https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/03/03/was-wittgenstein-right/

*Was Wittgenstein Right?*
BY PAUL HORWICH 
MARCH 3, 2013

A reminder of philosophy’s embarrassing failure, after over 2000 years, to 
settle any of its central issues.


The singular achievement of the controversial early 20th century 
philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein was to have discerned the true nature of 
Western philosophy — what is special about its problems, where they come 
from, how they should and should not be addressed, and what can and cannot 
be accomplished by grappling with them. The uniquely insightful answers 
provided to these meta-questions are what give his treatments of specific 
issues within the subject — concerning language, experience, knowledge, 
mathematics, art and religion among them — a power of illumination that 
cannot be found in the work of others.

Admittedly, few would agree with this rosy assessment — certainly not many 
professional philosophers. Apart from a small and ignored clique of 
hard-core supporters the usual view these days is that his writing is 
self-indulgently obscure and that behind the catchy slogans there is little 
of intellectual value. But this dismissal disguises what is pretty clearly 
the real cause of Wittgenstein’s unpopularity within departments of 
philosophy: namely, his thoroughgoing rejection of the subject as 
traditionally and currently practiced; his insistence that it can’t give us 
the kind of knowledge generally regarded as its raison d’être.

Wittgenstein claims that there are no realms of phenomena whose study is 
the special business of a philosopher, and about which he or she should 
devise profound a priori theories and sophisticated supporting arguments. 
There are no startling discoveries to be made of facts, not open to the 
methods of science, yet accessible “from the armchair” through some blend 
of intuition, pure reason and conceptual analysis. Indeed the whole idea of 
a subject that could yield such results is based on confusion and wishful 
thinking.

This attitude is in stark opposition to the traditional view, which 
continues to prevail. Philosophy is respected, even exalted, for its 
promise to provide fundamental insights into the human condition and the 
ultimate character of the universe, leading to vital conclusions about how 
we are to arrange our lives. It’s taken for granted that there is deep 
understanding to be obtained of the nature of consciousness, of how 
knowledge of the external world is possible, of whether our decisions can 
be truly free, of the structure of any just society, and so on — and that 
philosophy’s job is to provide such understanding. Isn’t that why we are so 
fascinated by it?

If so, then we are duped and bound to be disappointed, says Wittgenstein. 
For these are mere pseudo-problems, the misbegotten products of linguistic 
illusion and muddled thinking. So it should be entirely unsurprising that 
the “philosophy” aiming to solve them has been marked by perennial 
controversy and lack of decisive progress — by an embarrassing failure, 
after over 2000 years, to settle any of its central issues. Therefore 
traditional philosophical theorizing must give way to a painstaking 
identification of its tempting but misguided presuppositions and an 
understanding of how we ever came to regard them as legitimate. But in that 
case, he asks, “[w]here does [our] investigation get its importance from, 
since it seems only to destroy everything interesting, that is, all that is 
great and important? (As it were all the buildings, leaving behind only 
bits of stone and rubble)” — and answers that “(w)hat we are destroying is 
nothing but houses of cards and we are clearing up the ground of language 
on which they stand.”

Given this extreme pessimism about the potential of philosophy — perhaps 
tantamount to a denial that there is such a subject — it is hardly 
surprising that “Wittgenstein” is uttered with a curl of the lip in most 
philosophical circles. For who likes to be told that his or her life’s work 
is confused and pointless? Thus, even Bertrand Russell, his early teacher 
and enthusiastic supporter, was eventually led to complain peevishly that 
Wittgenstein seems to have “grown tired of serious thinking and invented a 
doctrine which would make such an activity unnecessary.”

But what is that notorious doctrine, and can it be defended? We might boil 
it down to four related claims.

— The first is that traditional philosophy is scientistic: its primary 
goals, which are to arrive at simple, general principles, to uncover 
profound explanations, and to correct naïve opinions, are taken from the 
sciences. And this is undoubtedly the case.

—The second is that the non-empirical (“armchair”) character of 
philosophical investigation — its focus on conceptual truth — is in tension 
with those goals.  That’s because our concepts exhibit a highly 
theory-resistant complexity and variability. They evolved, not for the sake 
of science and its objectives, but rather in order to cater to the 
interacting contingencies of our nature, our culture, our environment, our 
communicative needs and our other purposes.  As a consequence the 
commitments defining individual concepts are rarely simple or determinate, 
and differ dramatically from one concept to another. Moreover, it is not 
possible (as it is within empirical domains) to accommodate superficial 
complexity by means of simple principles at a more basic (e.g. microscopic) 
level.

— The third main claim of Wittgenstein’s metaphilosophy — an immediate 
consequence of the first two — is that traditional philosophy is 
necessarily pervaded with oversimplification; analogies are unreasonably 
inflated; exceptions to simple regularities are wrongly dismissed.

— Therefore — the fourth claim — a decent approach to the subject must 
avoid theory-construction and instead be merely “therapeutic,” confined to 
exposing the irrational assumptions on which theory-oriented investigations 
are based and the irrational conclusions to which they lead.

Consider, for instance, the paradigmatically philosophical question: “What 
is truth?”. This provokes perplexity because, on the one hand, it demands 
an answer of the form, “Truth is such–and-such,” but on the other hand, 
despite hundreds of years of looking, no acceptable answer of that kind has 
ever been found. We’ve tried truth as “correspondence with the facts,” as 
“provability,” as “practical utility,” and as “stable consensus”; but all 
turned out to be defective in one way or another — either circular or 
subject to counterexamples. Reactions to this impasse have included a 
variety of theoretical proposals.  Some philosophers have been led to deny 
that there is such a thing as absolute truth. Some have maintained 
(insisting on one of the above definitions) that although truth exists, it 
lacks certain features that are ordinarily attributed to it — for example, 
that the truth may sometimes be impossible to discover. Some have inferred 
that truth is intrinsically paradoxical and essentially incomprehensible. 
And others persist in the attempt to devise a definition that will fit all 
the intuitive data.

But from Wittgenstein’s perspective each of the first three of these 
strategies rides roughshod over our fundamental convictions about truth, 
and the fourth is highly unlikely to succeed. Instead we should begin, he 
thinks, by recognizing (as mentioned above) that our various concepts play 
very different roles in our cognitive economy and (correspondingly) are 
governed by defining principles of very different kinds. Therefore, it was 
always a mistake to extrapolate from the fact that empirical concepts, such 
as red or magnetic  or alive stand for properties with specifiable 
underlying natures to the presumption that the notion of truth must stand 
for some such property as well.

Wittgenstein’s conceptual pluralism positions us to recognize that notion’s 
idiosyncratic function, and to infer that truth itself will not be 
reducible to anything more basic. More specifically, we can see that the 
concept’s function in our cognitive economy is merely to serve as a device 
of generalization. It enables us to say such things as “Einstein’s last 
words were true,” and not be stuck with “If Einstein’s last words were that 
E=mc², then E=mc2; and if his last words were that nuclear weapons should 
be banned, then nuclear weapons should be banned; … and so on,” which has 
the disadvantage of being infinitely long!  Similarly we can use it to say: 
“We should want our beliefs to be true” (instead of struggling with “We 
should want that if we believe that E=mc², then E=mc²; and that if we 
believe … etc.”). We can see, also, that this sort of utility depends upon 
nothing more than the fact that the attribution of truth to a statement is 
obviously equivalent to the statement itself — for example, “It’s true that 
E=mc²” is equivalent to “E=mc²”. Thus possession of the concept of truth 
appears to consist in an appreciation of that triviality, rather than a 
mastery of any explicit definition. The traditional search for such an 
account (or for some other form of reductive analysis) was a wild-goose 
chase, a pseudo-problem. Truth emerges as exceptionally unprofound and as 
exceptionally unmysterious.

This example illustrates the key components of Wittgenstein’s 
metaphilosophy, and suggests how to flesh them out a little further. 
Philosophical problems typically arise from the clash between the 
inevitably idiosyncratic features of special-purpose concepts —true, good, 
object, person, now, necessary — and the scientistically driven insistence 
upon uniformity. Moreover, the various kinds of theoretical move designed 
to resolve such conflicts (forms of skepticism, revisionism, mysterianism 
and conservative systematization) are not only irrational, but 
unmotivated.The paradoxes to which they respond should instead be resolved 
merely by coming to appreciate the mistakes of perverse overgeneralization 
from which they arose. And the fundamental source of this irrationality is 
scientism.

As Wittgenstein put it in the “The Blue Book”:

Our craving for generality has [as one] source … our preoccupation with the 
method of science. I mean the method of reducing the explanation of natural 
phenomena to the smallest possible number of primitive natural laws; and, 
in mathematics, of unifying the treatment of different topics by using a 
generalization. Philosophers constantly see the method of science before 
their eyes, and are irresistibly tempted to ask and answer in the way 
science does. This tendency is the real source of metaphysics, and leads 
the philosopher into complete darkness. I want to say here that it can 
never be our job to reduce anything to anything, or to explain anything. 
Philosophy really is “purely descriptive.

These radical ideas are not obviously correct, and may on close scrutiny 
turn out to be wrong. But they deserve to receive that scrutiny — to be 
taken much more seriously than they are. Yes, most of us have been 
interested in philosophy only because of its promise to deliver precisely 
the sort of theoretical insights that Wittgenstein argues are illusory. But 
such hopes are no defense against his critique. Besides, if he turns out to 
be right, satisfaction enough may surely be found in what we still can get 
— clarity, demystification and truth.

NOTE: A response to this post by Michael P. Lynch will be published in The 
Stone later this week.
[ 
https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/03/05/of-flies-and-philosophers-wittgenstein-and-philosophy/
 
]

Paul Horwich is a professor of philosophy at New York University. He is the 
author of several books, including “Reflections on Meaning,” 
“Truth-Meaning-Reality,” and most recently, “Wittgenstein’s Metaphilosophy.”
[  https://as.nyu.edu/content/nyu-as/as/faculty/paul-g-horwich.html ]


cf.
*Language Games, Writing Games - Wittgenstein and Derrida: A Comparative 
Study*
Jolán Orbán
https://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Lang/LangOrba.htm


@philipthrift

-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email 
to everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion on the web visit 
https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/e01a036f-bde5-4b15-ad17-c845ba538ad0%40googlegroups.com.

Reply via email to