation or other religious goal.

Even discussions between co-religionists, however, may not qualify as 
confessions for purposes of the privilege.  For example, a conversation between 
a bishop
and a pedophile priest about his abuse of children and his next placement is 
not a confession, despite the elements of counseling involved.   No privilege 
attaches to such
conversations.

Marci
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-04 Thread Sisk, Gregory C.
Many reasons can be offered for the venerable privilege that originated as the 
priest-penitent privilege, including as Doug notes that the penitent having the 
confidence that confession is sacrosanct will be willing to share that which he 
or she withholds from all others and thereby be in a position to receive moral 
instruction and a direction for reconciliation from a priest that benefits all 
in society (much as does a lawyer for a client who confesses to past 
wrongdoing).

But another reason for this kind of religious accommodation of something so 
central to a faith is to consider what kind of a society we would be without 
it.  To tell someone that a basic sacrament or what is directly related to the 
sacramental nature of the church – whether it be use of an intoxicating 
substance in communion, confession to a priest to be reconciled to God, 
selection of ministers by apostolic succession – is forbidden or subject to the 
intrusive examination and regulation of the government should be most 
disturbing of all.  Without an accommodation to Catholic churches on use of 
wine during prohibition or in a dry county, without protection of the 
confidentiality of the confessional through a privilege, without selection of 
priests by apostolic succession free of the kind of government rules and 
judicial monitoring that are imposed by anti-discrimination statutes, the 
Catholic faith simply could not be observed in this country – other than by 
resort to underground groups and dissident activities.  (And, I recognize, 
other less mainstream faiths would be even more likely to suffer such 
governmental invasion, as witness the plight of Native American religions and 
others).

To be sure, there are and have been governments that require clergy to serve an 
informants on the people – not just to what they have witnessed as wrongdoing 
but what they hear through confession by the people.  And we have seen 
governments that demand a role in selecting or approving bishops and other 
ministers.  The China of today and the Poland of the communist era come most 
readily to mind.  That is not the kind of government that we Americans claim to 
have.

Those of us of faith appreciate that on many things we may be forced on a 
regular basis to balance that which is a demand of or influence from our faith 
against our civic duties and the strictures of the secular order.  I believe 
strongly that accommodation on many of these matters is appropriate, but 
appreciate that reasonable people will be of differing viewpoints in 
application in many instances.  Governmental control over sacraments, though, 
is quite another thing, ratcheting up the violation of religious freedom to a 
much higher level.  When worship itself is subjected to governmental monitoring 
and regulation, religious freedom becomes a hollow pledge.

I am not given to hyperbole.  I am more likely to be saddened than outraged 
when I see religious rights violated in this country.  And, as noted, I 
frequently can appreciate, if not be persuaded by, the opposing viewpoint.  I 
recoil from those, on both left and right, who exaggerate a dispute of the 
moment and contemplate an apocalyptic outcome justifying an extreme response.  
And I roll my eyes when some self-important celebrity or commentator threatens 
to leave the country if this or that policy is enacted or this or that 
politician is elected (and wish they would carry through on the threat 
afterward).  But a government that overreaches so far as to deny me the 
sacrament of confession, for example, would be a society to which I could no 
longer give my loyalty as a citizen.  Fortunately, despite some worrying 
remarks here and there, now and then, I remain confident that my fellow 
citizens will not bring us to that sad state of affairs.

Greg Sisk

Gregory Sisk
Laghi Distinguished Chair in Law
University of St. Thomas School of Law (Minnesota)
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN  55403-2005
651-962-4923
gcs...@stthomas.edu
http://personal.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.htmlhttp://personal2.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.html
Publications:  http://ssrn.com/author=44545
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-04 Thread Alan Brownstein
Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third parties; 
for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress as do the 
mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech that does not 
quite violate Brandenburg can incite violence. Further, the cost to the public 
in protecting speech can be extraordinarily high. cities incurred tens of 
thousands of dollars in police and other costs while trying to maintain order 
during Operation Rescue protests. Criminal procedure rights can make it more 
difficult to apprehend and punish people who commit crimes. Property rights can 
make it more difficult to protect the environment. Rights have always been 
expensive politcal goods.



It is true that the Establishment Clause imposes some constitutional 
constraints on the costs government may incur or impose on third parties in 
protecting religious liberty. Arguing that free exercise rights or statutory 
religious liberty rights should only be protected in situations in which doing 
so imposes virtually no costs on either the public or third parties, however, 
would treat religious liberty differently than almost all other rights and 
dramatically undermine their utility for people attempting to exercise such 
rights.


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 5:53 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I think Marc’s point is solid and underappreciated.  Following up on it, does 
anyone know of any literature that tries to think about “burdens on third 
parties” across constitutional rights?  We accept such burdens as a matter of 
course with defamation law, as Marc notes.  Yet we also accept them in other 
contexts.  Guns would be one obvious example.  But also think of, for example, 
busing during the Civil Rights Era.  White suburban families had to accept 
busing of their kids to distant and sometimes difficult schools, because 
desegregation was that important.  Or think about abortion: I think the Court 
was right to hold spousal consent and notification laws unconstitutional, but 
there are real issues of third-party harms there too.

Best, Chris



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-04 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
Greg’s argument is obviously quite eloquent.  But I think it is telling that it 
is really predicated on Catholic theology, including the “sacramental” nature 
of confession and the joint duty of the penitent/sinner to confess and of the 
priest to keep the confession confidential.  And, of course, there is rarely 
any difficulty in identifying who counts as a “priest.”  There is an almost 
2000-year-old institution one of whose main functions is ordaining a special 
group of people who can engage in certain sacramental roles.  I’ve already 
indicated that I’m inclined to be sympathetic to such claims because of the 
theology they’re connected with (whether or not, of course, I subscribe to it 
myself).  But I’m not clear why this just justify the broader privilege.  It’s 
telling as well, isn’t it, that we refer to it a privilege attaching to the 
“clergy” rather than simply to priests, and it’s not clear what it means to 
call non-Catholics “penitents.”  If there’s a) no religious duty to confess; b) 
no religious duty to preserve confidences; and c) a belief that breach of 
either duty will generate some kind of divine sanction (including in the 
afterlife), then I continue not to see the difference between, say, a rabbi and 
a truly empathetic hairdresser.  Indeed, as suggested earlier, I find it 
difficult to distinguish as well between a legally-recognized spouse and, say, 
a “work-spouse,” let alone, of course, in those states that don’t recognize 
same-sex marriage, a member of a “civil union.”  (I assume, for example, that 
Texas does not recognize a “spousal privilege” of a legally-married same-sex 
couple from Massachusetts who have been transferred to Texas to serve military 
duty.  Am I wrong?)

I share Greg’s fear of the totalitarian state that calls on us to inform on one 
another, but that is precisely the state we live in today, save for those very 
few people lucky enough to be able to claim a strong testimonial privilege.  
But, as in all “equal protection” cases, there are millions of others who are 
similarly situated.  Is the solution to give millions more people such 
privileges or to pare down the existing privileges to those that can survive 
intellectual challenge?

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sisk, Gregory C.
Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 10:27 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Many reasons can be offered for the venerable privilege that originated as the 
priest-penitent privilege, including as Doug notes that the penitent having the 
confidence that confession is sacrosanct will be willing to share that which he 
or she withholds from all others and thereby be in a position to receive moral 
instruction and a direction for reconciliation from a priest that benefits all 
in society (much as does a lawyer for a client who confesses to past 
wrongdoing).

But another reason for this kind of religious accommodation of something so 
central to a faith is to consider what kind of a society we would be without 
it.  To tell someone that a basic sacrament or what is directly related to the 
sacramental nature of the church – whether it be use of an intoxicating 
substance in communion, confession to a priest to be reconciled to God, 
selection of ministers by apostolic succession – is forbidden or subject to the 
intrusive examination and regulation of the government should be most 
disturbing of all.  Without an accommodation to Catholic churches on use of 
wine during prohibition or in a dry county, without protection of the 
confidentiality of the confessional through a privilege, without selection of 
priests by apostolic succession free of the kind of government rules and 
judicial monitoring that are imposed by anti-discrimination statutes, the 
Catholic faith simply could not be observed in this country – other than by 
resort to underground groups and dissident activities.  (And, I recognize, 
other less mainstream faiths would be even more likely to suffer such 
governmental invasion, as witness the plight of Native American religions and 
others).

To be sure, there are and have been governments that require clergy to serve an 
informants on the people – not just to what they have witnessed as wrongdoing 
but what they hear through confession by the people.  And we have seen 
governments that demand a role in selecting or approving bishops and other 
ministers.  The China of today and the Poland of the communist era come most 
readily to mind.  That is not the kind of government that we Americans claim to 
have.

Those of us of faith appreciate that on many things we may be forced on a 
regular basis to balance that which is a demand of or influence from our faith 
against our civic duties and the strictures of the secular order.  I believe 
strongly that accommodation on many of these matters is 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-04 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
everyone.  What is distinctive about the clergy-penitent privilege is that it 
protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to unburden 
themselves to sympathetic listeners but can't assume that it is protected in 
the same way.  Aren't we back to the conundra involving conscientious 
objection and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court could adopt Paul 
Tillich and say that secularists, too, have ultimate concerns equivalent to 
religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar move with regard to clergy 
privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger (assuming, at least, one 
version of the facts in that case, which may or may not be entirely correct) 
and Widmar v. Vincent on equality grounds, i.e., those who are religious 
should not be selected out for worse treatment than those who are secular.  If 
I can use a facility for meetings of my philosophy club, then I think that 
others should be free to use the facility for meetings of the Good News Club. 
 But it is telling that we're talking about a privilege that is denied to 
each and every secular person (unless they can afford a shrink, though even 
there the privilege is significantly more constrained than is the case with a 
priest), and equality arguments go by the boards.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 11:35 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties


Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third parties; 
for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress as do the 
mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech that does not 
quite violate Brandenburg can incite violence. Further, the cost to the public 
in protecting speech can be extraordinarily high. cities incurred tens of 
thousands of dollars in police and other costs while trying to maintain order 
during Operation Rescue protests. Criminal procedure rights can make it more 
difficult to apprehend and punish people who commit crimes. Property rights can 
make it more difficult to protect the environment. Rights have always been 
expensive politcal goods.



It is true that the Establishment Clause imposes some constitutional 
constraints on the costs government may incur or impose on third parties in 
protecting religious liberty. Arguing that free exercise rights or statutory 
religious liberty rights should only be protected in situations in which doing 
so imposes virtually no costs on either the public or third parties, however, 
would treat religious liberty differently than almost all other rights and 
dramatically undermine their utility for people attempting to exercise such 
rights.


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Christopher Lund 
[l...@wayne.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 5:53 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
I think Marc's point is solid and underappreciated.  Following up on it, does 
anyone know of any literature that tries to think about burdens on third 
parties across constitutional rights?  We accept such burdens as a matter of 
course with defamation law, as Marc notes.  Yet we also accept them in other 
contexts.  Guns would be one obvious example.  But also think of, for example, 
busing during the Civil Rights Era.  White suburban families had to accept 
busing of their kids to distant and sometimes difficult schools, because 
desegregation was that important.  Or think about abortion: I think the Court 
was right to hold spousal consent and notification laws unconstitutional, but 
there are real issues of third-party harms there too.

Best, Chris



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including punishment 
in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs to innocent 
third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy differently from 
one's best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when the 
result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being denied 
the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike with the 
conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent exemption is indeed 
limited to religious communications, with no secular philosophical analog.  
(The psychotherapist-patient privilege, I think, is quite different, partly 
because it requires communications to someone who is licensed by the state, 
requires a state-prescribed course of training, and is usually quite expensive, 
and partly because it tends to have fewer exceptions.)

Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by 
hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular 
exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious objector 
exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of contraceptive 
benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for the employer 
mandate.

Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think that Don 
has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she wants Carl to 
be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has been exempted from 
the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions) duty to testify as a 
result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As a result, she doesn't 
win the $500,000 that she would have been legally entitled to but for the 
clergy-congregant privilege.

Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to testify 
in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds that it 
imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why would the 
application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer mandate an 
Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege. 

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner. 

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
 parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
 penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when 
 the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative 
 evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being denied 
the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike with the 
conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent exemption is indeed 
limited to religious communications, with no secular philosophical analog.  
(The psychotherapist-patient privilege, I think, is quite different, partly 
because it requires communications to someone who is licensed by the state, 
requires a state-prescribed course of training, and is usually quite 
expensive, and partly because it tends to have fewer exceptions.)

Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by 
hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular 
exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious objector 
exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of 
contraceptive benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for 
the employer mandate.

Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think that Don 
has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she wants Carl 
to be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has been exempted 
from the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions) duty to testify as 
a result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As a result, she doesn't 
win the $500,000 that she would have been legally entitled to but for the 
clergy-congregant privilege.

Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to testify 
in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds that it 
imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why would the 
application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer mandate an 
Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?

Eugene

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I strongly suspect that Doug is right.  Still, I do wonder how often cases do 
arise beyond the Catholic Church (which probably fulfills my conditions for the 
privilege).

sandy

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu] 
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 10:06 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Levinson, Sanford V
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege. 

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner. 

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
(religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
 parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
 penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when 
 the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative 
 evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being 
denied the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike 
with the conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent 
exemption is indeed limited to religious communications, with no 
secular philosophical analog.  (The psychotherapist-patient privilege, 
I think, is quite different, partly because it requires communications 
to someone who is licensed by the state, requires a state-prescribed 
course of training, and is usually quite expensive, and partly because 
it tends to have fewer exceptions.)

Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by 
hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular 
exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious objector 
exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of 
contraceptive benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for 
the employer mandate.

Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think that Don 
has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she wants Carl 
to be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has been exempted 
from the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions) duty to testify as 
a result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As a result, she doesn't 
win the $500,000 that she would have been legally entitled to but for the 
clergy-congregant privilege.

Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to testify 
in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds that it 
imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why would the 
application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer mandate an 
Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?

Eugene

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law University of Virginia Law School
580 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Ira Lupu
And the clergy-penitent privilege is one of many such privileges --
doctor-patient, lawyer-client, spousal privilege, etc.  They are designed
to encourage communication within relationships the law values.  So this
example is like Walz -- it does not involve special treatment for religion.
 It is that kind of special treatment that triggers the concern for third
party harms (Estate of Thornton v. Caldor).


On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:05 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the
 least sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't
 describe very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would
 confess to their priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks
 who confessed. The word would obviously get around to perps that this is
 what priests do when you confess.

 So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the
 privilege deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the
 privilege.

 Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases,
 toward encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American
 case on the privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and
 returned them to the owner.

 On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
  Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
 This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only
 justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to
 confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question
 believes that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't
 be enough that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless
 divine punishment is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years
 that the only defense of religious privileges is the belief on the part of
 the claimant that commission of the act in question will generate divine
 sanctions.  This is probably too strict, since I (still) support the
 critique of Smith, and I have no reason to believe that the ingestion of
 peyote was a divine command violation of which would generate some kind of
 punishment (including punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo
 makes very real the costs to innocent third parties of treating any and all
 members of the clergy differently from
   one's
 best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.
 
 sandy
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
 Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
 
 One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on
 third parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy
 (and penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even
 when the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly
 probative evidence.
 
 What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being
 denied the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike
 with the conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent exemption is
 indeed limited to religious communications, with no secular philosophical
 analog.  (The psychotherapist-patient privilege, I think, is quite
 different, partly because it requires communications to someone who is
 licensed by the state, requires a state-prescribed course of training, and
 is usually quite expensive, and partly because it tends to have fewer
 exceptions.)
 
 Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by
 hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some
 secular exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious
 objector exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of
 contraceptive benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for
 the employer mandate.
 
 Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think
 that Don has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she
 wants Carl to be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has
 been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions)
 duty to testify as a result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As
 a result, she doesn't win the $500,000 that she would have been legally
 entitled to but for the clergy-congregant privilege.
 
 Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to
 testify in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds
 that it imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why
 would the application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer
 mandate an Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?
 
 Eugene

 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Well, people do talk incautiously in contexts where no privilege is 
available, and their statements are used as a result.  Some people might not 
talk if they knew a privilege was unavailable, but others still might, 
especially if they feel they need to unburden themselves, and even more 
especially if they feel that such confession is a religious necessity.  (As I 
understand it, for instance, many psychiatrists' patients do say things to the 
psychiatrists that alert the psychiatrists to a danger to third parties, even 
though there is an exception to the privilege and to professional ethics in 
such situations, and even though under Tarasoff psychiatrists sometimes have a 
duty to disclose such threats.  Not a perfect analogy, I realize, but I hope a 
helpful one.)

So the consequence is that some litigants would not have benefited from 
the absence of a clergy-penitent privilege, since the penitent wouldn't have 
confessed.  But others would have, and I would think that there would be a 
considerable number of such others.  Under the Establishment Clause burden on 
nonbeneficiaries argument, why should it be necessary that the $500,000 loss 
to Barbara be guaranteed, as opposed to simply happening with some regularity 
to people in Barbara's shoes?

Eugene

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:40 PM
To: Douglas Laycock; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I strongly suspect that Doug is right.  Still, I do wonder how often cases do 
arise beyond the Catholic Church (which probably fulfills my conditions for the 
privilege).

sandy

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu]
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 10:06 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Levinson, Sanford V
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege. 

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner. 

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
(religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
 parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
 penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when 
 the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative 
 evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being 
denied the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike 
with the conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent 
exemption is indeed limited to religious communications, with no 
secular philosophical analog.  (The psychotherapist-patient 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I don't think that's right.  First, recall that the employer 
mandate exemption is supposed to be one of at least a few such exemptions 
(grandfathered plans and under-50-person plans being the other ones); fewer 
than the privileges, but not by that much.

Second, as I mentioned, the clergy-penitent privilege is 
unusually strong -- in California, as I understand it, it has no exemptions, 
while the others have some pretty big ones (e.g., the doctor-patient privilege 
doesn't apply at all to criminal cases, Cal. Evid. Code 998, and there are many 
exceptions to the spousal privilege and the lawyer-client privilege).  It is 
also unusually easy to get:  Unlike with doctors, lawyers, psychotherapists, 
there is no requirement of government licensure or extended professional 
training (though of course some but not all religions do require extended 
training as a matter of their own practice).  Perhaps because of this, for many 
people a clergyman is the only person whose sympathetic ear and helpful counsel 
they can get for free, which doubtless makes it easier for the clergy to spread 
their own messages as part of such counsel.

In that sense, the closer analogy isn't Walz but, I would 
think, Texas Monthly.  There too there were doubtless many products that were 
exempt from sales tax (most food items being the classic example in most 
states).  But this wasn't enough:  The fact that Texas grants other sales tax 
exemptions (e. g., for sales of food, agricultural items, and property used in 
the manufacture of articles for ultimate sale) for different purposes does not 
rescue the exemption for religious periodicals from invalidation. What is 
crucial is that any subsidy afforded religious organizations be warranted by 
some overarching secular purpose that justifies like benefits for nonreligious 
groups. There is no evidence in the record, and Texas does not argue in its 
brief to this Court, that the exemption for religious periodicals was grounded 
in some secular legislative policy that motivated similar tax breaks for 
nonreligious activities. It certainly appears that the exemption was intended 
to benefit religion alone.  Likewise, the purpose of the clergy-penitent 
privilege is quite different from that of the spousal privilege, the 
lawyer-client privilege, and the doctor-patient privilege, and I think 
different even from the psychotherapist-patient privilege (where the 
resemblance is stronger but still on balance quite distant).

This isn't to say that Texas Monthly necessarily invalidates the 
clergy-penitent privilege -- the privilege does lift a government-imposed 
substantial burden on religious practice, and it isn't as clearly a preference 
for propagation of religious ideas (which is what the concurrences stressed).  
I just don't think that the clergy-penitent privilege can be saved on the 
grounds that it does not involve special treatment for religion.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

And the clergy-penitent privilege is one of many such privileges -- 
doctor-patient, lawyer-client, spousal privilege, etc.  They are designed to 
encourage communication within relationships the law values.  So this example 
is like Walz -- it does not involve special treatment for religion.  It is that 
kind of special treatment that triggers the concern for third party harms 
(Estate of Thornton v. Caldor).

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:05 PM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege.

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner.

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I once wrote an article, Testimonial Privileges and the Preferences of 
Friendship, 1984 DUKE LAW JOURNAL 631-662 (1984), the general thesis of which 
is that there is no truly plausible general theory of such privileges. (The 
title, incidentally, comes from Rousseau, who wrote that the preferences of 
friendship are thefts committed against the fatherland.   All men are our 
brothers; all should be our friends.  No doubt there's something scary in that 
notion, but it also captures the often-arbitrary partiality in allowing a small 
subset of individuals to refuse to offer evidence of criminal (or even 
tortious) behavior.   But if one does defend such partialities and loyalties, 
then why must one be married, for example (especially in the modern world) to 
get an intimacy privilege, and why, exactly, do family members (other than 
spouses) have no privileges?  Well-off people can go to psychiatrists, while 
less well-off talk to their bartenders and hairdressers (or, simply, best 
friends or workmates, none of whom are covered.  Are nurse-practitioners (who 
will play an increasingly important role in the delivery of medical services) 
covered (a genuine, not a rhetorical, question, since I don't know what the 
answer is, and if it varies state by state, do we really expect ordinary people 
to realize whether they are protected or not)?   In that article, I offered the 
thought-experiment of privilege tickets, a limited number of which we would 
get when we turned 18 and could distribute throughout our lifetimes to those we 
wished to immunize from state inquiries.

Maybe the real question is what is contained within Chip's etc.  If there are 
literally dozens of privileges, then one can engage in a gestalt switch and say 
that it is discriminating against the clergy to deny them what
A-Y get.  But if we're really talking about a small subset of people (none of 
whom get the kind of absolute privilege that the clergy apparently get), then 
I must say it looks an awful lot like Establishment to me, and I find Eugene's 
reference to the Texas Monthly case very persuasive.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 10:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

And the clergy-penitent privilege is one of many such privileges -- 
doctor-patient, lawyer-client, spousal privilege, etc.  They are designed to 
encourage communication within relationships the law values.  So this example 
is like Walz -- it does not involve special treatment for religion.  It is that 
kind of special treatment that triggers the concern for third party harms 
(Estate of Thornton v. Caldor).

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:05 PM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege.

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner.

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: