JF:>>This, in part at least,
was a consequence of Stalin's
regime opting to support the
'reflexology' of Ivan Pavlov
and Vladimir Bekhterev.
While we in the West tend
to think of Pavlov as having
been a psychologist, he
did not view himself as
such.  He was trained
as a physiologist and
he always saw himself as
a physiologist.  He described
his famous work on conditioned
reflexes as part of the physiology
of the higher nervous system.
He was generally dismissive
of psychology which he
tended to view as a kind
of pseudo-science.<<

But the agendas behind 'reflexology' weren't just physiology, were
they? Not when you turn to the shared concerns that emerge from
medicine, social sciences, logics and math, and philosophy.

Perhaps Pavlov was skeptical that the various concerns that converged
under the label 'psychology' would ever come together in some unified
approach to research.

It's also informative to see what two of his more important
contemporaries outside the Soviet Union thought about such
matters--such as Stumpf and Wundt. In retrospect we can see that
psychology never did come together as a unified science, and
contradictory approaches and philosophies don't so much compete as
they do co-exist (often quite ignorant of each other). Finally, it's
interesting to note how Vygotsky points out that the crisis is
actually a 'bottom up' one, and not simply the concern of
theoreticians.

See:

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/stumpf/#PsyMin

1. Biographical Sketch

Stumpf's intellectual biography is rich and complex due to his long
university career that lasted more than 50 years, his academic
achievements, and his philosophical work. To complete this
biographical sketch, the reader is invited to consult Stumpf's
autobiography (published in 1924) and Sprung's biography, published in
German under the title Carl Stumpf – Eine Biografie (2006).
1848    Carl Friedrich Stumpf was born on April 21, 1848 in Wiesentheid
in Franconia, Germany.
1859-1863       Attended the Gymnasium in Bamberg; studied music and
composed several pieces.
1864-1865       Attended the Gymnasium in Aschaffenburg where he studied
Plato with Hocheder.
1865    Entered the University of Würzburg; during his first year, he
studied aesthetics and law.
1866    Met Franz Brentano on July 14, during the disputatio for his
habilitation and then decided to study philosophy with Brentano.
During the period from 1867 to 1870 he attended Brentano's lectures on
the history of philosophy, metaphysics, Comte and the positivists, and
logic.
1867-1868       Because Brentano had not been habilitated to supervise
dissertations, he recommended that Stumpf study with Hermann Lotze in
Göttingen; Stumpf attended Lotze's lectures on psychology, history of
philosophy since Kant, philosophy of nature, and practical philosophy;
he also took courses from the physiologist G. Meissner and the
physician W. Weber.
1868    Graduated on August 13, 1868 with a dissertation on Plato and
then returned to Würzburg in order to study with Brentano.
1869-1870       Entered the ecclesiastical seminary in Würzburg and due to
the influence of Brentano and Lotze, he resigned in July 1870.
1870    Returned to Göttingen to prepare his habilitation on
mathematical axioms under the supervision of Lotze and successfully
defended it in October 1870.
1870-1873       Lectured at the University of Göttingen where he founded
the Eskimo society along with mathematician Felix Klein; he also met
Fechner and probably Frege, who studied in Göttingen during this
period.
1873    Published an important treatise on the origin of space
perception, and dedicated it to Lotze.
1873-1879       Appointed to his first professorship at the University of
Würzburg at the age of 25 to replace Brentano, who moved to Vienna in
1874.
1878    Married Hermine Biedermann (1849-1930).
1879-1884       Moved to Prague and in 1880 his friend Anton Marty arrived
there; Marty was a professor there until the end of his career; Stumpf
developed professional contacts with Mach and maintained a close
relationship with Ewald Hering.
1882    Visited by William James in Prague, and this encounter marked
the beginning of a lasting friendship between both philosophers.
1883    Published the first volume of Tonpsychologie.
1884-1889       Replaced Ulrici at the University of Halle and became a
colleague of Georg Cantor and J. E. Erdmann.
1887    Husserl published his habilitation thesis on the origin of the
concept of number, which was supervised by Stumpf.
1889-1894       Arrived in Munich in 1889 as successor to Prantl.
1890    Published the second volume of Tonpsychologie; he also worked
with H. Ebbinghaus, H. von Helmholtz, and G. E. Müller, among others,
on the prestigious journal Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie
der Sinnesorgane, of which Stumpf was one of the founding editors.
1891    Involved in a controversy with Wundt and his students on
experiments and on Fechner's law.
1894    Joined the philosophy faculty in Berlin after a long period of
hesitation; this marked the beginning of a new era in his intellectual
life.
1896    Presided at the third International Congress of Psychology in Munich.
1898    Founded the Beiträge zur Akustik und Musikwissenschaft, which
contains many treatises written by Stumpf and his students.
1900    Founded the Institute of Psychology in Berlin, which gave rise
to Gestalt Psychology; started the Phonogramm-Archiv in Berlin,
including some phonographic recordings of a Siamese company performing
in Berlin; in the same year, along with Kemsies, he started the Berlin
Gesellschaft für Kinderpsychologie.
1900-1901       Husserl's groundwork Logical Investigations was published
and dedicated to Stumpf.
1904    Asked by the Board of Education to investigate the well-known
case of “clever Hans”; and in 1907 the results of this investigation
were published by Stumpf and his assistant O. Pfungst in the book
Clever Hans (The Horse of Mr. von Osten): A Contribution to
Experimental Animal and Human Psychology.
1906    Published three important treatises, which were extensively
discussed by philosophers and psychologists: “Erscheinungen und
psychische Funktionen,” “Zur Einteilung der Wissenschaften” and Über
Gefühlsempfindungen.”
1907-1909       Accepted the honorific position of rector of the University
of Berlin; pronounced his first address “Renaissance of Philosophy” on
the state of philosophy since Lotze.
1908    Robert Musil, the author of The Man without Qualities, wrote a
dissertation on Mach under the supervision of Stumpf.
1909    Wolfgang Köhler received his PhD with a dissertation supervised
by Stumpf and published under the title “Akustische Untersuchungen I;”
Travelled to Cambridge to celebrate the 100th anniversary of Darwin.
1911    Published Die Anfänge der Musik in which he summarized the
results of his research on ethnomusicology.
1912-1913       Established a station for anthropoids on Tenerife for the
Academy of Sciences; as a member of the Academy, Stumpf recommended
his student Köhler as director of this station; Köhler began his
investigations in 1913, the results of which were published in his
classic book The Mentality of Apes (1917).
1921    Appointed as professor emeritus in Berlin and continued to teach
philosophy in Berlin until Summer 1923.
1922    Köhler succeded Stumpf as director of the Institute of Psychology.
1923    With E. M. von Horbostel, edited four volumes of the classical
Sammelbände für vergleichende Musikwissenschaft. The fourth volume
contains a study on popular music in Romania by the well-known
composor Béla Bartok.
1923    Festschrift in honor of Stumpf's 75th anniversary in the
gestaltist journal Psychologische Forschung; this volume includes
contributions by his students A. Gelb, C. von Allesch, W. Köhler, K.
Koffka, M. Wertheimer, and K. Lewin, among others.
1926    Published the results of extensive research on the nature of
vowels and sounds of speech in Die Sprachlaute;
Experimentell-phonetische Untersuchungen.
1927-1928       Published a short biography on his friend W. James, based
of their correspondence, William James nach seinen Briefen.
1928    Published Gefühl und Gefühlsempfindung, an important collection
of papers on emotions and feelings.
1928    Celebrated his 80th birthday for which an allocution was given
by his friend and colleague Max Planck.
1936    Carl Stumpf died on December 25 in Berlin at the age of 88.
1939-1940       On the recommendation of Max Planck, his son Felix Stumpf
published the two volumes of his monumental work Erkenntnislehre.

What Stumpf calls phenomenology in his two Academy treatises of 1906
is a field of study to which he dedicated many works, from his early
investigation on the origin of spatial perception up to his 1926 book
on vowels and phonetics. Note that this phenomenology is not to be
confused with that of his student Husserl, whether in the latter's
Logical Investigations, in which it is defined as descriptive
psychology, or in his subsequent books, namely the first book of
Ideas, in which it is understood as a transcendental phenomenology,
and refers to a general program in philosophy. On the one hand, the
field of phenomenology in Stumpf's sense is limited to phenomena and
their properties, and is defined narrowly as a science of phenomena;
on the other hand, while recognizing the significant contribution made
by Husserl to phenomenology, Stumpf believes that the very idea of a
“pure” phenomenology in Ideas I is simply a contradiction in itself.
Stumpf's phenomenology is also different from Mach's phenomenalism and
the latter's conception of the objects of physics as “permanent
possibilities of sensation,” to use the expression found in J.S. Mill.
Mach's doctrine of elements, while making an important contribution to
the domain of phenomenology, must be dissociated from his empiricism,
according to which objects of physics, just as those of psychology,
are reducible to elements or to complexes of elements. Stumpf's
reference regarding phenomenology is that of the physiologist E.
Hering. Hering deserves merit for having recognized, for physiology
and psychology, the importance of a preliminary study of phenomena and
having thus conferred a privileged status to the field of
phenomenology, in comparison to that of physics and physiology,
serving as a starting point for empiricists such as Helmholtz. In
fact, by adopting this starting point in Sehdinge, Hering would have
recognized the methodological primacy of phenomenology over the other
sciences and its propaedeutic status in the study of the essential
properties or attributes (space, intensity, brightness, etc.) of sense
phenomena.

The study of formations and of objects of thought in general belongs
to this second neutral science called “eidology,” an expression that
Stumpf borrowed from Herbart. Stumpf first introduced the notion of
formation [Gebilde] in 1902 in order to characterize the specific
contents of functions or what he also calls the objective correlates
of a psychical function. Formations are contents that enter into the
consciousness by carrying out specific functions in the sense that to
every class and subclass of acts there corresponds a certain content
specific to each and every act. All psychical functions, from the
simplest to the most complex, have their specific contents: concepts,
states of affairs and values, to name only the most important ones.
For example, the act of abstraction, which is responsible for the
formation of concepts, namely the concept of space, has a concept as
its own specific content. States of affairs are contents of judgment,
and they are comparable to Meinong's objectives, Husserl's
objectivity, and Bolzano's “proposition in itself,” and they play a
central role in Stumpf's logic. They are “correlates” of thought, and
contrary to individual acts, they have an objective character. The
objectivity of formations, however, is not to be understood in terms
of intentional inexistence (Brentano) or in the sense of Platonic
realism (Bolzano and Frege), because any formation is logically
dependent of the act that produces it, and the existence of states of
affairs is logically linked to that of the act of judgment. States if
affairs are therefore abstracted in the sense that they cannot exist
independently of the acts by which they are produced. The same rule
can be found in the field of more complex functions such as emotions,
desires and voluntary actions, whose specific contents are values. The
very possibility of a neutral science such as eidology shows that we
can study values for themselves, independently of functions. Yet
Stumpf claims that it is not possible to dissociate formations from
their original functions.

Relations form the third group of objects whose study belongs to a
general theory of relations. This theory represents an important part
of logic and of formal ontology whose task, in fact, is to study those
laws governing formal relations between objects and parts of objects.
This aspect of the general theory of relations is comparable to
Husserl's pure logic, while in the field of psychology it corresponds
to what Lotze calls “relational thought” and to the analysis of
elementary mental structures in Dilthey's descriptive psychology. The
relations of structure between psychical functions and the hierarchy
within the domain of simple and complex functions obey what Stumpf
refers to as “laws of structure” between parts or aspects of a whole.
Its task is to establish relations between phenomena, functions, and
formations and to investigate the origins of complex relations in
simple relations, fixed by means of definition, and to determine the
structural laws to which they obey. To these Grundverhälnisse or
fundamental relations belong, among others, the concepts of analogy,
equality, and fusion that Stumpf examines succinctly in the second
volume of Tonpsychologie, as being the relations of logical and real
dependency, the part-whole relations, and relations of real dependency
between psychical functions. These relations are not “forms of
thought” in a Kantian sense; they are not imposed on sensory material
by means of any psychical functions; rather, they are immanent to
phenomena and are perceptible directly and without intermediary.
Sensory contents are noticed or remarked in themselves, and each of
these relations is, to again use the scholastic expression, anens
rationis cum fundamento in re. The notion of fusion designates one of
the forms of relations that structure the sensory material. It defines
itself as the relation between two phenomena (or contents of
sensation) by virtue of which they do not merely form a sum, but a
whole. Stumpf argues that those elements which fuse into a whole, for
example the quality and intensity of sounds in a melody, are not
changed, but that this relation of fusion establishes a narrower unity
between these contents that is perceptible as a gestalt. To use the
well-known case of the melody, moments of quality and of intensity
form in that case a unitary whole which is perceptible as a “quality
of form,” and it is precisely the unitary character of this
perception, the fact that it is perceptible in one stroke and
immediately as unitary form, that Stumpf tries to account for through
his notion of a relation of fusion.

Now, what is the place of philosophy in this classification of
sciences? Considering Stumpf's involvement in the empirical fields of
acoustics and ethnomusicology for example historians of philosophy
have made contradictory judgments as to the philosophical bearing of
his work. However, even in Stumpf's empirical research, philosophy has
always remained the “lady of the house.” It is true that philosophy
must start from below and that this bottom-up procedure is akin to the
methodology of the natural sciences; but Stumpf's philosophy is as
much alien to positivism as it is to constructivism and speculative
philosophy in general. The importance he attached to the research
domain of neutral sciences in philosophy and the task assigned to the
sciences of nature in the study of these domains, clearly shows his
distance from Kantianism. Stumpf believes, however, that the social
sciences, understood as the sciences of complex functions, are
privileged over the sciences of nature for reasons that explicitly
concern the foundational status of descriptive psychology for human
sciences and its central position in philosophy. In this regard, the
philosophical disciplines par excellence, such as logic and ethics,
are based on mental functions which, as we know, belong to the field
of psychology. But philosophy as a whole is also distinct both from
the sciences of nature and from the sciences of mind, in that it is
the most general science of all. It defines itself as the science of
the most general objects or metaphysics. As such, philosophy is prima
philosophia, although in a sense quite different from the classical
metaphysics, since it is meant as being in continuity with existent
sciences. Its tasks are numerous and diverse, ranging from treating
general issues related to time, and space to treating those related to
mind-body problems. One of the questions to which Stumpf paid a
particular attention was that of the psychophysical relations. In his
studies on Spinoza and in his conference entitled “Body and Soul,” for
example, Stumpf criticized the theory of parallelism that was dominant
in the nineteenth century since Fechner, and which had adopted, after
Lotze, the theory of interactionism, which recognizes the causal
action of bodily processes on the psychical and vice versa. This
interactionnism goes hand in hand with a form of critical realism,
according to which the hypothesis of the existence of the
spatiotemporal world is a necessary and unavoidable assumption, one
that is also generally believed in the natural sciences.

--------------------

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wilhelm-wundt/


In founding the experimental science of psychology, Wundt, in effect,
simply “triangulated” a media via between the available options: he
rejected Fechner's mysticism while maintaining his experimental
approach; at the same time, Wundt went beyond the purely physical
interpretation of physiological experiments à la Helmholtz, arguing
that at least in humans experimentation could reveal law-like
regularities of inner (psychological) reality. Thus, to use the phrase
of Ben-David and Collins, he established the “hybrid science” whose
dual provenance is expressed in Wundt's name for it, “physiological
psychology” (Ben-David and Collins, 1966: 459; Kusch, 1995: 122,
ff.).[21]  Wundt's interest, both to scholars of the history of
philosophy and to contemporary philosophers of mind, flows ultimately
from the definition, methodology, and “metaphysics” of this
physiological psychology. Sections 3 and 4 are devoted to a
description of its definition, method, and doctrine, while Section 5
concerns its theoretical underpinnings. The practical and theoretical
limits of experimental psychology will be treated in Section 6, on
Völkerpsychologie.
----------------------

http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/crisis/psycri13.htm

And we assert that this line will lie in between the formulas of
Husserl and Feuerbach. The thing is that in Marxism the problem of
epistemology with regard to psychology has not been stated at all and
the task of distinguishing the two problems about which Høffding is
talking did not arise. The idealists, on the other hand, elaborated
this idea with great clarity. And we claim that the viewpoint of our
“Marxists” is Machism in psychology: it is the identification of being
and consciousness. It is one of two things: either the mind is
directly given to us in introspection, and then we side with Husserl;
or we must distinguish subject and object, being and thinking in it,
and then we side with Feuerbach. But what does this imply? It implies
that my joy and my introspectional comprehension of this joy are
different things.

There is a citation from Feuerbach that is very popular in Russia:
“what for me [or subjectively] is a [purely] mental, non-material,
suprasensory act, is in itself [or objectively] a material, sensory
act” [Feuerbach]. It is usually cited in confirmation of subjective
psychology. But this speaks against it. One may wonder what we must
study: this act as such, as it is, or as it appears to me? As with the
analogous question about the objective existence of the world, the
materialist does not hesitate and says: the objective act as such. The
idealist will say: my perception. But then one and the same act will
turn out to be different depending on whether I am drunk or sober,
whether I am a child or an adult, whether it is today or yesterday,
whether it regards me or you. What is more, it turns out that in
introspection we cannot directly perceive thinking, comparison – these
are unconscious acts and our introspectional comprehension of them is
not a functional concept, i.e., it is not deduced from objective
experience. What must we, what can we study: thinking as such or the
thinking of thinking? There can be no doubt whatsoever about the
answer to this question. But there is one complication which prevents
us from reaching a clear answer. All philosophers who have attempted
to divide psychology have stumbled upon this complication. Stumpf
distinguished mental functions from phenomena and asked who, which
science, will study the phenomena rejected by physics and psychology.
He assumed that a special science would develop which is neither
psychology nor physics. Another psychologist (Pfander, 1904) refused
to accept sensations as the subject matter of psychology for the sole
reason that physics refuses to accept them. What place is left for
them? Husserl’s phenomenology is the answer to this question.

In Russia it is also asked: if you will study thinking as such and not
the thinking of thinking; the act as such and not the act for me; the
objective and not the subjective – who, then, will study the
subjective itself, the subjective distortion of objects? In physics we
try to eliminate the subjective factor from what we perceive as an
object. In psychology, when we study perception it is again required
to separate perception as such, as it is, from how it seems to me. Who
will study what has been eliminated both times, this appearance?

But the problem of appearance is an apparent problem. After all, in
science we want to learn about the real and not the apparent cause of
appearance. This means that we must take the phenomena as they exist
independently from me. The appearance itself is an illusion (in
Titchener’s basic example: Muller-Lyer’s lines are physically equal,
psychologically one of them is longer). This is the difference between
the viewpoints of physics and psychology. It does not exist in
reality, but results from two non-coincidences of two really existing
processes. If I would know the physical nature of the two lines and
the objective laws of the eye, as they are in themselves, I would get
the explanation of the appearance, of the illusion as a result. The
study of the subjective factor in the knowledge of this illusion is a
subject of logic and the historical theory of knowledge: just like
being, the subjective is the result of two processes which are
objective in themselves. The mind is not always a subject. In
introspection it is split into object and subject. The question is
whether in introspection phenomenon and being coincide. One has only
to apply the epistemological formula of materialism, given by Lenin (a
similar one can be found in Plekhanov) for the psychological
subject-object, in order to see what is the matter:

the only ‘property’ of matter connected with philosophical materialism
is the property of being an objective reality, of existing outside of
our consciousness ... Epistemologically the concept of matter means
nothing other than objective reality, existing independently from
human consciousness and reflected by it. [Lenin, Materialism and
Empirio-Criticism]

Elsewhere Lenin says that this is, essentially, the principle of
realism, but that he avoids this word, because it has been captured by
inconsistent thinkers.

Thus, this formula seemingly contradicts our viewpoint: it cannot be
true that consciousness exists outside our consciousness. But, as
Plekhanov has correctly established, self-consciousness is the
consciousness of consciousness. And consciousness can exist without
self-consciousness: we become convinced of this by the unconscious and
the relatively unconscious. I can see not knowing that I see. That is
why Pavlov [1928] is right when he says that we can live according to
subjective states, but that we cannot analyse them.





------------------

http://lchc.ucsd.edu/MCA/Paper/crisis/psycri01.htm#p100


In the latter, this leading role of psychopathology is no longer
connected with the central concept of the unconscious, as in Freud and
Adler, i.e., not with the actual priority of the given discipline in
the elaboration of the basic idea, but with a fundamental
methodological view according to which the essence and nature of the
phenomena studied by psychology can be revealed in their purest form
in the extreme, pathological forms. We should, consequently, proceed
from pathology to the norm and explain and understand the normal
person from pathology, and not the other way around, as has been done
until now. The key to psychology is in pathology, not only because it
discovered and studied the root of the mind earlier than other
branches, but because this is the internal nature of things, and the
nature of the scientific knowledge of these things is conditioned by
it. Whereas for traditional psychology every psychopath as a subject
for study is more or less — to a different degree — a normal person
and must be defined in relation to the latter, for the new systems
each normal person is more or less insane and must be psychologically
understood precisely as a variant of some pathological type. To put it
in more straightforward terms, in certain systems the normal person is
considered as a type and the pathological personality as a variety or
variant of this main type; in others, on the contrary, the
pathological phenomenon is taken as a type and the normal as one of
its varieties. And who can predict how the future general psychology
will decide this debate?

On the basis of such dual motives (based half on facts, half on
principle) still other systems assign the leading role to
zoopsychology. Of this kind are, for example, the majority of the
American courses in the psychology of behaviour and the Russian
courses in reflexology, which develop their whole system from the
concept of the conditional reflex and organise all-their material
around it. A number of authors propose that animal psychology, apart
from being given the actual priority in the elaboration of the basic
concepts of behaviour, should become the general discipline with which
the other disciplines should be correlated. As the logical beginning
of a science of behaviour, the starting point for every genetic
examination and explanation of the mind, and a purely biological
science, it is precisely this science which is expected to elaborate
the fundamental concepts of the science and to supply them to kindred
disciplines.

This, for example, is the view of Pavlov. What psychologists do can in
his opinion have no influence upon animal psychology, but what
zoopsychologists do determines the work of psychologists in a very
essential way. The latter build the superstructure, but the former lay
the foundation [Pavlov, 1928, Lectures on Conditioned Reflex]. And
indeed, the source from which we derive all our basic categories for
the investigation and description of behaviour, the standard we use to
verify our results, the model according to which we align our methods,
is zoopsychology.

_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to