NDTR is an acronym for “Nomenclature and Divisions of Triadic Relations,” 
EP2:289-99, fifth section of the 1903 Syllabus, and the main text this thread 
has been referring to, so far.

 

Since I included in my post a few quotes from MS 7, which we discussed at some 
length back in the spring of 2014, I’ll post my transcription of the manuscript 
here (from a photocopy of it posted to the list by Vinicius Romanini, I think). 
It’s an interesting text because it prefigures (or refigures?) many of the 
things Peirce says about signs in “New Elements,” which follows immediately 
after NDTR in EP2. The lack of paragraphing is Peirce’s.    — gary f.

 

On the Foundations of Mathematics

MS 7, c. 1903 [gf transcription, 4 Apr 2014, Peirce's underlining rendered as 
italics] 

§1. Mathematics deals essentially with Signs. All that we know or think is so 
known or thought by signs, and our knowledge itself is a sign. The word and 
idea of a sign is familiar but it is indistinct. Let us endeavor to analyze it. 

It is plain at the outset, first, that a sign is not any particular replica of 
it. If one casts one's eye down a printed page, every ‘the’ is the same word, 
and every e the same letter. The exact identity is not clear. Secondly, a sign 
may be complex; and the parts of a sign, though they are signs, may not possess 
all the essential characters of a more complete sign. Thirdly, a sign 
sufficiently complete must be capable of determining an interpretant sign, and 
must be capable of ultimately producing real results. For a proposition of 
metaphysics which could never contribute to the determination of conduct would 
be meaningless jargon. On the other hand, the cards which, slipped into a 
Jacquard loom, cause appropriate figures to be woven, may very properly be 
called signs although there is no conscious interpretation of them. If not, it 
can only be because they are not interpreted by signs. In fact, in the present 
condition of philosophy, consciousness seems to be a mere quality of feeling 
which a formal science will do best to leave out of account. But a sign only 
functions as a sign when it is interpreted. It is therefore essential that it 
should be capable of determining an interpretant sign. Fourthly, a sign 
sufficiently complete must in some sense correspond to a real object. A sign 
cannot even be false unless, with some degree of definiteness, it specifies the 
real object of which it is false. That the sign itself is not a definite real 
object has been pointed out under “firstly”. It is only represented. Now either 
it must be that it is one thing to really be and another to be represented, or 
else it must be that there is no such thing [a]s falsity. This involves no 
denial that every real thing may be a representation, or sign, but merely that, 
if so, there must be something more in reality than mere representation. Since 
a sufficiently complete sign may be false, and also since it is not any replica 
or collection of replicas, it is not real. But it refers to a real object. 
Consequently, a sign cannot have a sign as its sole object; though it may refer 
to an object through a sign; as if one should say, “Whatever the Pope, as such, 
may declare will be true,” or as a map may be a map of itself. But supposing 
the Pope not to declare anything, does that proposition refer to any real 
object? Yes, to the Pope. But, fifthly, even if there were no pope, still, like 
all other signs sufficiently complete, there is a single definite object to 
which it must refer; namely, to the ‘Truth,’ or the Absolute, or the entire 
Universe of real being. Sixthly, a sign may refer, in addition, and specially, 
to any number of parts of that universe. Seventhly, every interpretant of a 
sign need not refer to all the real objects to which the sign itself refers, 
but must, at least, refer to the Truth. Eighthly, an interpretant may refer to 
an object of its sign in an indefinite manner. Thus, given the sign, ‘Enoch was 
a man, and Enoch was translated,’ an interpretant of it would be ‘Some man was 
translated.’ Ninethly, a sign may refer to its interpretant in such a way that, 
in case the former sign is incomplete, the interpretant, being an interpretant 
of the completer sign, may refer to a sign to which the first sign does not 
specially refer, but only generally refers. Thus, the sign ‘Any man there may 
be is mortal’ does not refer to any real man, unless it so happens that it is a 
part of a sign which otherwise refers to such a real thing. But if it be a part 
of a sign of which another part is ‘some man sings,’ the sign ‘some man is 
mortal’ becomes an interpretant of it. This may be more conveniently expressed 
by speaking of an ‘utterer’ and an ‘interpreter.’ Then the utterer says to the 
interpreter, “you are at liberty to understand me as referring to any man [of] 
whom you can get any indication, and of him, I say, ‘he is mortal.’” Tenthly, a 
sign sufficiently complete must signify some quality; and it is no more 
important to recognize that the real object to which a sign refers is not a 
mere sign than to recognize that the quality it signifies is not a mere sign. 
Take the quality of the odor of attar. There is no difficulty in imagining a 
being whose entire consciousness should consist in this alone. But, it may be 
objected, if it were contrasted with nothing could it be recognized? I reply, 
no; and besides, such recognition is excluded by the circumstance that a 
recognition of the smell would not be the pure smell itself. It may be doubted 
by some persons, however, whether the feeling could exist alone. They are the 
persons whom it ought to be easiest for me to convince of my point. For they, 
at least, must admit that if such pure homogeneous quality of feeling were to 
exist alone, it would not be a sign. Everybody ought to admit it because it 
would be alone, and therefore would have no object different from itself. 
Besides, there would be no possible replica of it, since each of two such 
things would be nonexistent for the other; nor could there be any third who 
should compare them. So, then, the whole question of whether such a quality is 
a sign or not resolves itself into the question of whether there could be such 
a tinge upon the consciousness of a being, supposing the being could be 
conscious (for I shall show presently that the fact that he would be asleep is 
only in my favor). In order to decide this question, it will be sufficient to 
look at any object parti-colored in bright red and bright blue and to ask 
oneself a question or two. Would there be any possibility of conveying the idea 
of that red to a person who had no feeling nearer to it than that blue? Plainly 
not, the quality of the red is in the red itself. The proximity of the blue 
heightens the shock up[on] the seer[']s organism, emphasizes it, renders it 
vivid, perhaps slightly confuses the feeling. But the red quality is altogether 
positive and would remain if the blue were not there. If every other idea were 
removed, there would be no shock, and there would be sleep. But the quality of 
that sleep would be red, in this sense, that if it were taken away frequently 
and brought back so as to wake the being up, the tinge of his consciousness 
would be of that quality. A quality, in itself, has no being at all, it is 
true. It must be embodied in something that exists. But the quality is as it is 
positively and in itself. That is not true of a sign, which exists only by 
bringing an interpretant to refer to an object. A quality, then, is not a sign. 
Eleventhly, we may assume that this is as true of what is, with excusable 
inaccuracy, called a composite quality as of a simple one. In itself, one 
quality is as simple as another. A person who should be acquainted with none 
but the spectral colors would get no idea of white by being told that it was 
the mixture of them all. One might as well tell him to make a mixture of water, 
patriotism, and the square root of minus one. Find a man who has had no idea of 
patriotism; and if you tell him that it is the love of one's country, if he 
knows what love is, and what a man's country, in its social sense, is, he can 
make the experiment of connecting ideas in his imagination, and noting the 
quality of feeling which arises upon this composition. Tell him this in the 
evening, and he will repeat the experiment several times during the night, and 
in the morning he will have a fair idea of what patriotism means. He will have 
performed an experiment analogous to that of mixing colored lights in order to 
get an idea of white. If a treasure is buried in the midst of a plain, and 
there are four signal poles, the place of the treasure can be defined by means 
of ranges, so that a person who can take ranges and set up new poles can find 
the treasure. In like manner the name of any color may be defined in terms of 
four color disks so that a person with a color-wheel can experimentally produce 
the color and thereafter be able to use the name. Every definition to be 
understood must be treated as a precept for experimentation. The imagination is 
an apparatus for such experimentation that often answers the purpose, although 
it often proves insufficient. No point on the plain where the treasure is hid 
is more simple than other. Colors may be defined by various systems of 
coördinates, and we do not know that one color is in itself simpler than 
another. It is only in a limited class of cases that we can define a quality as 
simply a mixture of two qualities. In most cases, it is necessary to introduce 
other relations. But even when that is the case, if a quality is defined as 
being at once a and b, there will always be another way of defining it as that 
which is at once c and d. Now all that is either a or c will have a certain 
quality p, common and peculiar to that class; the class of possible objects 
that are b or c will be similarly related to a quality, r; and the class of 
possible objects that are either b or d will be similarly related to a quality, 
s. Then that quality which was defined as, at once, a and b, can be more 
analytically defined as that which is at once p, q, r, and s; and so on ad 
infinitum. We may not be able to make out these qualities; but there is reason 
to believe that any describable class of possible objects has some quality 
common and peculiar to it. It is certain that a pure quality, in its mode of 
being as a pure quality, does not cease to be because it is not embodied in 
anything. Every situation in life appears to have its peculiar flavor. This 
flavor is what it is positively and in itself. For the experiment by which it 
may be reproduced an adequate prescription may be given; but the definition 
will not itself have that flavor. To say that a flavor, or pure quality, is 
composed of two others, is simply to say that on experimentally mixing these 
others in a particular way, that first flavor will be reproduced. Every 
sufficiently complete sign determines a sign to the effect that on a certain 
occasion, that is, in a certain object a certain flavor or quality may be 
observed. 

This attempt to begin an analysis of the nature of a sign may seem to be 
unnecessarily complicated, unnatural, and ill-fitting. To that I reply that 
every man has his own fashion of thinking; and if such is the reader's 
impression let him draw up a statement for himself. If it is sufficiently full 
and accurate, he will find that it differs from mine chiefly in its 
nomenclature and arrangement. [Not unlikely he might insist on distinctions 
which I avoid as irrelevant.] He will find that, in some shape, he is brought 
to recognize the same three radically different elements that I do. Namely, he 
must recognize, first, a mode of being in itself, corresponding to my quality; 
secondly, a mode of being constituted by opposition, corresponding to my 
object; and thirdly, a mode of being of which a branching line Y is an 
analogue, and which is of the general nature of a mean function corresponding 
to the sign. 

§2. Partly in hopes of reconciling the reader to my statement, and partly in 
order to bring out some other points that will be pertinent, I will review the 
matter in another order. 

The reference of a sign to the quality which is its ground, reason, or meaning 
appears most prominently in a kind of sign of which any replica is fitted to be 
a sign by virtue of possessing in itself certain qualities which it would 
equally possess if the interpretant and the object did not exist at all. Of 
course, in such case, the sign could not be a sign; but as far as the sign 
itself went, it would be all that [it] would be with the object and 
interpretant. Such a sign whose significance lies in the qualities of its 
replicas in themselves is an icon, image, analogue, or copy. Its object is 
whatever that resembles it its interpretant takes it to be the sign of, and [it 
is a] sign of that object in proportion as it resembles it. An icon cannot be a 
complete sign; but it is the only sign which directly brings the interpretant 
to close quarters with the meaning; and for that reason it is the kind of sign 
with which the mathematician works. For not only are geometrical figures icons, 
but even algebraical arrays of letters have relations analogous to those of the 
forms they represent, although these relations are not altogether iconically 
represented. 

The reference of a sign to its object is brought into special prominence in a 
kind of sign whose fitness to be a sign is due to its being in a real reactive 
relation,—generally, a physical and dynamical relation,—with the object. Such a 
sign I term an index. As an example, take a weather-cock. This is a sign of the 
wind because the wind actively moves it. It faces in the very direction from 
which the wind blows. In so far as it does that, it involves an icon. The wind 
forces it to be an icon. A photograph which is compelled by optical laws to be 
an icon of its object which is before the camera is another example. It is in 
this way that these indices convey information. They are propositions. That is 
they separately indicate their objects; the weather-cock because it turns with 
the wind and is known by its interpretant to do so; the photograph for a like 
reason. If the weathercock sticks and fails to turn, or if the camera lens is 
bad, the one or the other will be false. But if this is known to be the case, 
they sink at once to mere icons, at best. It is not essential to an index that 
it should thus involve an icon. Only, if it does not, it will convey no 
information. A cry of “Oh!” may be a direct reaction from a remarkable 
situation. But it will convey, perhaps, no further information. The letters in 
a geometrical figure are good illustrations of pure indices not involving any 
icon, that is they do not force anything to be an icon of their object. The cry 
“Oh!” does to a slight degree; since it has the same startling quality as the 
situation that compells it. The index acts compulsively on the interpretant and 
puts it into a direct and real relation with the object, which is necessarily 
an individual event (or, more loosely, a thing) that is hic et nunc, single and 
definite. 

A third kind of sign, which brings the reference to an interpretant into 
prominence, is one which is fit to be a sign, not at all because of any 
particular analogy with the quality it signifies, nor because it stands in any 
reactive relation with its object, but simply and solely because it will be 
interpreted to be a sign. I call such a sign a symbol. As an example of a 
symbol, Goethe's book on the Theory of Colors will serve. This is made up of 
letters, words, sentences, paragraphs etc.; and the cause of its referring to 
colors and attributing to colors the quality it does is that so it is 
understood by anybody who reads it. It not only determines an interpretant, but 
it shows very explicitly the special determinant, (the acceptance of the 
theory) which it is intended to determine. By virtue of thus specially showing 
its intended interpretant (out of thousands of possible interpretants of it) it 
is an argument. An index may be, in one sense, an argument; but not in the 
sense here meant, that of an argumentation. It determines such interpretant as 
it may, without manifesting a special intention of determining a particular 
interpretant. It is a perfection of a symbol, if it does this; but it is not 
essential to a symbol that it should do so. Erase the conclusion of an 
argumentation and it becomes a proposition (usually, a copulative proposition). 
Erase such a part of a proposition that if a proper name were inserted in the 
blank, or if several proper names were inserted in the several blanks, and it 
becomes a rhema, or term. Thus, the following are rhematic: 

Guiteau assassinated ______ 
______ assassinated ______

Logicians generally would consider it quite wrong for me to call these terms; 
but I shall venture to do so.

 

From: sji.confor...@gmail.com [mailto:sji.confor...@gmail.com] On Behalf Of 
Sungchul Ji
Sent: 18-Dec-15 16:22



Gary F, Jeff, List,

 

Please excuse my ignorance.

What is NDTR ?

 

Thanks in advance.

 

Sung

 

-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to