I think Kees gets to the heart of the relationship between feeling and
esthetics here.

 

I think we should also need to bear in mind that Peirce's "esthetics" has
nothing to do with the development of taste, be it literary, artistic,
culinary or whatever. Taste is indeed always contingent on embodiment and
usually on cultural context too. Esthetics is just the science that ethics
has to appeal to for its idea of "good", so that logic can have an ethical
grounding for its normative judgment of reasoning. We might say that just as
phaneroscopy observes the phaneron and asks, "What are its indecomposable
elements?", esthetics looks at the phaneron and asks, "What could possibly
be good about it (or about any ingredient of it)?"

 

gary f.

 

From: Cornelis de Waal [mailto:cdw...@iupui.edu] 
Sent: 22-Mar-14 9:11 AM
To: Matt Faunce; peirce-l@list.iupui.edu
Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] de Waal Seminar: Chapter 4, The Normative Science of
Logic

 

Dear Matt, Cathy, List

 

 

It is sure hard to keep up with this list, especially since there are now
various parallel threads, and I'm very much impressed with Gary Richmond who
seems to on the ball pretty much every day. The moderation of this list
surely got into good hands. 

 

I want to pick up on some aspects of Matt's questions, as others have done
also, and say something more about Peirce's criticism of Sigwart in
connection with Peirce's esthetics, a discipline about which Peirce says
relatively little. 

 

When you look at Peirce's division of the sciences, esthetics follows
immediately after phaneroscopy and precedes ethics and logic, which follow
it in that order. It seems to me, though, that in Peirce's scheme of things
the higher sciences cannot be derived from the more basic ones. And Peirce
does not go that route either. Instead he argues backward from what he
believes logic should be, to what this requires in terms of a more basic and
also broader discipline he identifies as ethics, which in a similar vein
requires certain other things to be settled before it can do its job and
that fall outside its purview, which brings Peirce to what he terms
esthetics, and esthetics, finally, is constrained by the results of
phaneroscopy. The argument he gives is rather neat and hinges on, or is
inspired by, his doctrine of the categories.

 

This means, though, that when discussing esthetics this should take place
within the context of what Peirce takes logic to be, which is the enterprise
of distinguishing good from bad reasoning, where the former is defined as
any reasoning such that the truth of the premises gives us some assurance
that the conclusion be true as well. This may run from an airtight deductive
argument to a very tentative abduction.

 

By taking this course, Peirce rejects the idea, he ascribes to Sigwart, that
logic be grounded in psychology. Psychology, which Peirce takes to be a
descriptive science, can tell us how people do reason, what they do feel
when they see something that appears obvious to them etc., but it cannot
tell us how people should reason. Sigwart argued, at least in Peirce's
reading of him, that a certain feeling of necessity accompanies certain
arguments and that it is this feeling that enables us to distinguish a
necessary argument from one that is, say, a very compelling abductive
argument. Now feeling, both at the individual and the collective level, has
proven to be an unreliable guide to logic, in that bad arguments can
nonetheless elicit very strong feelings that the conclusion is inescapable.
In fact there is a whole discipline, called rhetoric, which seems to be
specifically designed to giving people strong feelings that certain bad
arguments are strong ones. Hence, I think that, justifiably or not, Sigwart
exemplifies for Peirce a route he thinks should not be taken, namely to
develop logic through a study the actual operations of the mind, de facto
making it a descriptive enterprise.

 

Now Matt asks whether perhaps ultimately our instinctive "immediate feelings
of necessity" conform to the same esthetic ideals that Peirce's logic
ultimately conforms to, adding that it might be possible to say that that
logic is grounded in something like a final feeling of necessity experienced
at the end of inquiry. These are good questions. 

 

I think approaching the issue from this angle exposes an interesting
misconception, or an equivocation if you like. For Peirce what makes an
argument a good one has everything to do with the relationship of the
premises to the conclusion, and that of itself has nothing to do with what
anyone thinks or feels about this connection. I'm confining myself here to
this "feeling of necessity." When in an introductory logic class you
introduce a valid syllogism to your students and some feel it makes no
sense, others feel it is convincing without knowing why, and yet others feel
the conclusion inescapable, all those feelings do not matter; what matters
is that the form of the argument is such that the conclusion is inescapable.
Now it seems to me that if this is true, then one would need to add some
sustained argument to make the point that somehow those feelings, which are
not relevant for determining the validity of an argument when the final
opinion has not been reached, suddenly become the deciding factor to
determine the validity of that argument once the final opinion is reached.
I'm not sure what such an argument could look like, especially since any
attempt to analyze a (simple) feeling requires one to replace it with a
structure of claims, which causes one to rely on the relationship between
premises and conclusions, suggesting that the analysis of this relationship
is more basic in terms of grounding than any feeling thatmight be elicited
by being exposed to an argument. Briefly put, Peirce takes this approach to
be a wrong one and his discussion of ethics and esthetics is his attempt to
seek an alternative.

 

Before signing off, as the house is waking up, one brief comment on another
question of Matt, which I'll quote whole:

 

"If the esthetic ideal is "that which is objectively admirable without any
ulterior reason", "without any reason for being admirable beyond its
inherent character," since we have no outside standard to judge this
admirability by how can we even recognize it so to deliberately aim our
actions at it?"

 

I think the way to go about addressing this question is to go back to what I
said above: that we cannot derive the subsequent sciencesfrom the sciences
they are grounded in. Just as phaneroscopy cannot tell uswhat esthetics will
be like, esthetics cannot tell us what ethics will be like. It befalls to
the science of ethics to try to answer this question, and it does so by
introducing such outside standards; they do not somehow evolve from
esthetics but are alien to it.

 

Cheers,

 

Kees

 

-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to