Re: [EM] Does High Resolution Range offer a solution to the ABE?

2011-11-27 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/11/26 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 While working with MinMaxCardinalRatingsPairwiseOpposition (MMcrwPO) I got
 an
 idea that high resolution Range might have an acceptable solutin to the
 defection problem that we have been considering:

 Sincere ballots

 49 C
 x: AB
 y: BA

 where x appears to be slightly larger than y in the polls.

 The A and B factions can agree to enough support such that if they both
 follow
 through the one with the larger support will win, but if one defects, C X
 will win.

 In this case that level of support is about 96%.  If the A voters and the B
 voters both give 96% to their second choice, then A or B will win,
 depending on
 whether or not x is greater than y.  If anybody defects from this, then C
 sill win.

 This offers an equilibrium which is stable in the sense that if everyone
knows everyone else's ballot then nobody has the incentive to defect. But
it's drastically unstable and failure-prone if you dont have pre-election
polls that measure down to the last ballot.

That's one of the main advantages of a system like SODA. Because delegated
ballots are assigned after the election, by the time that happens everyone
does know the size of each faction down to the last ballot, and so
solutions of this nature are in principal feasible. (For instance, this
exact solution would work in SODR, that is to say SODA with Range instead
of Approval.)

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] More non-altruistic attacks on IRV usage.

2011-11-27 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

matt welland wrote:

On Sat, 2011-11-26 at 22:31 -0500, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

On 11/26/11 6:58 PM, matt welland wrote:



Also, do folks generally see approval as better than or worse than IRV?
they don't know anything about Approval (or Score or Borda or Bucklin or 
Condorcet) despite some effort by me to illustrate it regarding the 
state senate race in our county.


I wasn't clear. I want to hear opinions from the list: Is approval
better or worse than IRV and why?


In my opinion, Approval is somewhere between IRV and the advanced 
methods (good Condorcet methods, MJ, etc).


The reason I think Approval is better than IRV is that while IRV makes 
its own decision about essentially whether to emulate people voting both 
Nader and Gore, or Nader alone, Approval lets the voters decide on their 
own. The voters can therefore approve both if it's more important to 
beat Bush than to support Nader over Gore, or approve Nader only if 
Nader's got a chance.


The reason I think the advanced methods are better than Approval is that 
they take this burden off the voters when the voters are sincere. If you 
vote Nader  Gore  Bush in Schulze (say), then you're both helping 
Nader to win against (Gore, Bush) and Gore to win against Bush. If Gore 
is a CW with a sufficient margin that you don't create a cycle - well, 
then Gore wins. Same with Nader.


If there's a cycle, it gets a bit more tricky. The method is easier 
influenced by strategy and your vote could hurt you. The Condorcet 
criterion no longer says what the answer should be, and the method thus 
has to use more indirect reasoning to find out who should win.


At least it narrows down the region in which strange things can happen. 
The good Condorcet methods pass criteria like Smith and independence of 
Smith-dominated alternatives, and so further narrow down these regions.


So, in short: IRV makes a guess as to which comparisons are the most 
important (using the logic of least first-place votes = worst), and 
when it gets it wrong, there's your center squeeze. Approval gives the 
decision to the voters, who will do better if they have access to 
polling data. Condorcet looks at more comparisons at once, while MJ 
reads ratings using robust statistics to satisfy criteria like Majority 
and to deter strategy.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] More non-altruistic attacks on IRV usage.

2011-11-27 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/11/27 matt welland m...@kiatoa.com

 On Sat, 2011-11-26 at 22:31 -0500, robert bristow-johnson wrote:
  On 11/26/11 6:58 PM, matt welland wrote:

   Also, do folks generally see approval as better than or worse than IRV?
  they don't know anything about Approval (or Score or Borda or Bucklin or
  Condorcet) despite some effort by me to illustrate it regarding the
  state senate race in our county.

 I wasn't clear. I want to hear opinions from the list: Is approval
 better or worse than IRV and why?


I consider Approval to be better than IRV. Consider the case of Burlington,
which I think well-illustrates the flaws of both. Approval could easily
have failed in Burlington. Assuming most Republicans bullet voted (which is
probably strategically smart), then there would be a chicken dilemma for
the Democratic and Progressive voters. They could bullet vote and risk
electing the Republican, or approve 2 and give up their voice in the choice
between D and P. So in theory any of the three candidates could win.

In that sense, Approval is as bad or worse than IRV. But then look at how
people would react (if the system were un-repealable). In Approval, people
could adjust their vote until they got a result they liked better. The
eventual strategic equilibrium would be that the CW would tend to win. In
IRV, however, there's no way to change the result without voting
dishonestly. So you'd either be stuck with progressives winning, or people
would start to use two-party-lesser-evil strategy, and you'd get a
two-power lock on power as in plurality. I consider the corrupt,
non-competitive nature of either of these long-term results to be far worse
than a single spoiled election.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Jameson: MTA, MJ, MTAOC, SODA

2011-11-27 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

MIKE OSSIPOFF wrote:


If one is going to propose a method involving proxies, then Proxy DD is the 
biggest and most
ambitious improvment. I described it in a posting when you asked about it. 


Though it's a much more ambitious thing to ask for, maybe people _would_ want a
good proxy system such as Proxy DD.  A good single-winner method should be used 
with it.


Excuse me for hijacking the thread, but I haven't been following up on 
the development on proxy direct democracy. I assume this is the same 
thing as liquid democracy, i.e. that you have a direct democracy where 
the voters can subscribe or give their voting power to proxies.


What's the answer to the vote-buying objection to proxy democracy? This 
goes something like: we can easily offer some proxy money to vote for 
X, because we'll simply subscribe to this proxy and see if he tells his 
constituents to vote for X, and not give him any money if he doesn't. 
That, if unaddressed, would weaken proxy democracy's counterbalance to 
the power of money.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] STV and single constraints, like gender quotas

2011-11-27 Thread Peter Zbornik
Dear all,

do anyone of you know the best way to incorporate single constraints
into STV and proportional rankings from STV (see for instance:
http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm)?
For instance, the constraint can be that at least 1/3 of the elected
seats go to candidates of each gender.
I found some information in the links below, but I wonder if there are
better or more recent suggestions:
http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE9/P1.HTM
http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm

Best regards
Peter Zborník

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Jameson: MTA, MJ, MTAOC, SODA

2011-11-27 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/11/26 MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com


 Jameson:

 You said:

 There are other methods which you don't mention even though their
 advantages are similar to those of the ones you do.

 2011/11/25 MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com




 Regarding the co-operation/defection problem, there are about 4
 possibilities:



 1. Just propose MTA and Keep the co-operation/defection problem.

 Majority
  Judgment has similar advantages to MTA in this case.

 [endquote]

 Does it? Who knows?


Anyone who takes the time to read the academic
literaturehttps://sites.google.com/site/ridalaraki/majority-judgment
.


 Have its proponents told what criteria it meets and specifically what
 guarantees it
 offers?

 How does it do in the Approval bad-example?


Same as MTA. That is, honest-votes will reliably give a good result, unlike
unstable Approval; but strategic voting will lead to failure.


 (to compare it to MTAOC)


If you're unwilling to research the published answers to your own
questions, why do you persist in asking us to look up your alphabet soup in
old posts? For instance, I know what you mean by MTAOC (a system with a
strong dishonest-fill incentive, which could be almost as bad as Borda in
practice), but searching past messages for that acronym just gives the
written-out name, and then it would take a separate search (which, if you
happened to be using a strict search engine, would fail) to find the actual
definition.


 What majority-rule guarantees does it offer? Does it meet 3P or 1CM?


It meets 3P, which I happen to remember what it means. If you define
1CMhttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/1CMI'll tell you if it meets
that.



 It probably has a strategy situation very much like that of ordinary RV.
 The method of summed scores.


No. For most voters in real-world studies of MJ, their honest,
not-even-normalized MJ ballot was strategically optimal. That is clearly
far better than Range.



 4. Find a simpler method that has those advantages.

 Such as SODA.

 [endquote]

 Go ahead and propose the enactment of SODA somewhere if you think that a
 method involving
 delegates or proxies is as winnable as methods that do not.


I am working to do so. Note that SODA proxies are 100% optional, and also
bound to a predeclared strategy in ways that should prevent most corrupt
proxy use.


 If one is going to propose a method involving proxies, then Proxy DD is
 the biggest and most
 ambitious improvment. I described it in a posting when you asked about it.


Yes, you reinvented Liquid Democracy / Asset Voting / Delegable Proxy.
That's a very good system but it is a far, far more radical change than
SODA. As Kristofer pointed out, for one thing it abandons the secret ballot
entirely.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MMPO tiebreakers that don't violate FBC.

2011-11-27 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

Mike,

I like MMPO2 because (unlike MMPO1) it takes into account opposition from
supporters of eliminated candidates, so is more broad based, and it is easily
seen to satisfy the FBC. Also it allows more brad based support than MMPO3 where
only the support by top raters is considered in the tie breaking process.


MMPO2 sounds a lot like what I've called Ext-Minmax, but with pairwise 
opposition instead of wv or margins.


I originally devised of Ext-Minmax to resolve some tie problems while 
checking Smith,Minmax(margins) for mono-add-top failures - I didn't find 
any, but Kevin Venzke did.


What would the pairwise opposition equivalent of the Smith set be? Would 
it still be the Smith set - and would Smith,Ext-MMPO (to coin a term) 
pass mono-add-top?



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV and single constraints, like gender quotas

2011-11-27 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Peter Zbornik wrote:

Dear all,

do anyone of you know the best way to incorporate single constraints
into STV and proportional rankings from STV (see for instance:
http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm)?
For instance, the constraint can be that at least 1/3 of the elected
seats go to candidates of each gender.
I found some information in the links below, but I wonder if there are
better or more recent suggestions:
http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE9/P1.HTM
http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm


I don't know of any better rules than the naive rule off the top of my 
head. I will note this, however: if you use a combinatorial method like 
Schulze STV, it is very easy to accommodate both simple and complex 
rules. You just decide to consider only those seat compositions that are 
permitted by the constraints.


For instance, if you need at least one black and at least one woman (but 
they can be the same person), then you enumerate all possible 
permutations and remove those that have no blacks and no women. Then you 
run Schulze STV (or combinatorial method of choice) with respect to 
what's left.


This also works for constraints that can't easily be determined in 
advance or from the ballots themselves. If you say that the CW based on 
the same ballots, or the current chairman's pick, has to be on the 
council, first run the ballots through a Condorcet method (or ask the 
chairman) and only consider the seat compositions where the candidate in 
question is included.


I suppose you could make ordinary STV combinatorial by considering how 
many voters did we have to overrule to get the composition we wanted 
(where this is measured as number of last preferences for the candidate 
that was eliminated in each round, less the number of last preferences 
for the candidate that would have been eliminated by ordinary STV rules, 
using a forced elimination sequence that minimizes this number for the 
given composition), but it's not clear to me how you would go about 
actually calculating that minimizing sequence.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV and single constraints, like gender quotas

2011-11-27 Thread Peter Zbornik
Hi Kristofer,

I don't consider Schulze STV, only standard STV (IRV-based, fractional
static Droop quotas, not meek),
since it is the only method, which is simple to explain to
non-enthusiasts and widely used and have tested and widely used
software support for vote counting.

I guess, that by the naive approach you mean: elect seats normally,
if during the vote-count the, same number of seats remain must belong
to one quota group in order not to break the quota (i.e. if. all
remaining seats must belong to one quota group), elect only candidates
from this quota group.
Do you also to the naive approach count guarding candidates from
elimination, if it could mean not filling the quotas?

I guess a combinatorial method is CPO-STV and Schulze-STV?
I consider only single constraints (i.e. no combination of women and
skin color etc.).
I didn't understand your proposal how you could make ordinary STV
combinatorial.

Best regards
Peter Zborník

2011/11/27 Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com:
 Peter Zbornik wrote:

 Dear all,

 do anyone of you know the best way to incorporate single constraints
 into STV and proportional rankings from STV (see for instance:
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm)?
 For instance, the constraint can be that at least 1/3 of the elected
 seats go to candidates of each gender.
 I found some information in the links below, but I wonder if there are
 better or more recent suggestions:
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE9/P1.HTM
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm

 I don't know of any better rules than the naive rule off the top of my head.
 I will note this, however: if you use a combinatorial method like Schulze
 STV, it is very easy to accommodate both simple and complex rules. You just
 decide to consider only those seat compositions that are permitted by the
 constraints.

 For instance, if you need at least one black and at least one woman (but
 they can be the same person), then you enumerate all possible permutations
 and remove those that have no blacks and no women. Then you run Schulze STV
 (or combinatorial method of choice) with respect to what's left.

 This also works for constraints that can't easily be determined in advance
 or from the ballots themselves. If you say that the CW based on the same
 ballots, or the current chairman's pick, has to be on the council, first run
 the ballots through a Condorcet method (or ask the chairman) and only
 consider the seat compositions where the candidate in question is included.

 I suppose you could make ordinary STV combinatorial by considering how many
 voters did we have to overrule to get the composition we wanted (where this
 is measured as number of last preferences for the candidate that was
 eliminated in each round, less the number of last preferences for the
 candidate that would have been eliminated by ordinary STV rules, using a
 forced elimination sequence that minimizes this number for the given
 composition), but it's not clear to me how you would go about actually
 calculating that minimizing sequence.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV and single constraints, like gender quotas

2011-11-27 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Peter Zbornik wrote:

Hi Kristofer,

I don't consider Schulze STV, only standard STV (IRV-based, fractional
static Droop quotas, not meek),
since it is the only method, which is simple to explain to
non-enthusiasts and widely used and have tested and widely used
software support for vote counting.

I guess, that by the naive approach you mean: elect seats normally,
if during the vote-count the, same number of seats remain must belong
to one quota group in order not to break the quota (i.e. if. all
remaining seats must belong to one quota group), elect only candidates
from this quota group.
Do you also to the naive approach count guarding candidates from
elimination, if it could mean not filling the quotas?


Yes. These are the Church of England rules mentioned in your first link. 
If you need max 5 women, and 5 women have been elected, eliminate all 
remaining men; if you need min 5 women and only 5 women are left, 
protect them from elimination.



I guess a combinatorial method is CPO-STV and Schulze-STV?


A combinatorial method is any method that considers all possible ways to 
assign candidates to seats, and then determines the best assembly 
according to some rule. CPO-STV and Schulze STV would be combinatorial 
methods, as would (exhaustive) PAV and birational voting.



I consider only single constraints (i.e. no combination of women and
skin color etc.).
I didn't understand your proposal how you could make ordinary STV
combinatorial.


Okay, if you only consider single constraints, the Church rules should work.

As for making ordinary STV combinatorial, this is just trying to attach 
a metric to STV. Ordinary STV could be considered to elect the best 
assembly according to some measure involving the number of last-place 
votes for the candidates eliminated in each round. If that's the case, 
it should be possible to force STV to eliminate candidates in a certain 
order and then measure how good the resulting assembly is in 
comparison to the best possible. Then you could pick the one that is 
closest to best while still giving an assembly that passes the constraints.


For instance, say that ordinary STV for 2 seats goes like this:
A is elected
B is eliminated (first pref votes: C: 40, D: 35, B: 30).
C is elected
all done. This gets a score of 0, because the person with least last 
place votes was eliminated in the second round.


Then say we force D to be eliminated in the second round. Then we'd get:
A is elected
D is eliminated (fpv: C: 40, D: 35, B: 30). Penalty is 35-30 = 5.
B is elected (say).
all done. Then this has a penalty of 5 because STV would have 
eliminated B (at 30 first place votes) but you forced it to eliminate D 
(at 35) instead.


The problem is that, if you increase the number of seats, eliminate D 
then eliminate B is not the same thing as eliminate B then eliminate 
D. To be fair, you'd only have to count the order which gives the least 
penalty, and it's not obvious to me how that would be done.


Besides, the method is extremely complex.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] More non-altruistic attacks on IRV usage.

2011-11-27 Thread Juho Laatu
On 27.11.2011, at 8.05, matt welland wrote:

 On Sat, 2011-11-26 at 22:31 -0500, robert bristow-johnson wrote:
 On 11/26/11 6:58 PM, matt welland wrote:
 
 Also, do folks generally see approval as better than or worse than IRV?
 they don't know anything about Approval (or Score or Borda or Bucklin or 
 Condorcet) despite some effort by me to illustrate it regarding the 
 state senate race in our county.
 
 I wasn't clear. I want to hear opinions from the list: Is approval
 better or worse than IRV and why?

Unlike others, I think Approval might be worse.

Lets assume that there are two wings, left and right. Left has slight majority 
this time. Left consists of multiple candidates or multiple parties. Right has 
one candidate.

One basic problem of Approval is that all left supporters have to approve all 
plausible winners of the left wing in order to guarantee that left will win. 
That makes Approval quite numb to the opinions of the voters. If (almost) all 
approve all, the choice among left wing candidates will be random. Some voters 
might be tempted to approve only their favourites, and make them win this way. 
They may well succeed. But if number of strategic voters grows, then right 
wins. This kind of close competitions are not rare in politics. And in such 
situations one can not tell which candidate is the strongest among the left 
wing candidates (and a natural choice that all left supporters should approve). 
All candidates present themselves as likely winners, and their supporters tend 
to think that their favourite candidate is the strongest one.

Approval is nice because the ballots are simple. It works fine with two major 
parties and some new third parties. But when the third parties grow, the 
problems arise. There are no good solutions and no good guidance to the left 
voters in the situation where left wing has two or more plausible winners.

If one of the left wing candidates is a Condorcet winner (closer to the centre 
than the competing candidate), then that candidate may propose that all 
supporters of the other candidate should approve him although his supporters 
need not approve that other candidate. Maybe there are some voters that would 
even rank the right candidate second. But often there is no such clear order. 
And the other left candidate might be slightly ahead in first preferences.

IRV has its problems too. The reason why it might be better than Approval is 
that voters still have some sensible strategies, like ability to compromise. In 
the environment above left wing IRV voters will anyway rank all left wing 
candidates first. One of them will win, although the best of them might be 
eliminated too early. If there are two equally strong left candidates, the 
number of first preferences will decide which one of the left candidates will 
win. That is not as bad as the problems of Approval in this situation.

In IRV minor parties are a bigger problem than in Approval. In this example 
they may steal first preference votes from the second favourite of their 
supporters, and thereby make some worse left wing candidate win. In this 
situation the voters may compromise. If their own candidate has no chances to 
win, they might be ok with ranking the stronger second favourite above him. Not 
good, but at least the voters can do something. And even if they will do 
nothing, they would still get a left winner.

If there is a clear Condorcet winner (like in Burlington), IRV will have 
problems. So will Approval. But this mail is already too long, so I'll stop 
here.

My basic argument against Approval is that although IRV may make wrong 
decisions, it does not lead to as terrible situations as Approval does (with 
more than two plausible winners). In Approval the idea of all left wing voters 
approving all the left wing candidates sounds quite impossible. Therefore it is 
likely to violate the opinion of the majority. And the voters do not have any 
good strategies to fix the problem. Approving all the left wing candidates and 
letting a random one of them win, or to allow others (maybe the few strategic 
voters) to decide, does not sound like a system that voters would like to keep. 
In IRV people are (as we have seen) quite ignorant and don't understand that 
someone else than the (fair) IRV winner should have won. The results are a 
bit random, but often people just think better luck next time. So, 
impossible situations vs. randomish elimination process.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] More non-altruistic attacks on IRV usage.

2011-11-27 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

David L Wetzell wrote:




  The two major-party equilibrium would be centered around the de
  facto center.  




   But positioning yourself around the de facto center is dangerous in
   IRV. You might get center-squeezed unless either you or your voters
   start using strategic lesser-evil logic - the same sort of logic
   that IRV was supposed to free you from by being impervious to
   spoilers.


dlw: the cost of campaigning in less local elections is high enuf that 
it's hard for a major party to get center-squeezed.  And if such did 
happen, they could reposition to prevent it.  


Yes, I said that parties or voters could escape this problem by 
repositioning, i.e. adopting strategic lesser-evil logic.


If the cost of campaigning is high enough that only the two major 
parties can play the game, then money (what you call $peech) will still 
have serious influence. You might say that this is counterbalanced by 
the more local elections, so that minor parties can grow into major ones 
and there will be different minor-to-major parties in each location -- 
but you still have to convince the more local divisions (counties, 
cities, etc) to use IRV, and so the same problem applies there.


Or in other words: if you're right and there are only two major parties 
on the national scene (and so no center-squeeze problem), there will 
still be a center-squeeze problem in, say, Burlington's mayoral 
elections. Either Burlington has only two major parties (but then where 
would your more-local accountability come from?) or it has multiple 
parties, each of which has its own mayoral candidate, and the centermost 
n of which will be susceptible to center squeeze.


You want local areas to support smaller parties so they can grow and 
challenge the major parties. Well, then the local environment must be 
conducive to growth. If the parties have to strategically balance IRV's 
center squeeze (which forces them towards the wings) against the voter 
support they get from moving closer to the center, that's not exactly 
conducive to such growth. Nor is it so if the voters have to keep the 
breakdown point of IRV (when minor becomes major) in mind when voting. 
Can the parties really be as flexible as you'd like when they're facing 
the additional constraint of having to walk that tightrope produced by 
the election method itself?


(It might well be that the nature of IRV, plus cost of campaigning means 
there could only be two national-level parties. I don't think cost of 
campaigning alone would force there to be only two national-level 
parties - e.g. France - but the answer to that question isn't critical 
to what I wrote above. I'm saying that even if we assume what you're 
saying, you get into trouble on a more local level.)



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV and single constraints, like gender quotas

2011-11-27 Thread James Gilmour
Peter
If you haven't already found the Church of England Regulations for STV with 
constraints, they are here:
  http://www.churchofengland.org/media/1307318/stv%20regulations.doc
These are the only published regulations for STV with constraints that I know 
of.

Your first link (below) is to a Joe Otten paper that describes one way of 
ordering a list with STV.  If that is one of the tasks
you have, you may find it useful also to look at the method devised by Colin 
Rosenstiel:
  http://www.cix.co.uk/~rosenstiel/stv/orderstv.htm 
and
  http://www.cix.co.uk/~rosenstiel/stv/ordstvdt.htm

James Gilmour


 -Original Message-
 From: election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com 
 [mailto:election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com] On 
 Behalf Of Peter Zbornik
 Sent: Sunday, November 27, 2011 10:55 AM
 To: Election Methods; election-methods
 Subject: [EM] STV and single constraints, like gender quotas
 
 
 Dear all,
 
 do anyone of you know the best way to incorporate single 
 constraints into STV and proportional rankings from STV (see 
 for instance: http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm)?
 For instance, the constraint can be that at least 1/3 of the 
 elected seats go to candidates of each gender. I found some 
 information in the links below, but I wonder if there are 
 better or more recent suggestions: 
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE9/P1.HTM
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm
 
 Best regards
 Peter Zborník
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em 
 for list info
 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV and single constraints, like gender quotas

2011-11-27 Thread Juho Laatu
On 27.11.2011, at 12.55, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 Dear all,
 
 do anyone of you know the best way to incorporate single constraints
 into STV and proportional rankings from STV (see for instance:
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm)?
 For instance, the constraint can be that at least 1/3 of the elected
 seats go to candidates of each gender.
 I found some information in the links below, but I wonder if there are
 better or more recent suggestions:
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE9/P1.HTM
 http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue9/p5.htm
 
 Best regards
 Peter Zborník

I once implemented such a method (brute force and optimizing versions). The 
implementation was quite straight forward. It just considered results that meet 
certain criteria better than other results. It included (and started with) 
proportional raking (planned to elect e.g. chairmen for the group at the same 
time), and ability to elect certain number of representatives from various 
(possibly overlapping groups). The implementation fixed the representatives 
that were elected using proportional ordering (i.e. they were not changed 
afterwards in the full proportional phase even if there was some more 
proportional result (resulting iteration could be too complex)).

That was thus a quite straight forward exercise, and I didn't have any other 
interesting options / criteria in my mind to implement.

One could support at least, exactly or at most certain number of 
representatives from a certain set. The proportional ranking based group of 
chairmen could also have similar requirements. With multiple groups you could 
say e.g. that there must be at least 3 blacks, at least 3 women and at least 5 
representatives that are either black or women. What other rules would be 
useful?

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Approval vs. IRV

2011-11-27 Thread Kathy Dopp
 Nov 2011 23:05:49 -0700
 From: matt welland m...@kiatoa.com

 I wasn't clear. I want to hear opinions from the list: Is approval
 better or worse than IRV and why?

Approval is a far superior system to FPTP and IRV because approval:

1. unlike FPTP and IRV, it solves the spoiler problem of a nonwinning
candidate altering who would otherwise win;

2. unlike IRV, it is precinct-summable and easy to manually
statistically audit for accuracy and so preserves or allows for
timely, understandable, election accuracy verification;

3. unlike IRV, it looks at all the candidate choices of all voters,
thus treating all voters' votes equally and fairly and is thus
monotonic;

4. unlike IRV, it is simple to implement using the same ballot style
as FPTP, with a fairly simple programming change in the tally program;

5. unlike IRV, it preserves the rights of voters to have their votes
counted fairly and equally with other voters and to participate in the
final counting rounds (final decision-making process);

6.  unlike IRV, It is very simple for voters to figure out how to best
strategize (i.e. for single-winner elections, If your favorite
candidate is one of the top-two most likely vote-getters, bullet vote.
Otherwise, vote for both your favorite(s) and one of the likely
top-two vote getters. In other words, the simple principle is that a
vote for your 2nd choice candidate may cause the 2nd choice, rather
than your 1st choice candidate to win, so vote for a 2nd, 3rd,...
choice if you don't mind them winning the contest.)

7,  unlike IRV, it increases the chances of a popular 3rd party
candidate winning rather than being a system for keeping the smaller
party candidates from interfering with the 2 major parties (true once
people figure out how to strategize with IRV by ranking one of the 2
major party candidates 1st)

In other words, approval voting is administratively, educationally,
and technically simple and equitable, and thus doable - and unlike IRV
actually makes substantial improvements over FPTP because it solves
the spoiler problem and does not create nonmonotonicity and huge
administrative, technical, auditability and other practical problems.


-- 

Kathy Dopp
http://electionmathematics.org
Town of Colonie, NY 12304
One of the best ways to keep any conversation civil is to support the
discussion with true facts.
Renewable energy is homeland security.

Fundamentals of Verifiable Elections
http://kathydopp.com/wordpress/?p=174

View some of my research on my SSRN Author page:
http://ssrn.com/author=1451051

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] More non-altruistic attacks on IRV usage.

2011-11-27 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

David L Wetzell wrote:


KM:I think this is where we differ, really. On a scale from 0 to 1,
you think their relative merit is something like:



0: Plurality
0.7: IRV3/AV3
0.72: Condorcet, MJ, etc



while I think it's something like:



0: Plurality
0.25: IRV
0.3: IRV3/AV3
0.7: Condorcet, MJ, etc.



(Rough numbers.)



If you're right, of course arguing for Condorcet seems like an
angels-on-the-head-of-a-pin thing - and it's even harmful because
X_IRV * p(IRV)  X_Condorcet * p(Condorcet) . The step from
IRV3/AV3 to Condorcet is only 0.02 after all, and the momentum
difference is huge! But if I'm right (and this is why I keep
bringing up the examples where IRV has been used), then going for
IRV is much more likely to rebound on you later.



dlw: This is a good statement of our diffs.  I'd say I rank the partial 
use of PR to get a contested duopoly (or to prevent a contested 
monopoly) very high, while you rank it rather low, especially relative 
to the development of a multi-party system, not unlike what you have in 
Norway.  This is likely a matter of political cultural differences, 
which makes my valuations more likely to be prevalent in the US.


I base my low confidence of PR's capacity to pull stronger towards 
competition than IRV does towards consolidation in that IRV pulls 
stronger wherever it's been tried. You say they aren't applicable. You 
may have that opinion, but then there's little I can show that will help.


So there are two disagreements. Ultimately, I think that multiparty 
democracy would be better than your contested two-party rule. I could 
pull market analogies for this (oligopolies and cartels), or I could 
simply say it's harder to buy off ten than to buy off two. Here you 
may claim that this is because of my political difference if you want to 
do so.


However, stronger is this: even if you wanted a contested two-party 
rule, I think IRV would pull too strongly. Again I take my evidence from 
other countries where that is the case - where the major two are the 
same as they have been a long time ago, and again, you say that's not 
applicable. Of course, nothing is absolute: even with Plurality, your 
own major parties have changed a few times since the time of the 
Founding Fathers. I just don't think IRV will make a difference.


So if we boil down our disagreement further, I think that we *can* 
generalize from other IRV nations. You think we can't, because your 
rules are different. There have been many IRV elections (so there are 
samples to pick), but not very many different systems of government in 
which IRV is placed. If I pull 100 local Australian elections and 
NatLibs or Labor win in 95 of them, you could say that's because of the 
Australian rules so they only count as one sample.


I think you're judging IRV too harshly on account of Burlington VT.  The 
sample size is too small to make such a strong judgment.


Well, Burlington just confirms things. The simulations say IRV can fail 
to pick the CW, and may squeeze the center out, and the less minor the 
minor parties are, the worse it gets. As Burlington agrees with the 
simulations, that doesn't count in IRV's favor.



  4. This is why I pick away at how the args in favor of other
  election rules get watered down or annihilated when you make the
  homo politicus / rational choice assumptions more realistic or
  you reduce the number of effective candidates, or you consider
  how perceived biases/errors get averaged out over time and
  space, or you focus on the import of marketing and how IRV has
  the advantage in that area of critical importance to the
  probability of successful replacement of FPTP.




   You try to do so. From my point of view, when I give you examples
   from the real world, you say that it'll be different here (re
   Australia on the one hand and France on the other, for instance).
   When I pull from theory, you say that the theory doesn't apply
   because it assumes too much; and when I pick examples where theory
   and practice seem to agree (Burlington), you say that that's just
   because the status-quo-ists put pressure to bear on IRV.



dlw: 1. Well, the sample of IRV uses is small, which makes it hard to 
render verdict on it.


So why would IRV improve things enough over Plurality? That verdict, 
too, has to come from somewhere.


2.  AU does use IRV/PR in the opposite from ideal mix if the goal is to 
increase the number of competitive elections.   
3. WRT France, we disagreed on matters of taxonomy.  I classified their 
top two as a hybrid.  You classified it as a winner-take-all and used it 
to show how IRV has been improved upon and could be improved upon further.  


Let me try your pragmatism for a minute. You say that our disagreement 
about top-two is taxonomy. Why should taxonomy matter, though? If I have 
a tacs-type voting method, and an intar-type voting 

Re: [EM] Approval vs. IRV

2011-11-27 Thread Juho Laatu
On 27.11.2011, at 18.35, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 Nov 2011 23:05:49 -0700
 From: matt welland m...@kiatoa.com
 
 I wasn't clear. I want to hear opinions from the list: Is approval
 better or worse than IRV and why?
 
 Approval is a far superior system to FPTP and IRV because approval:
 
 1. unlike FPTP and IRV, it solves the spoiler problem of a nonwinning
 candidate altering who would otherwise win;

True. In Approval nonwinning candidates cause no harm. But plausible winners 
may spoil the election.

 
 2. unlike IRV, it is precinct-summable and easy to manually
 statistically audit for accuracy and so preserves or allows for
 timely, understandable, election accuracy verification;

True. But it is also possible to record the votes locally in IRV and then send 
the collected data forward (and based on that data, check the votes later 
locally).

 
 3. unlike IRV, it looks at all the candidate choices of all voters,
 thus treating all voters' votes equally and fairly and is thus
 monotonic;

True. But Approval collects only very little information, and in that sense it 
does not look at many of the preferences of the voters.

 
 4. unlike IRV, it is simple to implement using the same ballot style
 as FPTP, with a fairly simple programming change in the tally program;

In the USA Approval can often be implemented with only small changes to the 
FPTP procedure. But that is a local and history dependent criterion (i.e. does 
not apply in some other countries).

 
 5. unlike IRV, it preserves the rights of voters to have their votes
 counted fairly and equally with other voters and to participate in the
 final counting rounds (final decision-making process);

The algorithm of IRV is quite weird, but fully ranked votes will participate 
also in the final rounds. Approval has its own problems. If it turns out that 
candidates A and B were the most popular candidates, voters who approved both 
of them or neither of them may feel that their vote was not counted when the 
final decision was made.

 
 6.  unlike IRV, It is very simple for voters to figure out how to best
 strategize (i.e. for single-winner elections, If your favorite
 candidate is one of the top-two most likely vote-getters, bullet vote.
 Otherwise, vote for both your favorite(s) and one of the likely
 top-two vote getters. In other words, the simple principle is that a
 vote for your 2nd choice candidate may cause the 2nd choice, rather
 than your 1st choice candidate to win, so vote for a 2nd, 3rd,...
 choice if you don't mind them winning the contest.)

In Approval finding the best strategy may be very difficult when the number of 
potential winners is three or higher (that is maybe my biggest concern in 
Approval). Also in IRV one may easily fail to find the best strategy (and the 
result of the election may get worse). In IRV sincere voting is however a quite 
reasonable way to vote. In Approval voters need to identify the best strategy 
to cast an efficient vote. Sometimes they may face a dilemma where they must 
either not take position in the key question or risk electing a bad candidate.

 
 7,  unlike IRV, it increases the chances of a popular 3rd party
 candidate winning rather than being a system for keeping the smaller
 party candidates from interfering with the 2 major parties (true once
 people figure out how to strategize with IRV by ranking one of the 2
 major party candidates 1st)

It is true that Approval can elect compromise candidates, while IRV clearly 
favours large parties. I consider methods that can elect compromise candidates 
to be better general purpose single winner methods. But the choice of method 
depends here very much on what kind of results the society in question wants to 
have. In the USA where the tradition is e.g. to elect single winners to form 
single winner governments, I can understand if some people prefer methods that 
favour large parties.

Also methods that aim at electing only from the strongest groupings have their 
place in the family of voting methods. (Such methods, that would also eliminate 
some of the problems of IRV, have been discussed recently on this mailing 
list.) I'm not sure if IRV was planned this way or if that property is 
accidental. But that property may well be one reason why the old parties are 
happier to support IRV than some of the other methods (i.e. to keep competition 
out, not necessarily to support the philosophy of electing only strong 
candidates).

Approval can handle small 3rd parties very well. In a (former) two-party system 
the problems of Approval are likely to emerge only when those small 3rd parties 
grow almost as strong as the smaller one of the two old strong parties.

 
 In other words, approval voting is administratively, educationally,
 and technically simple and equitable, and thus doable - and unlike IRV
 actually makes substantial improvements over FPTP because it solves
 the spoiler problem and does not create nonmonotonicity and huge
 administrative, 

Re: [EM] Robert Bristow Johnson wrt Burlington et al.

2011-11-27 Thread David L Wetzell


 dlw:   The two major-party equilibrium would be centered around the
de facto center.


 KM:   But positioning yourself around the de facto center is dangerous
in IRV. You might get center-squeezed unless either you or your
voters start using strategic lesser-evil logic - the same sort of
logic that IRV was supposed to free you from by being impervious
to spoilers.

 dlw: the cost of campaigning in less local elections is high enuf that
 it's hard for a major party to get center-squeezed.  And if such did
 happen, they could reposition to prevent it.


 RBJthe counterexample, again, is Burlington Vermont.  Dems haven't sat in
 the mayor's chair for decades.


dlw: Not sure this is a relevant counter example.  With IRV, the two major
parties would become the Progs and the Dems who would be centered around
the de facto center of Burlington.


 --
 -- Forwarded message --
 From: matt welland m...@kiatoa.com
 RBF: the counterexample, again, is Burlington Vermont.  Dems haven't sat in
  the mayor's chair for decades.

 MW: Is this due to a split of the liberal vote by progressives or other
 liberal blocs? Or is it due to a truly Republican leaning demographic?


dlw: More to the point, this is not an arg against IRV since it was only
tried for one election in Burlington.


 MW:Also, do folks generally see approval as better than or worse than IRV?

 To me Approval seems to solve the spoiler problem without introducing
 any unstable weirdness and it is much simpler and cheaper to do than
 IRV.


dlw: I would not describe IRV as introducing unstable weirdness.  It
maintains a two-party dominated system and facilitates that those two major
parties tend to position themselves around the de facto (shifting) center.


 What do you think of the IRV3/AV3 system that treats the up to 3 ranked
 votes as approval votes to get 3 finalists with IRV used in the final
 stage?




 -- Forwarded message --
 From: robert bristow-johnson r...@audioimagination.com
 To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Date: Sat, 26 Nov 2011 22:31:03 -0500
 Subject: Re: [EM] More non-altruistic attacks on IRV usage.
 On 11/26/11 6:58 PM, matt welland wrote:


 MW:Is this due to a split of the liberal vote by progressives or other
 liberal blocs? Or is it due to a truly Republican leaning demographic?

 RBS:Burlington is, for the U.S., a very very liberal town with a
 well-educated and activist populace.  it's the origin of Ben  Jerry's and
 now these two guys are starting a movement ( http://movetoamend.org/ ) to
 get a constitutional amendment to reverse the obscene Citizens United
 ruling of the Supreme Court.

 the far north end of Burlington (called the New North End, also where i
 live) is a little more suburban in appearance and here is where the GOP
 hangs in this town.

 the mayors have been Progs with an occasional GOP.  it is precisely the
 center squeeze syndrome and IRV didn't solve that problem. and without
 getting Condorcet adopted, i am not sure how it will be reversed.


dlw: If you had given IRV another election, it would have likely solved the
problem.   You cannot seriously think that one Burlington has driven a
stake in the heart of IRV for once and forever.




 RBS:but the only voting methods folks generally see here are FPTP, FPTP
 with a delayed runoff, and IRV.  and, thanks to FairVote, nearly everyone
 are ignorant of other methods to tabulate the ranked ballot than the STV
 method in IRV.


dlw: And it was hard work to get people to get IRV..., just think how hard
it would be to teach them about 4 very heterogeneous election rules.






 -- Forwarded message --
 From: Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 To: David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
 Date: Sat, 26 Nov 2011 22:32:53 -0600
 Subject: Re: [EM] More non-altruistic attacks on IRV usage.
 Here's I think the crux of your mistake:

  We can't say it's just a matter of opinion, cuz it's probably not such,


 I don't want to get too far into philosophical issues here, but I think
 that in one sense we can basically take it for granted that it's not such:
 that, in the proverbial phrase, God does, in fact, know whether
 p(irv_succeeds_broadly | voting_reform_succeeds_broadly ) is close to 1,
 close to 0.5, or close to 0. (I say that as shorthand; I'm actually quite
 convinced God doesn't exist, I'm just saying I believe in objective truth.)


dlw: Args about God are for another list-serve...  I'd say I'd bet my life
that P(irv_succeeds_broadly_among_single-winner_elections | maintain
existing voting reform strategy(+ IRV3/AV3 tweak)) 
P(another_election_rule_replaces_irv_and succeeds_broadly_et al. | existing
voting reform strategy is subverted on the basis of electoral analytical
args + Burlington, VT case-study)


  But the fact that the truth is out there, does not imply that it is
 either desirable or possible for people to stop arguing about it before we
 have much clearer evidence 

Re: [EM] An ABE solution

2011-11-27 Thread Kevin Venzke
Mike,


De : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com
À : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 26 Novembre 2011 13h39
Objet : [EM] An ABE solution


This was answered in the first part of the paragraph that you're quoting. What 
Woodall calls a preferential
election rule is by definition a rank method.

Kevin


Kevin said:

By definition an election method doesn't use
approval ballots. 

[endquote]

Whose definition? 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Re : An ABE solution

2011-11-27 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
 
My perspective is the following:
1. Most real-world elections will have a sincere CW, although that might not 
be visible from the ballots.
1a. Those elections without a sincere CW don't really have a wrong answer, 
so I don't worry as much about the pathologies in that case.
2. Therefore, we can divide FBC-violating strategies into two (overlapping) 
classes: those which work when there is not a CW among the other voters, 
which I will call offensive strategies, and which usually work by creating 
a false cycle; and those which work when there is no CW among the other 
voters, which I will call defensive.
3. I consider that a method with no offensive FBC violations is good 
enough. That's why I've used those labels: why would defensive strategies 
be a problem if offensive ones weren't?


Having some problems understanding where you're coming from. A defensive 
FBC-violating strategy isn't likely going to be 
provoked by an offensive FBC-violating strategy. I would expect it to be 
provoked by the truncation of other voters.

If you want to say that it's enough for methods to not be suspectible to 
strategies that would necessitiate defensive compromise
from other voters, then I might agree, but that is almost the same thing, in 
practice, as saying the method should satisfy FBC.


Kevin, I suspect that you're probably closer to the truth than I am on this, 
because you have more experience twiddling the knobs on your simulator. But 
your brief assertions here don't really give me enough fodder for me to 
understand why I'm wrong, if I am.


Do you agree with me that lack of a sincere CW will be rare? Do you agree 
with me that some methods have strategic possibilities which are irrelevant 
as long as there is a sincere CW who is known as such by most voters? Do you 
agree that some FBC violations fall into that category? 


Apparently you do not agree that all FBC violations which start from a non-CW 
scenario fall into that category; and apparently this is because 
non-FBC-violating truncation strategies could cause the non-CW scenario. If 
I've read you correctly on this, you may well be right, but I don't follow 
all the logic. But even if I have and you are, the questions in the preceding 
paragraph are more important for the big picture.


Jameson
 

I suspect I don't understand you more than that I think you are wrong. My best 
guess as to what you are saying involves trying
to interpret the thought behind your rhetorical question (why would defensive 
strategies be a problem if offensive ones weren't)
which seems to me to assume that defensive FBC-violating strategies depend on 
there being offensive FBC-violating strategies.

Let's grant that we only care about the situation that there is a sincere CW. 
I'm not sure how to answer your other questions in the 
second paragraph. Maybe I'll understand their importance after another 
exchange.

I would like to understand what you are referring to when you talk about an 
offensive FBC-violating strategy. You say this strategy
usually creates a false cycle. Does this strategy also directly betray one's 
favorite? Or what do you mean by FBC-violating here?
If it does betray the favorite, then you seem to be describing a strategy 
where some voters bury their favorite in order to create 
a false cycle (probably by creating a pairwise defeat over that favorite, or 
something comparable in effect) that achieves something 
preferable. But if this was creating a cycle then I have to wonder who was the 
preexisting winner? Surely it would have been the 
favorite?

I hope you see where I am coming from. As far as I can understand, the 
offensive FBC-violating strategy is a strange idea, so I
can hardly see it as the obvious thing to blame for provoking defensive 
FBC-violating strategies.

My impression of what provokes defensive FBC-violating strategies is not based 
on sims. It's just based on asking the question,
if there is a sincere CW but not a voted one, what kind of inaccuracies might 
exist on the cast votes? It could be many things
besides offensive compromise.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Robert Bristow Johnson wrt Burlington et al.

2011-11-27 Thread Jameson Quinn


 dlw: I believe you're serious.   Like I said, I'm not that motivated by
 money(especially for a guy with a PhD in Econ.)  It's a byproduct of me
 being an aspie.  So I'd feel bad about taking you up on the 2nd one and the
 first bet is inadequately framed in my view


C'mon. Neither of them is worth more than about $60 in net present value. I
can afford that plus the risk.

I realize that bet 1 is underspecified, but I don't think your direction
for specifying it is good because it relies on a lot of work that would be
better spent just promoting reform. I think we could develop an objective
metric of support which didn't require so much intervention.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Robert Bristow Johnson wrt Burlington et al.

2011-11-27 Thread David L Wetzell
meh,
I don't want to take bet number 1.  This list-serve is skewed towards smart
and politically-interested folks, who equally importantly tend to be
arm-chair/list-serve/blog activists.  Methinks, we tend to project our
attributes too much onto the general voting population as a matter of
wishful thinking and a relative lack of experience.  We also tend to think
of the possibilities a lot more and can get attached to our pet rules.

It's relatively easy for a smart person like you to come up with a SODA
election rule than it is to rally and lead an organization into promoting
it successfully for there are different skills involved. We got the former
quite a bit and the latter not so much.  This leads to conflict because
those who think they ought to be calling the shots about the direction of
electoral reform are not making the key decisions.  And we value different
stuff, which tends to lead to further estrangements.  My view of myself is
that I'm trying to bridge the two somewhat, by being careful about not
idealizing voters.  And, I'm playing the conservative, a selective defender
of the working orthodoxy of electoral activists.  I'm defending their
marketing pitch and their  right to decide what's important and what's
not-so-important.  What's telling and what's not-so-telling, like the
Burlington VT setback for IRV.

So I'll take bet number 2, but not number 1.  I think we're too estranged
from the realities of electoral activism on this list-serve and have other
factors that hinder us from coming to a good working consensus and/or
properly appreciating the X*P of IRV.

dlw

On Sun, Nov 27, 2011 at 6:10 PM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:


 dlw: I believe you're serious.   Like I said, I'm not that motivated by
 money(especially for a guy with a PhD in Econ.)  It's a byproduct of me
 being an aspie.  So I'd feel bad about taking you up on the 2nd one and the
 first bet is inadequately framed in my view


 C'mon. Neither of them is worth more than about $60 in net present value.
 I can afford that plus the risk.

 I realize that bet 1 is underspecified, but I don't think your direction
 for specifying it is good because it relies on a lot of work that would be
 better spent just promoting reform. I think we could develop an objective
 metric of support which didn't require so much intervention.

 Jameson



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Re to Kristof M

2011-11-27 Thread David L Wetzell
On Sat, Nov 26, 2011 at 3:20 PM, David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com wrote:

 Here's a bunch of responses


dlw: SL may be more proportional than LR Hare, but since I'm advocating for
the use of a mix of single-winner and multi-winner election rules, I have
no problems with the former being biased towards bigger parties and the
latter being biased somewhat towards smaller parties.  For there's no need
to nail PR if PR itself does not nail what we really want PP,
proportionality in power.  This is also part of why I prefer small-numbered
PR rules (less proportional) that increase the no. of competitive elections
and maintain the legislator-constituent relationship.


  KM:You might be able to get something more easily understood yet
 retaining some of the compensation part of the first version, by doing
 something like this: first elect the single winner/s. Then start STV with
 the single winner/s marked as elected (and thus with vote transfers already
 done).


 dlw:The rub here is the desirability of guaranteeing that the Condorcet
winner is elected.  In more local elections that attract less attention,
I put less emph on the usefulness of rankings and thereby the Condorcet
winner.


 KM:So the balancing point depends on how much you value single-winner
 balance against PR diversity. You could probably do some calculations to
 find out to what degree increasing the single-winner share lowers the
 probability of small-party kingmakers getting undue power, but ultimately,
 you'd have to make a value judgement.

  dlw: I'm intrigued by the 3:1 ratio  approach for a number of reasons,
including its simplicity...  If a party is really popular, it'd
typically get 3 of the seats and a two seat edge over its closest rival.
This is half of what is the case if it's just a single-winner.  If no party
is really popular then the top party gets 2 seats and a one seat advantage,
only one-fourth of what would typically happen...The goal being: a meld
between the de facto current system in countries like the UK and a EU-style
PR system...


 dlw:   1. While all forms of PR fall short of proportionality in
 representation, the best predictor of proportionality is the number of
 contested seats.


  KM:The Hix-Johnston-MacLean document states that these effects are weak.
 To quote:
 Turnout is usually higher at elections in countries with PR than in
 countries without, It also tends to be even higher in PR systems with
 smaller multi-member constituencies, and also tends to be higher where
 citizens can express preferential votes between individual politicians from
 the same political party rather than simply choosing between pre-ordered
 party lists. In general, the more choice electors are offered, the greater
 the likelihood that they will turn out and exercise it. However these
 effects are not particularly strong, there is some evidence that highly
 complex electoral systems suppress turnout, and turnout levels may partly
 reflect influences other than the electoral system, for instance in some
 countries voting is compulsory.
 So I don't think you can necessarily draw that conclusion. The apparent
 competitiveness between seats may be lesser (because of what I mentioned
 above in that single-member districts are much more win-all/lose-all), but
 that doesn't mean the real change in voter opinion from term to term is any
 greater in SMD countries.


dlw: I interpret what they're saying is that other factors also come into
play that impact the competitiveness of elections.  So my conclusion could
still beuseful, even if it abstracts from a lot of real-world stuff that
also affects voter-turnout.  The election rules that best guarantee
proportionality tend to reduce voter interest in elections, thereby making
PR not the key criteria for choosing an election system.


 2. Proportionality in representation does not entail proportionality in
 power and the latter is desired more than the former. As such, it seems
 that minority dissenters will need to use extra-political methods (not
 unlike #OWS) to move the center, regardless of whether PR or another mixed
 system is used.

 Proportionality in representation is correlated with proportionality in
 power. The correlation isn't perfect, as Banzhaf and Shapley-Shubik's
 measures make apparent, but to leap on that and conclude that
 proportionality isn't proportional... that's unwarranted.


dlw: But it waters down the desirability of nailing PR even further and
opens the door to a greater valuation of other conflicting criteria.


 KM:If anything, when proportional representation disagrees with
 proportionality in power, the power favors the minority parties. Minor
 party kingmakers can make themselves costly if they know there won't be any
 coalition without them. Hence the presence of thresholds in most PR
 systems: these keep too minor parties from becoming potential kingmakers.
 Over here, the threshold of 4% keeps most swing parties (as one may call
 them) out of power. 

[EM] ranked pair method that resolves beath path ties.

2011-11-27 Thread Ross Hyman


When beat path produces a tie, this method can produce a single winner unless 
the tie is genuine.  It is the same method I presented earlier except for the 
addition of the Removing step, which resolves the ties. 

Candidates are classed in two categories: Winners and
Losers.  Initially, all candidates are Winners.  Every candidate has
an associated Set of candidates that includes itself and those candidates that
have defeated it.  Every candidate initially has a set composed of itself
and no other candidates.  Winners are those candidates who have no Winners
in their set aside from themselves.



The pairs are ranked in order.  All pairs
are ranked in the form AB indicating more voters rank A above B than rank B
above A.  Pairs with equal votes for A
above B and B above A are not ranked.  For
winning votes ranking, AB is ranked higher than CD if more voters
ranked A above B than ranked C above D. 
If the same number of voters ranked A above B as ranked C above D then
AB is ranked higher than CD if more voters ranked D above C than ranked
B above A.  If the same number of voters
ranked A above B as ranked C above D and the same number ranked D above C as
ranked B above A then these pairs are equally ranked.

 

Affirm each group of equally ranked pairs in order, from
highest to lowest.   The count can
be ended before all pairs have been affirmed if only one Winner remains.

 

Affirming is composed of three steps: Combining sets,
Removing candidates from sets, and Reclassifying candidates.    

 

Affirming Step 1: Combining

When A  B is affirmed, the set for candidate A is added
to every set that includes candidate B (not just candidate B’s set).  The 
Combining step is performed for all pairs
of the same rank before moving on to the Removing step.

 

Affirming Step 2: Removing

Each pair of winning candidates that are in each others'
sets are deleted from those sets. Example if C is in D's set and D is in C's
set and both C and D are winners, then delete C from D's set and delete D from
C's set.).  All such pairs of candidates
are removed before moving on to the Reclassifying step.  The inclusion of this 
step resolves ties that
are not resolved by the beat path method.

 

Affirming Step 3: Reclassifying

All Winners that now have Winning candidates other than
themselves in their set are reclassified as Losers.

 

Example

7 A  B  C  D

6 C  D

5 D  B  A  C





A B  C D

A 0  7  12    7

B  5  0  12    7

C 6  6  0  13

D 11    11    5  0



C D 13,5

AC and BC 12,6

DA and DB 11, 7

AB  7,5



affirm CD

A(W): A(W)

B(W): B(W)

C(W): C(W)

D(L):C(W), D(L)

D was reclassified as a Loser since C(W) is in its set. 



affirm  AC and B  C

A(W): A(W)

B(W): B(W)

C(L): A(W), B(W), C(L)

D(L): A(W), B(W), C(L), D(L)

C was reclassified as a Loser since A(W) and B(W) are in its set. 



affirm D  A and D  B

A(W): A(W), B(W)*, C(L), D(L)

B(W): A(W)*, B(W), C(L), D(L)

C(L): A(W), B(W), C(L), D(L)

D(L): A(W), B(W), C(L), D(L)

A and B are both winners. A is in B's set and B is in A's set. So A is deleted
from B's set and B is deleted from A's set.

A(W): A(W), C(L), D(L)

B(W): B(W), C(L), D(L)

C(L): A(W), B(W), C(L), D(L)

D(L): A(W), B(W), C(L), D(L)



affirm A  B

A(W):A(W), C(L), D(L)

B(L): A(W), B(L), C(L), D(L)

C(L): A(W), B(L), C(L), D(L)

D(L): A(W), B(L), C(L), D(L)

B was reclassified as a Loser since A(W) is in its set. 





A wins.  With beat
path, A and B are tied.


 

 

 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] ranked pair method that resolves beat path ties.

2011-11-27 Thread robert bristow-johnson


so this is interesting.  it seems to be an extension of Tideman 
ranked-pairs that considers first the margins and then the opposing 
votes (or winning votes for the opponent) to break ties.  is that 
essentially it?


On 11/27/11 10:21 PM, Ross Hyman wrote:


When beat path produces a tie, this method can produce a single winner 
unless the tie is genuine.  It is the same method I presented earlier 
except for the addition of the Removing step, which resolves the ties.



Candidates are classed in two categories: Winners and Losers.  
Initially, all candidates are Winners.  Every candidate has an 
associated Set of candidates that includes itself and those candidates 
that have defeated it.  Every candidate initially has a set composed 
of itself and no other candidates.  Winners are those candidates who 
have no Winners in their set aside from themselves.


The pairs are ranked in order.All pairs are ranked in the form AB 
indicating more voters rank A above B than rank B above A.



now this is ranked pairs w.r.t. margins.


Pairs with equal votes for A above B and B above A are not ranked.


not immediately, but is this not what the procedure below is about?

For winning votes ranking, AB is ranked higher than CD if more 
voters ranked A above B than ranked C above


If the same number of voters ranked A above B as ranked C above D then 
AB is ranked higher than CD if more voters ranked D above C than 
ranked B above A.




so maybe i got it wrong, first it's Winning Votes that determines the 
order of ranking and then Margins is used to break the tie?


If the same number of voters ranked A above B as ranked C above D and 
the same number ranked D above C as ranked B above A then these pairs 
are equally ranked.




because *both* the winning votes is tied and the margins is tied.  what 
else is there?


i wonder if it would be better to first rank each pair according to 
Margins and then, in the case of tie of Margins, Winning Votes are used 
to break the tie to determine which pair result has priority over the other.


for some reason, i like Margins because it is the product of the percent 
spread (which indicates how decisive a defeat is) times the number of 
voters participating (which indicates how important the pair election 
is).  that product is a natural measure for how important and decisive a 
pairwise defeat is.  Winning Votes, all by itself, should not be the 
sole (or primary in the present case) decider.  what if there is a lot 
of voters, but the pair-election is close (say a defeat by 1 vote)?  
it's not a decisive defeat, but Winning Votes would say it is.  i think 
Margins is more salient than Winning Votes.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] ranked pair method that resolves beath path ties.

2011-11-27 Thread Markus Schulze

Dear Ross Hyman,

you wrote (27 Nov 2011):

 A and B are both winners. A is in B's set and B is in A's set.
 So A is deleted from B's set and B is deleted from A's set.

 A(W): A(W), C(L), D(L)

 B(W): B(W), C(L), D(L)

 C(L): A(W), B(W), C(L), D(L)

 D(L): A(W), B(W), C(L), D(L)



 affirm A  B

 A(W):A(W), C(L), D(L)

 B(L): A(W), B(L), C(L), D(L)

 C(L): A(W), B(L), C(L), D(L)

 D(L): A(W), B(L), C(L), D(L)

 B was reclassified as a Loser since A(W) is in its set.

When I understand your proposal correctly, then you are
basically saying that, when contradicting beatpaths have the
same strength, then they are cancelling each other out and
the next strongest beatpath decides.

I believe that your proposal can lead to a violation of
monotonicity. Let's say that there is one beatpath from
candidate X to candidate Y of strength z and two beatpaths
from candidate Y to candidate X of strength z. Then these
beatpaths cancel each other out. However, if one of the two
beatpaths from candidate Y to candidate X is weakened, then this
beatpath decides that candidate Y is ranked ahead of candidate X
in the collective ranking. (This is problematic especially when
the weakened beatpath was the direct comparison Y vs. X.)

By the way: In my paper, I also recommend that the ranked
pairs method should be used to resolve situations where the
Schulze winner is not unique. However, the precise formulation
is important. See section 5 stage 3 of my paper:

http://m-schulze.webhop.net/schulze1.pdf

Markus Schulze


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info