I believe Hegel's Phenomenology of the Spirit is a sort of psychology.
 After some of Blunden's discussion, I've been thinking that "Spirit"
in Hegel is roughly culture in the modern anthropological sense -
custom, tradition, a certain People or nation's history.  So, the
title below might be better _The Spirit of European Phenomenology or
Personality type_


The Phenomenology of Spirit


The title page of the original 1807 publication
Part of a series on
G. W. F. Hegel

Phänomenologie des Geistes (1807) is one of G.W.F. Hegel's most
important philosophical works. It is translated as The Phenomenology
of Spirit or The Phenomenology of Mind due to the dual meaning in the
German word Geist. The book's working title, which also appeared in
the first edition, was Science of the Experience of Consciousness. On
its initial publication (see cover image on right), it was identified
as Part One of a projected "System of Science", of which the Science
of Logic was the second part. A smaller work, also titled
Phenomenology of Spirit, appears in Hegel's Encyclopedia of the
Philosophical Sciences, and recounts in briefer and somewhat altered
form the major themes of the original Phenomenology.

It formed the basis of Hegel's later philosophy and marked a
significant development in German idealism after Kant. Focusing on
topics in metaphysics, epistemology, physics, ethics, theory of
knowledge, history, religion, perception, consciousness, and political
philosophy, The Phenomenology is where Hegel develops his concepts of
dialectic (including the Master-slave dialectic), absolute idealism,
ethical life, and aufhebung. The book had a profound effect in Western
philosophy, and "has been praised and blamed for the development of
existentialism, communism, fascism, death of God theology, and
historicist nihilism."[1]

Contents [hide]
1 Structure
1.1 The Preface
1.2 Introduction
1.3 Consciousness
1.4 Self-Consciousness
1.5 Reason
1.6 Spirit
1.7 Religion
2 Criticism
3 Hegelian dialectic
4 References
5 English translations of The Phenomenology of Spirit
6 Secondary literature
7 External links


[edit] Structure
The book consists of a Preface (written after the rest was completed),
an Introduction, and six major divisions (of greatly varying size):
Consciousness, Self-Consciousness, Reason, Spirit, Religion, and
Absolute Knowledge. Most of these have further hierarchical
subdivisions, and some versions of the book's table of contents also
group the last four together as a single section on a level with the
first two.

Due to its obscure nature and the many works by Hegel that followed
its publication, even the structure or core theme of the book itself
remains contested. First, Hegel wrote the book under close time
constraints with little chance for revision (individual chapters were
sent to the publisher before others were written). Furthermore,
according to some readers, Hegel may have changed his conception of
the project over the course of the writing. Secondly, the book abounds
with both highly technical argument in philosophical language, and
concrete examples, either imaginary or historical, of developments by
people through different states of consciousness. The relationship
between these is disputed: whether Hegel meant to prove claims about
the development of world history, or simply used it for illustration;
whether or not the more conventionally philosophical passages are
meant to address specific historical and philosophical positions; and
so forth.

Jean Hyppolite famously interpreted the work as a bildungsroman that
follows the progression of its protagonist, Spirit, through the
history of consciousness[2], a characterization that remains prevalent
among literary theorists. However, others contest this literary
interpretation and instead read the work as a "self-conscious
reflective account"[3] that a society must give of itself in order to
understand itself and therefore become reflective. Martin Heidegger
saw it as the foundation of a larger "System of Science" that Hegel
sought to develop[4], while Alexandre Kojève saw it as akin to a
"Platonic Dialogue ... between the great Systems of history."[5] It
has even been called "a philosophical rollercoaster ... with no more
rhyme or reason for any particular transition than that it struck
Hegel that such a transition might be fun or illuminating."[6]

[edit] The Preface
The Preface to the Phenomenology, all by itself, is considered one of
Hegel's major works and a major text in the history of philosophy,
because in it he sets out the core of his philosophical method and
what distinguishes it from that of any previous philosophy, especially
that of his German Idealist predecessors (Kant, Fichte, and
Schelling).

Hegel's approach, referred to as the Hegelian method, consists of
actually examining consciousness' experience of both itself and of its
objects and eliciting the contradictions and dynamic movement that
come to light in looking at this experience. Hegel uses the phrase
"pure looking at" (reines Zusehen) to describe this method. If
consciousness just pays attention to what is actually present in
itself and its relation to its objects, it will see that what looks
like stable and fixed forms dissolve into a dialectical movement. Thus
philosophy, according to Hegel, cannot just set out arguments based on
a flow of deductive reasoning. Rather, it must look at actual
consciousness, as it really exists.

Hegel also argues strongly against the epistemological emphasis of
modern philosophy from Descartes through Kant, which he describes as
having to first establish the nature and criteria of knowledge prior
to actually knowing anything, because this would imply an infinite
regress, a foundationalism that Hegel maintains is self-contradictory
and impossible. Rather, he maintains, we must examine actual knowing
as it occurs in real knowledge processes. This is why Hegel uses the
term "phenomenology". "Phenomenology" comes from the Greek word for
"to appear", and the phenomenology of mind is thus the study of how
consciousness or mind appears to itself. In Hegel's dynamic system, it
is the study of the successive appearances of the mind to itself,
because on examination each one dissolves into a later, more
comprehensive and integrated form or structure of mind.

[edit] Introduction
Whereas the Preface was written after Hegel completed the
Phenomenology, the Introduction was written beforehand. It covers much
of the same ground, but from a somewhat different perspective.

In the Introduction, Hegel addresses the seeming paradox that we
cannot evaluate our faculty of knowledge in terms of its ability to
know the Absolute without first having a criterion for what the
Absolute is, one that is superior to our knowledge of the Absolute.
Yet, we could only have such a criterion if we already had the
improved knowledge that we seek.

To resolve this paradox, Hegel adopts a method whereby the knowing
that is characteristic of a particular stage of consciousness is
evaluated using the criterion presupposed by consciousness itself. At
each stage, consciousness knows something, and at the same time
distinguishes the object of that knowledge as different from what it
knows. Hegel and his readers will simply "look on" while consciousness
compares its actual knowledge of the object --what the object is "for
consciousness" -- with its criterion for what the object must be "in
itself". One would expect that, when consciousness finds that its
knowledge does not agree with its object, consciousness would adjust
its knowledge to conform to its object. However, in a characteristic
reversal, Hegel explains that under his method, the opposite occurs.

As just noted, consciousness' criterion for what the object should be
is not supplied externally, rather it is supplied by consciousness
itself. Therefore, like its knowledge, the "object" that consciousness
distinguishes from its knowledge is really just the object "for
consciousness" - it is the object as envisioned by that stage of
consciousness. Thus, in attempting to resolve the discord between
knowledge and object, consciousness inevitably alters the object as
well. In fact, the new "object" for consciousness is developed from
consciousness' inadequate knowledge of the previous "object." Thus,
what consciousness really does is to modify its "object" to conform to
its knowledge. Then the cycle begins anew as consciousness attempts to
examine what it knows about this new "object".

The reason for this reversal is that, for Hegel, the separation
between consciousness and its object is no more real than
consciousness' inadequate knowledge of that object. The knowledge is
inadequate only because of that separation. At the end of the process,
when the object has been fully "spiritualized" by successive cycles of
consciousness' experience, consciousness will fully know the object
and at the same time fully recognize that the object is none other
than itself.

At each stage of development, Hegel, adds, "we" (Hegel and his
readers) see this development of the new object out of the knowledge
of the previous one, but the consciousness that we are observing does
not. As far as it is concerned, it experiences the dissolution of its
knowledge in a mass of contradictions, and the emergence of a new
object for knowledge, without understanding how that new object has
been born.

(continued)

_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to