RE: Shielding child whose mother is A from father's Blifestyle/ideology/religion?

2008-01-24 Thread Newsom Michael
Marty puts the matter in the right analytical framework.  

Arrangements regarding important child rearing issues are made, where
the family is intact, by the parents (typically) and the parents are
free, within fairly broad limits to be as unreasonable as they wish to
be.  They are constrained by few to no legal rules or standards in
deciding how to present (or not to present) difference to their
children.

When the family unit is no longer intact, because of divorce (more
precisely, because of the entry of a decree of divorce), the state acts
in loco parentis.  And here is where the problem lies.  The typical
answer is the impossibly vague best interests of the child standard.
But conceptually, the problem is virtually incapable of defensible
solution.  Parents are entitled to be unreasonable precisely because
of considerations of autonomy and privacy, neither of which makes much
sense when applied to the state acting in loco parentis: hence something
unmanageable, like best interests of the child.

I think that many family court judges are trying -- to one degree or
another -- to act like reasonable parents.  Of course they fail
miserably at that endeavor time and time again because, at least in
part, it is not clear that anybody knows what a reasonable parent is.
But the stubborn fact remains that few are likely to defend the notion
that the state, acting in loco parentis, can be unreasonable.

I recall a report that I ran across a couple of years ago that
contrasted child raising practices of upper income professionals and low
to middle income working class members.  The differences were like night
and day.  This is not the place to debate the relative merits of the
different approaches that the report highlighted, but it is the place to
note that deciding which approach is best, or most reasonable
ultimately turns on a series of value judgments which are, I think,
highly contestable.

I am sure that there is a place in all of this for careful consideration
of constitutional norms, but I must confess that I am not sure whether
nice judgments about those norms tell us much about reasonable
parenting, and I think that, in the final analysis, we are stuck with
debates about reasonable parenting, debates which may be both futile
and unedifying.  I disagree with Marty, I think, on the salience of the
EC in thinking through or trying to construct a defensible notion of the
reasonable parent -- the state acting in loco parentis.  There are
situations where the state gets to advance religion, or particular
religions, is ways that, on the surface would appear to violate the EC:
the military, the prison system, and other institutions where the state
functions like a parent given the control that the state has over
military personnel, prisoners, and other institutionalized persons.
These are cases where it could be said that the state is acting in loco
parentis.

Two final points:

Children who were raised by unreasonable parents may have a dickens of
a time adjusting to reasonable parents.  (The reverse is also
something to worry about, even if no solutions easily come to mind.)

One could say a lot about the institution of divorce, but it suffices to
note that divorce is, probably, unsettling, if not traumatic, for both
parents and children, in ways that we perhaps can never fully come to
know.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Thursday, January 24, 2008 5:06 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Cc: Volokh, Eugene
Subject: Re: Shielding child whose mother is A from father's
Blifestyle/ideology/religion?

I don't think Eugene's test case helps us see the problem clearly in
these religion 
disputes.  In deciding the best interests of the child, it is
virtually 
inevitable that a court will eventually be required to evaluate the
philosophy 
to which the child will be exposed -- a philosophy that can be conveyed
through 
words or deeds.  I forget how Eugene's article came out on this, but I
tend not 
to think there's much of a free speech problem here:  It's not a penalty
against 
the disfavored parent so much as it is the state acting in a sort of
parens 
patriae context, making the child a ward of the state in a sense for
purposes of 
the custody decision.  The state is permitted to itself teach the child
to 
prefer certain viewpoints -- such as that racism is bad -- and is
therefore 
permitted to favor certain viewpoints to which the child will be
exposed, as a 
virtual necessity of deciding what is best for the child.  It would be
almost perverse not to consider what the child will be taught, and
exposed to, in making such a determination.  (Think of our own 
children:  yes, of course we care for their material well-being; but
most of us are fortunate enough to be able to spend much more time
worrying about the values and beliefs, and modes of thinking, that our
children 
will 

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-09 Thread Newsom Michael
I don't know where you get your information.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 6:29 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?


Help me out here:  The major purveyors of informal violence --
murders, robberies, assaults, and the like -- are *not* street thugs?
Who are they then?  The Phelps crowd?  Politically motivated right-wing
activists?

(I should say that as to one important class of informal
violence, which is rape, bedroom thugs -- date-rapists -- are a more
major purveyor than street thugs; but street thugs are a major category
even there, and *the* major category as to the other kinds of violence.)

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 2:13 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigayspeech?
 
 No, the major purveyors are not street thugs.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 4:59 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigayspeech?
 
 
   The major purveyors of informal violence are street thugs.
 Politically motivated violence, whether motivated by left 
 ideologies (anarchism, labor extremism, the Weather 
 Underground, the Black Panthers, the Black Muslims) or right 
 ideologies (racism, anti-gay ideology when hostility to 
 homosexuals was a matter of ideology rather than as a matter 
 of social routine, as it has often been in the past), is 
 fortunately pretty rare.  Whether one categories violence 
 that's partly influenced by general praise of violence and of 
 violent lifestyles -- for instance, the violence that is 
 glamorized by some rap music -- as left, right, or 
 something else is an exercise left to the reader.
 
   Eugene
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom 
  Michael
  Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 12:32 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against 
  antigayspeech?
  
  Formal violence = violence perpetrated by the state, 
 typically through 
  the forms and the processes of the criminal law, but not 
 exclusively 
  so, of course.  (The easiest example being violence perpetrated 
  through the use of military force.)
  
  Informal violence = lynching, cross-burnings, assassinations, 
  vigilante justice, gay-bashing, and the like.  The state 
 may support 
  or condone such violence, but informal violence is not 
 conduced by the 
  formal instrumentalities of the state, enforcement of criminal 
  sanctions, police enforcement, military force, or otherwise.
  
  The political right is far more guilty of informal violence 
 than the 
  political left is.  Just think about who the major purveyors of 
  informal violence have been throughout our history.  One 
 could start 
  with the Ku Klux Klan, clearly a right-wing outfit.  Think 
 about those 
  who indulged in mob violence against African-Americans and 
 gays.  The 
  rhetoric of those mob attacks is hardly the language of the 
 political 
  left.
  
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Esenberg, 
  Richard
  Sent: Tuesday, November 06, 2007 8:31 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against 
  antigayspeech?
  
  Violence is visited far more by those on the political 
 right on those 
  on the political left than is the reverse case.
  
  What do mean by violence, formal and informal. In contemporary 
  America, direct political violence is, thankfully, relatively rare 
  unless you define violence in a way that departs from its customary 
  usage. Perhaps the idea is that political rhetoric leads to 
 criminal 
  activity by others, but the notion that this happens to any 
  substantial degree (as well as the assertion that violence, 
 however we 
  may define it, is a disproportionately a malady of the political 
  right) do not strike me as self evident.
  
  I suppose that you can always argue for the special protection of 
  those we regard as discrete, insular and socially 
 disadvantaged, but 
  isn't it hard to do that without some notion of what type 
 of criticism 
  (or verbal
  attacks) are permissible. If gays are in, how about fundamentalist 
  Christians and Muslims who also feel put upon by the larger 
 society. 
  How about Jews? Need we have special concern about rhetoric 
 denouncing 
  the Jewish lobby? After a few easy cases (and maybe

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-09 Thread Newsom Michael
I accept your helpful point.  I did not mean to suggest that informal
violence is random.  The Ku Klux Klan perpetrated informal, albeit
organized, violence.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Jean Dudley
Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 7:15 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?


On Nov 7, 2007, at Wednesday,November 7, 2007,3:28 PM, Volokh, Eugene  
wrote:

   Help me out here:  The major purveyors of informal violence --
 murders, robberies, assaults, and the like -- are *not* street thugs?
 Who are they then?  The Phelps crowd?  Politically motivated right- 
 wing
 activists?

   (I should say that as to one important class of informal
 violence, which is rape, bedroom thugs -- date-rapists -- are a more
 major purveyor than street thugs; but street thugs are a major  
 category
 even there, and *the* major category as to the other kinds of  
 violence.)

   Eugene


Let's turn it over on its head:  Are the Ku Klux Klan street  
thugs?  Were the men who murdered Matthew Shepard street thugs?  I  
think not.  I also think there is a difference between the two  
groups:  One has a long-standing history, a complex organization, the  
other was simply (!) a matter of mob mentality on a smaller scale.   
Oddly enough, neither group would be called street thugs by other  
members of their community.  They's just a bunch of good ol' boys.

I think what's missing here is a distinction that informal violence  
by itself connotes random violence;  It must be qualified with the  
word organized, and compared to Official (or formal) violence,  
defined as organized and sanctioned by law and or government.

In closing, the concept of street thug is misleading.  Only a  
miniscule amount of violence is perpetrated by the truly antisocial,  
psychopathic, or homeless.

Jean Dudley.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-09 Thread Newsom Michael
Your response clarifies the differences in our positions, for which I am
grateful.

Just one brief comment: I would import the asymmetry that I earlier
described into First Amendment jurisprudence, in much the same way that
I totally reject Powell's mischievous deconstruction of race in his
opinion in Bakke.  (I have an article coming out soon that makes, at
some length, the argument against Powell.)


-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Esenberg,
Richard
Sent: Thursday, November 08, 2007 2:13 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?

Perhaps, the use of the term informal violence here is a bit broad to
be meaningful. We could distinguish between violence that is politically
motivated and violence that, while not itself aimed at any political
end, is asserted to be a response to political points of view which
supposedly arouse sentiments against some group. There is, of course,
haze around the boundaries of that, but I think it's a serviceable
enough distinction to mean something to most people.

As for politically motivated violence, it's far from obvious that this
is uniquely - or even mostly - associated with political viewpoints that
are commonly categorized as being on the right. In my lifetime (and I am
not young), I could make a credible argument that most politically
motivated violence in this country (and there has not been much) took
place in the late 60's and early 70s and was almost entirely from the
left.

As to informal violence, Scott has a point. While I think that the
categories of left and right mean something (if not always as much as we
commonly assume they do),  they don't seem very helpful here. I am not
sure what it means to say, in 2007, that the KKK was a right wing
organization other than that we have chosen to assign racism to the
right. Many of the notorious southern segregationists - think Bilbo and
Long - were, in many respects, men of the left. And they were racists.


I assume that Professor Newsom might say that this reflects the lack of
consensus about race on the left, but would argue that the attitudes
that he wants to characterize as contributing to or constituting
informal violence are most often associated with the right. But even if
you think that's true (and can avoid the anachronism of assuming that
the right in 1921 is like the right of 2007), I don't see where the
left-right distinction helps in forming a set of principles to govern
situations like these.


It seems to me that political rhetoric on both the left and the right
might have the potential to stimulate - or to be seized upon as a
justification for - violence. But just as I would be reluctant to blame
radical firebrands for property crimes or civil unrest, I don't know
that that the Roman Catholic Church or evangelical Christians are
responsible for the attack on Matthew Shepard.

If there is an asymmetry that justifies an asymmetrical rule must have
something to do with the nature of the victim than the source of the
attack. The argument has to be that certain groups are more likely to be
bullied so we ought to be more sensitive to speech directed at them.

One problem with that is that the choice of vulnerable groups is
necessarily ideological. Professor Newsom is not bothered by the
potential social and political isolation of religious traditionalists
because he thinks there is no moral equivalence between saying don't
visit violence on me and saying, as he suggests traditionalists do,
don't keep me from visiting violence on others in order to follow my
religious beliefs. But that requires assuming that these traditional
religious beliefs visit violence on others. Certainly there are people
who will have no problem making that assumption, but is it one that
ought to be imported into First Amendment analysis?

Another problem is that it is a static analysis. It assumes that
asymmetrical rules don't produce asymmetrical behavior. This seems
implausible as Scalia suggests.


Rick Esenberg
Visiting Assistant Professor of Law
Marquette University Law School
Sensenbrenner Hall 321C
1103 W. Wisconsin Avenue
Milwaukee, Wisconsin 53201
(o) 414-288-6908
(m)414-213-3957
[EMAIL PROTECTED]





-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 2:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?

Formal violence = violence perpetrated by the state, typically through
the forms and the processes of the criminal law, but not exclusively so,
of course.  (The easiest example being violence perpetrated through the
use of military force.)

Informal violence = lynching, cross-burnings, assassinations, vigilante
justice, gay-bashing, and the like.  The state may support or condone
such violence, but informal violence

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-07 Thread Newsom Michael

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Monday, November 05, 2007 3:03 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory
 against antigayspeech?

 Let me make two related points.

 1.People who dislike Phelps' group may do so for a variety of
 reasons, some reasons being principled, some being tactical
 or strategic only.

 2.There is a powerful psychological link between gays and the
 Phelps group's conduct at the funeral of fallen warriors, and it is
 this: an anti-gay backlash could result because if it weren't
 for gays, or the gay agenda, whatever that is, Phelps'
 group would not be causing such pain and harm.  In other
 words, gay people may well be the target.  Gay people might
 be viewed as the cause of the outrageous behavior at
 funerals. Have any of the families who have been affronted
 said anything positive about gays?  And if so, how often has
 this happened?

 The connection between the two points is clear: a tactical
 objection to the Phelps group might merely be that its
 behavior is not the best way
 -- in the view of the tactical objector -- to stir up an
 anti-gay backlash.

 I make a similar point in a forthcoming article: liberal
 evangelical Protestants (and this includes secular
 rationalist Protestants) might have a complex, but
 essentially tactical objection to proselytizing techniques
 employed by pietistic evangelical Protestants: namely that
 while it is good that such proselytizing might bring
 non-Protestants into the pan-Protestant nomos, such
 proselytizing thereafter becomes counterproductive from the
 point of view of liberal evangelical Protestants because they
 believe -- rationalists that they are, or tend to be -- that
 conversion of the mind is the only way that they will build
 up their numbers, and the appeals of pietistic evangelical
 Protestants, with their emphasis on the heart and the soul,
 hinder conversion of the mind.

 I can't really respond to Eugene's proposed perspective
 because I do not think that we agree as to what is at stake.
 There is an ideological asymmetry in the fact and experience
 of violence, both formal and informal, in the United States.
 Violence is visited far more by those on the political right
 on those on the political left than is the reverse case.
 (This is so, in my opinion, because the political right is
 largely united in its views on race whereas the political
 left is more often than not divided.  The political right has
 greater cohesion, therefore, which enables it better to
 practice violence against those that it dislikes.  There are,
 of course, other factors that contribute to the asymmetry,
 not least of which might be that Americans lean towards the
 political right, and not the left.)

 Stimulating violence against African-Americans or against
 gays, longtime victims of such violence, calling directly or
 indirectly, overtly or covertly, for the use or application
 of violence, given the reality of the patterns of violence in
 America, is not something that ought to be protected under
 the banner of free speech.

 I can't read the First Amendment as privileging bullying or
 worse.  The speech-conduct distinction can be easily
 manipulated to encourage bullying and the like.  By the same
 token it can be manipulated to discourage such behavior.  I
 prefer the second course, not the first.  I am not saying
 that Eugene means to encourage bullying, but the practical
 consequences of his approach might lead to that unfortunate result.

 The relevance of Romer and Lawrence is, in my view, this:
 the cases attempt, among other things, to hold the line
 against fomenting violence
 -- both formal and informal -- against gay people.

 I share the views of many who have spoken on the Westboro
 matter arguing that we ought to be able to protect mourning
 and grief from the likes of the Phelps group.  Indeed, I have
 said so myself in so many words.  But, above and beyond that,
 I think that the real target of the Phelps group is gay
 people, and that real desire is to foment an anti-gay backlash.
 It is the second point that I had failed to make in earlier
 posts and I wish to correct that mistake now.  The real issue
 is violence -- formal or informal -- against gays and whether
 the First Amendment gets in the way of trying to contain such
 violence.



 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 6:47 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory
 against antigayspeech?


   OK, let me present it from a different perspective:
 Many traditionalist Christians have argued that civil rights
 victories for the gay rights movement mean losses for
 traditionalist Christians -- in particular, loss of free
 speech and the right to spread

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-07 Thread Newsom Michael
I can't see how one can equate gays and traditionalist religionists.
There is an asymmetry here too, by the way.  It is one thing to say:
don't visit violence on me and quite another to say don't keep me
from visiting violence on others in order to follow my religious
beliefs.  There is no moral equality between the two.

The best example of the kind of false analogy that I have in mind is
Powell's opinion in Bakke where he argues, amazingly enough, that all
people, including whites are minorities, completely ignoring, of
course, the salient fact that whites of various ethnic background came
together to oppress African-Americans and other non-whites.

Scalia, as usual, is wrong, wrong, wrong.  He ignores the reality of the
asymmetry of violence in America, something he is routinely wont to do.


-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Esenberg,
Richard
Sent: Tuesday, November 06, 2007 8:31 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?

Violence is visited far more by those on the political right
on those on the political left than is the reverse case.

What do mean by violence, formal and informal. In contemporary America,
direct political violence is, thankfully, relatively rare unless you
define violence in a way that departs from its customary usage. Perhaps
the idea is that political rhetoric leads to criminal activity by
others, but the notion that this happens to any substantial degree (as
well as the assertion that violence, however we may define it, is a
disproportionately a malady of the political right) do not strike me as
self evident.

I suppose that you can always argue for the special protection of those
we regard as discrete, insular and socially disadvantaged, but isn't it
hard to do that without some notion of what type of criticism (or verbal
attacks) are permissible. If gays are in, how about fundamentalist
Christians and Muslims who also feel put upon by the larger society. How
about Jews? Need we have special concern about rhetoric denouncing the
Jewish lobby? After a few easy cases (and maybe not even that many), I
think it's hard to make distinctions like this without advancing a
judgment that is either entirely subjective or based upon ideological
presuppositions.

But even if that's not the case, what about the impact of an asymmetric
rule that reflects this supposed ideological asymmetry? Don't we expect
rules to affect the behavior that they govern? To paraphrase Scalia in
R.A.V., if we allow one side to fight freestyle while the other must
follow the Marquis of Queensbury rules, isn't it almost certain that,
human nature being what it is, those who can fight freestyle will?

Rick Esenberg
Marquette University Law School




From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, November 05, 2007 9:43 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?

Well, let me probe again the question I raised in the post below
(which Michael quotes).  I take it that to the extent that speech can be
punished because it indirectly promotes violence -- which is to say, to
the extent that Brandenburg v. Ohio is overruled, at least when speech
comes from the political right (and Phelps' anti-American,
antipatriotic speech is treated as being of the political right) -- we
should worry much more about facially polite speech by mainstream
religious groups and mainstream religious leaders than about facially
extremely rude speech by the extremely marginal.  No-one much listens to
Phelps, and the very extremism of both his manner and his message
undermines him, and makes it highly unlikely that his speech will
actually foment violence.  On the other hand, condemnation of
homosexuality, even in facially peaceful tones and with peaceful
messages -- for instance, by the Catholic Church, by orthodox Muslim or
Jewish denominations, or by many traditionalist Protestants -- probably
does indirectly promote violence against gays.  The speakers may not
intend that, but surely the effects of their speech are much more
harmful to gays than the effects of Phelps' speech.

Under Michael's rationale, then, it seems to me that a ban on
mainstream religious teachings that promote hostility towards
homosexuality (even if they don't on their face or in their intentions
call for violence against homosexuals) would be perfectly
constitutional:  Recognition of gay rights would lead, and should lead,
to suppression of traditionalist religious groups' right to promote
their religious beliefs.  Or am I mistaken?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Monday, November 05, 2007 3:03 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-07 Thread Newsom Michael
1. I disagree with your framing because the question as you frame it is
relatively unimportant.

2. We also need to recognize the logical implications of your argument:
unwarranted support for bullies and worse. 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 5:02 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?


Well, Michael can disagree with my framing of the question; but
the question still remains:  If he's right that the Phelpsians' speech
can be suppressed in the name of protecting gays, then wouldn't speech
by traditionalist Catholics, Protestants, Muslims, and Jews who condemn
homosexuality -- speech that is not nearly as nasty on its face, but
that is doubtless more dangerous in its effect -- be equally
prohibitable?  I'd still like to hear where Michael stands on that
issue.  

As best I can read the logic of his analysis, then indeed such
speech, including those religious groups' basic teaching (including
literally quoting and endorsing the relevant passages from the Bible)
could be outlawed.  He and some others might think that's good.  But I
just think it's important to recognize that that's the logical
implication of his argument.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 12:22 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigayspeech?
 
 First, he who frames the question controls the discourse.  I 
 wish to emphasize both the reality and the asymmetry of 
 violence, both formal and informal, visited upon discrete 
 insular minorities.  You wish to emphasize speech, without 
 regard, or at least much regard to the consequences of that 
 speech.  We are going to have a difficult time bridging this gap.
 
 Second, I would not say that the speech at issue here indirectly
 promotes violence against ostracized groups.  I believe it is 
 a clever strategy intentionally designed to promote violence. 
  I don't know what facially polite means.  The question is 
 the promotion of violence, promoted politely or otherwise.
 
 3. History and experience teach us to worry much more about 
 the right than the left when it comes to violence directed 
 against insular and discrete minorities, like gays and 
 African Americans.
 
 4. The question, of course, is who is entitled to the greater 
 protection, in the event of a conflict:  victims of violence 
 or mainstream (or not so mainstream) religious groups.  See 
 point 1 above.
 We have different priorities and interests.  I strongly prefer mine.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Monday, November 05, 2007 10:43 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigayspeech?
 
 
   Well, let me probe again the question I raised in the 
 post below (which Michael quotes).  I take it that to the 
 extent that speech can be punished because it indirectly 
 promotes violence -- which is to say, to the extent that 
 Brandenburg v. Ohio is overruled, at least when speech comes 
 from the political right (and Phelps' anti-American, 
 antipatriotic speech is treated as being of the political 
 right) -- we should worry much more about facially polite 
 speech by mainstream religious groups and mainstream 
 religious leaders than about facially extremely rude speech 
 by the extremely marginal.  No-one much listens to Phelps, 
 and the very extremism of both his manner and his message 
 undermines him, and makes it highly unlikely that his speech 
 will actually foment violence.  On the other hand, 
 condemnation of homosexuality, even in facially peaceful 
 tones and with peaceful messages -- for instance, by the 
 Catholic Church, by orthodox Muslim or Jewish denominations, 
 or by many traditionalist Protestants -- probably does 
 indirectly promote violence against gays.  The speakers may 
 not intend that, but surely the effects of their speech are 
 much more harmful to gays than the effects of Phelps' speech.
 
   Under Michael's rationale, then, it seems to me that a 
 ban on mainstream religious teachings that promote hostility 
 towards homosexuality (even if they don't on their face or in 
 their intentions call for violence against homosexuals) would 
 be perfectly
 constitutional:  Recognition of gay rights would lead, and 
 should lead, to suppression of traditionalist religious 
 groups' right to promote their religious beliefs.  Or am I mistaken?
 
   Eugene
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom 
  Michael
  Sent: Monday, November 05, 2007 3:03 PM

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-07 Thread Newsom Michael
No, the major purveyors are not street thugs.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 4:59 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?


The major purveyors of informal violence are street thugs.
Politically motivated violence, whether motivated by left ideologies
(anarchism, labor extremism, the Weather Underground, the Black
Panthers, the Black Muslims) or right ideologies (racism, anti-gay
ideology when hostility to homosexuals was a matter of ideology rather
than as a matter of social routine, as it has often been in the past),
is fortunately pretty rare.  Whether one categories violence that's
partly influenced by general praise of violence and of violent
lifestyles -- for instance, the violence that is glamorized by some rap
music -- as left, right, or something else is an exercise left to
the reader.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 12:32 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigayspeech?
 
 Formal violence = violence perpetrated by the state, 
 typically through the forms and the processes of the criminal 
 law, but not exclusively so, of course.  (The easiest example 
 being violence perpetrated through the use of military force.)  
 
 Informal violence = lynching, cross-burnings, assassinations, 
 vigilante justice, gay-bashing, and the like.  The state 
 may support or condone such violence, but informal violence 
 is not conduced by the formal instrumentalities of the state, 
 enforcement of criminal sanctions, police enforcement, 
 military force, or otherwise.
 
 The political right is far more guilty of informal violence 
 than the political left is.  Just think about who the major 
 purveyors of informal violence have been throughout our 
 history.  One could start with the Ku Klux Klan, clearly a 
 right-wing outfit.  Think about those who indulged in mob 
 violence against African-Americans and gays.  The rhetoric of 
 those mob attacks is hardly the language of the political left. 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Esenberg, Richard
 Sent: Tuesday, November 06, 2007 8:31 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigayspeech?
 
 Violence is visited far more by those on the political right 
 on those on the political left than is the reverse case.
 
 What do mean by violence, formal and informal. In 
 contemporary America, direct political violence is, 
 thankfully, relatively rare unless you define violence in a 
 way that departs from its customary usage. Perhaps the idea 
 is that political rhetoric leads to criminal activity by 
 others, but the notion that this happens to any substantial 
 degree (as well as the assertion that violence, however we 
 may define it, is a disproportionately a malady of the 
 political right) do not strike me as self evident.
 
 I suppose that you can always argue for the special 
 protection of those we regard as discrete, insular and 
 socially disadvantaged, but isn't it hard to do that without 
 some notion of what type of criticism (or verbal
 attacks) are permissible. If gays are in, how about 
 fundamentalist Christians and Muslims who also feel put upon 
 by the larger society. How about Jews? Need we have special 
 concern about rhetoric denouncing the Jewish lobby? After a 
 few easy cases (and maybe not even that many), I think it's 
 hard to make distinctions like this without advancing a 
 judgment that is either entirely subjective or based upon 
 ideological presuppositions.
 
 But even if that's not the case, what about the impact of an 
 asymmetric rule that reflects this supposed ideological 
 asymmetry? Don't we expect rules to affect the behavior that 
 they govern? To paraphrase Scalia in R.A.V., if we allow one 
 side to fight freestyle while the other must follow the 
 Marquis of Queensbury rules, isn't it almost certain that, 
 human nature being what it is, those who can fight freestyle will?
 
 Rick Esenberg
 Marquette University Law School
 
 
 
 
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, 
 Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Monday, November 05, 2007 9:43 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigayspeech?
 
 Well, let me probe again the question I raised in the 
 post below (which Michael quotes).  I take it that to the 
 extent that speech can be punished because it indirectly 
 promotes violence -- which is to say, to the extent that 
 Brandenburg v

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-07 Thread Newsom Michael

You make some rather sweeping claims regarding the use of the terms
left and right.  I would appreciate any authority to which you could
refer me that might support those claims.  

I don't think that any of the claims that you make are defensible, but I
am open to persuasion by respectable authority on one or more of them.
Speaking of authority, you might want to take a look at Michael Dawson,
Black Visions which shows, in my opinion, that the terms do have
substance and coherence.  Certainly in the crucible of race the terms
do, as Dawson argues. If you recall, I indicated that the major
difference between the left and the American political and ideological
right was that the latter largely had a consensus view of race whereas
the American left did not.  I made the point deliberately and with a
fair amount of thought beforehand.

If you like, I can explain my views of the Civil War off list.  I do not
see the conundrum that you do.  

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Scott Idleman
Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 5:05 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against
antigayspeech?


It seems that the use of the words left and right, in some of the
recent 
posts, is both very controlling of the discourse and, quite possibly, 
tautological.  Indeed, I get the sense that these terms are being used
as 
labels to define, after-the-fact, those whose sociopolitical
philosophies 
yield certain outcomes, rather than those who adhere to certain 
philosophical views.  In other words, the right categorizes
after-the-fact 
those persons or perspectives that generate a lot of violence as defined
by 
Professor Newsom, while the left categorizes after-the-fact those
persons 
or perspectives that generate relatively little violence as defined by 
Professor Newsom.  In this sense, the distinction may be ideologically 
useful, but it is analytically (or pragmatically) unhelpful.

The distinction, or its use, is also very ahistorical.  It is employed 
entirely in retrospect, with arguably little regard for the
circumstances 
and perspectives of the time.  The framers, at the time, were in many 
respects progressives, even radicals, but they are presently viewed by
some 
as privileged racists -- I think they would be considered perpetrators
of 
violence under Professor Newsom's model -- who are not deserving of 
admiration, much less having public schools named after them.  And what
of 
the Union under President Lincoln?  It waged the bloodiest war, and 
singularly most destructive domestic campaign, in the name of
progressive 
ends.  Was it an act of the right -- as it sought the conservatist end
of 
maintaining the geopolitical boundaries and constitutional structure of
the 
nation -- or was it an act of the left -- as it sought to end slavery
and 
create a better nation?

I also get the sense that the term violence is being used to describe,

selectively, policies or conduct that disproportionately or
intentionally 
visit burdens upon marginal groups.  But again that's an invitation to 
tautology, or at least after-the-fact labeling.  Isn't taxation, backed
up 
by the coercive force of the state (including the use of the criminal
law), 
a form of violence or an act that carries with it the threat of
violence? 
If so, why aren't liberal policies of redistribution-via-taxation
policies 
of violence?  Why aren't compulsory schooling, vaccination requirements,
and 
mandatory sensistivity training--and the list goes on--similarly forms
of 
violence?  If they are not considered such, I think it is only because
of a 
selective use of the term violence.

I don't get the sense that Professor Volokh and others are trying to
control 
the discourse as much as they are trying to apply reason to difficult 
questions that arise in society and, eventually, in the legal system.  I
do 
think, however, that the redefinition and use of loaded terms like 
violence is a manipulation of discourse for ideological ends,
especially 
when others who do not accept or understand such definitions are 
categorically labeled as wrong.

Scott Idleman
Marquette University Law School


- Original Message - 
From: Newsom Michael [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wednesday, November 07, 2007 2:22 PM
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against 
antigayspeech?


 First, he who frames the question controls the discourse.  I wish to
 emphasize both the reality and the asymmetry of violence, both formal
 and informal, visited upon discrete insular minorities.  You wish to
 emphasize speech, without regard, or at least much regard to the
 consequences of that speech.  We are going to have a difficult time
 bridging this gap.

 Second, I would not say that the speech at issue here indirectly
 promotes violence against ostracized groups.  I believe

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigayspeech?

2007-11-05 Thread Newsom Michael
 take it that Michael disagrees:  His view is that Romer
and Lawrence should indeed lead the Court to uphold restrictions on
antigay speech, which I take it would include antigay religious
teachings.  Moreover, I take it that the assertedly compelling
government interest in protecting gays is *much* more jeopardized by
mainstream antigay teachings (even when they are comparatively politely
framed), from groups such as traditionalist Protestants, Catholics,
Muslims, and orthodox Jews, than by Phelps' gang of kooks (which if
anything would lead to some extra sympathy for gay rights, by tying
extremist antigay bigotry to extreme anti-Americanism).  So under his
rationale, the Court should uphold general bans on anti-gay-rights
teachings, including religious teachings.

If that's right, then weren't the traditionalist Christian views
who complained about the gay rights movement, and in particular about
the indirect consequences of its validation in cases such as Romer and
Lawrence, quite prescient?  If Michael's views are to prevail, then it
really is a question of choosing whose rights we protect -- the sexual
autonomy and equality of gays and lesbians, or the free speech and the
religious speech rights of traditionalist Christians.  When the first
group wins, the second loses (again, if Michael's views are to be
accepted).

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 12:41 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigay speech
 
 No, not remarkable.  
 
 Viewpoint neutrality is a chimera and an illusion, in my 
 opinion.  I do agree that the Court is not likely to agree, 
 but that does not mean that the Court is right, but merely 
 that the Court has spoken -- wrongheadedly.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 2:56 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigay speech
 
 
   Wow, that really is a remarkable First Amendment 
 position:  The government is constitutionally permitted to 
 ban antigay speech (all antigay speech? some antigay speech? 
 only antigay speech at funerals?), but I take it 
 constitutionally forbidden from banning progay speech, 
 anticapitalist speech, anti-Christian speech, and so on.  
 Might as well chuck all the Court's pretensions to viewpoint 
 neutrality out the window if that sort of exception is 
 accepted (though fortunately I can't count a single vote for 
 it on today's Court).
 
   Eugene 
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom 
  Michael
  Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 11:29 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against 
  antigay speech
  
  David has it right: a compelling governmental interest in 
 protecting a 
  discrete and insular minority -- one that is routinely victimized.
  
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of David Cruz
  Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 8:12 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against 
  antigay speech
  
  I too found that comment a little cryptic.  If Michael meant to be 
  doctrinal rather than just attitudinally predictive, my 
 guess would be 
  that he didn't mean that a different First Amendment rule 
 would apply, 
  but that those decisions might somehow justify a conclusion that 
  there's a compelling governmental interest present.  But it 
 wasn't at 
  all clear to me, so perhaps Michael might clarify.
  
  David B. Cruz
  Professor of Law
  University of Southern California Gould School of Law Los 
 Angeles, CA 
  90089-0071 U.S.A.
  
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, 
  Eugene
  Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 4:43 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigay 
  speech
  
  I'm puzzled -- do Romer and Lawrence really justify not just 
  protection of gays against governmental discrimination, but a 
  different First Amendment rule for antigay speech than for 
  pro-gay-rights speech or a wide range of other speech?
  
  Eugene
  
  Michael Newsom writes:
  
   That said, I have no idea of what the Court would do with
  this case,
   but my guess is that the Court would overturn the jury 
 verdict 5-4, 
   although Kennedy, on the strength of Romer and Lawrence, 
 might vote 
   with the moderates and the case would come out the other
  way, 5-4 to
   uphold the jury verdict (although the punitive damages might be 
   reduced

RE: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Newsom Michael
No, we don't all agree on a rigid speech-conduct distinction.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 2:43 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Speech and conduct


Setting aside all the other factors for now, I hope we could
agree that viewing this sort of picketing as conduct is the wrong way
for courts to go.  The picketing is offensive precisely because of the
message it communicates.  The noncommunicative components (the presence
of people, the fact that they occupy space on the sidewalk, the fact
that they carry signs on sticks) are irrelevant here (unless the
picketing somehow blocked the driveway into the cemetery or some such,
which I don't believe it did).  

Treating this speech as conduct works as poorly, I think, as
Justice Blackmun's view in Cohen v. California that Cohen's absurd and
immature antic ... was mainly conduct and little speech.  Whatever the
bottom line, it seems to me that courts should confront the true nature
of what's going on here, and what's going on here is speech that's
offensive precisely because it's speech.

Eugene

 
Alan Brownstein writes:

I think Eugene is right. This is, at its core, a content-based
restriction on speech. The context, in my judgment, is primarily
relevant to three questions: whether the penalty on speech can be
justified because of the consequences of the speech, whether the context
is such that we want to view this expression as something other than
speech (some kind of conduct) or  whether we view this as some kind of
speech that is not protected by the first amendment. It is never been
clear to me which of these reasons explains why certain kinds of
expressive activities can be punished as harassment - but clearly it is
permissible to punish harassment in certain circumstances. The tort of
IIED raises a similar mystery. I'm not suggesting that there isn't an
answer that justifies at least some applications of the cause of action.
But I don't think courts have told us what that answer is yet.

I would prefer that the situation in this case (and others like
it) be resolved by statutory limits on disruptive speech on public
property adjacent to places like cemeteries, funeral homes, hospitals
etc..  The benefit of a statute is that it can designate the contexts
which we consider totally inappropriate for extremely hurtful speech at
specific times and places. IIED leaves that question up to the
discretion of juries.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: IIED and vagueness

2007-11-02 Thread Newsom Michael
Could you please provide a full and complete factual description of the
Code Pink conduct?  I need to understand how it is analogous, in
concrete, factual terms, with the behavior of the Phelps group.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Esenberg,
Richard
Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 9:20 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: IIED and vagueness

As others have suggested, I think it goes like this. It seems quite
possible to suppose that military families will be offended by
demonstrators, either, as with Code Pink, outside a military hospital
(or, say at a military funeral), who suggest that their loved ones were
wounded or killed in vain. Heck, we don't even have to speculate because
news reports about those demonstrations reflected that families and
servicemen were mightily offended.

If you want to say that there ought to be some rule that requires some
level of nastiness that may not have been present at the Code Pink
demonstrations, it's not hard to imagine (there are ample real world
examples) that the demonstrators referred to soldiers as baby killers
or to those who sent them overseas as war criminal.

Incidentally, I would be interested in references to studies showing
that violence and insult are not evenly distributed across the political
spectrum.

Rick Esenberg
Marquette University School of Law

From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 5:58 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: IIED and vagueness

Could you be a bit more specific about the factual context of the Code
Pink demonstrations?  How is it analogous to Westboro's conduct?

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Esenberg,
Richard
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 12:48 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: IIED and vagueness

Well, it certainly seems outrageous to me but I suspect that other
reasonable people might regard the Code Pink demonstrations outside the
Walter Reed Army Medical Center as, if not equally outrageous, at least
comparable in their tendency to upset those who are presumably in a
place in which there is some expectation of privacy and repose. (Don't
we regard hospitals, like funerals, as places in which a certain decorum
can be expected?)

A standard that would potentially restrict such protests seems
problematic and, again, it seems even more troubling to make it, as
seems to have been done here, a jury question.


Rick Esenberg
Visiting Assistant Professor of Law
Marquette University Law School
Sensenbrenner Hall
1103 W. Wisconsin Avenue
Milwaukee, Wisconsin 53201
(o) 414-288-6908
(m)414-213-3957
[EMAIL PROTECTED]



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 11:17 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: IIED and vagueness

What makes it outrageous is not the content per se, but the content in
the context.  And doesn't the old workhorse, our erstwhile objective
standard of outrageous to a reasonable person, save it from
unconstitutional vagueness?

Steve

On 11/1/07, Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 Isn't a restriction on speech that is outrageous, and
inflicts
 severe emotional distress, where the speaker knows there's a high
 probability that severe emotional distress will be inflicted
 unconstitutionally vague, suffering from all three of the Grayned
 problems (risk of viewpoint discrimination in enforcement, difficulty
of
 telling when one is complying with the law, and resulting deterrent
 effect)?  'Outrageousness' in the area of political and social
 discourse has an inherent subjectiveness about it which would allow a
 jury to impose liability on the basis of the jurors' tastes or views,
or
 perhaps on the basis of their dislike of a particular expression.  (I
 also think it's unconstitutionally even setting aside the vagueness,
but
 as in many instances the vagueness is such an important problem that
it
 makes it hard to do the rest of the constitutional analysis, since
it's
 so hard to tell just what speech the law will restrict, even if
limited
 to cases where plaintiffs are private figures.)

 Eugene


--
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigay speech

2007-11-02 Thread Newsom Michael
David has it right: a compelling governmental interest in protecting a
discrete and insular minority -- one that is routinely victimized.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of David Cruz
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 8:12 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigay
speech

I too found that comment a little cryptic.  If Michael meant to be
doctrinal rather than just attitudinally predictive, my guess would be
that he didn't mean that a different First Amendment rule would apply,
but that those decisions might somehow justify a conclusion that there's
a compelling governmental interest present.  But it wasn't at all clear
to me, so perhaps Michael might clarify.

David B. Cruz
Professor of Law
University of Southern California Gould School of Law
Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071
U.S.A.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 4:43 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigay
speech

I'm puzzled -- do Romer and Lawrence really justify not just
protection of gays against governmental discrimination, but a different
First Amendment rule for antigay speech than for pro-gay-rights speech
or a wide range of other speech?

Eugene

Michael Newsom writes:

 That said, I have no idea of what the Court would do with 
 this case, but my guess is that the Court would overturn the 
 jury verdict 5-4, although Kennedy, on the strength of Romer 
 and Lawrence, might vote with the moderates and the case 
 would come out the other way, 5-4 to uphold the jury verdict 
 (although the punitive damages might be reduced, the Court 
 likely to send a signal, I think, in the Valdez case that it 
 is prepared to rein in punitive damages).
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: IIED and vagueness

2007-11-02 Thread Newsom Michael
1.  The Phelps group is doing more than just arguing a point of
view regarding sin and homosexuality.

2.  There is a difference between saying God bless American
soldiers and Bush killed this soldier.  The second clearly is meant
to insult.  The relevant question is whether, in the context of a
funeral, the mourners have to put up with stuff that might offend them,
insult them, or harass them at a time of great grief and sorrow.

3.  The relevant question ought to be not whether we believe Phelps'
logic, but whether the Constitution forbids protecting people at a time
of great sorrow and grief from obscene, targeted insult-as-violence. 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 12:35 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: IIED and vagueness


It seems to me that this would make matter of public concern
even mushier and viewpoint-based than it already is (or perhaps it would
just illustrate the mushiness and potential for viewpoint
discrimination).  As best I can tell, the protesters are arguing that
the nation has sinned by allowing homosexuality, or allowing gays in the
military, or what have you, and the death of soldiers is God's righteous
judgment on the country.  That's their viewpoint, vile and illogical as
it is.

I take it we'd agree that a demonstration outside a military
funeral saying God bless American soldiers is on a matter of a public
concern.  So, I assume, is a demonstration saying President Bush killed
this soldier.  So, I assume, is a demonstration saying Soldiers are
murderers, and deserve to die (again, reprehensible as such a
demonstration would be).  The relationship between this matter and the
funeral of the soldier, who after all had been exercising government
power on behalf of our nation, seems hardly attenuated.  Phelps et al.'s
view may be irrational, but the connection between it and the funeral of
the soldier is more attenuated or irrelevant only because we don't
believe his logic.  

The 3 am calls strike me as a rather weak analogy.  The problem
there isn't that the relationship between the speech and me is
attenuated, or that the message is irrelevant.  If you called me at 3 am
each morning to tell me that my publicly expressed views in some First
Amendment debate are unsound -- assume I'm even a limited public figure
as to that debate -- that would also be punishable, even though the
speech is closely related to me and my public commentary.  It might be
punishable under a Rowan-like rationale, especially once I tell you
stop bothering me, since restricting the speech to me doesn't at all
interfere with your conveying the message to others.  It might be
punishable under some rule that bars repeated unsolicited phone calls
during certain hours.  But the rationale here would be genuinely
unrelated to any message that I might be conveying, to its supposed
irrelevance to my participation in a matter of public concern, or the
tendency of the message (even coupled with the time, place, and manner
in which it's delivered) to offend me because of what it says.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Brownstein, Alan
 Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 2:58 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: IIED and vagueness
 
 I understand that there is a clear sense in which the 
 protestors comments involve speech on a matter of public 
 concern. But the relationship between that matter of public 
 concern and the family whose son has died and is being buried 
 is pretty attenuated. If the protestors just said John Doe 
 should rot in Hell, that would not be a matter of public 
 concern. Does adding Because we think the U.S. is immoral, 
 John Doe should rot in Hell change the statement enough to 
 make a difference. (By analogy, if I call Eugene up at 3:00 
 am each morning to tell him to vote for Hillary Clinton, 
 should it be harder for courts to hold me liable for 
 harassment because my statements are a matter of public 
 concern -- indeed they are pure political speech.) 
 
 I guess what I am asking is whether the impropriety and 
 irrelevance of the circumstance should influence our 
 conclusion as to whether what is being said is a matter of 
 public concern. If these protestors show up at the funeral of 
 any citizen with similar signs and argue that it is good 
 whenever any American dies because our country does not hate 
 gay people enough, should that alter the analysis? Isn't 
 there a sense that these people are just using the emotional 
 pain they cause and the anger generated by their outrageous 
 activities to gain attention for their message? 
 
 Should speakers be allowed to use the distress caused to 
 patients at hospitals or mourners at funerals as a way of 
 amplifying their largely unrelated speech on matters of 
 public 

RE: Phelps, IIED, offensiveness, and precedent

2007-11-02 Thread Newsom Michael
The Phelps case is easy because of the unique facts.  I don't think that
the Code Pink protests come close to matching the Phelps' protests.
Several writers in this thread have made the point that there is
something special about funerals, and ceremony, and ritual, and grief,
and that the law ought to be able to accommodate that special quality of
funerals.

 

It is not enough to suppose that first amendment principles (if that
means free speech only) trump everything else because then we have
privileged every imaginable and horrible type of bullying, harassment or
worse.  Of course, it is easy enough to say that at some point speech
becomes action and therefore subject to regulation and prohibition of a
sort not typically associated with speech.  But a more straightforward
approach would recognize that some speech needs to be regulated, even
prohibited. 

 

The only question that remains is where might one draw lines, a concern
that is important, but hardly controlling.  

 

It is enough to focus on the social, cultural, and psychological reality
of funerals.  That really cannot be all that difficult to do, can it?
Has not the law acquitted itself well if it does that? 

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Brad  Linda
Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 1:00 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Phelps, IIED, offensiveness, and precedent

 

I've been following this issue with great interest as a conservative
evangelical who considers the Phelps gang (I refuse to call them a
church) truly evil and indefensible and who (and I realize this is
probably not Christ-like love) likes to contemplate Mr. Phelps ultimate
appearance before the highest Judge of all.

 

A couple of different questions came to mind as I've been reading the
discussion, though.

 

First, a number of people have characterized the protests as offensive,
and it's true, they are.  However, it seems to me that the fact that
they are offensive is not the real issue.  I've seen protestors outside
Promise Keepers events that I have attended which I found offensive.
I've also seen protestors that oppose abortion (which I do, too) that
have protested in ways which I thought were offensive.  I'm not familiar
with the Code Pink protests, but the description of them here sounds
like something I would find offensive.

 

There is a difference, though, between that which offends and that which
causes pain.  If Phelps' band of idiots wants to demonstrate in front of
a recruiting center, that's one thing.  But when they picket a funeral
and intrude on the family's time to bid farewell to their loved ones,
that is designed to cause harm and inflict pain on the grieving.  That's
where the idea of a claim based on IIED has a lot of appeal to me.
Isn't it possible to make the legal distinction between offensive and
painful, or does that merely invite somebody to make the argument (a
baseless one, to my mind) that simply being offended is painful?

 

The other question that comes to mind regards the potential precedent
being set here.  In my 17 years working at a major university, I saw the
assertion made on many occasions that anybody who says that sexual
intimacy between two member of the same sex is wrong is both offensive
and guilty of hate speech.  If this verdict stands (and I do hope there
is a way for it to not only stand but be etched in stone), how can it be
done without opening a Pandora's box for a lawsuit against any minister
who preaches a sermon in which he states that sex outside of a
heterosexual marriage is sin, on the grounds that it was deemed
offensive and unprotected hate speech?  And if so, wouldn't that set a
dangerous precedent (i.e., if what Phelps said was offensive and
therefore actionable, why shouldn't what Pastor X says be actionable if
somebody finds it offensive)?  For example, if a practicing homosexual
could file a hate speech suit against a minister who preaches that
homosexual behavior is sin, what is to stop the practicing adulterer
from filing suit using the same rationale against a minister who
preaches against adultery?

 

Brad Pardee

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigay speech

2007-11-02 Thread Newsom Michael
No, not remarkable.  

Viewpoint neutrality is a chimera and an illusion, in my opinion.  I do
agree that the Court is not likely to agree, but that does not mean that
the Court is right, but merely that the Court has spoken --
wrongheadedly.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 2:56 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against antigay
speech


Wow, that really is a remarkable First Amendment position:  The
government is constitutionally permitted to ban antigay speech (all
antigay speech? some antigay speech? only antigay speech at funerals?),
but I take it constitutionally forbidden from banning progay speech,
anticapitalist speech, anti-Christian speech, and so on.  Might as well
chuck all the Court's pretensions to viewpoint neutrality out the window
if that sort of exception is accepted (though fortunately I can't count
a single vote for it on today's Court).

Eugene 

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 11:29 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigay speech
 
 David has it right: a compelling governmental interest in 
 protecting a discrete and insular minority -- one that is 
 routinely victimized.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of David Cruz
 Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 8:12 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory 
 against antigay speech
 
 I too found that comment a little cryptic.  If Michael meant 
 to be doctrinal rather than just attitudinally predictive, my 
 guess would be that he didn't mean that a different First 
 Amendment rule would apply, but that those decisions might 
 somehow justify a conclusion that there's a compelling 
 governmental interest present.  But it wasn't at all clear to 
 me, so perhaps Michael might clarify.
 
 David B. Cruz
 Professor of Law
 University of Southern California Gould School of Law Los 
 Angeles, CA 90089-0071 U.S.A.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 4:43 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Is First Amendment viewpoint-discriminatory against 
 antigay speech
 
   I'm puzzled -- do Romer and Lawrence really justify not 
 just protection of gays against governmental discrimination, 
 but a different First Amendment rule for antigay speech than 
 for pro-gay-rights speech or a wide range of other speech?
 
   Eugene
 
 Michael Newsom writes:
 
  That said, I have no idea of what the Court would do with 
 this case, 
  but my guess is that the Court would overturn the jury verdict 5-4, 
  although Kennedy, on the strength of Romer and Lawrence, might vote 
  with the moderates and the case would come out the other 
 way, 5-4 to 
  uphold the jury verdict (although the punitive damages might be 
  reduced, the Court likely to send a signal, I think, in the Valdez 
  case that it is prepared to rein in punitive damages).
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To 
 subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To 
 subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To 
 subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change

RE: IIED and vagueness

2007-11-01 Thread Newsom Michael
Could you be a bit more specific about the factual context of the Code
Pink demonstrations?  How is it analogous to Westboro's conduct? 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Esenberg,
Richard
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 12:48 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: IIED and vagueness

Well, it certainly seems outrageous to me but I suspect that other
reasonable people might regard the Code Pink demonstrations outside the
Walter Reed Army Medical Center as, if not equally outrageous, at least
comparable in their tendency to upset those who are presumably in a
place in which there is some expectation of privacy and repose. (Don't
we regard hospitals, like funerals, as places in which a certain decorum
can be expected?)

A standard that would potentially restrict such protests seems
problematic and, again, it seems even more troubling to make it, as
seems to have been done here, a jury question.


Rick Esenberg
Visiting Assistant Professor of Law
Marquette University Law School
Sensenbrenner Hall
1103 W. Wisconsin Avenue
Milwaukee, Wisconsin 53201
(o) 414-288-6908
(m)414-213-3957
[EMAIL PROTECTED]



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 11:17 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: IIED and vagueness

What makes it outrageous is not the content per se, but the content in
the context.  And doesn't the old workhorse, our erstwhile objective
standard of outrageous to a reasonable person, save it from
unconstitutional vagueness?

Steve

On 11/1/07, Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 Isn't a restriction on speech that is outrageous, and
inflicts
 severe emotional distress, where the speaker knows there's a high
 probability that severe emotional distress will be inflicted
 unconstitutionally vague, suffering from all three of the Grayned
 problems (risk of viewpoint discrimination in enforcement, difficulty
of
 telling when one is complying with the law, and resulting deterrent
 effect)?  'Outrageousness' in the area of political and social
 discourse has an inherent subjectiveness about it which would allow a
 jury to impose liability on the basis of the jurors' tastes or views,
or
 perhaps on the basis of their dislike of a particular expression.  (I
 also think it's unconstitutionally even setting aside the vagueness,
but
 as in many instances the vagueness is such an important problem that
it
 makes it hard to do the rest of the constitutional analysis, since
it's
 so hard to tell just what speech the law will restrict, even if
limited
 to cases where plaintiffs are private figures.)

 Eugene


--
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: IIED and vagueness

2007-11-01 Thread Newsom Michael
Some of what I am about to say I have said before.  But here goes
anyway.

What would be the risk of viewpoint discrimination, in a practical,
real-world, sense?  I am not aware of any other groups who attempt to
inflict severe emotional distress on the occasion of the funeral of a
soldier killed in combat.  Studies of the pattern of violence and insult
tend to show that it is not evenly distributed across viewpoints -- or
ideologies.  Put in simple English, I seriously doubt that
insult-as-weapon is, in any sense of the word, neutral and any rule
that treated it that way would be quite at variance with the real world
and would, as a consequence, unnecessarily privilege and protect a
narrow band of people, on the political right, who seem to favor
insult-as-weapon on the occasion of the funeral of a soldier killed in
combat.  (A fact pattern, by the way, that can be easily managed and
controlled such that the slippery slope argument has little merit.)

Is there no room left for common decency, or is everything, in the name
of a formalist view of the Free Speech Clause, up for grabs for fear of
viewpoint discrimination?

Nor am I sure that the proper object of the law is bright-line rules.
Such a view tends to suggest, as Richard Pildes has helpfully pointed
out in an article that he wrote on modern formalism, that law-makers,
particularly judicial law-makers (i.e. appellate court judges), are
somehow worth more than law-appliers (i.e. trial court judges and
perhaps intermediate appellate court judges as well), a proposition that
is far from self-evident or easily defended.

That said, I have no idea of what the Court would do with this case, but
my guess is that the Court would overturn the jury verdict 5-4, although
Kennedy, on the strength of Romer and Lawrence, might vote with the
moderates and the case would come out the other way, 5-4 to uphold the
jury verdict (although the punitive damages might be reduced, the Court
likely to send a signal, I think, in the Valdez case that it is prepared
to rein in punitive damages).

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 11:24 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: IIED and vagueness


Isn't a restriction on speech that is outrageous, and inflicts
severe emotional distress, where the speaker knows there's a high
probability that severe emotional distress will be inflicted
unconstitutionally vague, suffering from all three of the Grayned
problems (risk of viewpoint discrimination in enforcement, difficulty of
telling when one is complying with the law, and resulting deterrent
effect)?  'Outrageousness' in the area of political and social
discourse has an inherent subjectiveness about it which would allow a
jury to impose liability on the basis of the jurors' tastes or views, or
perhaps on the basis of their dislike of a particular expression.  (I
also think it's unconstitutionally even setting aside the vagueness, but
as in many instances the vagueness is such an important problem that it
makes it hard to do the rest of the constitutional analysis, since it's
so hard to tell just what speech the law will restrict, even if limited
to cases where plaintiffs are private figures.)

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Thursday, November 01, 2007 5:13 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Anti-gay church verdict
 
 And, of course, unlike in Hustler, the persons at whom the 
 speech was directed here were not public figures.
 
 On this point, I highly recommend Robert Post's article on 
 Hustler, The Constitutional Concept of Public Discourse: 
 Outrageous Opinion, Democratic Deliberation,  Hustler 
 Magazine v. Falwell, 103 Harvard Law Review 603 (1990).
 
  -- Original message --
 From: Douglas Laycock [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  
  
Tough call.  Hustler v. Falwell says that intentional 
 infliction of 
  emotional distress, when based on political speech, requires actual 
  malice.  But there the IIED claim was based on the content of the 
  speech.  Here, assuming the plaintiff's lawyer made a sensible jury 
  argument, the IIED claim is based on time, place, and manner.  They 
  could have said these things, but they could not disrupt a funeral 
  while they said them.  A court could plausibly distinguish 
 those cases 
  if it chose.
  
Quoting Joel [EMAIL PROTECTED]:
  
   From:Father wins millions from war funeral pickets
   http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/21566280/[1]
  
  
  
   The church members testified they are following their religious
  beliefs by
   spreading the message that soldiers are dying because America is
  too
   tolerant of homosexuality.
  
  
  
   Attorneys for the church maintained in closing arguments Tuesday
  that the
   burial was a public event and that even 

RE: Michigan RFRA?

2007-10-04 Thread Newsom Michael
Thanks for the scorecard.  It is helpful!

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, October 04, 2007 2:33 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Michigan RFRA?


Reid v. Kenowa Hills Public Schools, 261 Mich.App. 17, 680
N.W.2d 62 (2004), seems to adopt the Sherbert/Yoder strict scrutiny
model as a matter of Michigan constitutional law.  On the other hand, it
relies on an earlier state supreme court decision that rested on a
hybrid rights Free Exercise Clause theory, and doesn't expressly discuss
the Sherbert vs. Smith issue, so perhaps it might not be the strongest
precedent on this score.

Here's the scorecard, as I see it:

RFRA statutes (12):  AZ, CT, FL, ID, IL, MO, NM, OK, PA, RI, SC,
TX.
RFRA constitutional amendment (1):  AL.
Sherbert/Yoder under state constitution (12):  AK, IN, ME, MA,
MI, MN, MT, NC, OH, VT, WA, WI.
Smith under state constitution (4):  MD, NJ, OR, TN.
Ambiguous, leaning in favor of Smith (1):  KS.
Uncertainty expressly noted (4):  CA, HI, NY, UT.
Nothing said (16):  AR, CO, DE, GA, IA, KY, LA, MS, NE, NV, NH,
ND, SD, VA, WV, WY.

Eugene





From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Thursday, October 04, 2007 7:17 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Michigan RFRA?


There are 13 state rfras; Michigan is not one of them.  


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Visiting Professor of Public Affairs
Kathleen and Martin Crane Senior Research Fellow
Program in Law and Public Affairs
Woodrow Wilson School
Princeton University


-Original Message-
From: Ed Brayton [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Religionlaw Listserv religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Thu, 4 Oct 2007 1:38 am
Subject: Michigan RFRA?


Does anyone on the list know if Michigan has passed their own
version of RFRA? If so, can you tell me where to find it in the Michigan
code? Thanks.
 
Ed Brayton
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be
viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly)
forward the 
messages to others.



Email and AIM finally together. You've gotta check out free AOL
Mail
http://o.aolcdn.com/cdn.webmail.aol.com/mailtour/aol/en-us/index.htm?nc
id=AOLAOF0002000970 !


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Suing God (honest, it's a lawsuit that has really been filed)

2007-09-18 Thread Newsom Michael
You remember correctly.  He has been in office, I believe, for a very
long time.  His constituents keep sending him back.  Maybe we ought to
worry a bit more about what THEY think.

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Tuesday, September 18, 2007 11:14 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Suing God (honest, it's a lawsuit that has really been
filed)

 

  I don't know Chambers reasons for the lawsuit. But just to temper
the reaction that he must be mad, Chambers, if I remember correctly, is
a wily politician with a good reputation for fighting for his community.

Bobby


-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Tue, 18 Sep 2007 10:55 am
Subject: RE: Suing God (honest, it's a lawsuit that has really been
filed)

Chambers obviously doesn't expect to win this lawsuit.  And I assume he
is not one of those borderline mentally ill chronic litigants.  So what
can he hope to accomplish?  Is he just making a theological/political
point?  That if God gets credit for good things that happen, He is also
responsible for bad things that happen?  

Not exactly a new argument, and likely overwhelmed by reaction to the
absurdity of the lawsuit.

Quoting Ed Brayton [EMAIL PROTECTED]:

 Yep, one and the same.

 Ed Brayton

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] ] On Behalf Of Volokh,
Eugene
 Sent: Monday, September 17, 2007 10:35 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Suing God (honest, it's a lawsuit that has really been
 filed)


 Isn't Sen. Ernie Chambers the Chambers from Marsh v. Chambers?
 First he tries to get prayers out of the state legislature, then he up
 and sues God.  Well then.

 Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] ] On Behalf Of Will Linden
 Sent: Monday, September 17, 2007 7:24 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Suing God (honest, it's a lawsuit that has
 really been filed)


   I assume this would be thrown out for the same reasons as
 the suit filed against Satan and his staff (CORPUS JURIS
 HUMOROUS). There is no clear ground of jurisdiction, since no
 allegation of residence in Douglas Country has been made, and
 there are no directions for service of notice of proceedings.
 In addition, should this give rise to a class action, there
 is no assurance that the petitioner would fairly represent
 the interests of the class.



 At 09:02 PM 9/17/07 -0500, you wrote:

 I'm embarrassed to admit that this guy is a long-term state senator
 here in Nebraska.  This does, however, seem to be the
 biggest possible
 interaction between religion and law.
 
  From
 
 http://news.yahoo.com/s/ap/20070917/ap_on_fe_st/odd_suing_god_2http
http://webmail.aol.com/horde/services/go.php?url=http%3A%2F%2Fnews.yaho
o.com%2Fs%2Fap%2F20070917%2Fap_on_fe_st%2Fodd_suing_god_2%3Ehttp :
  //news.yahoo.com/s/ap/20070917/ap_on_fe_st/odd_suing_god_2
 
 LINCOLN, Neb. - Fed up with the threats, tired of natural disasters,
 the state's longest-serving state senator is using his legal muscle
 against who he says is the culprit - God. State Sen. Ernie
 Chambers of
 Omaha sued the Almighty in Douglas County District Court last week.
 
 
 
 Chambers says in his lawsuit that God has made terroristic threats
 against the senator and his constituents, inspired fear and caused
 widespread death, destruction and terrorization of millions upon
 millions of the Earth's inhabitants.
 
 Chambers also says God has caused fearsome floods ... horrendous
 hurricanes, terrifying tornadoes.
 
 He's seeking a permanent injunction against God.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,
 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
http://webmail.aol.com/horde/services/go.php?url=http%3A%2F%2Flists.ucl
a.edu%2Fcgi-bin%2Fmailman%2Flistinfo%2Freligionlaw 
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be
 viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages
 that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members
 can (rightly
 or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To
 subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
http://webmail.aol.com/horde/services/go.php?url=http%3A%2F%2Flists.ucl
a.edu%2Fcgi-bin%2Fmailman%2Flistinfo%2Freligionlaw 

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives;
 and list members 

RE: Recent Threads

2007-09-10 Thread Newsom Michael
I think that the Baylor Study rests on a different set of survey
questions.  My sense, although it is only intuitive, is that the Baylor
Study methodology is entirely sound, and probably better than the
methodology of most of the other surveys of the religious views of the
American people.   

 

More to the point, I had forgotten to mention the fuller discussion of
what it means to be unaffiliated in the context of the study, a
discussion that supports my interpretation of the 10.8% figure.  Of the
10.8%, 37.1% don't believe in God or some higher power but 62.9% believe
in God or some higher power.  Furthermore, given the careful treatment
of the theology of God, the Baylor Study would lead one to conclude that
some higher power might resemble strongly one of the four conceptions
of God that the Study analyzed.

 

Another way to look at this is to consider the possibility that
rationalistic or liberal religion can take on a secular focus in which
there is little to no room for God.  Remember that the Deists taught
that God was essentially a beneficent watchmaker who, after creating the
universe, removed Himself to the far side of the clouds to tend to his
knitting, leaving the world to run in accordance with the laws that He
had instituted and put in place.  It does not take much to move from
this view of God to a view of God as merely a higher power.  If that
is the case, and I believe that it is, then only 4% of Americans could
be said not to believe in God/higher power-perhaps-of the-Deist-sort.

 

Again, given the sound methodology of the Study, I just don't see a
surge.  Doug, take a look at the Study.  You can find it on-line, I
think, I just don't happen to have the web address.  But go to the
Baylor Institute for Studies of Religion website.



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Sunday, September 09, 2007 6:58 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Recent Threads

 

Michael Hout and Claude Fischer at Berkely report a number of studies
with similar results, showing that people reporting no religious
preference doubled from 7% to 14% in the 90s.  Why More Americans Have
No Religious Preference: Politics and Generations, 67 Am. Soc. Rev. 165
(2002).  Tweaking the data, they find that some of the difference is a
difference between the young adult generation and the recently deceased
generation, and that part of the difference is people with weak
religious affiliations now reporting none. This second group is entirely
confined to political liberals and moderates; these appear to be people
who do not want to report themselves as religious because to them,
conservative Christians have given all religion a bad name.

The Baylor study may have picked up a small reversal of trend, or it may
have asked a slightly different question.  

Quoting Newsom Michael [EMAIL PROTECTED]:

 I wonder if there is a surge of people reporting no religion.  The
 Baylor study -- an extraordinary piece of social science work -- that
 came out a year ago shows that 89.2% of Americans have a religious
 affiliation, and of the remaining 10.8%, the study characterizes them
as
 persons without a religious preference, denomination, or place of
 worship.  One cannot fairly say that the unaffiliated necessarily
have
 no religion, for it is possible to be an unaffiliated Christian, and
 even if one could say that the unaffiliated have no religion, how is
 10.8% a surge?  It would seem to me that to be a surge one would
 have to have good data that showed, for example, that 25 years ago,
the
 unaffiliated constituted something under 5 or 6% of the American
 people.

 I don't know for sure, but I suspect that the unaffiliated have been
 around for a long time in the United States, and in numbers not that
far
 removed from 10.8%.

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas
Laycock
 Sent: Thursday, September 06, 2007 11:05 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Recent Threads

 Some Christians proselytize; some don't.  Same with atheists.

 There is clearly a hostile secular reaction to evangelical activism
and
 political influence; it is visible in our politics and in some of the
 resistance to free exercise claims, and it shows up statistically in a
 surge of people reporting no religion in surveys about religious
 belief.  It's not a reaction to the Christian Reconstructionists, who
 are numerically trivial.  But many of the folks having the reaction
 can't tell the difference between the conservative values voters and
 the Christian Reconstructionists.

 The mission is a central religious experience in Mormonism. What Fred
 Gedicks described is the social understanding of the faith.  The
 reality of any religion lies not in formal doctrine but in the social
 understanding, practices, and lived experience of its faithful.  That
 smart people on this list can doubt whether

RE: But that's what it MEANS

2007-09-10 Thread Newsom Michael
I note with some interest that in a recent piece on the visit of Pope
Benedict XVI to Mariazell in Austria, includes a statement to the effect
that progressive Catholics might not like the Holy Father's
proselytizing for the traditions of the faith. I seriously doubt that
the word as used can be fairly said to be pejorative. 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Monday, September 10, 2007 5:13 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: But that's what it MEANS

I agree with Mr. Linden to a certain extent -- that if an identifiable
group considers a term offensive, others should in general respect
their desire that it not be used.

But the word proselityzation does not identify a group in the same
way that Chrisitan, or Muslim, or Jew, or Hindu, or Black does.

To say someone shared the spirit with me is cryptic jargon known
only to those ina particular community that talks that way.

Steve


On 9/8/07, Will Linden [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
Mr. Jamar claims the position that if a description conforms to
what he
 considers the accurate denotational meaning of words, we should
ignore
 connotations.

  I can not buy this. Some people respond to complaints about
labelling
 cults by proclaiming what they say is an accurate and objective
 meaning of the word, and refuse to acknowledge the complete disconnect
 between their accurate scientific usage and the real world's use
of the
 word as a bogeyman label.

   I doubt that Jamar would accept the accuracy criterion in
regard to
 the fat Jewess reference I cited.

As for something being an accurate description of their
 behavior. precisely what I have been saying is that it is NOT
applied
 to people who engage in identical BEHAVIOR for causes which do not
fall in
 the religion box. From recent posts, I am sure that I would be
 indignantly corrected if I said that Hitchens, Dawkins and Sam
Harris are
 proselytizing for atheism; and similarly if I applied to people who
 engage in face to face confrontations, even abuse ones, to demand
that I
 change my political and social views, my taste in music, or my choice
of
 leisure activities.

  What about people who insist that Jew is ipso facto
offensive,
 and insist on Jewish person instead? Perhaps Mr. Levinson would
enlighten
 us on this, and how it seems to have contributed to the brouhouha over
 Google search rankings and jewwatch.com


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.



-- 
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: But that's what it MEANS

2007-09-10 Thread Newsom Michael
The point is that the article was referring to a dispute, if that be the
word, between Catholics.  That is rather different than a dispute
between Catholics and non-Catholics, for example.  (I do not buy into
the notion that the Culture Wars are quite what Hunter and others claim
that they are, but that is another discussion, one which I take up in an
article that will be out in a few months.)

 

I am a liberal, with only a few reservations, in politics, that is.  I
enjoy and feel a close bond with several of my fellow Catholics who may
fairly be described as deeply conservative in their political views.  We
recognize the powerful common bond that is our Catholic faith, and we
act upon it.  (It turns out that in theological terms I am really an
orthodox, if not conservative, Catholic.

 

So, with all due respect, I think that your suggestion overlooks the
nature of the dynamic that holds Catholics of different persuasions
together as Catholics. 

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Richard
Dougherty
Sent: Monday, September 10, 2007 6:24 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: But that's what it MEANS

 

Really?  I thought that was exactly how it was meant.  As Will suggests,
if he were a progressive (not stipulating now what that means) he would
probably be described as sharing the good news.

Richard J. Dougherty

-Original Message-
From: Newsom Michael [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent 9/10/2007 4:50:42 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: But that's what it MEANS

I note with some interest that in a recent piece on the visit of Pope
Benedict XVI to Mariazell in Austria, includes a statement to the effect
that progressive Catholics might not like the Holy Father's
proselytizing for the traditions of the faith. I seriously doubt that
the word as used can be fairly said to be pejorative.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Recent Threads

2007-09-07 Thread Newsom Michael
I wonder if there is a surge of people reporting no religion.  The
Baylor study -- an extraordinary piece of social science work -- that
came out a year ago shows that 89.2% of Americans have a religious
affiliation, and of the remaining 10.8%, the study characterizes them as
persons without a religious preference, denomination, or place of
worship.  One cannot fairly say that the unaffiliated necessarily have
no religion, for it is possible to be an unaffiliated Christian, and
even if one could say that the unaffiliated have no religion, how is
10.8% a surge?  It would seem to me that to be a surge one would
have to have good data that showed, for example, that 25 years ago, the
unaffiliated constituted something under 5 or 6% of the American
people.

I don't know for sure, but I suspect that the unaffiliated have been
around for a long time in the United States, and in numbers not that far
removed from 10.8%.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Thursday, September 06, 2007 11:05 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Recent Threads

Some Christians proselytize; some don't.  Same with atheists.

There is clearly a hostile secular reaction to evangelical activism and 
political influence; it is visible in our politics and in some of the 
resistance to free exercise claims, and it shows up statistically in a 
surge of people reporting no religion in surveys about religious 
belief.  It's not a reaction to the Christian Reconstructionists, who 
are numerically trivial.  But many of the folks having the reaction 
can't tell the difference between the conservative values voters and 
the Christian Reconstructionists.

The mission is a central religious experience in Mormonism. What Fred 
Gedicks described is the social understanding of the faith.  The 
reality of any religion lies not in formal doctrine but in the social 
understanding, practices, and lived experience of its faithful.  That 
smart people on this list can doubt whether the Mormon mission is 
religious dramatically illustrates what is wrong with the 
compelled/motivated distinction.

I agree -- and have testified -- that the religious motivation must be 
substantial or primary and not just lurking in the background 
somewhere.  That means the resulting line is one of degree and not a 
bright line.  But to say the Mormon mission is not distinguishable from 
any other reason for taking a year off is like saying that because 1 
isn't much different from 2, and 2 isn't much different from 3, and so 
on -- that 1 is indistinguishable from 100 or a hundred trillion or any 
other number.

Douglas Laycock
Yale Kamisar Collegiate Professor of Law
University of Michigan Law School
625 S. State St.
Ann Arbor, MI  48109-1215
  734-647-9713

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Recent Threads

2007-09-07 Thread Newsom Michael
I have an article coming out soon that has the word proselytizing in
its title.  Like Steve, I thought that I was being accurate.

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Thursday, September 06, 2007 12:16 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Recent Threads

 

Curious.  I've had many a christian tell me it is their obligation to
proselytize -- using that very word.

I don't see anything pejorative in it at all.  It is quite accurate.  

On 9/6/07, Will Linden [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

On Thu, 6 Sep 2007, Douglas Laycock wrote:

 Some Christians proselytize; some don't.  Same with atheists.

Proseleytize is one of those funny words, like cult and
superstition, which can only be applied to Somebody Else BY
DEFINITION. 
We share, you preach, They proseleytize.  Consequently, I have dropped
it
from my vocabulary.



Will Linden  [EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://www.ecben.net/
Magic Code: MAS/GD S++ W++ N+ PWM++ Ds/r+ A- a++ C+ G- QO++ 666 Y
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw 

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others. 




-- 
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: EC Compelling Interest

2007-07-23 Thread Newsom Michael
Isn't the whole point of the EC that the government cannot be permitted
to be a willing speaker when it comes to God-talk?  And isn't this the
reason why a per se analysis is more consistent with that purpose than
any compelling interest test might be?  The EC contains its own
compelling interest, doesn't it?  And isn't that compelling interest
essentially freedom FROM religion?  (Why, for the sake of discussion,
should X's freedom OF religion trump Y's freedom FROM religion?  And
isn't it true, therefore, that large claims of freedom OF religion, of
Free Exercise, should be viewed with a great deal of suspicion
especially given the categorical nature of the EC, of freedom FROM
religion, whereas there is no comparable categorical freedom OF
religion?  Of course my Protestant Empire thesis provides a useful way
of assessing both freedom FROM and freedom OF religion claims.  I have
another Protestant Empire piece coming out shortly which looks at this
problem in part through the lens or prism of proselytizing in the public
schools and elsewhere.) 

 

Isn't it also true, therefore, that to characterize the objection to the
display as a heckler's veto begs the question to be decided?  If the
government cannot be a willing speaker then the censor is not the
heckler but is the EC itself.  It is interesting to recall that the
pre-Incorporation common school religion cases divided on this point.
The state courts that upheld prayer and Bible reading in public schools
almost always characterized the objectors as hecklers.  The minority
of state courts that struck down or limited these practices never used
such terminology in describing those who objected to these religious
exercises.

 

Was the pre-Incorporation state court minority right when it struck down
or limited Bible reading and prayer in the public schools? Were Engel
and Schempp correctly decided?

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Rick Duncan
Sent: Monday, July 23, 2007 5:14 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: EC  Compelling Interest

 

Of course, one of the problems with a compelling interest test is no one
really knows what interests are extraordinarily important and which are
less so. And different folks may have different scales of importance.

 

In the case of a holiday display, one could view this as a case
involving a willing speaker (the county govt) and a willing audience
(those who wish to enjoy the holiday expression) who are being censored
by a heckler's veto under the EC. I think it is important that govt
speech be available to those who wish to receive it. Is it
extraordinarily important? I don't know. I would at least like to see
the Ct apply the compelling interest test and explain why this
speech/non-censorship interest is not important.

 

Alternatively, the compelling interest in such cases might be the govt's
strong interest in diversity and equal regard for religious citizens in
a pluralistic public square. If all sorts of secular holidays are
celebrated in the public square (gay pride, cinco de mayo, Columbus Day,
pork producers day, etc), many people of faith might well feel
disrespected and deeply injured by being the only subgroups in the
community whose holidays are not celebrated.

 

And what about the compelling interest of school officials to decide
which curriculum best meets the needs of students in the public schools
trumping EC attacks on ID, music curriculum, and the Pledge of
Allegiance? 

 

Just some thoughts. I don't think these cases are as easy as Eugene
seems to think they are, because what may not seem important to some may
seem very important to others. And the fact that the Ct doesn't even
play the game suggests that maybe the reason is that there is no game to
be played because the EC applies as a categorical rule without a
balancing test.

 

Rick Duncan

Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

Rick: You might well be right, but it's hard to tell without
some cases that test our sense of this, by coming out
differently under
strict scrutiny than under per se invalidation. It's hard to see
a
compelling interest behind government holiday displays -- one
can surely
argue that endorsement shouldn't be seen as implicating the
Establishment Clause, but it's harder to say that it does
implicate it
but that it's just extraordinarily important to allow it.

Eugene




From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Rick
Duncan
Sent: Sunday, July 22, 2007 4:45 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: EC  Compelling Interest


When the Ct strikes down a law under the EC, it usually declares
the law unconstitutional w/out any type of scrutiny. Why
doesn't the
Ct at least go through 

RE: Lofton / Falwell Not Preacher He SHOULD Have Been

2007-05-17 Thread Newsom Michael
I wish that it were clear that there is a sharp line dividing the two.
There is, after all, a powerful dynamic relation between law and
morality, as there is between law and psychology, law and theology, and
any number of other relevant and germane factors and considerations.

Falwell obviously sought to link law and morality.  

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, May 17, 2007 1:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Lofton / Falwell Not Preacher He SHOULD Have Been


A discussion of Falwell's role in the development of Religion
Clauses law is surely entirely on-topic.  A discussion of whether
Falwell acted in sad or sinful ways under one's own theological view
(however sincere or well-reasoned) of what behavior is sad or sinful
strikes me as no more on-topic than a discussion of whether, say,
Justices Brennan or Blackmun acted in sad or sinful ways.

Eugene

  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 05/17/07 9:01 AM 
  
  
 In a message dated 5/16/2007 9:59:21 P.M. Eastern Daylight 
 Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
 
 Please remember that this is a list devoted to the law of 
 government and religion -- not on whether some people 
 (recently dead or  otherwise) acted in sad or sinful ways, 
 except insofar as that pretty  closely connects to the law of 
 government and religion.
  
 
 
 
 
 I am incredulous  that an open  discussion of one of 
 the most important operatives in  religion and 
 constitutionalism in the last three decades should be 
 inappropriate  on this List. Of course, this is Eugene's List 
 and therefore I will respect his  wishes. But I could not 
 disagree more with his sense of relevance or  appropriateness 
 in this matter.
  
 Bobby
 
 Robert Justin Lipkin
 Professor of Law
 Widener  University School of Law
 Delaware
 
 Ratio  Juris
 , Contributor: _  http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/_
 (http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/)
 Essentially Contested  America, Editor: 
 _http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/_
 (http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/) 
 
 
 
 ** See what's free at 
 http://www.aol.com.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To 
 subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

2007-01-29 Thread Newsom Michael
The question is whether there is some sort of firewall around the
deed/contract cases.  I am just not sure that there is, thus giving
the courts some room to impose secular norms in other situations, should
they choose to do so.  That's all that I mean to say.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 5:56 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

Hmm -- interesting, but any chance you could point to some
specific cases that impose not secular norms related to contract and
deed interpretation, but also secular norms that would justify courts
deciding whether a church decision was the product of fraud or
collusion?

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 2:54 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
 
 You may be right on the point.  I may be confusing the 
 anti-communism of lower courts that got reversed on appeal.  
 But, that said, the post-Wolf era can only be reasonably 
 explained in terms of the imposition of secular norms -- at 
 least some of the time.  And it follows, I think, that it is 
 altogether possible that secular norms might be imposed in 
 the Virginia case.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
 Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 5:45 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
 
 Kedroff and Kreshik were also decided in favor of the 
 Soviet-controlled Russian Orthodox Church, despite the NY 
 legislature's efforts to the contrary.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 5:32 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
 
   Well, I firmly endorse a secular norm of disliking Communism.
 Nonetheless, unless I'm mistaken the Milivojevich Court held 
 *in favor* of the Yugoslav (and I take it 
 Communist-influenced) hierarchy.  The hierarchy tried to 
 remove the American bishop; the Illinois Supreme Court 
 invalidated the removal as 'arbitrary' because the 
 proceedings resulting in those actions were not conducted 
 according to the Illinois Supreme Court's interpretation of 
 the Church's constitution and penal code, and that the 
 Diocesan reorganization was invalid because it was beyond the 
 scope of the Mother Church's authority to effectuate such 
 changes without Diocesan approval.  The Supreme Court 
 reversed the Illinois decision, and the Communist-influenced 
 hierarchy won.  That seems to suggest that the Court was 
 following a norm of deference to the hierarchical 
 authorities, whether the heads were under the influence of 
 Communists or not.  Am I missing something here?
 
   Eugene
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom 
  Michael
  Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 2:25 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
  
  That is all well and good, but I have the sense that the Court 
  nonetheless applied secular norms in some post-Wolf cases, indeed 
  perhaps going so far as to constitutionalize a Congregationalist 
  polity even in hierarchical churches (be they Episcopalian or 
  Presbyterian in their polity).  If this isn't the application of 
  secular norms, then what is it?
  
  As to the post-Wolf cases, it is difficult to argue that 
 they can be 
  easily reconciled, there being a real difference on the precise 
  question of secular norms.  I think that the law is anything but 
  clear, post-Wolf.
  
  One more point, the property dispute cases involving 
 Eastern Orthodox 
  Churches certainly reflect secular norms -- a dislike of communism, 
  for openers.
  
   
  
  
  Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, 
  Eugene
  Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 4:40 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
  
  [W]hether or not there is room for marginal civil court review  
  under the narrow rubrics of fraud or collusion
  when church tribunals act in bad faith for secular purposes, no 
  arbitrariness exception in the sense of an inquiry whether the 
  decisions of the highest ecclesiastical tribunal of a hierarchical 
  church complied with church laws and regulations is consistent with 
  the constitutional mandate that civil courts are bound to 
 accept the 
  decisions of the highest judicatories of a religious 
 organization of 
  hierarchical polity on matters of discipline

RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

2007-01-29 Thread Newsom Michael
I don't disagree with the major thrust of what you say, except that I
wonder whether judges will avoid intruding in other categories of
cases.

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 6:50 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

 

There are no post-Wolf cases in the Supreme Court.  They have repeatedly
denied cert, letting lower courts apply and abuse Wolf however they
want.  Some state courts have indeed imposed congregational polities on
hierarchical churches, at least with respect to property ownership.  The
Russian Orthodox case in Massachusetts may be the most absurd of these.
But there is very little of this judicial intrusion, even in the lower
courts, in minister cases, and virtually none outside the context of
sexual harassment.

Quoting [EMAIL PROTECTED]:

 In a message dated 1/26/2007 5:26:13 PM Eastern Standard Time,
 [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
 That is all well and good, but I have the sense that the Court
 nonetheless applied secular norms in some post-Wolf cases, indeed
 perhaps going so far as to constitutionalize a Congregationalist
polity
 even in hierarchical churches (be they Episcopalian or Presbyterian in
 their polity).  If this isn't the application of secular norms, then
 what is it?

 As to the post-Wolf cases, it is difficult to argue that they can be
 easily reconciled, there being a real difference on the precise
question
 of secular norms.  I think that the law is anything but clear,
 post-Wolf.

 One more point, the property dispute cases involving Eastern Orthodox
 Churches certainly reflect secular norms -- a dislike of communism,
for
 openers.
 Even Justice Scalia expressly carved out the Ministerial Exception in
 Employment Div. v. Smith (neutral laws of general applicability 
 analysis)...it is a
 little dfifficult to respond to your sense that the Court applied
secular
 norms without you referring to specific cases from which you derive 
 that sense

 Donald C. Clark, Jr.
 2333 Waukegan Road
 Suite 160
 Bannockburn, Illinois 60015
 847-236-0900
 847-236-0909 (fax)


 This message is a PRIVATE communication. This message and all
attachments
 are a private communication sent by a law firm and may be confidential
or
 protected by privilege. If you are not the intended recipient, you are
 hereby notified that any disclosure, copying, distribution or use of
the
 information contained in or attached to this message is strictly
 prohibited.  Please notify the sender of the delivery error by
replying to
 this message, and then delete it from your system.  Thank you.




**
 **

 IRS Circular 230 Disclosure:  To comply with requirements imposed by
the
 IRS, we inform you that any U.S. federal tax advice contained herein
 (including any attachments), unless specifically stated otherwise, is
not
 intended or written to be used, and cannot be used, for the purposes
of (i)
 avoiding penalties under the Internal Revenue Code or (ii) promoting,
 marketing or recommending to another party any transaction or matter
 herein.



Douglas Laycock
Yale Kamisar Collegiate Professor of Law
University of Michigan Law School
625 S. State St.
Ann Arbor, MI  48109-1215
  734-647-9713

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

2007-01-26 Thread Newsom Michael
I will defer to those who know this area of the law better than I do,
but, isn't it the case that secular courts will impose secular notions
of procedural due process on adjudications by religious bodies?  If that
is so, then this case may be but so important, if it turns out that the
Episcopal Bishop transgressed those secular due process norms.  And if
that be the case, then isn't the appropriate judicial remedy a judgment
directing the Episcopal Bishop to give Moyer a fair trial?

One more thought that may be even more important:  if the Episcopal
Church's own rules contain due process protections and the Episcopal
Bishop has failed to follow them, then isn't it appropriate for a
secular court at least to order the religious organization to follow its
own rules, quite apart from any notions of constitutional (i.e. secular)
due process?

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 8:52 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

This may be of interest to some list members who are researching,
writing or teaching in this area:

From this morning's Philadelphia Inquirer, at 
http://www.philly.com/mld/philly/news/16548224.htm 

Judge lets ousted priest sue in test of First Amendment
The Episcopal bishop had denied the Montco cleric a church trial.

Clearing the way for a landmark test of the First Amendment, a
Montgomery County Court judge has allowed an Episcopal priest to sue his
bishop for removing him from priesthood.

In a decision released yesterday, Judge Thomas Branca rejected Bishop
Charles E. Bennison Jr.'s argument that the Rev. David Moyer had no
right to settle their differences with a civil trial.

Bennison's lawyers had argued in four appearances before Branca that
the First Amendment barred civil courts from deciding cases involving
religious personnel disputes.

But Moyer's lawyers replied that the priest had no other remedy because
Bennison denied him due process by removing him without a church trial,
as church law requires.

They also say Bennison fraudulently concealed relevant documents from
the diocesan standing committee, the diocese's administrative body,
which endorsed Moyer's removal.

John Lewis, Moyer's lawyer, said yesterday that he believed Moyer v.
Bennison would be the first time that a case will go to trial which
involves ecclesiastical discipline of a priest in a hierarchical
church.

[remainder of article at cited URL]

For those not following the story, this most recent news is the latest
in a long line of posturing, maneuvering, voting, disputes, etc.,
between two groups in the church who take diametrically opposed views on
at least several hot-button issues.

I post this with a question mark in the topic because I'll let others
confirm or reject the proposition that this is  the first time that a
case will go to trial which involves ecclesiastical discipline of a
priest in a hierarchical church.


Jim Maule
Professor of Law, Villanova University School of Law
Villanova PA 19085
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://vls.law.vill.edu/prof/maule
mauledagain.blogspot.com 
President, TaxJEM Inc (computer assisted tax law instruction)
(www2.taxjem.com)
Publisher, JEMBook Publishing Co. (www.jembook.com)
Maule Family Archivist  Genealogist (www.maulefamily.com)



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

2007-01-26 Thread Newsom Michael
I will be the first to admit that I may have misread Jones v. Wolf, but
neutral principles of law is a rather capacious concept, and don't
forget Gonzalez v. Roman Catholic Archbishop of Manila and the
insistence there of the right of the Court to provide a remedy where
there was fraud, collusion, or arbitrariness in the proceedings before
the religious tribunal.

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 2:31 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

 

In a message dated 1/26/2007 1:11:21 PM Eastern Standard Time,
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

I will defer to those who know this area of the law better than
I do,
but, isn't it the case that secular courts will impose secular
notions
of procedural due process on adjudications by religious bodies?
No, indeed quite to the contrary and appropriately so

 

If that
is so, then this case may be but so important, if it turns out
that the
Episcopal Bishop transgressed those secular due process norms.
And if
that be the case, then isn't the appropriate judicial remedy a
judgment
directing the Episcopal Bishop to give Moyer a fair trial?
One more thought that may be even more important:  if the
Episcopal
Church's own rules contain due process protections and the
Episcopal
Bishop has failed to follow them, then isn't it appropriate for
a
secular court at least to order the religious organization to
follow its
own rules, quite apart from any notions of constitutional (i.e.
secular)
due process?  No, the state has no constitutionally permissible
role in ensuring that ecclesiastical process either meets secular
notions of due process or in enforcing what it interprets to be the
process selected at any given point in time by an ecclesiastical body

 

While I have not read any opinion that may have accompanied this judge's
order, the press report, if accurate, suggests that this judge has
strayed beyond both federal and state constitutional boundaries...I have
obtained the exact opposite outcome in a case raising similar issues
from another judge in Montgomery County

 

Donald C. Clark, Jr.
2333 Waukegan Road
Suite 160
Bannockburn, Illinois 60015
847-236-0900
847-236-0909 (fax)

This message is a PRIVATE communication. This message and all
attachments
are a private communication sent by a law firm and may be confidential
or
protected by privilege. If you are not the intended recipient, you are
hereby notified that any disclosure, copying, distribution or use of the
information contained in or attached to this message is strictly
prohibited.  Please notify the sender of the delivery error by replying
to
this message, and then delete it from your system.  Thank you.





IRS Circular 230 Disclosure:  To comply with requirements imposed by the
IRS, we inform you that any U.S. federal tax advice contained herein
(including any attachments), unless specifically stated otherwise, is
not
intended or written to be used, and cannot be used, for the purposes of
(i)
avoiding penalties under the Internal Revenue Code or (ii) promoting,
marketing or recommending to another party any transaction or matter
herein.

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

2007-01-26 Thread Newsom Michael
Some of the other cases come out the other way, if I remember them
correctly. 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 5:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

Well, I firmly endorse a secular norm of disliking Communism.
Nonetheless, unless I'm mistaken the Milivojevich Court held *in favor*
of the Yugoslav (and I take it Communist-influenced) hierarchy.  The
hierarchy tried to remove the American bishop; the Illinois Supreme
Court invalidated the removal as 'arbitrary' because the proceedings
resulting in those actions were not conducted according to the Illinois
Supreme Court's interpretation of the Church's constitution and penal
code, and that the Diocesan reorganization was invalid because it was
beyond the scope of the Mother Church's authority to effectuate such
changes without Diocesan approval.  The Supreme Court reversed the
Illinois decision, and the Communist-influenced hierarchy won.  That
seems to suggest that the Court was following a norm of deference to the
hierarchical authorities, whether the heads were under the influence of
Communists or not.  Am I missing something here?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 2:25 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
 
 That is all well and good, but I have the sense that the 
 Court nonetheless applied secular norms in some post-Wolf 
 cases, indeed perhaps going so far as to constitutionalize a 
 Congregationalist polity even in hierarchical churches (be 
 they Episcopalian or Presbyterian in their polity).  If this 
 isn't the application of secular norms, then what is it?
 
 As to the post-Wolf cases, it is difficult to argue that they 
 can be easily reconciled, there being a real difference on 
 the precise question of secular norms.  I think that the law 
 is anything but clear, post-Wolf.
 
 One more point, the property dispute cases involving Eastern 
 Orthodox Churches certainly reflect secular norms -- a 
 dislike of communism, for openers.
 
  
 
 
 Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 4:40 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
 
 [W]hether or not there is room for marginal civil court 
 review  under the narrow rubrics of fraud or collusion 
 when church tribunals act in bad faith for secular purposes, 
 no arbitrariness exception in the sense of an inquiry 
 whether the decisions of the highest ecclesiastical tribunal 
 of a hierarchical church complied with church laws and 
 regulations is consistent with the constitutional mandate 
 that civil courts are bound to accept the decisions of the 
 highest judicatories of a religious organization of 
 hierarchical polity on matters of discipline, faith, internal 
 organization, or ecclesiastical rule, custom, or law. For 
 civil courts to analyze whether the ecclesiastical actions of 
 a church judicatory are in that sense arbitrary  must 
 inherently entail inquiry into the procedures that canon or 
 ecclesiastical law supposedly requires the church judicatory 
 to follow, or else in to the substantive criteria by which 
 they are supposedly to decide the ecclesiastical question. 
 But this is exactly the inquiry that the First Amendment 
 prohibits; recognition of such an exception would undermine 
 the general rule that religious controversies are not the 
 proper subject of civil court inquiry, and that a civil court 
 must accept the ecclesiastical decisions of church tribunals 
 as it finds them. Watson itself requires our conclusion in 
 its rejection of the analogous argument that ecclesiastical 
 decisions of the highest church judicatories need only be 
 accepted if the subject matter of the dispute is within their 
 jurisdiction.  Serbian Eastern Orthodox Diocese v.
 Milivojevich, 426 U.S. 696, 713 (1976).
 
 
 
 
   From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
   Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 1:24 PM
   To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
   Subject: Re: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
   
   
   In a message dated 1/26/2007 4:20:12 PM Eastern 
 Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
 
   I will be the first to admit that I may have 
 misread Jones v. Wolf, but neutral principles of law is a 
 rather capacious concept, and don't forget Gonzalez v. Roman 
 Catholic Archbishop of Manila and the insistence there of the 
 right of the Court to provide a remedy where there was 
 fraud, collusion, or arbitrariness in the proceedings

RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

2007-01-26 Thread Newsom Michael
You may be right on the point.  I may be confusing the anti-communism of
lower courts that got reversed on appeal.  But, that said, the post-Wolf
era can only be reasonably explained in terms of the imposition of
secular norms -- at least some of the time.  And it follows, I think,
that it is altogether possible that secular norms might be imposed in
the Virginia case.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 5:45 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

Kedroff and Kreshik were also decided in favor of the Soviet-controlled
Russian Orthodox Church, despite the NY legislature's efforts to the
contrary.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 5:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?

Well, I firmly endorse a secular norm of disliking Communism.
Nonetheless, unless I'm mistaken the Milivojevich Court held *in favor*
of the Yugoslav (and I take it Communist-influenced) hierarchy.  The
hierarchy tried to remove the American bishop; the Illinois Supreme
Court invalidated the removal as 'arbitrary' because the proceedings
resulting in those actions were not conducted according to the Illinois
Supreme Court's interpretation of the Church's constitution and penal
code, and that the Diocesan reorganization was invalid because it was
beyond the scope of the Mother Church's authority to effectuate such
changes without Diocesan approval.  The Supreme Court reversed the
Illinois decision, and the Communist-influenced hierarchy won.  That
seems to suggest that the Court was following a norm of deference to the
hierarchical authorities, whether the heads were under the influence of
Communists or not.  Am I missing something here?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 2:25 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
 
 That is all well and good, but I have the sense that the 
 Court nonetheless applied secular norms in some post-Wolf 
 cases, indeed perhaps going so far as to constitutionalize a 
 Congregationalist polity even in hierarchical churches (be 
 they Episcopalian or Presbyterian in their polity).  If this 
 isn't the application of secular norms, then what is it?
 
 As to the post-Wolf cases, it is difficult to argue that they 
 can be easily reconciled, there being a real difference on 
 the precise question of secular norms.  I think that the law 
 is anything but clear, post-Wolf.
 
 One more point, the property dispute cases involving Eastern 
 Orthodox Churches certainly reflect secular norms -- a 
 dislike of communism, for openers.
 
  
 
 
 Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Friday, January 26, 2007 4:40 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Landmark First Amendment Religion Litigation?
 
 [W]hether or not there is room for marginal civil court 
 review  under the narrow rubrics of fraud or collusion 
 when church tribunals act in bad faith for secular purposes, 
 no arbitrariness exception in the sense of an inquiry 
 whether the decisions of the highest ecclesiastical tribunal 
 of a hierarchical church complied with church laws and 
 regulations is consistent with the constitutional mandate 
 that civil courts are bound to accept the decisions of the 
 highest judicatories of a religious organization of 
 hierarchical polity on matters of discipline, faith, internal 
 organization, or ecclesiastical rule, custom, or law. For 
 civil courts to analyze whether the ecclesiastical actions of 
 a church judicatory are in that sense arbitrary  must 
 inherently entail inquiry into the procedures that canon or 
 ecclesiastical law supposedly requires the church judicatory 
 to follow, or else in to the substantive criteria by which 
 they are supposedly to decide the ecclesiastical question. 
 But this is exactly the inquiry that the First Amendment 
 prohibits; recognition of such an exception would undermine 
 the general rule that religious controversies are not the 
 proper subject of civil court inquiry, and that a civil court 
 must accept the ecclesiastical decisions of church tribunals 
 as it finds them. Watson itself requires our conclusion in 
 its rejection of the analogous argument that ecclesiastical 
 decisions of the highest church judicatories need only be 
 accepted if the subject matter of the dispute is within their 
 jurisdiction.  Serbian Eastern Orthodox Diocese v.
 Milivojevich, 426 U.S. 696, 713 (1976).
 
 
 
 
   From: [EMAIL

RE: Frances Patterson

2006-09-27 Thread Newsom Michael








Colleagues, please excuse me, but I need
to get in touch with Frances Patterson. If she is following this list, I hope
that she will contact me ASAP. I am working on an article, and an earlier post
from her on this list raised some matters that are particularly relevant to
that enterprise. 






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: From the list custodian re: theological discussions

2006-09-02 Thread Newsom Michael
I agree. 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Brian Landsberg
Sent: Saturday, September 02, 2006 4:22 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: From the list custodian re: theological discussions

Hallelujah!

 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 9/2/2006 1:02:49 PM 
I thought I'd briefly note that as a general matter, purely
theological discussions -- such as what the Bible allows or forbids --
are not on-topic for the list; the list is about the secular law
related
to religious practice, practitioners, and institutions (what I
somewhat
clunkily call The Law of Government and Religion), and not about
religious law.  One-shot queries for help with questions of religious
law (such as the one that started the thread) are generally fine,
since
there are likely quite a few people on the list who would have answers
to such questions, and such queries are therefore an easy way of
advancing people's research.   But extended discussions about
religious
law are generally off-topic.

This having been said, I haven't spoken up about the polygamy
thread, because many list members seem to have been interested in it,
and because the list has been relatively quiet on other matters, so it
hasn't been detracting from on-topic discussions.  (I've also been
swamped with other things, so I didn't really focus on the thread
until
recently.)  I did, however, want to note that this thread shouldn't be
seen as precedent for other on-list theological discussions; and to
suggest that now that the thread has been active for some days and
several dozen posts, it might be worthwhile to wind it down.  Thanks,

The list custodian
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw 

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Rep. Harris (R-Fla.) on Church and State

2006-08-28 Thread Newsom Michael








Arent theological claims a bit
beyond the scope of the discussion on this listserv?  I have no problem with
theological claims, and would have no problem discussing this claim.  But not
here.









From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, August 28, 2006 2:12
PM
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]; Law
 Religion issues for Law Academics; UCLA Law Class
Subject: RE: Rep. Harris (R-Fla.)
on Church and State







God is absolutely in control. 











By me kings reign





and rulers decree justice





By me princes rule, and nobles





all the judges of the earth. Proverbs 8:15-16 (NKJV)











Debra Cook











-- Original message -- 
From: Gordon James Klingenschmitt [EMAIL PROTECTED] 



AlthoughI'm not a lawyer, I am working on my PhD in Theology, and
of course my Navy Chaplain issues put me attheintersection of
church and state...so perhaps I'm qualified tocomment on
Senator-candidate Katherine Harris' comments about separation and
legislating God's will. 











1) I said essentially the same thing as Ms. Harrisin my
1999interview with US News and World Report (paraphrased from my
memory): Many Americans want to electpoliticians
wholegislate tolerance of sin,just so they won't have to forsake
their favorite sins. But God will nevermake sin legal. Won't
itbe tragic one day, whenAmerican citizens standbefore God to
be judged, and say 'but I thought that was legal...' and discover (too late)
that God disagrees. Government's highest duty then, is to pass laws God
agrees with, lest itdo its citizens an eternal disservice. 











2) Many anti-Christians quote separation of church and
state as if that somehow means Christians aren't allowed to vote.
But we who shareChristian values have just as much right to vote, lobby,
advocate, publish, and legislate our values as any other
citizens.Liberals often use thephrase separation
as a means to intimidate and silence Christian voters from fully
participating. But we will not be silenced, nor shouldwe be
intimidated. 











3) The First Amendment doesn't prohibit the legislation of
Christian laws, any more than it prohibits the legislation of
Muslim values or Atheist values or Sandy
Levinson's values. Theoretically we could organize and
legislatethe Ten Commandments directly into the U.S. Constitution, if we
had 2/3rdof Senators and 3/4 of the States to vote them in.
Perhapsthat would angeranti-Christian voters, but then we're
angered by their pro-abortion/pro-homosexual laws too. 











4) PresidentBush shouldn't disown her comments, rather it's
possible heagrees with her theology. Here's a clip from 1999 interview
of Meet The Press:





MR. RUSSERT: Reverend Land, The Washington Post reported this: 'I
believe God wants me to be president,' the Rev. Richard Land, head of the
public policy arm of the Southern Baptist Convention, quoted George Bush as
saying. When did George Bush tell you that? 





DR. RICHARD LAND: Well, he told me that--he told a group of us that the
day he was inaugurated for his second term as governor of the state in 1999.











5) I disagree theologically, however,with both of them, if they
believe as Katherine Harris says,'God is the one who chooses our
rulers.' There's ample evidenceto the contrary, that the Devil
himself often chooses our rulers, and evil morals are legislated by those who
campaign (and win) on platforms announcing their intention to
legislatethe devil's will. Somewrongly assume all
American laws are the same as God's laws. But God
himselfdisagrees with many American laws on the books, for example, the
new Navy policy that prohibits chaplains from praying in Jesus nameoutside
the chapel. Our duty is always to fight the devil, and his laws. 











6) When American law conflicts with God's law, Christians have a
duty to disobey human law, and obey God's law.Our duty
towardcivil disobediencehas been recognized by great Americans
throughout history, for example Martin Luther King, Patrick Henry, the Founding
Fathers (Declaration of Independence) etc. 











7) The very notion of our 3-branch system of Government
(President, Congress, Courts) came from the Bible, and is patterned after God's
personality, from Isaiah 33:22: For the LORD is our judge,the
LORD is our lawgiver,the LORD is our king;it is he who will save
us. We must therefore votewhat God has told our conscience to
legislate,what we know is right, and we must never legislate evil.
If our government ceases to reflect God's personality, woe to us all, for the
devil's tyranny will become a heavy yoke upon our necks, and true Christian
Liberty will be lost forever.











Gordon James Klingenschmitt





www.persuade.tv 












Sanford Levinson
[EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:





Date: Sat, 26 Aug 2006
16:28:48 -0500
From: Sanford
Levinson [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: 

RE: Fox News Forgets Fact in Christian Graduation Speech Story

2006-08-15 Thread Newsom Michael








Not everybody is happy.











From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On
Behalf Of Ed Brayton
Sent: Sunday, August 06, 2006
12:47 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: Re: Fox News Forgets Fact
in Christian Graduation Speech Story





[EMAIL PROTECTED]
wrote: 





I much appreciate the kind words
(particularly coming from the author of the conlaw book I still use and have
been using since law school).











There was actually anotherinteresting fact
about the Erica Corder case in Monument, CO that wasn't in the Fox News
story.Erica Corder'sfather is on the board of directors of James
Dobson's Focus on the Family which is based near there (the father's connection
to FoFis reported in the Colorado Springs Gazette). If anyone's
interested, I took my argument to the Colorado Springs Gazette online forum in
more extended written form at: http://forums.gazette.com/gazette/viewtopic.php?t=345start=30











What I'm having difficulty figuring out, however, is
exactly where to draw the line in graduation speech preapproval cases. Does
anyone have any good citations (or opinions) on when preapproval of a message
becomes endorsement? Also, how do high schools fashion preapproval policies so
they are not arbitrary or discriminatory?





I would argue that if the graduation speaker is chosen
according to some objective criteria, as when the valedictorian automatically
is invited to speak, then the school should not exercise any control over the
content of their speech at all. Then the speech is purely their own, there is no
message of endorsement, and the student can say whatever they want. Free speech
preserved, establishment clause problem eliminated, everyone hapy.

Ed Brayton






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Teenagers The Spirit of Liberty

2006-05-24 Thread Newsom Michael
With all due respect, the prayer was hardly private.

-Original Message-
From: Kurt Lash [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, May 23, 2006 10:14 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Teenagers The Spirit of Liberty

I think that the denigration of Rick and his original post has gone a 
bit overboard.

As I understand the facts (and I could be wrong), the students voted 
on a graduation speaker and that speaker planned on including a prayer 
as part of her speech.  In an injunction based on a suit filed only 
days before, the judge prohibited the student from praying.  
Apparently prayers were a traditional part of the ceremony, but it's 
not clear how they took place.

But taking the facts as known, I am not at all convinced that the 
Court's establishment clause jurisprudence forbids all prayers by 
invited private speakers (including students) at school events.  Could 
she have been held in contempt if she declared God have mercy on the 
souls of those killed in Iraq?  It seems to me that when the 
government opens a space for private speech, forbiding private 
speakers from engaging in religion talk raises serious First 
Amendment issues.  

It begs the question to assert tyranny of the majority.  As I tell 
my students, the only thing worse than a tyranical majority is a 
tyrannical minority--or a single tyrant.  The issue is whether a 
supermajority of the people, at a moment in time, enshrined a 
principle in our constitution which justifies the injunction in this 
case.  Unless I am wrong about the facts, I am not at all convinced 
that it does.

The students' action/protest not only accepted (for the moment) the 
court's ruling (no lynch mob here), I thougt its symbolism was quite 
potent: The courts cannot silence our private religious speech.  
They may have acted from a religious/majoritarian impulse, but the 
constitutional principle involved protects both the majority and 
minority from unwarranted government censorship--whether by courts or 
by school boards, and whether the speech is secular or religious.  

Kurt Lash
Loyola Law School (L.A.)

PS: There is, of course, a serious issue regarding the degree to which 
members of an an audience may prevent a speaker from speaking, or a 
ceremony from taking place, through their disruptive protests--whether 
religious or secular based. This issue, however, has nothing to do 
with the establishment issues raised by those responding to Rick's 
post.

Content-type: multipart/alternative;
 boundary=Boundary_(ID_ZW+hF43hOXfSlPtjprWkmg)
Content-transfer-encoding: 8BIT


--Boundary_(ID_ZW+hF43hOXfSlPtjprWkmg)
Content-type: text/plain; charset=iso-8859-1
Content-transfer-encoding: 8BIT

I see from earlier news stories that the student first asked the principal to 
not schedule prayers at the graduation, and the principal refused.  The prayers 
objected to originally were clearly out of line under current case law.  School 
authorities shouldn't be in the business of telling kids when to pray -- and is 
that not exactly what scheduling prayers is?
   
  Rick, is there any reason this group shouldn't be compared to the lynch mob 
that goes after a suspected horse thief?  The fellow may be guilty, and a court 
can determine that later -- but lynching is illegal, and shouldn't we trust to 
the courts to arrive at a near-just conclusion?
   
  I graduated from a high school where I was one of 2 students -- about 1% of 
the graduating class -- not of the predominant religion.  I understand exactly 
what the plaintiff in the case complained about.  It's scary that a ruling from 
a federal court is not enough to preserve religious rights against a mob.  I'm 
deeply troubled by that.
   
  Ed Darrell
  Dallas

Rick Duncan [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
Here is the way I look at it. One poor kid tried to censor his classmates 
with the help of a powerful legal ally, the ACLU.
   
  His classmates did not like being silenced by the poor kid. So they made a 
stand--not to ostracize the poor kid, but to stand up for their liberty of 
religious expression at their own commencement. They did not violate the spirit 
of the EC. The spirit of the EC deals with government coercion and religion. 
The true spirit of the Religion Clause is on the side of the students who would 
not be cowed and silenced by the ACLU and the unelected judiciary. 
   
  I am proud of these kids. I hope their spirit spreads to many other schools 
and impacts many other commencements. There is no need to ask  school officials 
to sponsor prayer. All students need to do is pray: without asking for 
endorsement or permission from government authorities.
   
  Cheers, Rick Duncan

[EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
Some info from the involved ACLU affiliate is at this link:
   
  http://www.aclu-ky.org/news.html#Grad%20Prayer
   
  That info includes the following paragraph:
   
  School-sponsored prayer constitutes a symbolic and tangible ‘preference… 
given by 

RE: How one school district found religion

2006-05-24 Thread Newsom Michael












Cross-religious dialogue,
without some understanding of its context or setting, can hardly be the measure
or substance of toleration. Actions also help shape and define
toleration. They are at least as important as words are. Of course,
in some settings, words take on action-like qualities.
(Context is relevant in determining whether such dialogue is nothing more than
an effort to advance an imperialist Protestant agenda. 



There is precious little evidence that teaching
about religion can be separated from teaching religion.
Curriculum design, teacher training and competence, institutional and community
pressures, including Protestant  or other majoritarian religious --
imperialism, can all work to change a course about religion into
a course that teaches religion. That is precisely why such courses in
elementary and secondary public schools are an extremely bad idea. (There
are other objections largely having to do with coverage  what religions
are or are not included in the courses and what aspects of religious belief,
practice, theology, text, ritual and ceremony are or are not to be included in
the courses.)



Conversations about religious diversity
and tolerance need to take place more rather than less often. But such
conversations do not require discussions of religious belief, practice,
theology, text, ritual and ceremony. That said, even these discussions
can be subverted, depending, of course, on the pressures brought to bear on the
shape and character of those discussions. 



The Religion Clauses contain a theory of
toleration. It is just not clear what the boundaries of it might
be. There is no doubt that the Clauses require intra-Protestant
toleration. The struggle, since the Founding, has been over whether the
Clauses require toleration of non Protestants, Christians or not. In
light of the text of the Clauses and the struggles of religious outsiders to be
included within their protection, one could fairly read the Clauses as favoring,
if not mandating tolerance of [some] non Protestants over intolerance. Teaching
toleration of those religions falling within the protection of the Clauses,
therefore, is hardly unconstitutional. (Some might say that all religions are
protected. I wonder. But that is another conversation altogether.)



I dont think that the existence of tolerated
intolerant religions presents a constitutional problem.
Interestingly the belief-action distinction actually serves some useful purpose
here. Adherents of tolerated intolerant religions can
believe anything that they want to. But their actions are subject to constitutional
norms regarding tolerance, and, hence, are subject to regulation. 



 











From: Vance R. Koven
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, May 24, 2006 8:36
AM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: Re: How one school district
found religion





A very interesting
article that raises (one might say begs) the question of the extent to which it
is constitutionally permissible for the state to encourage adherents of
intolerant religions to be tolerant. The last paragraph of the
article summarizes the school system's position nicely: 



Limiting deeply held beliefs to the private sphere breeds suspicion and
tension. True religious liberty prevails not only when people feel comfortable
expressing their beliefs, but also when they learn to discuss religious
differences with civility and respect.




Some on this list might complain that the whole concept of encouraging
cross-religious dialogue under state sponsorship smacks of imperial
Protestant theology. To the extent the exercise is about more than
etiquette there might be something to this, though it might not be a persuasive
objection. What should an adherent of Wahabism think about such a program, if
the adherent buys into the theology represented in the school textbooks quoted
here the other day? 

There certainly is an important state interest in promoting personal security.
Is adopting a platform of enforced religious tolerance the
least restrictive means of achieving that objective? From the
article, it seems clear that participants in the program grew to see the
similarities between religious belief systems. What if this outlook results in
higher levels of intermarriage between religious adherents (prohibited in some
religions) and a consequent decrease in adherents of some religions or a
decrease in religious institutional participation? 

Bottom line, can the state adopt a policy that religious adherents have to
get with the program of religious liberty, or are we now required
on the one hand to literalize the First Amendment to prevent the adoption of
any policy on the interaction between belief and action in secular society (to
the extent anyone acknowledges the existence of such a thing), or on the other
to deconstruct the First Amendment as an obsolete imposition of one religious
point of view? Or are we allowed, with or without acknowledging that 

RE: Bullying of Christian Students in Public Schools

2006-05-24 Thread Newsom Michael








How is toleration advanced if a group of
intolerant students is allowed to bully and harass gay and lesbian students?
This question is especially acute in light of the sorry history of harassment 
and worse  of gay and lesbian people. And it would be disingenuous
in the extreme to argue that all that the Slavic Christians were doing was
expressing their faith. In this context their words took on
an action-like quality and that warrants their regulation or outright
suppression in the public schools.



I do not condone threats leveled against
these Slavic Christians. Those are clearly wrong. There are better
ways to confront intolerant bullies.



 









From: Rick Duncan
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, May 24, 2006 1:49
PM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: Bullying of Christian
Students in Public Schools





Did someone mention
bullying of students in the government schools. Here is a case of real
bullyingtaking place inthe Tolerant State
(from a press release of the Pacific Justice Institute):

05.23.2006


Students
Plead With School Boards for Safe Schools and Free Speech 

Sacramento, CAStudents
and their parents packed out a school board meeting at the Roseville Joint
 Unified School
  District in response to the suspensions received
for peacefully expressing their religious beliefs. Numerous students of Slavic
descent passed out Christian literature and wore t-shirts that read,
Homosexuality is sin. Jesus can set you free. (For further
details, see PJI press release  May 2, 2006.) In addition to asking for
their rights to speech and the free exercise of religion, these students and
their parents asked the board to fulfill its obligations to protect students
from threats, violence and other forms of harassment.

Viktor Lavor, a junior, told the board that Slavic Christian students, while
leafleting, were threatened by hostile peers that they would get beat
up after school. Another pupil described how they went into the
cafeteria wearing their shirts. While sitting in the cafeteria at
breakfast, we had things like bottles, pieces of food and other objects thrown
at us, said Lyana Tagintsev. I felt unprotected, she said.
Taginstev told the board that the school is suppose to protect us like
any other students, but I didnt see them try to do anything.
Later that day, Lavor and Taginstev, along with 10 other students were summoned
to the office by school officials. We were given two options: either to
take off the shirts and go back to class or keep the shirts on and face two
days suspension. After praying, our group chose to keep the shirts on and stand
up for what we knew was the truth. If we would take off our shirts we would be
cowards, Lavor said. Nadia Militan, who did not wear the shirt that day
saw the other students in the school office who were suspended. Originally from
the Ukraine,
she told the board that this kind of speech suppression makes me wonder
if American schools follow the US Constitution. Later I asked one
of my friends if they had any more shirts. They did and I put it on in front of
the office administration. They suspended me as well, Militan told an
attentive board. 

In nearby San Juan
 Unified School
  District, parents and students intend to address
that school board about similar hostility and suppression of speech targeting
Slavic Christians. Students leafleted and wore the same t-shirts as their
friends in Roseville.
My review of the evidence so far indicates that the threats and actual
violence against the students at San Juan is as bad if not worse than what is
happening at Roseville, said Kevin Snider who is the PJI attorney
representing the students from both districts. 

These students are pleading with the school boards to respect the rights
of speech and to provide safe schools, stated Brad Dacus, PJI president.
We are hopeful that the elected officials for these two districts will
send a clear message on the rights of students to peacefully express themselves
without fear of violence. 

The Pacific Justice Institute is a non-profit 501(c)(3) legal defense
organization specializing in the defense of religious freedom, parental rights,
and other civil liberties. 
P.O. Box 276600 
Sacramento, CA 95827-6600 
Phone: (916) 857-6900 
Fax (916) 857-6902 
Internet: 
www.pacificjustice.org








Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska
College of Law 
Lincoln, NE
 68583-0902












It's a funny thing about us human beings: not many of us doubt God's
existence and then start sinning. Most of us sin and then start doubting His
existence. --J. Budziszewski (The Revenge of Conscience)











Once again the ancient maxim is vindicated, that the perversion
of the best is the worst.-- Id.











Yahoo!
Messenger with Voice. PC-to-Phone calls for ridiculously low rates.






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, 

RE: More on chaplains

2006-05-12 Thread Newsom Michael








It seems that the question on the table is
the rights of military chaplains, especially evangelical
Protestant ones who seem to be at the forefront of the agitation here. 



But their rights have to be understood
in context. The military chaplaincies were not established in order to
further or advance the rights of chaplains. Rather, they
were created in order to respond to the legitimate needs of military personnel
to have access to clergy. I suppose, since we are talking about the
military, in some sense, that it is worth pointing out that there is a
hierarchy of rights here. First and foremost are the rights
of the military institutions in the discharge of their important and awesome
responsibilities. Second, are the rights of the military (and some
civilian) personnel, in response to which, chaplains are appointed. The rights
of military chaplains are clearly subordinate to the first two.



I have little doubt but that this rank ordering
passes constitutional muster. The government does not have to provide
chaplains, in the first place, and, when it does, it can set the terms and
conditions for their engagement.



The proposed legislation reorders the hierarchy.
Not only does it threaten and undermine military cohesion and esprit de corps,
but, given the unique circumstances involved, it may be unconstitutional in
that it appears to endorse religion. It goes far beyond accommodating
religion, (the appointment of chaplains to preside at religious ceremonies and
rituals at which attendance is not required, and which respond directly to the spiritual
and religious needs of military personnel) which might be constitutionally
permissible, but here, given the realities of the situation, it endorses not
only religion(s) as against non-religion(s), (given the practical effect of the
bill to allow chaplains to deliver clearly sectarian prayers at public
occasions, rather different than voluntary religious services) but it endorses,
in practical and foreseeable effect, a particular religion or set of religions.




Now, considering the Israel amendment, it essentially
eschews toleration of the intolerant. But in this particular circumstance,
that is probably constitutionally required in order to avoid the clearly
unconstitutional endorsement of a particular religion that this bill will
necessarily foster or encourage.



The question of tolerating the intolerant
is excruciatingly difficult. But in this particular context, the endorsement
test (not to mention Lemon, or the earlier strict separationist test), makes it
clear that the military cannot tolerate intolerant chaplains bent on displaying
their intolerance in public settings in the military. (It will not do to
argue that these chaplains are merely expressing their faith. As noted
above, in the context of the military, the rights of the chaplains are subordinate
to the rights of the military-as-institution, and of military personnel.
A faith which says, in essence, that its substantive theological content is
more important than the context or setting in which the content receives
_expression_ is, in a very real sense, fervent  and intolerant. Time
keeps me from more fully explicating the point. But perhaps it is enough
to understand that some religions believe that if their followers preach (and public
prayer can be and often is a form of preaching), others will be converted
because of the preaching, and that, therefore, the right to preach trumps
everything else. I am not going to argue whether there is Biblical or
other warrant for such a view of preaching. But I will note that there
are some who believe very much in the power and force of preaching, but also
believe that circumstances, setting, and context matter. I would say that
those who hold this view are, for present purposes, tolerant.)



Under the coercion test, as
Scalia and others understand it, the proposed bill probably passes muster.
Military chaplains bent on displaying their partisan, sectarian religious
beliefs probably could not be said to coerce in some direct,
physical, or threatening way. On the other hand, I think that
psychological coercion results from such exercises and, given that more
generous  and realistic  view of coercion, I would say
that the proposed bill flunks the coercion test as well. (Santa Fe ISD
comes to mind.) 









From: Sanford Levinson
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, May 12, 2006 9:59 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: RE: More on chaplains







House Injects Prayer Into Defense Bill

By
Alan Cooperman and Ann Scott Tyson
Washington
Post Staff Writers
Friday, May 12, 2006; A05

The
House passed a $513 billion defense authorization bill yesterday that includes
language intended to allow chaplains to pray in the name of Jesus at public
military ceremonies, undercutting new Air Force and Navy guidelines on
religion

Before
the bill reached the House floor, Republicans on the House Armed Services
Committee added the 

RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax Status

2006-04-18 Thread Newsom Michael
All well and good, but it just seems to me that somewhere there is a
disconnect between the forms (501(c)(3) and 501(c)(4)) and the
underlying reality.  That is all that I meant to say.  The taxed dollars
and the nontaxed dollars may be working toward the same substantive end
or objective.

  
-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, April 18, 2006 11:02 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

Corporations and other nonprofits do it all the time.  The contributions
to the 501(c)(4) are not tax deductible. 


Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
   512-232-1341 (phone)
   512-471-6988 (fax)

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 5:50 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

So I take it that it is proper for the minister to exhort his
congregation, in a sermon, to write checks for a 501(c)(4).  I wonder. 

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 6:47 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

If they write a check out of the 501(c)(3), they're guilty.  They could
have raised money for a 501(c)(4) to write that check.  If the spiritual
leader just talks, they're constitutionally protected in my view.  If
they start spending money to duplicate his political sermons, they're
over the line.  

Follow the money is a pretty good rule here, both for religious liberty
and for tax policy.  The tax policy is that untaxed money should not be
used for political purposes.


Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
   512-232-1341 (phone)
   512-471-6988 (fax)

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 5:41 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

I am not so sure that the line that Doug draws between political ads and
sermons is clear.  What about a sermon that exhorts the congregation to
participate in a particular get-out-the-vote drive?

---Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 4:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

The reason these restrictions have been upheld as to 501(c)(3)
organizations is that they can conduct their political activities
through a 501(c)(4) or through a PAC.  to the extent that that is true
of churches (or any other not-for-profit), they should all be subject to
the same rules.  So when a church spends identifiable money on political
ads, or leaflets, or get-out-the-drives, it could raise that money after
tax through its PAC or 501(c)(4) affiliate, and it should be required to
do so. 

Some things can not be done through the PAC or 501(c)(4) affiliate.  the
religious speech of the spiritual leader is not delegable; the same
words from the staff member who leads the PAC or the 501(c)(4) affiliate
is not the same statement, because it lacks the moral authority of the
spiritual leader.  And the cost of the minister's salary does not depend
on what he says in a sermon; with or without touching on political
matters, he would be giving a sermon anyway.  The marginal cost of his
mentioning politics is zero.  So I would not let the IRS yank the tax
exemption because of the political implications or the political literal
meaning of moral or religious comments of a spiritual leader.


Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
   512-232-1341 (phone)
   512-471-6988 (fax)

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 12:16 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax Status

Rick Garnett has an interesting Op-Ed in USA Today about politics in
sermons:
http://www.usatoday.com/news/opinion/editorials/2006-04-16-forum-religio
n_x.htm

Rick makes an excellent point, I think, about how debate on public
issues -- and even partisan politics -- should not necessarily be
checked at the church door.  Indeed, at a conference here at Georgetown
last week, there was some interesting discussion about how mainstream
churches have been conspicuously absent from the public discussion
regarding torture -- and about how the public perception and political
salience of that issue might change dramatically if it were to become

RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax Status

2006-04-17 Thread Newsom Michael
So I take it that it is proper for the minister to exhort his
congregation, in a sermon, to write checks for a 501(c)(4).  I wonder. 

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 6:47 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

If they write a check out of the 501(c)(3), they're guilty.  They could
have raised money for a 501(c)(4) to write that check.  If the spiritual
leader just talks, they're constitutionally protected in my view.  If
they start spending money to duplicate his political sermons, they're
over the line.  

Follow the money is a pretty good rule here, both for religious liberty
and for tax policy.  The tax policy is that untaxed money should not be
used for political purposes.


Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
   512-232-1341 (phone)
   512-471-6988 (fax)

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 5:41 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

I am not so sure that the line that Doug draws between political ads and
sermons is clear.  What about a sermon that exhorts the congregation to
participate in a particular get-out-the-vote drive?

---Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 4:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax
Status

The reason these restrictions have been upheld as to 501(c)(3)
organizations is that they can conduct their political activities
through a 501(c)(4) or through a PAC.  to the extent that that is true
of churches (or any other not-for-profit), they should all be subject to
the same rules.  So when a church spends identifiable money on political
ads, or leaflets, or get-out-the-drives, it could raise that money after
tax through its PAC or 501(c)(4) affiliate, and it should be required to
do so. 

Some things can not be done through the PAC or 501(c)(4) affiliate.  the
religious speech of the spiritual leader is not delegable; the same
words from the staff member who leads the PAC or the 501(c)(4) affiliate
is not the same statement, because it lacks the moral authority of the
spiritual leader.  And the cost of the minister's salary does not depend
on what he says in a sermon; with or without touching on political
matters, he would be giving a sermon anyway.  The marginal cost of his
mentioning politics is zero.  So I would not let the IRS yank the tax
exemption because of the political implications or the political literal
meaning of moral or religious comments of a spiritual leader.


Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
   512-232-1341 (phone)
   512-471-6988 (fax)

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, April 17, 2006 12:16 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Law  Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: Rick Garnett on Campaigning from the Pulpit -- and Tax Status

Rick Garnett has an interesting Op-Ed in USA Today about politics in
sermons:
http://www.usatoday.com/news/opinion/editorials/2006-04-16-forum-religio
n_x.htm

Rick makes an excellent point, I think, about how debate on public
issues -- and even partisan politics -- should not necessarily be
checked at the church door.  Indeed, at a conference here at Georgetown
last week, there was some interesting discussion about how mainstream
churches have been conspicuously absent from the public discussion
regarding torture -- and about how the public perception and political
salience of that issue might change dramatically if it were to become a
major concern of important religious denominations.  (That's a topic
that's thread-worthy in and of itself:  Isn't it really remarkable, and
disheartening, that U.S. churches have been so quiet on the issue of
torture?)  Of course, issues such as torture, or abortion, or capital
punishment, or poverty, can be discussed in churches, and in sermons,
*without* any partisan political expression -- but sometimes it is and
will be appropriate for preachers, and congregants, to name names (even
when such n!
 ames ar
e those of persons running for office), and even to urge political
change.

So I agree with Rick that there is nothing (necessarily) inappropriate
about the insertion of political speech from the pulpit.  

But Rick then takes a major leap to the additional conclusion that
churches should retain their 501(c)(3) status even if they engage in
political activity -- a status that all other nonprofits would lose if
they engaged in exactly the same expression.  I know this argument is
often made, but I must confess that I just

RE: Excessive entanglement

2006-04-10 Thread Newsom Michael
I think that any analysis of the structure of the First Amendment has to
begin with a decision as to what religion is.  If it is only a variety
of speech then one might reach one set of conclusions.  If religion is
something more than speech, then it becomes difficult to argue that the
various First Amendment Clauses all blend together somehow.

The problem is that the speech only understanding of religion
privileges some religions, and disfavors liturgical religions.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, April 10, 2006 1:23 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Excessive entanglement

Well, this is what seems to me to be the puzzle.  The text
surely does mention religion explicitly, so it's possible that religious
institutions should be treated differently.  But it also mentions speech
explicitly, and protects freedom of speech as well as free exercise of
religion, so it's possible that in those zones where the concern is
protection of religion, speech, and press from the government, the three
should be treated the same.  If we are concerned that excessive
entanglement between government and religion will lead the government to
unduly control, surveill, inspect, and intrude on religious
institutions, why shouldn't we be equally concerned that excessive
entanglement between government and leading privately run speaking (here
opinion-molding and idea-transmitting) institutions will lead the
government to unduly control, surveill, inspect, and intrude on those
privately run speaking institutions?

One possible answer is that the Religion Clause, with its
establishment and free exercise component, reads differently from the
Speech/Press Clause.  But why is it proper to put excessive entanglement
*as a threat to the independence and integrity of religious
institutions* in the category of those things that lead to
constitutional concern only as to religion, rather than in the category
of those things that lead to constitutional concern as to religion,
speech, and press?  I can certainly see why excessive entanglement *as a
concern about preference for religion* would be put in the
religion-is-special box.  But given that both the Religion Clause and
the Speech/Press Clause are concerned about protecting institutions from
undue government intrusion, why isn't excessive entanglement *as a
concern about undue control of/surveillance of/inspection of/intrusion
on institutions* an equal concern as to religious institutions and
privately run speech/press institutions?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Monday, April 10, 2006 9:50 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Excessive entanglement
 
 
 I think that when it comes to religious organizations, the 
 Religion Clauses create a zone of autonomy that may have 
 quite different contours than is the case with newspapers and 
 universities.  Certainly, as to universities, how do we 
 explain *public* universities?  Obviously there we permit, if 
 not insist upon, rather pervasive monitoring, don't we? And 
 even with regard to private universities, governments 
 regulate any number of activities and functions that they do 
 not regulate when it comes to religious organizations.  
 Employment comes to mind, just for openers.  
 
 Newspapers are perhaps more interesting.  But, here again, 
 doesn't the government intrude into such areas as employment 
 in ways that the government does not in connection with 
 religious organizations?  Surely there are other examples, 
 none of which seem particularly controversial,
 troublesome, or problematic.   (By the way, recall the excessive
 entanglement that existed with regard to *broadcast* media 
 by virtue of licensing requirements regarding the use of 
 assigned frequencies in the electro-magnetic spectrum.)
 
 The autonomy of universities and newspapers seems to generate 
 less practical and less constitutional concern than does the 
 autonomy of religious institutions.  And, I think, the 
 constitutional text suggests
 -- if not commands -- that this be so.
  
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Saturday, April 08, 2006 3:42 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Excessive entanglement
 
   Yes, but why was the monitoring (a large part of the asserted
 entanglement) an impermissible entanglement?  I take it that 
 this is because it would risk putting the religious schools 
 too much under the supervision and potential control of the 
 government.  The monitoring would involve [a] comprehensive, 
 discriminating, and continuing state surveillance, and would 
 require state inspection and evaluation of the religious 
 content of a religious organization, which is pregnant with 
 dangers of excessive government direction of church schools

RE: Excessive entanglement

2006-04-10 Thread Newsom Michael
But why are we concerned about government entanglement with religious
institutions?  Aren't the reasons advanced in Lemon largely limited to
religious institutions?  Or, at least, doesn't the Court appear to be
concerned with what it identifies as a unique set of problems limited to
religious institutions?

Recall, as I indicated earlier, there are three separate grounds for
concern about excessive government entanglement with religious
institutions in the Court's opinion.  I think that you have to analyze
those grounds and determine whether, as I think is the case, that those
grounds are all rooted in a set of concerns that are limited to
religious institutions.   

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, April 10, 2006 4:28 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Excessive entanglement

I'm still not sure how this helps advance the excessive
entanglement point.  Even if religious institutions are
constitutionally different from other institutions, and must labor under
some extra burdens and get some extra benefits, it hardly follows, I
take it, that they are different in all respects.  And if the concern
with some forms of excessive entanglement is that the government would
improperly control/surveill/influence religious institutions, why
shouldn't we be as worried under the Speech/Press part of the First
Amendment about improper control of newspapers and private universities
as we are under the Religion part about improper control of churches?

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Monday, April 10, 2006 1:15 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Excessive entanglement
 
 
 I think that any analysis of the structure of the First 
 Amendment has to begin with a decision as to what religion 
 is.  If it is only a variety of speech then one might reach 
 one set of conclusions.  If religion is something more than 
 speech, then it becomes difficult to argue that the various 
 First Amendment Clauses all blend together somehow.
 
 The problem is that the speech only understanding of 
 religion privileges some religions, and disfavors liturgical 
 religions.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Monday, April 10, 2006 1:23 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Excessive entanglement
 
   Well, this is what seems to me to be the puzzle.  The 
 text surely does mention religion explicitly, so it's 
 possible that religious institutions should be treated 
 differently.  But it also mentions speech explicitly, and 
 protects freedom of speech as well as free exercise of 
 religion, so it's possible that in those zones where the 
 concern is protection of religion, speech, and press from the 
 government, the three should be treated the same.  If we are 
 concerned that excessive entanglement between government and 
 religion will lead the government to unduly control, 
 surveill, inspect, and intrude on religious institutions, why 
 shouldn't we be equally concerned that excessive entanglement 
 between government and leading privately run speaking (here 
 opinion-molding and idea-transmitting) institutions will lead 
 the government to unduly control, surveill, inspect, and 
 intrude on those privately run speaking institutions?
 
   One possible answer is that the Religion Clause, with 
 its establishment and free exercise component, reads 
 differently from the Speech/Press Clause.  But why is it 
 proper to put excessive entanglement *as a threat to the 
 independence and integrity of religious
 institutions* in the category of those things that lead to 
 constitutional concern only as to religion, rather than in 
 the category of those things that lead to constitutional 
 concern as to religion, speech, and press?  I can certainly 
 see why excessive entanglement *as a concern about preference 
 for religion* would be put in the religion-is-special box.  
 But given that both the Religion Clause and the Speech/Press 
 Clause are concerned about protecting institutions from undue 
 government intrusion, why isn't excessive entanglement *as a 
 concern about undue control of/surveillance of/inspection 
 of/intrusion on institutions* an equal concern as to 
 religious institutions and privately run speech/press institutions?
 
   Eugene
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
  Newsom Michael
  Sent: Monday, April 10, 2006 9:50 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Excessive entanglement
  
  
  I think that when it comes to religious organizations, the
  Religion Clauses create a zone of autonomy that may have 
  quite different contours than is the case with newspapers and 
  universities.  Certainly, as to universities, how do we 
  explain *public* universities

RE: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution

2006-04-07 Thread Newsom Michael
The courts -- and the legislature -- get to decide what is traditionally 
within the religious sphere, or who gets to decide what is or is not within 
that sphere.  The Religion Clauses are not self-executing.

The belief-action distinction is not particularly helpful here precisely 
because of the overlap, the expanding spheres of both church and state.  That 
is what seems to matter here.

I am not as sanguine about accommodation as others might be.  My largest 
concern about accommodation is that it all too often functions as a cover for 
majoritarian suasion, if not outright coercion.   Those concerned about the 
rights of religious minorities, therefore, tend not to embrace the view that 
accommodation is normatively or prescriptively the proper default position.

I also think that there is a tendency to confuse hostility to religion with 
hostility to the overreaching of majoritarian religion.  They are not the same 
thing.  

-Original Message-
From: Gregory Wallace [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, April 06, 2006 7:06 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution

I¹m not sure the answer is as simple as saying that they¹re denouncing a
practice, not religious truth, or that the resolution is not aimed at the
liturgy, sacraments, or other matters ³traditionally within the religious
sphere² (who gets to decide what¹s included here?). Such responses hearken
back to the old belief-action distinction that provides little real
protection for religious freedom. To tell religious persons that they can
believe whatever they want, but any attempt to act on those beliefs is
subject to government regulation, prohibition, or condemnation makes
religious freedom a fairly empty guarantee. In many instances, you can¹t
neatly separate religious practice from religious truth, because the
practice reflects the religious believer¹s effort to follow religious truth.
The reason that Catholic charities do not place children with homosexual
couples is because they believe that it would be in violation of Church
teaching to do so. To denounce the practice as ³wrong² or ³unacceptable² can
suggest the same about the truth or doctrine behind the practice.
 
Of course, government policy and religious doctrine are not always going to
be in agreement. One need look no farther than the issue of abortion to see
that legal doctrine and Catholic teaching are incompatible. But, to my
knowledge, the neither the Supreme Court nor any other government
institution has ever explicitly condemned Catholic teaching on abortion as
false and untrue, and urged Catholics everywhere in America to refuse to
follow it.² It¹s one thing for government to say we¹re going to apply
different rules in the secular sphere; it¹s quite another for government to
say a particular religion¹s teaching or views are unacceptable and should
not be followed. While one can infer government disapproval from the
adoption of different rules, that inference is not a necessary one.
 
Michael is correct that the problem here is due, at least in part, to
³overlap²religious believers carrying out religious obligations within the
secular sphere. But in such circumstances, the Religion Clause cases seem to
counsel that religious freedom is best served by accommodation, not
hostility. (Here, an accommodation of the sort suggested in the thread on
the Catholic charities in Boston may be appropriate.) The Supreme Court on
several occasions has described the Establishment Clause as forbidding not
only state action that advances or endorses religion, but also such action
that evinces hostility toward religion. While no cases have tested the
latter, it seems to me that both endorsement and condemnation pose
significant threats to religious freedom.
 
One last thought: Do you suppose that this resolution has made Cardinal
Levada feel like an ³outsider² in his political community?
 
Greg Wallace
Campbell University School of Law
 



 From: Newsom Michael [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Date: Thu, 6 Apr 2006 13:23:52 -0400
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Conversation: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution
 Subject: RE: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution
 
 These questions are posed to no one in particular, so everybody is free to
 respond -- or not.
 
 Does it matter that Catholic Charities is what Noonan and Gaffney might call a
 double duty organization or institution?  That is, the spheres or both
 church and state have grown so that they frequently overlap.
 
 The resolution does not attack or criticize Church teaching regarding the
 liturgy or the sacraments.  One could say that matters that traditionally have
 been within the religious sphere are not the subject of the resolution.  (It
 is precisely when the state does

RE: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution

2006-04-07 Thread Newsom Michael








How is the position at issue anything
other than discrimination?











From: Marc Stern
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, April 07, 2006 8:47
AM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: San Francicso Board
of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution





Marci makes the mistake of conflating the
public square with government. Of course, given the debate over homosexuality the
church (and other religious groups holding the same position( will have to
defend their position in the public square. The question is whether government
ought to enter the debate explicitly .While l I am not sure that the
Supervisors offended the constitution, it certainly seems to me a breach of
church-state etiquette for the Supervisors to have said what they did. But even
if they had been quiet there would be plenty of debate in San Francisco and elsewhere about the
morality of a position that discriminates  against homosexuals, 

Marc Stern











From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Thursday, April 06, 2006
11:00 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: San Francicso Board
of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution









The only way to defend this analysis is
to wish away most of the free exercise jurisprudence, includingthe Smith
decision. The Religion Clause cases have, in fact, been based on the
belief/conduct distinction. (As have the free speech cases.)
As I argue in God vs. the Gavel, conduct is rightly regulated by government
because of its capacity to harm others. 











The robust protection of the right to believe
whatever one wants, coupled with the non-persecution principle (Lukumi) makes
for a remarkable free exercise jurisprudence. Why shouldn't religious
entities have to defend their actions in the public square? Certainly not
because everything they do is in the public interest.

















Marci

















In a message dated 4/6/2006 7:07:55 P.M.
Eastern Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:





I¹m not
sure the answer is as simple as saying that they¹re denouncing a
practice, not religious truth, or that the resolution is not aimed at the
liturgy, sacraments, or other matters ³traditionally within the religious
sphere² (who gets to decide what¹s included here?). Such responses hearken
back to the old belief-action distinction that provides little real
protection for religious freedom. To tell religious persons that they can
believe whatever they want, but any attempt to act on those beliefs is
subject to government regulation, prohibition, or condemnation makes
religious freedom a fairly empty guarantee. In many instances, you can¹t
neatly separate religious practice from religious truth, because the
practice reflects the religious believer¹s effort to follow religious truth.
The reason that Catholic charities do not place children with homosexual
couples is because they believe that it would be in violation of Church
teaching to do so. To denounce the practice as ³wrong² or ³unacceptable² can
suggest the same about the truth or doctrine behind the practice.

Of course, government policy and religious doctrine are not always going to
be in agreement. One need look no farther than the issue of abortion to see
that legal doctrine and Catholic teaching are incompatible. But, to my
knowledge, the neither the Supreme Court nor any other government
institution has ever explicitly condemned Catholic teaching on abortion as
false and untrue, and urged Catholics everywhere in America to refuse to
follow it.² It¹s one thing for government to say we¹re going to apply
different rules in the secular sphere; it¹s quite another for government to
say a particular religion¹s teaching or views are unacceptable and should
not be followed. While one can infer government disapproval from the
adoption of different rules, that inference is not a necessary one.

Michael is correct that the problem here is due, at least in part, to
³overlap²religious believers carrying out religious obligations within
the
secular sphere. But in such circumstances, the Religion Clause cases seem to
counsel that religious freedom is best served by accommodation, not
hostility. (Here, an accommodation of the sort suggested in the thread on
the Catholic charities in Boston
may be appropriate.) The Supreme Court on
several occasions has described the Establishment Clause as forbidding not
only state action that advances or endorses religion, but also such action
that evinces hostility toward religion. While no cases have tested the
latter, it seems to me that both endorsement and condemnation pose
significant threats to religious freedom.

One last thought: Do you suppose that this resolution has made Cardinal
Levada feel like an ³outsider² in his political community?

Greg Wallace
Campbell University School
of Law
















___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To 

RE: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution

2006-04-06 Thread Newsom Michael
These questions are posed to no one in particular, so everybody is free to 
respond -- or not.

Does it matter that Catholic Charities is what Noonan and Gaffney might call a 
double duty organization or institution?  That is, the spheres or both church 
and state have grown so that they frequently overlap.

The resolution does not attack or criticize Church teaching regarding the 
liturgy or the sacraments.  One could say that matters that traditionally have 
been within the religious sphere are not the subject of the resolution.  (It is 
precisely when the state does concern itself with these matters that we have 
Establishment, as, for example, with the efforts of the Tudor and Stuart states 
to outlaw the doctrine of Transubstantiation.)  The resolution attacks the area 
of overlap, the rendering of certain social services.  It is hard to make out 
a clear EC violation in such a case, or at least I think so.

On the other hand, the resolution -- unwisely in my view -- appears to attack 
the Church's ecclesiology, the very idea of being in communion with the See of 
Rome.  We know that English Protestants, beginning with the Tudor Sate, sought 
to attack the authority of the See of Rome, as a matter of state policy.  
Again, that is the stuff of establishment, it seems to me.  

So perhaps one might ask whether the overlap stuff in the resolution, which 
probably does not raise EC concerns, trumps the ecclesiology stuff, or whether 
the ecclesiology stuff in the resolution trumps the overlap stuff.

Perhaps it matters that there is strong whiff of traditional Protestant Empire 
anti-Catholicism in this resolution.  Is that fact, standing by itself, an 
adequate basis for concluding that the resolution presents serious EC problems? 
 (This is another way of saying that the impermissible elements of the 
resolution trump the permissible elements.)

Not entirely in jest, one can ask whether the Lynch/Allegheny -- or the 
McCreary/Van Orden -- approach to context ought to control the analysis here.  
Thus, does the overlap stuff function essentially like the plastic reindeer, 
the Santa Claus figure and striped candy canes?  Does the overlap stuff 
function essentially like the other monuments in Austin (but not like the 
documents in Kentucky that finally showed up)?  (This is another way of saying 
that the permissible elements of the displays trump the elements that would be 
impermissible if displayed alone or in different contexts.) 


-Original Message-
From: Alan Brownstein [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, April 06, 2006 12:59 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic CharitiesResolution 

I think Greg's point has more force to it than some other list-members suggest. 
But there are two counter-arguments that might mitigate it.

1. I wonder if there is there a secular purpose analogy that can be drawn 
here? Just as government can not pass laws enforcing religiously based moral 
principles or promote messages for exclusively religious reasons, but can do 
either,in many circumstances, when there is a secular reason for doing so -- 
perhaps a similar argument applies to criticisms of religious beliefs. If the 
government's criticism reflects a religious purpose (denying the truth of a 
religious belief on theological grounds), it violates the Establishment Clause. 
But if the argument is that the religious belief should be criticized for 
secular reasons, it doesn't. I'm not committed to this idea. I just thought of 
it.

2. A common argument raised against claims that government expression of 
religious messages or promotion of religious displays endorses religious 
beliefs is that the government is merely acknowledging what many of its 
constituents believe to be important and true. It isn't endorsing or affirming 
the truth of anything. Again, can a similar argument be raised here -- that the 
Board is simply acknowledging that many people in SF hold certain beliefs. I 
have never been impressed by this argument when it is used to refute claims of 
endorsement -- but if it works in one situation, it arguably applies in the 
other as well. (Of course, the Board could have expressed itself using 
different language if it was only acknowledging what many SF residents believe.)

Constitutional arguments aside, I see little of value in resolutions like this. 
Does anyone think resolutions like this serve any useful purpose? Would it 
serve any useful purpose if a city in which a majority of the residents were 
religious conservatives adopted a resolution condemning gay organizations in 
the city for saying or doing things that they construed to be anti-religious.

Alan Brownstein  


-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Gregory Wallace
Sent: Thursday, April 06, 2006 7:59 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: San Francicso Board of Supervisors Catholic 

RE: Excessive entanglement

2006-04-04 Thread Newsom Michael
Isn't Lemon v. Kurtzman a good place to begin a meaningful inquiry into
the contours of excessive entanglement?  Burger identifies several
considerations that informed the judgment of the Court on this point:
the substantial religious character of the[] church-related schools';
the need to monitor the financial and programmatic limitations and
conditions of the Pennsylvania and Rhode Island statutory schemes; and
the divisive political potential of these state programs.

I am not sure that excessive entanglement with private universities or
newspapers bears any resemblance to excessive entanglement with
religious organizations, particularly parochial schools.  So the
question is not whether one is worse than the other, unless one wants to
consider whether apples are worse than oranges.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, April 03, 2006 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Excessive entanglement

Can anyone pass along a good argument for why excessive
entanglement is worse when the government entangles itself with
religious institutions (e.g., churches) than with secular expressive
institutions (e.g., private universities, newspapers, and so on)?

I realize that the First Amendment has an Establishment of
Religion Clause, and not an Establishment of Universities/Newspapers
Clause, but that doesn't itself tell us that much about excessive
entanglement.  If the concern, for instance, is that entanglement might
unduly inhibit religious institutions (cf. Agostini), it's not clear why
we shouldn't also be concerned about entanglement unduly inhibiting
universities or newspapers.  If the concern is that entanglement might
let the government improperly influences the views of what should be
rival centers of power, it again isn't clear why the same shouldn't
apply at least as to universities and newspapers.  The same is true if
the concern is that we should be worried about pervasive government
supervision of institutions whose actions might be chilled by such
supervision.

I suppose this might be a good way to identify what excessive
entanglement means -- presumably it means the sort of entanglement that
we mind precisely because of the institution's *religious* qualities,
rather than the qualities it shares with nonreligious institutions (such
as being constitutionally valuable and thus the sort of thing we don't
want to inhibit, or as being rival power centers and thus the sort of
thing we don't want the government to unduly control).  In any case, I'd
love to hear people's thoughts on this.  Many thanks,

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Sabbatarians and deadlines

2006-03-27 Thread Newsom Michael
Isn't Gonzales v. O Centro rather more helpful than either Sherbert or
Yoder?  

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 27, 2006 1:09 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Sabbatarians and deadlines

(1)  I appreciate the arguments for this sort of weighing, but
I wonder whether the weighing is consistent with the statutory language.
RFRAs generally provide that Government shall not substantially burden
a person's exercise of religion, . . . except . . . Government may
substantially burden a person's exercise of religion only if it
demonstrates that application of the burden to the person . . . is in
furtherance of a compelling governmental interest; and . . . is the
least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental
interest.  Sounds like three separate prongs (substantial burden, least
restrictive means, and compelling governmental interest), no?

(2)  Even if we are to engage in weighing, would people care
to speak to how courts should evaluate the weight of the burden, the
weight of the interest, and whether denying the exemption is the least
restrictive means of serving the interest?  In particular, how are
courts to evaluate the [w]here would this end? concern, given that
this concern is present in most religious exemption cases -- including
Sherbert and Yoder, the two paradigm cases whose test RFRA was intended
to restore -- and that RFRA therefore seems to be an attempt to require
courts to grant exemptions (at least sometimes) despite this slippery
slope risk?

Eugene

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Monday, March 27, 2006 9:55 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Sabbatarians and deadlines


the burden and compellingness are not absolutes.  it is a weighing test
with less burden needing to be shown if the state interest is slight and
more compellingness needing to be shown if the burden is heavy.


so I reject the linear sort of analysis Eugene's question posits.  I
think it reflects a serious misapprehension of the way this sort of test
works in these sorts of cases.  Strict scrutiny is just a poor label
for what is really going on.


Steve


On Mar 27, 2006, at 12:06 PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote:


I sympathize with Steve's general argument, but I wonder how it fits
within the RFRA framework.  Is it that having five days instead of six
-- or two days instead of three -- isn't a substantial burden?  That it
is a burden, but denying the exemption passes strict scrutiny?  That
despite the RFRA language, some test other than strict scrutiny applies?
-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Monday, March 27, 2006 8:01 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Sabbatarians and deadlines


Where would this end?  Sabbatarians who observe a day of no work,
including studies, would need an extra 16 days to prepare for classes?
Or an extra reading period to prepare for exams?  And it would need to
be worked out so that they get the same number of days between each
exams? 


How is the law review competition not, for constitutional purposes,
conducted by the school, btw?


We try to accommodate those students by not having assignments due on
Saturdays.  And we make special arrangements for moot court competitions
to hold arguments on Fri and Sunday for those participants.  And so on.
But I see no obligation to accommodate to the extent your inquiry
suggests.


Steve


On Mar 24, 2006, at 7:57 PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote:


Thinking about some of our UCLA Law School assignments,
especially ones that have relatively short deadlines, led me to ask
this:  Do public universities in states with accommodation regimes
(under RFRA or under Sherbert/Yoder-based state Free Exercise Clause
rules) have an obligation to extend some deadlines for Sabbatarians?  


The law review competition, for instance, starts Thursday
afternoon and ends Wednesday afternoon; it's generally believed that
many students really do need all six days to do a good job.  Say the
competition was conducted by school (which it isn't, but say it was).
Sabbatarians would have only five days on which they could do the
competition, but others have six; would the school have an obligation to
give Sabbatarians an extra day?


What if this were a 72-hour take home exam, given Friday morning
and due Monday morning?


Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or 

RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-23 Thread Newsom Michael








Ed, we are largely together here. We
need to understand, however, what within the confines of those
organizations means. But that, in turn, invites an inquiry more
generally into the reach or ambit of religious associational autonomy and privacy.
The difficulty largely concerns activities conducted by religious organizations
that, to use Noonan and Gaffneys felicitous term, do double duty, that
is, serve both religious and secular purposes. The Court has indicated
some unwillingness, at least in Title VII cases, to probe too deeply into the boundary,
if any, that might exist between the religious and the secular. See
Amos. But it would be difficult to argue that the courts should never
consider the boundary question, regardless of circumstances.



It would be fair to consider, given the
history of oppression, whether a claim that an activity is religious
might merely in reality be a sham, a cover for continued oppression.
Oppression should never qualify as religious.



We wont get neat and tidy results,
using such and approach, but we stand a good chance of getting fair and
defensible results if we do. 











From: Ed Brayton [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, March 22, 2006
6:41 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Catholic Charities
Issue





Newsom Michael wrote: 

I
am not sure that we have a mirror here. Gay people are trying to get out
from under an oppressive regime the likes of which conservative believers have
not had to endure  nor are likely to.

While I agree with this, I don't think it really cuts
against Doug's argument. And I say this as a very vocal proponent of gay
rights. I absolutely agree that gay people have lived under an oppressive
system for far too long and I strongly support gay marriage, gay adoptions and
a myriad of other correctives. But I don't think that gay liberation requires
forcing churches and religious organizations to change either their personal
beliefs or their actions *within the confines of those organizations*. In fact,
I think it is dangerous for gay rights proponents to push for policies that
would place such a requirement because it undermines our own arguments in favor
of self-determination and freedom of association. It's not just a bad idea as a
practical matter, it's unprincipled as well. We certainly want to prevent such
people from imposing their beliefs on the private behavior of gays (and the
rest of us, in a wide range of other ways as well); but we undermine our
principled position if we then seek to have government impose restrictions on
their private behavior (as opposed to the laws they advocate).

Ed Brayton






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Oppression should never qualify as 'religious'

2006-03-23 Thread Newsom Michael
The sentence has to be read in context.  The issue is the reach or ambit
of claims of religious associational autonomy and privacy.  To the
extent that the law recognizes or grants or accommodates the claim, the
law is declaring the claim to be religious.  I suppose one could say
that we accommodate some religious claims and not others.  But it is not
unheard of, in legal analysis and discourse, to say that if we grant a
claim then the claim is X and if we do not grant or enforce a claim
then the claim is not X.  My use of quotation marks clearly indicates
that I was using the term in precisely that sense.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, March 23, 2006 2:26 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Oppression should never qualify as 'religious'

I'm puzzled here; I can certainly understand a rule under which
the government may have a compelling interest in stopping oppressive
conduct, though then the question is what constitutes oppression.  But
at the threshold, where we're deciding whether conduct is religious or
not, how can it make sense to treat conduct that (say) an actor believes
to be mandated by his religious belief system as not religious simply
because we think this conduct is oppressive?

Eugene



Michael Newsom writes: 

 Ed, we are largely together here.  We need to understand, however, what
within the confines of those organizations means.  But that, in turn,
invites an inquiry more generally into the reach or ambit of religious
associational autonomy and privacy.  The difficulty largely concerns
activities conducted by religious organizations that, to use Noonan and
Gaffney's felicitous term, do double duty, that is, serve both religious
and secular purposes.  The Court has indicated some unwillingness, at
least in Title VII cases, to probe too deeply into the boundary, if any,
that might exist between the religious and the secular.  See Amos.  But
it would be difficult to argue that the courts should never consider the
boundary question, regardless of circumstances.
 
It would be fair to consider, given the history of oppression, whether a
claim that an activity is religious might merely in reality be a sham,
a cover for continued oppression.  Oppression should never qualify as
religious.
 
We won't get neat and tidy results, using such and approach, but we
stand a good chance of getting fair and defensible results if we do. 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-22 Thread Newsom Michael
I don't understand your point about free passes.

-Original Message-
From: Nathan Oman [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, March 22, 2006 6:28 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue

I am not sure that we have a mirror here.  Gay people are trying to get
out from under an oppressive regime the likes of which conservative
believers have not had to endure - nor are likely to.

This just seems to muddy the issue to me.  Doug's claim is not that gays
and conservative Christians have suffered comperable levels of
oppression, but that both should be accord a space in which to work out
their visions of the good free of collective coercion.  Furthermore, I
think that it is a mistake for gays -- or any other oppressed minority
-- to use the fact of their oppression to suggest that they get some
sort of free pass on the basic commitments of philosophical liberalism,
given that they are much more likely to persuade those who disagree with
them by appeals to liberalism than by attacks upon it.

NBO


--
**
Nathan Oman

It is a misleading cult that teaches that the remedy of our ills is to
have the law give over, once and for all, the strivings of the centuries
for a rational coherence, and sink back in utter weariness to a justice
that is the flickering reflection of the impulse of the moment.  
  -- Benjamin Cardozo
--
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-21 Thread Newsom Michael








Virtually all of the religious claims that
you refer to involve efforts to exclude, marginalize or, perhaps, even worse. Of
course those who are excluded or marginalized, or worse, would resist, as well
they should. 











From: Marc Stern
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006 8:48
AM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue





You could add the op[position to enhance d
protection for religions workers in the workplace because such legislation
might empower claims impinging on gay rights, gay groups that sued Yeshiva
University over it refusal to allow gay couples access to a married only
dorm in its medical school, the opposition to an exemption for Catholic
Charities in Boston, the suit over doctors refusing to assist lesbian
couple have a child by artificial insemination and on and on.What ever
the merits of particular suits, there has been as pattern of opposition to
religious claims in the gay rights context. 

.

Marc Stern

f











From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, March 20, 2006 8:25 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue















From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Newsom Michael
Sent: Mon 3/20/2006 3:36 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue





Could you give some examples of gay rights
proponents who ignore religious liberty interests?



Doug Laycock's Answer: The gay
rights groups organized and led the charge that killed the Religious Liberty
Protection Act. They did itby insisting on a categorical exception
for all civil rights cases, refusing to rely on the case law that most civil
rights claimspresentcompelling interests or their own view that all
civil rights claims present compelling interests.



All civil rights claims would
include challenges to the male-only priesthood. It would include claims
of religious discrimination in awarding membership or leadership positions in
churches and other religions organizations. In Colorado and several other states, civil
rights laws prohibit employers from penalizing any lawful off-the-job
activity. So civil rights claims include any immoral, disreputable,
but not illegal act you can think of: using pornography, appearing in
pornography, moonlighting at a strip club, gambling heavily in lawful casinos,
and similar things that religious organizations might tell their employees not
to do. The gay rights groups and the coalition of civil rights
organizations they put together refused to listen to any such argument.
They wanted a global and absolute civil rights exception; take it or leave
it. They produced party-line gridlock over that demand.



At the state and local level, gay rights
groups insist on no religious exemption to gay rights laws or, if they can't
prevail on that, the narrowest possible definition of religious organizations
entitled to exemption.



I assume it was these recurring political
conflicts, in which gay rights groups simply refuse to recognize any competing
interest on the other side of the table, that Alan Brownstein was referring to,
and not the occasional acts of disruptive protest.



Of course many of the conservative
religious groups are equally intractable with respect to gay rights
organizations. In the particular case of RLPA, most of themwere at
all time willing to concede the compelling-interest exception, fully
understanding that courts were likely to find a compelling interest in most
civil rights claims.























Douglas Laycock





University of Texas Law School





727 E. Dean Keeton St.





Austin, TX 78705





512-232-1341





512-471-6988 (fax)












___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious Groups and Gays and Lesbians

2006-03-21 Thread Newsom Michael
 couples access to a married only
dorm in its medical school, the opposition to an exemption for Catholic Charities
in Boston, the suit over doctors refusing to assist lesbian couple have a
child by artificial insemination and on and on.What ever the merits of
particular suits, there has been as pattern of opposition to religious claims
in the gay rights context. 

.

Marc Stern

f











From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, March 20, 2006 8:25
PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue















From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Newsom Michael
Sent: Mon 3/20/2006 3:36 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue





Could you give some examples of gay rights
proponents who ignore religious liberty interests?



Doug Laycock's Answer: The gay
rights groups organized and led the charge that killed the Religious Liberty
Protection Act. They did itby insisting on a categorical exception
for all civil rights cases, refusing to rely on the case law that most civil
rights claimspresentcompelling interests or their own view that all
civil rights claims present compelling interests.



All civil rights claims would
include challenges to the male-only priesthood. It would include claims
of religious discrimination in awarding membership or leadership positions in
churches and other religions organizations. In Colorado and several other states, civil
rights laws prohibit employers from penalizing any lawful off-the-job
activity. So civil rights claims include any immoral, disreputable,
but not illegal act you can think of: using pornography, appearing in
pornography, moonlighting at a strip club, gambling heavily in lawful casinos,
and similar things that religious organizations might tell their employees not
to do. The gay rights groups and the coalition of civil rights
organizations they put together refused to listen to any such argument.
They wanted a global and absolute civil rights exception; take it or leave
it. They produced party-line gridlock over that demand.



At the state and local level, gay rights
groups insist on no religious exemption to gay rights laws or, if they can't
prevail on that, the narrowest possible definition of religious organizations
entitled to exemption.



I assume it was these recurring political
conflicts, in which gay rights groups simply refuse to recognize any competing
interest on the other side of the table, that Alan Brownstein was referring to,
and not the occasional acts of disruptive protest.



Of course many of the conservative
religious groups are equally intractable with respect to gay rights
organizations. In the particular case of RLPA, most of themwere at
all time willing to concede the compelling-interest exception, fully
understanding that courts were likely to find a compelling interest in most
civil rights claims.























Douglas Laycock





University of Texas Law School





727 E. Dean Keeton St.





Austin, TX 78705





512-232-1341





512-471-6988 (fax)













___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private. Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
wrongly) forward the messages to others.










___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-21 Thread Newsom Michael








Take a look at David M. Smolin, Regulating
Religious and Cultural Conflict in a Postmodern America: A Response to Professor
Perry, 76 Iowa
L. Rev. 1067 (1991). Smolin, a member of the Religious Right, essentially says,
among other things, that he wants to imprison gays because of their sexual
conduct. I am not aware of any movement on the part of gays and lesbians to
imprison Professor Smolin.











From: Douglas Laycock
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006 1:31
PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue





I do not mean to include any right to
harass and intimidate. I do mean to include the right to live their own
lives in their faith, and to run their own institutions, which necessarily
includes the right to exclude from those institutions persons who do not accept
their faith or the obligations that faith imposes.







Douglas Laycock

University of Texas
 Law School

727 E. Dean
  Keeton St.

Austin, TX 78705

 512-232-1341 (phone)

 512-471-6988 (fax)















From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006
12:23 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue

If by religious liberty
interests you mean the right to exclude, and perhaps even to harass and
intimidate, then I suppose that you have responded fairly to my query. If
one were to define religious liberty interests differently, then
your example does not respond to my query. 











From: Douglas Laycock
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On
Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, March 20, 2006 8:25
PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue















From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Newsom Michael
Sent: Mon 3/20/2006 3:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue





Could you give some examples of gay rights
proponents who ignore religious liberty interests?



Doug Laycock's Answer: The gay
rights groups organized and led the charge that killed the Religious Liberty
Protection Act. They did itby insisting on a categorical exception
for all civil rights cases, refusing to rely on the case law that most civil
rights claimspresentcompelling interests or their own view that all
civil rights claims present compelling interests.



All civil rights claims would
include challenges to the male-only priesthood. It would include claims
of religious discrimination in awarding membership or leadership positions in churches
and other religions organizations. In Colorado and several other states, civil
rights laws prohibit employers from penalizing any lawful off-the-job
activity. So civil rights claims include any immoral, disreputable,
but not illegal act you can think of: using pornography, appearing in
pornography, moonlighting at a strip club, gambling heavily in lawful casinos,
and similar things that religious organizations might tell their employees not
to do. The gay rights groups and the coalition of civil rights
organizations they put together refused to listen to any such argument.
They wanted a global and absolute civil rights exception; take it or leave
it. They produced party-line gridlock over that demand.



At the state and local level, gay rights
groups insist on no religious exemption to gay rights laws or, if they can't
prevail on that, the narrowest possible definition of religious organizations
entitled to exemption.



I assume it was these recurring political
conflicts, in which gay rights groups simply refuse to recognize any competing
interest on the other side of the table, that Alan Brownstein was referring to,
and not the occasional acts of disruptive protest.



Of course many of the conservative
religious groups are equally intractable with respect to gay rights
organizations. In the particular case of RLPA, most of themwere at
all time willing to concede the compelling-interest exception, fully
understanding that courts were likely to find a compelling interest in most
civil rights claims.























Douglas Laycock





University of Texas Law School





727 E. Dean Keeton St.





Austin, TX 78705





512-232-1341





512-471-6988 (fax)












___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-21 Thread Newsom Michael
I would.  I agree with you that when it comes to selection of clergy,
special considerations come into play that are not present in the other
cases.

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006 1:54 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics '
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue

I assume then that Michael would have no problem with the law requiring
the
Catholic Church to ordain women.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Sent: 3/21/2006 10:31 AM
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue

Virtually all of the religious claims that you refer to involve efforts
to exclude, marginalize or, perhaps, even worse.  Of course those who
are excluded or marginalized, or worse, would resist, as well they
should. 

 

  _  

From: Marc Stern [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006 8:48 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue

 

You could add the op[position to enhance d protection for religions
workers in the workplace because such legislation might empower claims
impinging on gay rights, gay groups that sued Yeshiva University over it
refusal to allow gay couples access to  a married only dorm in its
medical school, the opposition to an exemption for Catholic Charities in
Boston, the suit over doctors refusing to assist  lesbian couple have a
child by artificial insemination and on and onWhat ever the merits
of
particular suits, there has been as pattern of opposition to religious
claims in the gay rights context. 

.

Marc Stern

f

 

  _  

From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, March 20, 2006 8:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue

 

 

  _  

From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Newsom Michael
Sent: Mon 3/20/2006 3:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue

Could you give some examples of gay rights proponents who ignore
religious liberty interests?  

 

Doug Laycock's Answer:  The gay rights groups organized and led the
charge that killed the Religious Liberty Protection Act.  They did it by
insisting on a categorical exception for all civil rights cases,
refusing to rely on the case law that most civil rights claims present
compelling interests or their own view that all civil rights claims
present compelling interests.

 

All civil rights claims would include challenges to the male-only
priesthood.  It would include claims of religious discrimination in
awarding membership or leadership positions in churches and other
religions organizations.  In Colorado and several other states, civil
rights laws prohibit employers from penalizing any lawful off-the-job
activity.  So civil rights claims include any immoral, disreputable,
but not illegal act you can think of:  using pornography, appearing in
pornography, moonlighting at a strip club, gambling heavily in lawful
casinos, and similar things that religious organizations might tell
their employees not to do.  The gay rights groups and the coalition of
civil rights organizations they put together refused to listen to any
such argument.  They wanted a global and absolute civil rights
exception; take it or leave it.  They produced party-line gridlock over
that demand.

 

At the state and local level, gay rights groups insist on no religious
exemption to gay rights laws or, if they can't prevail on that, the
narrowest possible definition of religious organizations entitled to
exemption.

 

I assume it was these recurring political conflicts, in which gay rights
groups simply refuse to recognize any competing interest on the other
side of the table, that Alan Brownstein was referring to, and not the
occasional acts of disruptive protest.

 

Of course many of the conservative religious groups are equally
intractable with respect to gay rights organizations.  In the particular
case of RLPA, most of them were at all time willing to concede the
compelling-interest exception, fully understanding that courts were
likely to find a compelling interest in most civil rights claims.

 

 

 

Douglas Laycock

University of Texas Law School

727 E. Dean Keeton St.

Austin, TX  78705

512-232-1341

512-471-6988 (fax)

 ATT5573046.txt 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw

RE: Religious Groups and Gays and Lesbians

2006-03-21 Thread Newsom Michael
Not when read together.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006 2:02 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious Groups and Gays and Lesbians

But of course religious liberty includes, at least sometimes,
the right to exclude.  We agree that it does so as to clergy hiring, for
instance.  There is likewise a presumptive right, under the
Sherbert/Yoder regime or under a RFRA regime, of religious people and
institutions to not deal with others when they think this dealing
violates their religious principles -- when, for instance, renting to an
unmarried straight couple or a gay couple is seen by the claimant's
religion as aiding and abetting a sin.  The question is when this right
is trumped by a compelling government interest in barring such
exclusion; the answer is sometimes (again, consider clergy hiring), and
we disagree about what those times are.  But few of us really think (I
think) that religious liberty *never* includes the right to exclude.

As to harass, of course, the question is what we mean by
harassment.  I take it that we'd agree that a religious school has the
right to teach that homosexuality is sinful, even if the pervasive
repetition of that message makes homosexual students creates a hostile
educational environment and thus constitutes hostile environment
harassment.  I take it that we'd also agree that other forms of
harassment are unprotected, for instance if someone wants to harass
using residential picketing in violation of a constitutional residential
picketing ordinance, or using continued unwanted mailings in violation
of the law upheld in Rowan, or using telephone calls in violation of a
constitutionally valid telephone harassment law.

My broader point is that general terms like exclude, harass,
and worse are probably cast at too high a level of generality here.

Eugene

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006 10:34 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious Groups and Gays and Lesbians



Doug, with respect, you misstate the case, unless you mean by religious
liberty the right to exclude, harass and worse.
 



From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On
Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Tuesday, March 21, 2006 9:35 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious Groups and Gays and Lesbians
 
As an empirical matter, it would be odd if gay rights groups, or any
other groups, supported religious exemptions from their favorite
legislation.  But it would not be contrary to their constituents'
interests.  
 
As Michael McConnell has pointed out, a regime of regulation plus
religious exemptions makes it possible to compromise otherwise
noncompromisable interests.  A strong gay rights law with a strong
religious exemption would be easier to enact than a weak gay rights law
without a religious exemption.  In a proposed regulation has no
religious exemptions, religious conscientious objectors have no choice
but to declare total war.  If a proposed regulation has reliable
religious exemptions, the stakes are much less.
 
Of course we see some of the conservative religious groups declaring
total war either way, partly for the reasons Marty suggests, and partly
because the pattern of gay-rights hostility to religious liberty has
destroyed all confidence that exemptions offered will be sensibly
interpreted or permanent.  We are in a quite unnecessary impasse, and
both sides are very much to blame.
 
Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
512-232-1341
512-471-6988 (fax)
 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tue 3/21/2006 8:24 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Religious Groups and Gays and Lesbians
A very small qualification to this discussion:  The examples Doug and
Marc cite are, if I'm not mistaken, all cases involving opposition to
religious exemptions.  Gay- and lesbian-rights groups will generally
oppose any exemptions from the laws that protect them, regardless of
whether the exemption has anything to do with religion.  That should not
be at all surprising, or alarming.  It's true of virtually any group or
organization that has secured certain legal protections, particularly
equality protections, or across-the-board restrictions.  Thus, for
example, I can assure you that the State Department and DEA were
vociferously opposed to the requested RFRA exemption for hoasca tea in
the recent case -- because they're opposed to any exceptions to
performance of treaty obligations or to the Controlled Substances Act.
(I was at the table for the discussions within the government, but I
don't think I'm revealing any non-obvious secrets by stating this.)
This doesn't make them hostile to religion.  (Although one might say it
makes them

RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-20 Thread Newsom Michael








No, it really isnt nonsense. Anti-gay
violence exists on a far larger scale than you are prepared to admit. Sorry.











From: Brad M Pardee
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 13, 2006 11:55
AM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue






Nonsense. The number of people who believe they
have the responsibility to bash in gay heads is a minute percentage
of those whose faith teaches that sexual intimacy is reserved for heterosexual
monogamous marriage, just as those who blow up abortion clinics are a minute
percentage of those faith teaches that legalized abortion is wrong. Assault
is never a matter of religious liberty and I can't begin to fathom why you would
see the two as intertwined in any way whatsoever. That fact that a
handful of fools who should be locked up think so doesn't mean that the vast
majority of those who fight for religious liberty are on their side. I've
seen enough of your postings to know that you know better than that.


Brad


Michael
wrote on 03/13/2006 10:22:58 AM:

 The fact that there are laws in place is,
often times, scant comfort.
 The religious liberty issue may, in the final
analysis for some people,
 merely mean the liberty to bash in gay heads,
all in name of God.






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups thathaveconscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws

2006-03-20 Thread Newsom Michael
Actually, it might follow that religions are entitled to benefits
without certain strings attached.  To suggest that religions are not is
to beg the question. 

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, March 14, 2006 1:42 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups
thathaveconscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws

Religions may have special and unique features for legal
purposes.  But it doesn't follow that one of those features is an
entitlement to get a government benefit while at the same time escaping
the generally applicable conditions attached to that benefit.  Maybe
there is a good reason for such an entitlement; it just needs somewhat
more proof than simply a denial that discrimination in clergy employment
constitutes discrimination, or an assertion that religions, religious
organizations, and religious believers have special and unique features.

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Thursday, March 09, 2006 4:32 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups that 
 haveconscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws
 
 
 I am still unpersuaded.  I don't see the relevance of your 
 examples. You see no difference between the relation between 
 clergy and religious organizations and other employment 
 relations?  We are talking about religions here.  The 
 Religion Clauses have to mean at least that we recognize -- 
 for better or for worse -- the special and unique features of 
 religions, religious organizations, and religious believers.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Thursday, March 09, 2006 7:07 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups that have 
 conscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws
 
   The desire to prevent discrimination based on 
 irrelevant attributes is surely one theory behind employment 
 discrimination laws. But the legislature (and the courts 
 interpreting the legislature's work) may also -- and often 
 does -- prohibit discrimination when it is relevant.  Manhart 
 is an example; I suspect that any actuary will tell you that 
 gender is quite relevant to determining mortality risk, yet 
 the Court held that this is prohibited by Title VII.  A 
 person's disability may be relevant to a job, and yet the 
 employer may still be required to ignore it, or even to spend 
 money to accommodate it.  The list could go on.
 
   The question is whether the legislature may decide not 
 to subsidize entities that discriminate based on sex, even 
 when such discrimination is quite relevant to the entity's 
 operation.  We don't care whether your discrimination is 
 relevant or not to the job qualifications, the legislature 
 may say; we just don't want money raised from taxpayers of 
 both sexes to be spent on a program that discriminates 
 against one sex (to paraphrase President Kennedy as to Title 
 VI).  Why isn't the legislature entitled to take this view?
 
   Eugene
 
 
 Rick Duncan writes:
 
 The basic idea behind employment discrimination laws is that 
 the protected characteristic (e.g. gender) is not a relevant 
 qualification for employment. Thus, there is no lawyer 
 gender, or contruction worker gender, or policeman gender. 
 Gender is not related to one's ability to do a job.
 
 That works fine for secular employment. But in the matter of 
 the religious priesthood or clergy, the state is 
 constitutionally without competence to judge what qualifies 
 one to be a priest or clergyman. Under the EC, it is an 
 excessive entanglement for the state to say, in effect, that 
 women and men are equally qualified to be God's priests or 
 shepherds on earth. Under the Free Exercise Clause, a law, 
 even a so-called generally applicable one, announcing that 
 women and men are equally well-qualified for any job, 
 including the job of priest or clergyman, s! trikes at the 
 core of religious liberty and is unconstitutional (if we must 
 employ Smith's dogma, call this the core example of a hybrid 
 claim in which free ex, free speech and freedom of expressive 
 and intimate association are linked to form a strong hybrid 
 right of 3 strands).
 
 How does the state know what are God's requirements to serve 
 in the inherently religious position of clergyman? It 
 doesn't. When it extends unemployment discrimination laws 
 into the priesthood (either by regulation or punitive tax 
 policy), it acts ultra vires and unconstitutionally. And even 
 if such laws are not technically denominational preferences 
 under Larson (because they don't facially classify on the 
 basis of religion), their primary effect is to advance the 
 religions which receive favorable tax treatment (i.e. those 
 that permit women clergy

RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-20 Thread Newsom Michael


-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 20, 2006 1:20 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue

Hmm; is there any data that would support this assertion?  (I
take it that the assertion is limited to political violence.)  I realize
that we're straying a bit from the law of government and religion, but
since this factual claim was made in the context of a discussion of a
Religion Clauses issue, it seems to me worthwhile to inquire into how
accurate this claim is.

Eugene



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Monday, March 20, 2006 10:16 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue


Actually Glendon's point is debatable.  In the United States, the
predominant pattern of violence is of violence visited by
traditionalists on progressives, not the other way around.
 



From: Rick Duncan [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, March 16, 2006 12:16 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities Issue
 
Jeff Jacoby has an excellent column in today's Boston Globe here. And
here is a money quote:
 
 
Note well: Catholic Charities made no effort to block same-sex couples
from adopting. It asked no one to endorse its belief that homosexual
adoption is wrong. It wanted only to go on finding loving parents for
troubled children, without having to place any of those children in
homes it deemed unsuitable. Gay or lesbian couples seeking to adopt
would have remained free to do so through any other agency. In at least
one Massachusetts diocese, in fact, the standing Catholic Charities
policy had been to refer same-sex couples to other adoption agencies.
 
The church's request for a conscience clause should have been
unobjectionable, at least to anyone whose pri! ority is rescuing kids
from foster care. Those who spurned that request out of hand must
believe that adoption is designed primarily for the benefit of adults,
not children. The end of Catholic Charities' involvement in adoption may
suit the Human Rights Campaign. But it can only hurt the interests of
the damaged and vulnerable children for whom Catholic Charities has long
been a source of hope.
Is this a sign of things to come? In the name of nondiscrimination, will
more states force religious organizations to swallow their principles or
go out of business? Same-sex adoption is becoming increasingly common,
but it is still highly controversial. Millions of Americans would
readily agree that gay and lesbian couples can make loving parents, yet
insist nevertheless that kids are better off with loving parents of both
sexes. That is neither a radical view nor an intolerant one, but if the
kneecapping of Catholic Charities is any indication, it may soon be
forbidden.
 
''As much as one may wish to live and let live, Harvard Law professor
Mary Ann Glendon wrote in 2004, during the same-sex marriage debate in
Massachusetts, ''the experience in other countries reveals that once
these arrangements become law, there will be no live-and-let-live policy
for those who differ. Gay-marriage proponents use the language of
openness, tolerance, and diversity, yet one foreseeable effect of their
success will be to usher in an era of intolerance and discrimination . .
. Every person and every religion that disagrees will be labeled as
bigoted and openly discriminated against. The ax will fall most heavily
on religious persons and groups that don't go along. Religious
institutions will be hit with lawsuits if they refuse to compromise
their principles.
 
The ax fell on Catholic Charities just two years after those words were
written. Where will it! have fallen two years hence?
 
 
Mary Ann's point is well-taken. If A, then B.
 
I wish I had thought of that!


 
 
Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska College of Law 
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902
 

When the Round Table is broken every man must follow either Galahad or
Mordred: middle things are gone. C.S.Lewis, Grand Miracle

I will not be pushed, filed, stamped, indexed, briefed, debriefed, or
numbered. --The Prisoner



Yahoo! Mail
Bring photos to life! New PhotoMail makes sharing a breeze. 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin

RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-13 Thread Newsom Michael
The fact that there are laws in place is, often times, scant comfort.
The religious liberty issue may, in the final analysis for some people,
merely mean the liberty to bash in gay heads, all in name of God.

-Original Message-
From: Brad Pardee [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 13, 2006 5:44 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Catholic Charities Issue

Michael Newsom wrote, Being 'marginalized' and called a 'homophobe' is
not 
quite the same thing as having your brains beat in because you are gay.
To 
suppose that the two are morally equivalent is to make, with respect, a 
categorical error.

It's true that these two are not morally equivalent.  However, if a
person 
is assaulted on the basis of their sexual orientation (or on the basis
of 
anything else, for that matter), there are laws in place to punish those

guilty of the attack (such as the murderers of Matthew Shepard, who are
both 
serving life sentences without possibility of parole).  In contrast, the

marginilization being described is being done BY the law, not in
violation 
of the law.  That is where the issue of religious liberty comes in.

Brad 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Catholic Charities Not Bending the Knee to Baal

2006-03-12 Thread Newsom Michael








The right thing to do? I am not so sure.
You did say that some children will suffer. Is that a good thing? Oops. This
discussion probably belongs off-list.











From: Rick Duncan
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]] 
Sent: Friday, March 10, 2006 11:15
PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Catholic Charities Not
Bending the Knee to Baal







From the Boston
Globe:

















The Boston
Archdiocese's Catholic Charities said Friday it would stop providing adoption
services because state law requires them to consider gays and lesbians as
parents.











The social services arm of the Roman Catholic
archdiocese has provided adoption services for about a century. But it says
state law allowing gays to adopt runs counter to church teachers on
homosexuality.











The world was very different when Charities
began this ministry at the threshold of the twentieth-century, the Rev.
J. Bryan Hehir and trustees chairman Jeffrey Kaneb said in a joint statement.
The world changed often and we adapted the ministry to meet changing
times and ! needs. At all times we sought to place the welfare of children at
the heart of our work.











But now, we have encountered a dilemma we cannot
resolve, they said.











The state's four Catholic bishops said earlier this
month that the law threatens the church's religious freedom by forcing it to do
something it considers immoral

















This was the right move for the Archdiocese to make. Really, it was the
only move they could make. It's sad that many children will suffer, but the
Archdiocese has to obey its conscience.









Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska
College of Law 
Lincoln, NE
 68583-0902












When the Round Table is broken every man must follow either Galahad or
Mordred: middle things are gone. C.S.Lewis, Grand Miracle

I will not be pushed, filed, stamped, indexed, briefed, debriefed, or
numbered. --The Prisoner











Yahoo! Mail
Bring photos to life! New
PhotoMail makes sharing a breeze. 






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Catholic Charities Issue

2006-03-12 Thread Newsom Michael








But the Religious Right Catholic, Protestant
and otherwise  insists that gay people CAN be reasonably asked to live
celibate lives, if they cannot live heterosexual lives.



I merely wish to point out that some deny
the equivalence that you posit. I am not saying that I agree or disagree with
that denial.



One wonders  hopes, perhaps, prays,
perhaps  that science can break the tie on the question of what is
reasonable. While some may hate to admit it, it would appear that science has
influenced religious thought from time to time. (I have especially in mind scientific
examination of the lives, values, prospects, hopes and the like of children
raised by openly gay parents, either single gay parents, or gay parents in
monogamous relationships that are marriage like. There is some
science on the point, but I suspect that the two sides on the question would
debate just what that science establishes or suggests.)











From: Alan Brownstein
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On
Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Saturday, March 11, 2006
11:46 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue









Not only isn't it impossible to have both
gay rights and religious liberty, the core of both sets of claims have
common foundations. It makes no more sense for a gay activist to insist that a
religious person should ignore the duties he or she owes to G-d (a duty
that,I believe, arises out of love and principle) -- because the
religious person can not reasonably be asked to do that --than it does
for a religious person to insist that a gay person should deny the love he (or
she) shares with another person whohe wants tospend his life
with -- because the gay person can not reasonably be asked to do that.











Alan Brownstein















From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Sat 3/11/2006 7:42 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Catholic Charities
Issue









It is not at all impossible to have both
gay rights and religious liberty. It is just that the gay rights
activists mostly refuse to recognize religious liberty (at least if any gay
rights issue is in anyway implicated), and the more conservative religious
liberty activists mostly refuse to recognize gay rights. Both sides want
the symbolic victory of having the state declare the other side wrong, and both
sides want to be assured they will never have to litigate a case at the
boundary between the two freedoms.











Alan Brownstein sketched a perfectly
sensible way to resolve the Massachusetts
dispute in a way that protects both sides -- gay parents would be free to adopt
through other state-funded agencies, and Catholic Charities would be free not
to place children with gay parents. More generally, strong gay rights
legislation with strong religious liberty exceptions would protect both
sides. 















Douglas Laycock





University of Texas
 Law School





727 E. Dean
  Keeton St.





Austin, TX 78705





512-232-1341





512-471-6988 (fax)















From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Rick Duncan
Sent: Sat 3/11/2006 8:22 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Catholic Charities
Issue







I think Marci and Doug are spot on. The state, as in Rust, says this is our
program, take it or leave it. CC says, okay, we'll leave
it. CC loses a part of its ministry, the state loses one of its
best adoption-service providers, and the kids stay in state custody longer
(and, for some, perhaps permanently, since CC was extra good at placing
hard-to-place children).











This is why some of us fight so hard against gay rights and gay
marriage--gay rights/marriage are incompatible (at least in certain situations)with
religious liberty. As in Massachusetts,
the state has to choose between religious liberty and gay rights. 











Some states choose gay rights. I choose religious liberty. I was born
and raised in Massachusetts,
but I couldn't live there now (and I don't think I even care to visit--not even
if I had Monster seats at fenway).











Cheers, Rick Duncan 











[EMAIL PROTECTED]
wrote:







What this
disputere: Catholic Charities illustrates is the danger of any religious
institution in relying upon government funding for its programs.
Government funding always comes with strings. In general, Catholic
Charities gets 86% of its funding from government sources, 14% from private,
with the vast majority of that coming from charities like United Way. A tiny portion is paid
by Catholics.I would assume that onits own dime, CC can
facilitate adoptions, but feel free to correct that assumption. 











The question is whether it is going to
accept the condition placed on it by the government's money.!
nbsp;CC is not required to take the government's money, right?This
is the Solomon Amendment -- private institution that has become dependent on
government largesse 

RE: StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscriminationlaws

2006-03-10 Thread Newsom Michael
With respect, I am not sure that characterizing the relation as akin to
that of employer and employee tells us how to decide the question.  I
cannot imagine that there is a strong governmental interest in the
gender of clergypersons.  Any expression or statement of such an
interest clearly results in meddling by the state, not to mention taking
sides in a contentious dispute that has deeply upset many Christians, at
least.

A secular category, like employment, cannot do justice to the
employment (solely for the sake of discussion) of clergy.

Consider, for example, the mess that the Court made of things in Jones
v. Wolf.  Thanks to neutral principles, hierarchical religious
institutions, institutions that have been such for 2000 years are
magically converted into congregationalist institutions for purposes of
working out or resolving church property disputes.  Jones tramples on
both Religion Clauses largely because of the totally inapt notion that
religious or church property disputes are essentially property disputes,
not religious disputes.

We should be loath to replicate the categorical error of Jones v. Wolf.


One final point: it is by no means clear that the relation between a
religious institution and its clergy is as simple as the typical
employment relation would suggest.  This is, of course, true because the
relation is also a RELIGIOUS relation.  That is, the sum and substance
of the problem. 

  
-Original Message-
From: Andrew Wyatt [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, March 08, 2006 6:26 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE:
StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscr
iminationlaws

I'm not denying the special nature of the clergy-laity relationship, in
fact or in law.  I'm simply trying to answer your question: Why might a
government properly deny benefits in some instances of
religiously-motivated discrimination (e.g. withholding funding from
churches that discriminate against women in the hiring of clergy) but
not in others (e.g. denying unemployment benefits to a man who refuses
to marry Jewish women)?

Bearing in mind that IANAL, it seems that courts have recognized a
strong government interest where workplace discrimination in concerned.
However, those interests may not be as strong in other forums, even if
state instruments--say, civil marriage--are involved.  If an individual
refuses to enter into a civil marriage for discriminatory reasons, there
may be a societal harm from that decision.  But there seems to be some
recognition that the societal harm from an employer refusing to hire
someone for discriminatory reasons is far greater, sufficient perhaps to
warrant government action of some kind.  There may be broad economic
ripples emanating from the latter sort of discrimination, as Eugene
noted.  To my eye, the power that employers have over their employees
seems qualitatively different than the co-equal character of the spousal
relationship. 

Andrew Wyatt

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscriminationlaws

2006-03-09 Thread Newsom Michael
My point is that there are some relationships that have a kind of
intimacy that the government ought to leave alone.  I think that the
Religion Clauses compel the government to leave the intimate relation
between clergy and religious institutions alone.  

The broader, and obvious, point is that not all discrimination is bad.
There are policy-based and legal reasons why some discrimination has to
be permitted, isn't that true?  Why is this odd?



-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, March 09, 2006 12:38 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE:
StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscr
iminationlaws

1)  My definition of discrimination here is simply the one the
Court applied in Manhart and various other cases:  The principle that
discrimination means that an entity treats a person in a manner which
but for that person's sex would be different.  City of Los Angeles
Dep't of Water  Power v. Manhart, 435 U.S. 702, 711 (1978);
International Union v. Johnson Controls, Inc., 499 U.S. 187, 200 (1991);
Newport News Shipbuilding  Dry Dock Co. v. EEOC, 462 U.S. 669, 683
(1983); see also EEOC v. Borden's, Inc., 724 F.2d 1390, 1393 (9th Cir.
1984); Allison-LeBlanc v. Department of Pub. Safety  Corrections, 671
So. 2d 448, 452 (La. Ct. App. 1995); DiBiase v. Smithkline Beacham
Corp., 847 F. Supp. 341, 348 (E.D. Pa. 1994).  The discrimination may be
quite rational, and not at all based on hostility -- the discrimination
in Manhart itself was based on the reality that women live longer than
men, a reality that pension plan funding schemes, which are after all
based on group-based statistics, can quite reasonably consider.  But the
Court concluded that this was prohibited discrimination.

2)  The principle under which Congress would deny exemptions to
groups that discriminate in this way is the one President Kennedy
elaborated as support for Title VI (albeit applied to sex as well as
race):  public funds, to which all taxpayers of all races [and both
sexes] contribute, not be spent in any fashion which . . . subsidizes .
. . racial [and sex] discrimination.  I should stress again that I
don't think this principle ought to be used with regard to tax
exemptions and clergy hiring -- but I don't think it's unreasonable or
incomprehensible for others to disagree with me on this.  The question
is whether adopting this principle to deny tax exemptions to all groups
that discriminate based on sex would violate the First Amendment; my
tentative thinking is that it probably won't, and that the Church's (and
other groups') right to discriminate based on sex free from government
*prohibition* doesn't necessarily imply that the government must
subsidize the exercise of this right.

3)  Denying government benefits to people who refuse to marry
people with green hair is an odd hypo; I find it hard to see any
rational basis for singling out green hair this way.  On the other hand,
if the government denied the child care tax credit to parents who
discriminated based on race or sex in hiring a child care provider, I
would think that's constitutional.  And, as we know, if the government
denies groups a tax exemption because of their exercise of their
constitutionally protected rights to lobby or electioneer, or otherwise
refuses to subsidize a wide range of constitutional rights, that too is
permissible.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Wednesday, March 08, 2006 12:58 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: 
 StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionst
 oantidiscriminationlaws
 
 
 I'm afraid that I don't understand your non-discrimination 
 principle. You have not indicated whether you think that it 
 is appropriate to deny a government benefit to individuals 
 who refuse to marry people with green hair.  If it is 
 inappropriate to do so then I am lost.  Marriage is an 
 intimate relation, to be sure, but so to is the relation 
 between clergy and laity in the context of a religious 
 institution, and we have 16 words in the First Amendment that 
 tell us that religion is something special.
 
 Generalized appeals to discrimination fail to get at the 
 real issues involved. 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Wednesday, March 08, 2006 12:47 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: 
 StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionst
 oantidiscr
 iminationlaws
 
   I'm afraid I still don't quite get it.  The core of the 
 argument, it seems to me, is that There has been an on-going 
 debate among Christian groups regarding the matter of women 
 clergy.  For the state to choose one side in that debate is 
 to make precisely what I said
 -- an unavoidable theological judgment

RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups that have conscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws

2006-03-09 Thread Newsom Michael
I am still unpersuaded.  I don't see the relevance of your examples.
You see no difference between the relation between clergy and religious
organizations and other employment relations?  We are talking about
religions here.  The Religion Clauses have to mean at least that we
recognize -- for better or for worse -- the special and unique features
of religions, religious organizations, and religious believers.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, March 09, 2006 7:07 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups that have
conscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws

The desire to prevent discrimination based on irrelevant
attributes is surely one theory behind employment discrimination laws.
But the legislature (and the courts interpreting the legislature's work)
may also -- and often does -- prohibit discrimination when it is
relevant.  Manhart is an example; I suspect that any actuary will tell
you that gender is quite relevant to determining mortality risk, yet the
Court held that this is prohibited by Title VII.  A person's disability
may be relevant to a job, and yet the employer may still be required to
ignore it, or even to spend money to accommodate it.  The list could go
on.

The question is whether the legislature may decide not to
subsidize entities that discriminate based on sex, even when such
discrimination is quite relevant to the entity's operation.  We don't
care whether your discrimination is relevant or not to the job
qualifications, the legislature may say; we just don't want money raised
from taxpayers of both sexes to be spent on a program that discriminates
against one sex (to paraphrase President Kennedy as to Title VI).  Why
isn't the legislature entitled to take this view?

Eugene


Rick Duncan writes:

The basic idea behind employment discrimination laws is that the
protected characteristic (e.g. gender) is not a relevant qualification
for employment. Thus, there is no lawyer gender, or contruction worker
gender, or policeman gender. Gender is not related to one's ability to
do a job.

That works fine for secular employment. But in the matter of the
religious priesthood or clergy, the state is constitutionally without
competence to judge what qualifies one to be a priest or clergyman.
Under the EC, it is an excessive entanglement for the state to say, in
effect, that women and men are equally qualified to be God's priests or
shepherds on earth. Under the Free Exercise Clause, a law, even a
so-called generally applicable one, announcing that women and men are
equally well-qualified for any job, including the job of priest or
clergyman, s! trikes at the core of religious liberty and is
unconstitutional (if we must employ Smith's dogma, call this the core
example of a hybrid claim in which free ex, free speech and freedom of
expressive and intimate association are linked to form a strong hybrid
right of 3 strands).

How does the state know what are God's requirements to serve in the
inherently religious position of clergyman? It doesn't. When it extends
unemployment discrimination laws into the priesthood (either by
regulation or punitive tax policy), it acts ultra vires and
unconstitutionally. And even if such laws are not technically
denominational preferences under Larson (because they don't facially
classify on the basis of religion), their primary effect is to advance
the religions which receive favorable tax treatment (i.e. those that
permit women clergy), and to inhibit the religions denied equal tax
treatment (those that don't ordain women). 

Rick Duncan
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscriminationlaws

2006-03-08 Thread Newsom Michael
The question is really not about discrimination at all.  It is about
discrimination in the selection of clergy, and not about some vast
range of government decisions.  Context matters.  I have not taken a
position on the balance to be struck between discrimination and other
kinds of decision-making by religious groups.

The ministerial exception recognizes the special, if not unique,
character of the selection of clergy.  That, it seems to me, calls into
serious question a decision by a government to deny a benefit to a
religious group that only accepts male clergy.

And, by the way, a closer examination of the context strongly suggests
that a neutral application of a general statute on the question of
the selection of Christian clergy, at least, is anything but neutral.
There has been an on-going debate among Christian groups regarding the
matter of women clergy.  For the state to choose one side in that debate
is to make precisely what I said -- an unavoidable theological judgment
-- in a highly contentious matter.  The government winds up taking sides
in a matter of which that it is better advised to steer clear.

There can be no broad, bright-line rule here.  Nobody would argue for an
anti-discrimination principle prohibits ALL forms and types of
discrimination.  People can discriminate in the selection of a spouse,
for example.  Or, would it be proper for the state to deny, say, social
security or other benefits to those who discriminate against people with
green hair in the selection of a spouse?  I don't think so.  The
particular facts associated with the selection of clergy, it seems to
me, control the particular and specific question. 

One final point: to deny a benefit is, UNDER THESE CIRCUMSTANCES, a rank
interference with religion and thus a violation the nonestablishment
principle.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 3:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE:
StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscr
iminationlaws

Now this I'm not sure I quite grasp.  Why is the state's
judgment that the Catholic Church discriminates based on sex in hiring
clergy -- followed by the application of a (hypothetical) generally
applicable rule that sex-discriminatory groups aren't entitled to tax
exemption (a rule, incidentally, that I wouldn't endorse as a policy
matter) -- an unavoidably theological judgment?  The Church is neither
secretive nor ambiguous in its men-only rule for the priesthood.

It's true that the state's decision would contradict the
Church's theological views, but that's true of a vast range of state
decisions.  And it's true that the Church has a constitutional right to
discriminate in choice of clergy; yet the government is not obligated to
subsidize the exercise of constitutional rights.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 12:09 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: State 
 RFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoanti
 discriminationlaws
 
 
 In this particular, specific instance, I believe that the 
 answer is yes.  Otherwise, the state winds up making what 
 are essentially and unavoidably theological judgments.  That 
 is not true in the other examples that you give.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 2:25 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: State RFRA 
 andnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidisc
 rimination
 laws
 
   I actually agree that religious groups should have a 
 right to discriminate in choice of clergy, much as 
 nonreligious groups should generally have a right to 
 discriminate in choice of leaders, speakers, and members (see 
 Boy Scouts v. Dale).  (The precise contours of the two rights 
 may be somewhat different, but the underlying reasons for 
 them, and their existence, are in my view quite related.)  
 Yet the question still remains whether the government has an 
 obligation to help subsidize this discriminatory practice, by 
 waiving nondiscrimination conditions attached to various 
 benefits (e.g., tax exemptions) that the groups seek.
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
  Newsom Michael
  Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 11:21 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: State RFRA 
  andnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjections 
  toantidiscrimination laws
  
  
  My point is that the ministerial exception should be 
 broadly construed
  and applied.   In the specific context of clergy, the state 
 should not
  quickly or easily claim that a religious organization is
  ineligible for a subsidy if it is guilty of what the state 
  claims is discrimination

RE: StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscriminationlaws

2006-03-08 Thread Newsom Michael
I'm afraid that I don't understand your non-discrimination principle.
You have not indicated whether you think that it is appropriate to deny
a government benefit to individuals who refuse to marry people with
green hair.  If it is inappropriate to do so then I am lost.  Marriage
is an intimate relation, to be sure, but so to is the relation between
clergy and laity in the context of a religious institution, and we have
16 words in the First Amendment that tell us that religion is something
special.

Generalized appeals to discrimination fail to get at the real issues
involved. 


-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, March 08, 2006 12:47 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE:
StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscr
iminationlaws

I'm afraid I still don't quite get it.  The core of the
argument, it seems to me, is that There has been an on-going debate
among Christian groups regarding the matter of women clergy.  For the
state to choose one side in that debate is to make precisely what I said
-- an unavoidable theological judgment -- in a highly contentious
matter.  The government winds up taking sides in a matter of which that
it is better advised to steer clear.  But the same is true of a vast
range of religious decisions.  There are or were on-going debates among
groups about race discrimination in student policies (Bob Jones), about
the advisability of participating in electoral politics (Branch
Ministries, the D.C. Cir. [?] case), about sex and religious
discrimination in choice of students (generally in the K-12 religious
school choice context) and more.

The state chooses sides in that debate, especially when it comes
to participation in state-provided policies, all the time.  Can it
really be that each such decision involves a forbidden theological
judgment?  That argument, I think, was made in Bob Jones, and rejected;
the Court pointed out that the fact that the government's policies match
the views of some religions (e.g., no race discrimination) doesn't make
them impermissible establishments of religion.

I actually agree that clergy selection should be different, when
government regulation is involved; I tentatively suspect otherwise as to
funding, though I'd be happy to be persuaded that I'm mistaken on this.
But I don't see how one can just say that it's different because the
government policies involve an unavoidable theological judgment (which
presumably would mean that they're per se unconstitutional, without even
a strict scrutiny escape hatch) -- the policies seem to involve the same
sort of judgments about, say, protecting people's economic opportunities
(clergy is a paying job, after all) or preventing tax money raised from
taxpayers of all races and sexes being used to subsidize race or sex
discrimination.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Monday, March 06, 2006 9:59 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: 
 StateRFRAandnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionst
 oantidiscriminationlaws
 
 
 The question is really not about discrimination at all.  It 
 is about discrimination in the selection of clergy, and not 
 about some vast range of government decisions.  Context 
 matters.  I have not taken a position on the balance to be 
 struck between discrimination and other kinds of 
 decision-making by religious groups.
 
 The ministerial exception recognizes the special, if not 
 unique, character of the selection of clergy.  That, it seems 
 to me, calls into serious question a decision by a government 
 to deny a benefit to a religious group that only accepts male clergy.
 
 And, by the way, a closer examination of the context strongly 
 suggests that a neutral application of a general statute 
 on the question of the selection of Christian clergy, at 
 least, is anything but neutral. There has been an on-going 
 debate among Christian groups regarding the matter of women 
 clergy.  For the state to choose one side in that debate is 
 to make precisely what I said -- an unavoidable theological judgment
 -- in a highly contentious matter.  The government winds up 
 taking sides in a matter of which that it is better advised 
 to steer clear.
 
 There can be no broad, bright-line rule here.  Nobody would 
 argue for an anti-discrimination principle prohibits ALL 
 forms and types of discrimination.  People can discriminate 
 in the selection of a spouse, for example.  Or, would it be 
 proper for the state to deny, say, social security or other 
 benefits to those who discriminate against people with green 
 hair in the selection of a spouse?  I don't think so.  The 
 particular facts associated with the selection of clergy, it 
 seems to me, control the particular and specific question. 
 
 One final point: to deny a benefit

RE: State RFRA and nonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws

2006-03-03 Thread Newsom Michael
My point is that the ministerial exception should be broadly construed
and applied.   In the specific context of clergy, the state should not
quickly or easily claim that a religious organization is ineligible for
a subsidy if it is guilty of what the state claims is discrimination.

The question is not really about discrimination, it is about
discrimination in the context of selecting clergy.  Because of this,
then there are some serious First Amendment issues that have to be
considered.  Hence a liberal and broad application of the exception
seems to make sense.  

If the question were about child marriage, or renting apartments the
result might be different.  Surely there is something rather unique and
special about the relation between a religious community and its clergy,
something not found in your examples. 

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 12:23 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: State RFRA and
nonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination
laws

Well, I was using the secular law definition of discrimination,
which (at least insofar as it's relevant here) is pretty much Stevens's
test in Manhart:  Does the institution treat[] a person in a manner
which but for that person's sex would be different?  If Jesus Christ
deliberately chose only men as apostles, then that was discrimination --
obviously not illegal either then or now (now because they weren't paid,
and thus weren't his employees), but that's a separate question than
whether it's discrimination.  By way of analogy, consider a landlord who
refuses to rent to unmarried couples or same-sex couples, because he
believes that renting to them would constitute aiding and abetting
fornication or homosexual conduct.  He may not see his conduct as
discrimination, just as compliance with God's will.  Yet discrimination
it is.

Nor am I quite sure why it would be unconstitutional for the
state to indulge in or act upon such statements (i.e., that
selecting priests based on sex is discrimination).  If the claim is that
it expresses disapproval of a faith to condemn as illegal conduct that
mirrors what the faith's holy figures do, that can't be quite right.
That Jesus was said to have driven the moneylenders from the Temple
doesn't mean that such conduct would be constitutionally protected if
conducted by a religious person (or a church official or even a
self-described Messiah) today.  Mohammed's marriage to a child bride may
have been perfectly proper by the standards of the time and place in
which he lived, but it doesn't mean that secular law can't ban it today;
it can ban it, even if such conduct is being performed as a religious
sacrament.

If the claim is that denying subsidies to a religious group
because it fails to satisfy a general condition attached to subsidy is
unconstitutional or a RFRA violation, that's less implausible.  Yet I
wonder why we should take this view.  The government subsidizes all
sorts of things because of its own reasons.  It subsidizes public
schools, but not private religious schools, even though educating one's
child in a pervasively religious atmosphere may be a sacrament to some
people.  It subsidizes child care, but not people who stay home to raise
their children, even though that's a sacrament to some people, too.  It
subsidizes (through tax exemption) nonlobbying, nonelectioneering
nonprofit speech but not lobbying or electioneering nonprofit speech.
Why can't it equally choose to subsidize those nonprofits that don't
discriminate, but not those that do discriminate (even though the latter
may have a constitutional right to discriminate, just as parents have
the right to send their kids to private schools, and just as groups have
the right to lobby or electioneer)?

Eugene

Michael Newsom writes:

 1) To say that a religious organization chooses its clergy
 discriminatorily requires some serious and sober 
 consideration of the theology of that organization.  The 
 exemption ought to apply broadly if only to keep secular 
 entities out of an area in which they have precious little 
 expertise (quite apart from any consideration of any 
 constitutional norms).  To say that the refusal to ordain 
 women is discrimination without consideration of the 
 context begs the question. One could just as easily say that 
 Jesus Christ discriminated against women by only choosing men 
 as apostles.  For the state to indulge in such statements -- 
 and to act upon them -- is precisely what the Religion 
 Clauses prohibit.  To subsidize religious organizations that 
 ordain women and to refuse to subsidize religious 
 organizations that do not is to establish a preference for 
 some religions over others. Doesn't that offend the 
 non-establishment principle?  If, of course, one chooses not 
 to recognize that religion and religious institutions occupy 
 a special place in the 

RE: State RFRA andnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscrimination laws

2006-03-03 Thread Newsom Michael
In this particular, specific instance, I believe that the answer is
yes.  Otherwise, the state winds up making what are essentially and
unavoidably theological judgments.  That is not true in the other
examples that you give.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: State RFRA
andnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjectionstoantidiscrimination
laws

I actually agree that religious groups should have a right to
discriminate in choice of clergy, much as nonreligious groups should
generally have a right to discriminate in choice of leaders, speakers,
and members (see Boy Scouts v. Dale).  (The precise contours of the two
rights may be somewhat different, but the underlying reasons for them,
and their existence, are in my view quite related.)  Yet the question
still remains whether the government has an obligation to help subsidize
this discriminatory practice, by waiving nondiscrimination conditions
attached to various benefits (e.g., tax exemptions) that the groups
seek.

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 11:21 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: State RFRA 
 andnonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjections 
 toantidiscrimination laws
 
 
 My point is that the ministerial exception should be broadly construed
 and applied.   In the specific context of clergy, the state should not
 quickly or easily claim that a religious organization is 
 ineligible for a subsidy if it is guilty of what the state 
 claims is discrimination.
 
 The question is not really about discrimination, it is about 
 discrimination in the context of selecting clergy.  Because 
 of this, then there are some serious First Amendment issues 
 that have to be considered.  Hence a liberal and broad 
 application of the exception seems to make sense.  
 
 If the question were about child marriage, or renting 
 apartments the result might be different.  Surely there is 
 something rather unique and special about the relation 
 between a religious community and its clergy, something not 
 found in your examples. 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Friday, March 03, 2006 12:23 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: State RFRA and 
 nonreligiousgroupsthathaveconscientiousobjections to 
 antidiscrimination laws
 
   Well, I was using the secular law definition of 
 discrimination, which (at least insofar as it's relevant 
 here) is pretty much Stevens's test in Manhart:  Does the 
 institution treat[] a person in a manner which but for that 
 person's sex would be different?  If Jesus Christ 
 deliberately chose only men as apostles, then that was 
 discrimination -- obviously not illegal either then or now 
 (now because they weren't paid, and thus weren't his 
 employees), but that's a separate question than whether it's 
 discrimination.  By way of analogy, consider a landlord who 
 refuses to rent to unmarried couples or same-sex couples, 
 because he believes that renting to them would constitute 
 aiding and abetting fornication or homosexual conduct.  He 
 may not see his conduct as discrimination, just as compliance 
 with God's will.  Yet discrimination it is.
 
   Nor am I quite sure why it would be unconstitutional 
 for the state to indulge in or act upon such statements 
 (i.e., that selecting priests based on sex is 
 discrimination).  If the claim is that it expresses 
 disapproval of a faith to condemn as illegal conduct that 
 mirrors what the faith's holy figures do, that can't be quite 
 right. That Jesus was said to have driven the moneylenders 
 from the Temple doesn't mean that such conduct would be 
 constitutionally protected if conducted by a religious person 
 (or a church official or even a self-described Messiah) 
 today.  Mohammed's marriage to a child bride may have been 
 perfectly proper by the standards of the time and place in 
 which he lived, but it doesn't mean that secular law can't 
 ban it today; it can ban it, even if such conduct is being 
 performed as a religious sacrament.
 
   If the claim is that denying subsidies to a religious 
 group because it fails to satisfy a general condition 
 attached to subsidy is unconstitutional or a RFRA violation, 
 that's less implausible.  Yet I wonder why we should take 
 this view.  The government subsidizes all sorts of things 
 because of its own reasons.  It subsidizes public schools, 
 but not private religious schools, even though educating 
 one's child in a pervasively religious atmosphere may be a 
 sacrament to some people.  It subsidizes child care, but not 
 people who stay home to raise their children, even though 
 that's a sacrament to some people, too.  It subsidizes 
 (through tax exemption

RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups thathaveconscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws

2006-03-02 Thread Newsom Michael
 Scouts but the Traditionalist
Christian Scouts, a group that sees itself as focused on shared
Christian (Protestant and Catholic) traditionalist moral values?  Assume
the group's leaders don't much insist that Scout leaders or members have
the same views on salvation through works, predestination,
transsubstantiation, or other theological points; but they do bar
homosexual behavior and other behavior that they see as sinful (but that
doesn't implicate antidiscrimination laws).  Would that be enough to
raise a RFRA claim, or does the mixture of denominations block that.  He

3)  Finally, say that the Boy Scouts believe that they have a
secular conscientious obligation -- not a religious one -- to limit
membership and leadership positions to heterosexuals.  The Scouts
sincerely and deeply believe this, precisely because they think it's
wrong to bring the prospect of erotic attraction into relations between
adolescents in this context.  And not only are they unfazed by the
question What about a group that claimed that boys and girls should not
participate together in the group's activities for fear of 'erotic'
attractions between boys and girls? -- they are indeed such a group;
they are, after all, the *Boy* Scouts, and (let's assume) part of their
reasons for being the Boy Scouts rather than the Child Scouts is
precisely to eliminate intragroup heterosexual erotic attractions.  Like
our view or not, they say, but it's our deeply felt conscientious view,
and subject to protection under RFRA by way of Seeger/Welsh.  (I don't
see what VMI has to say about this, since that simply says that the
government may not discriminate based on sex in government operations.)

All this is directly related to an article I'm writing, so I'd
love to hear more people's views on this subject!

Eugene


 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Tuesday, February 28, 2006 1:03 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: State RFRA and nonreligious groups that 
 haveconscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws
 
 
 I am troubled by your Boy Scouts hypo.  First, how does this 
 group have standing to raise a religious freedom claim?  What 
 is the Boy Scout's religion?  Dale was about associational 
 rights, not religion-based rights.  Second, when you 
 introduce possible erotic attractions, you load the dice.  
 What about a group that claimed that boys and girls should 
 not participate together in the group's activities for fear 
 of erotic attractions between boys and girls?  VMI ought to 
 settle this, shouldn't it?
 
 Isn't the first hypo easy?  Has the ministerial exception 
 vanished into thin air?  What about EEOC v. Catholic University?
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Monday, February 27, 2006 7:27 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: State RFRA and nonreligious groups that have 
 conscientiousobjections to antidiscrimination laws
 
   Say that a state has a RFRA that's written much like 
 the federal RFRA.  And say that a state or local government 
 body decides to exclude all groups that discriminate based on 
 race, sex, etc. in selecting officers, speakers, or members 
 from various benefit programs (access to government property, 
 access to fundraising drives, access to schools, etc.).
 
   1.  The Catholic Church is excluded from the benefit 
 because it discriminates based on sex in selecting priests.  
 It raises a RFRA objection to the exclusion, arguing that it 
 has a sincere religious belief that only men may be priests.  
 What should the result be?
 
   2.  The Boy Scouts are excluded from the benefit 
 because it discriminates based on sexual orientation in 
 selecting scoutmasters and members.  It raises a RFRA 
 objection to the exclusion, arguing that it has a deeply felt 
 conscientious belief that it would be wrong for them to put 
 homosexuals in role modeling positions, or that it would be 
 wrong for them to put young boys in positions where there is 
 especially likely to be erotic attraction between them (as 
 there is if some of the members are known to be homosexual).  
 This is a belief based on our religious traditions, the Scout 
 leadership says; and in any event, even if that's not 
 religious enough (since we belong to so many different 
 religious traditions), it's based on deeply held 
 conscientious beliefs, see Seeger and Welsh.  What should the 
 result be?
 
   Eugene
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, 
 see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives

RE: Breaking news in federal RFRA case

2006-02-24 Thread Newsom Michael








I will just note that Congress has the
discretion to decide how to handle the matter. You just dont agree with
the approach that Congress took. 











From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, February 24, 2006
10:48 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Breaking news in
federal RFRA case









Read the legislative history behind RFRA
from beginning to end --the administration of illegal drugs to children
by religious groupsis not there. It is awholesale
reconstruction of history to believethat Congress considered the issue in
any way, shape, or form. The vast majority, i.e., over 95%, of the
legislative history involves castigating the Supreme Court for Smith. The
practical consequences of RFRA were never approached, because Congress's
purpose was to reverse a Supreme Court decision, without any meaningful
consideration of what that would accomplish at a policy level. Now, there
are post hoc justifications for RFRA proffered all around, but they do not
displace what Congress actually considered and actually knew at the time it was
enacted. 











As to policy choices,it is my view
that RFRA isunsound constitutionally and policy-wise, but the latter does
not underminethe former. 











And, yes, the placement of a drug on
Schedule I does, indeed, end the discussion when the drugis being
administered to minors. The fact the drugs were delivered in a religious
context does not change the extraordinary interest of the children.











Marci

















In a message dated 2/23/2006 2:36:19 P.M.
Eastern Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:





You assume that the placement of a drug on Schedule I ends the
discussion. I hope that you do not think that it is jesting to suppose
that that placement does not end the discussion. Congress surely must
have some sense of the consequences of its decisions (1) to place the drug on
Schedule I and (2) to enact RFRA.
















___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Breaking news in federal RFRA case

2006-02-23 Thread Newsom Michael








You assume that the placement of a drug on
Schedule I ends the discussion. I hope that you do not think that it is
jesting to suppose that that placement does not end the discussion. Congress
surely must have some sense of the consequences of its decisions (1) to place
the drug on Schedule I and (2) to enact RFRA.



Thus the accommodation, by your view is blind.
But not by mine, or by Congress, for aught that appears.



Why is the enactment of RFRA any more formalistic
than the enactment of the drug law that establishes Schedule I?



Isnt the truth of the matter that you
have one policy perspective, one that, apparently, is not shared by Congress?











From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, February 22, 2006
7:58 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Breaking news in
federal RFRA case









I hope the paragraph belowwas in
jest. Schedule Idrugs are drugs that are considered to have no
beneficial use and to be dangerous. If children are drinking the
DMTin the tea, they are the victims of child abuse. I cannot
believe thatanyone on this listis willing to give a group a pass in
abusing children just because it is religious.It is one thing for adults
to choose to take such drugs, but quite another for that group to provide the
drugs to children.











With respect to RFRA, it's error lies in
its blind accommodation. It is a blind handout to religion. As I
argue in God vs the Gavel, I have no problem with legislative accommodation,
and in fact in many circumstances support it.But to be
legitimate,it must be passed pursuant to consideration of the public good
(i.e., Congress fulfilled its constitutionally appointed duty to make policy
choices) and not be merely, as RFRA was, a special interest gift. I may
disagree with the public policy balance, which is a wholly different
matter. Under RFRA, Congress shuffles those hard policy choices over to
the courts.











The defenses of RFRA as responsible
congressional enactment are formalistic in the extreme.











Marci

















In a message dated 2/22/2006 6:19:26 P.M.
Eastern Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:





I dont know how important it is that minors drink the tea.
Why is drinking it per se bad for minors, or for anybody else? It is only
bad because Congress said it was, at least as a general proposition.
However, Congress can properly decide to allow for a little play in the joints,
cant it? You seem to want to hem in Congress policy discretion on
matters of this sort, and there is no Constitutional basis for doing so.
If Congress passes bad  but constitutional  laws, then the answer is to elect
a different Congress. 


















___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Breaking news in federal RFRA case

2006-02-22 Thread Newsom Michael








I think that it is too early to tell one
way or the other. Dont forget that he has a wily antagonist, if that is
not too strong a word, in Justice Stevens.











From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, February 21, 2006
11:24 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Breaking news in
federal RFRA case







Can anything be read into the unanimous
nature of the opinion and Roberts being its author...Is this some indication
that Roberts is going to be a consensus builder on at least certain issues?











Donald C. Clark, Jr.
Counselor at Law
Bannockburn Lake Office
 Plaza I
2333 Waukegan Road
Suite 160
Bannockburn, Illinois 60015
(847) 236-0900 (telephone)
(847) 236-0909 (facsimiles)








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Breaking news in federal RFRA case

2006-02-22 Thread Newsom Michael








The Congress and the President that
enacted RFRA thought, rightly or wrongly, that there was a palpable, and not
lurking, constitutional error. On that point I agree with that Congress
and that President. But even if there were an error on the constitutional
point, it does not matter, unless your position is that Congress cannot, in the
exercise of policy-based discretion, decide that the Courts have to do the job
that Roberts wry comments referred to. In any event, the Court
ruled 8-0 that Congress could.



Your basic objection, which you have
repeated many times, is, if I have it right, that a number of police power
health, safety and regulatory concerns properly, if not necessasrily, trump the
autonomy claims of religious individuals and persons. That may or may not
be right, but surely doesnt Congress get to decide whether this is true
or not either as a general proposition or in specific cases? After all
Congress is the source of the relevant regulatory regimes in the first place.



I dont know how important it is
that minors drink the tea. Why is drinking it per se bad for minors, or
for anybody else? It is only bad because Congress said it was, at least
as a general proposition. However, Congress can properly decide to allow
for a little play in the joints, cant it? You seem to want to hem
in Congress policy discretion on matters of this sort, and there is no
Constitutional basis for doing so. If Congress passes bad  but constitutional
 laws, then the answer is to elect a different Congress. 















From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, February 21, 2006
12:49 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Breaking news in
federal RFRA case









I am not going to belabor the point,
Marty, but I strongly disagree with your interpretation of the application of
standards of review. The strict scrutiny standard puts the courts in the
business of second-guessing legislative judgment, normally where there is a
lurking constitutional violation. RFRA strict scrutiny is not triggered
by any lurking constitutional error, but rather bare second-guessing.
Trying to normalize what RFRA demands -- imposition of a constitutional
standard of review through legislation(which is only reflected in RLUIPA)
is a mistake in my view.











In this case in particular, the
inadequacies of the courts are shown. The Supreme Court was in no
position to investigate whether this drug is different from peyote, or, more
importantly from my point of view, whether the drug is routinely given to
minors (as it is). Had this specific exemption request been part of a
legislative inquiry, the regular use by minors could have been taken into account,
and, I presume, the compelling interest for denying its use documented.
There was no place for such an inquiry in the Court'sappellate review.
In any event, the Court is absolutely right that the federal government
asked for it, and here they have it.











Marci

















In a message dated 2/21/2006 12:29:30
P.M. Eastern Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:







I know we've been over this ground many
times, but perhaps it's still worth clarifying:











It's not a delegation of a
policy decision -- it's asking the courts to apply a legal
standard. For instance, in this case, it was Congress that decided that the
sky would not fall with the peyote exemption, and the federal government that
failed to explain why the harms in this case would be any worse or different
than in the peyote case. This was basic analogic reasoning, applying a
statutory standard --everyday stuff for the judiciary. Nor was it
beyond the Court's ken to conclude -- correctly -- that the exemption would not be
required if the treaty-based consequences would be severe, but that
thegovernment had not demonstrated that the consequences of breaching
the treaty would in fact be as draconian as the State Department alleged.


















___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Draft ID statutory language

2006-01-26 Thread Newsom Michael
Title: Message








With respect, I have a great deal of
difficulty in understanding this proposed language, and its purpose. I have a
great deal of concern about its probable effects or consequences. Let me just
pose three questions for now.



First, what is actual creation?
Without knowing what that means, it is impossible to assess the duty that the
first paragraph would impose on public school teachers. With regard to the
second paragraph, why single out evolution/ID? Isnt there far more to
teaching ABOUT religion than that? The focus is worrisome. Also with respect
to the second paragraph, how are you going to enforce the prohibition contained
in the proviso? 











From: Gibbens, Daniel
G. [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, January 26, 2006
12:48 AM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Draft ID statutory
language







Belowisdraft language fora billfor
our state legislature in light of pro-ID bills filed. Although the
deadline has passed for bill-filing this session,some
thinksomething of this sort may havefuture use. So comments
and criticismare requested.











Obviously the draft is an effort under the rubric of
pragmatism. It does not address critical issues such as
thedefinition for public school purposes of science, or
what's involved in teaching about religion. On the latter
issue, it simply relies on Brennan's concurring opinion in Schempp.













A. In courses presenting science-based information
pertaining to the development processes of life forms, including evolution
theory, or the development processes of physical matter, including big bang theory,
public school teachersshall make clear that there is no scientific
information available about the actual creation or origin of either; provided
that related religion-based information, including intelligent design theory,
shall not be presented in such courses.





B.
In non-science courses such as history, literature, and social studies, public
school teachers may present information about religion, about differences
between religious sects, and about religion-based views on the creation, origin
or development processes of life forms or of physical matter, including
intelligent design theory; provided that such teaching neither treats religion
or religious views as truth or as ignorance, nor promotes nor discriminates
against religion generally, any particular set of religious beliefs, or any
negative views about religion.







Dan Gibbens





University of Oklahoma
 College of Law





[EMAIL PROTECTED]











-Original
Message-
From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wednesday, January 18, 2006
7:57 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: School
 District drops Intelligent Design Class





I don't think is so hard to enforce. Most people most of the time
follow guidelines and this should be no different. We should not ban
something just because sometimes people stray across a fuzzy boundary
inadvertently or just because some people will intentionally try to abuse the
guidelines and further their own agendas. 













This desire for purity in this area baffles me. It is not
possible. We ought not fail to do or allow something just because it can
sometimes be abused. And we ought not fail to teach something or allow
something to be taught just because some people will be upset or draw the line
differently.











Steve











On Jan 18, 2006, at 6:39 PM, Newsom Michael wrote:









This
is, of course, the central problem: how to enforce the distinction between
teaching about religion and teaching religion. Enforcement, it strikes
me, is insuperably difficult. How does one make sure that the teachers do
not breach the line, and how does one make sure that the curriculum, or lesson
plan does not breach the line?



I am not sure, therefore, that one can reasonably assume that
teaching about religion will not become, in far too many cases, teaching
religion. Thus why should one favor teaching about religion in the public
elementary and secondary schools at all?









Prof. Steven D. Jamar   
  
vox: 202-806-8017

Howard University School of Law 
fax: 202-806-8428

2900 Van Ness Street NW
 mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]

Washington, DC
 20008
 http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar
























___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: teaching about religion in the public schools

2006-01-26 Thread Newsom Michael








The problem is just not the nature of the difficulties
teaching about religion necessarily raises, but also the problem of enforcement.
It does no good if the teachers will not abide by the resolution of the sticky
problems made by the appropriate school or other officials  including judges.











From: Sisk, Gregory C.
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, January 26, 2006
3:30 PM
To: 'Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: teaching about
religion in the public schools





(Note that I dont understand Alan
here to be saying otherwise, I was just using his post as a springboard to
anticipate the argument that some may make, and have made in the past, that
these kinds of sticky problems prove the impossibility and impropriety of
teaching about religion in public schools.)



Greg Sisk








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: School District drops Intelligent Design Class

2006-01-23 Thread Newsom Michael








We agree on the question of goals and
objectives, as set out in paragraphs 1 and 2. I still am not convinced,
however, that most teachers will be monitored, even informally, to make sure
that they act in accordance with our agreed upon goals and objectives.



It may be, in the final analysis,
necessary to grant that some aspects or subjects of learning, even the learning
that we need for the kind of civic culture that we want, may have to take place
outside of the common schools. I tend to favor national service of one
kind or another as a way of addressing some of those aspects or subjects.
At the same time, I recognize that this is an imperfect solution, and I may be
more resigned than you to muddling through, being dependent upon imperfect and
incomplete answers and strategies. (All of which makes my idealistic side
very uncomfortable, to say the least.) 











From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, January 19, 2006
4:48 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: School
 District drops Intelligent Design Class







Michael
raises important issues. But I think we eviscerate the idea of a civic culture
in a diverse, deliberative democracy if we capitulate to those more interested
in teaching conclusions than inquiry, or more perspicuously stated, more
interest in teaching conclusions incompatible with the conclusions and forms of
inquiry flowing from republican democracy. Except for some unpersuasive
postmodern critiques I don't believe there existarguments demonstrating
that connecting republican democracy and certain forms of education-and
excluding others--are impossible or unattractive. And while no parent should be
compelled to send her child to a publica (civic) school, I'm not terribly
sensitive to the argument that the government should pay parents to send their
children to private schools that are more concernedwith teaching
conclusions than forms of inquiry. Democracy requires a particular form of
civic culture, one that should be as open, diverse, and tolerant as is consistent
with maintaining that culture in the first place. For me, that places a heavy
burden to support public schools whether or not you send your child there.











I
have a child with special educational needs that the state, though required by
law to provide, does not. Thus, I have spent tens of thousands of dollars
to send her to private schools. That's my choice. I fully recognize my
responsibility asa taxpayer to support the public schools, and to make
theme as competitive and comprehensive as possible. In my view, I have a
political obligation to so whether or not my child benefits from them.











I
think there exist informal means of monitoring someone teaching a course in
philosophy or religion which discuss creationism, ID, the ontological proof of
the existence of God, the argument of evil, and so forth. The goal, in my view,
would be to teach these issues trying with all one's pedagogical skills to
argue that each issue is true and each issue is false. Let the children then
decide.











Bobby

Robert Justin Lipkin
Professor of Law
Widener University School
of Law
Delaware








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: School District drops Intelligent Design Class

2006-01-19 Thread Newsom Michael








Bobby, as they say in the hood, I
feel ya. I couldnt agree more that parenting and teaching
should be about teaching the child to develop thoughtful opinions
independently. I think, however, that there are many parents

and teachers who do not agree with us.
Some of the rhetoric bandied about these days tends to support that conclusion.



I suspect that we may disagree as to the
numbers and as to the depth of the feelings of those who are opposed to what
you and I believe in. And I think that that disagreement leads us to
rather different conclusions about how to think about teaching about religion.



This in turn leads to the most difficult
question in the law: on what basis can we fashion rules when lacking a
sufficient empirical basis for making informed rule choices? This
question never goes away for not even the most extreme formalist can completely
divorce himself or herself from the real world. (Indeed, I would never
suppose that, deep down inside, they really want to. Well leave
the motives of formalists for another discussion.)









From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, January 18, 2006
7:18 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: School
 District drops Intelligent Design Class







The
answer to Michael's pertinent question is critical. I suppose we know only what
to rule out, for example, I believe this is the class that the Lord
wanted me to teach. In my view, teaching in general should
stimulate(provoke respectfully and sensitively), and basically being more
concerned about assisting the student to derivehis or her own thoughtful
opinions independently. Teaching, I suppose, is similar to parenting. One
should want the student (child) to develop the critical and passionate capacity
to think for themselves even if the substantive conclusions are not your
own.Is there some litmusto





make sure that we have such a
teacher or are such a parent? No! At least not some general principle. But
then again, as in many other important pursuits, we develop intuitive
guidelines, which we shouldalways be ready to revise and refine.











My
point was imply this. That as both a teacher and a parent I want my
students and my daughter to be exposed to religious, social, political, and
scientific controversies by those whose primary stake in the controversy is not
getting the student or child to think asthe adult does, but rather to
think for themselves. It's inconceivable to me that in the public square
of a deliberative democracy we should seek anything else. Do I want my daughter
to adopt my fundamental values? Well, of course I do. But do I
think my parental responsibility should take the form of trying to persuade her
with whatever ratiocinative powers I possess that my substantive values are
correct. Absolutely not, except for one fundamental value, namely, that
pursuing justified convictions, where justified clearly refers to
some inter-subjective practice that others should be able to confirm and
respond to, is presumptively more important than a commitment to some set of
substantive results.











Bobby

Robert Justin Lipkin
Professor of Law
Widener University School
of Law
Delaware








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: School District drops Intelligent Design Class

2006-01-19 Thread Newsom Michael








Your answer depends on a judgment about
the likelihood of crossing the line from teaching about religion to teaching
religion. Sometimes is too elusive and slippery a word, and it
does not help us think through the problem.











From: Steven Jamar 
Sent: Wednesday, January 18, 2006
8:57 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: School
 District drops Intelligent Design Class





I don't think is so hard to enforce. Most people most of the time
follow guidelines and this should be no different. We should not ban
something just because sometimes people stray across a fuzzy boundary
inadvertently or just because some people will intentionally try to abuse the
guidelines and further their own agendas.













This desire for purity in this area baffles me. It is not
possible. We ought not fail to do or allow something just because it can
sometimes be abused. And we ought not fail to teach something or allow
something to be taught just because some people will be upset or draw the line
differently.











Steve











On Jan 18, 2006, at 6:39 PM, Newsom Michael wrote:









This
is, of course, the central problem: how to enforce the distinction between
teaching about religion and teaching religion. Enforcement, it strikes
me, is insuperably difficult. How does one make sure that the teachers do
not breach the line, and how does one make sure that the curriculum, or lesson
plan does not breach the line?



I am not sure, therefore, that one can reasonably assume that
teaching about religion will not become, in far too many cases, teaching
religion. Thus why should one favor teaching about religion in the public
elementary and secondary schools at all?











--

Prof. Steven D. Jamar  
  
 vox: 202-806-8017

Howard University School of Law 
fax: 202-806-8428

2900 Van Ness Street NW   
 
mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]

Washington, DC
 20008   
  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar



A word is not a crystal, transparent and unchanged, it is
the skin of a living thought and may vary greatly in color and content
according to the circumstances and the time in which it is used.



Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes in Towne v. Eisner, 245 U.S. 418, 425
(1918)




















___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

2006-01-18 Thread Newsom Michael
For an interest to be compelling does a state have to be prepared to
bankrupt itself?

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 8:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

If the interest is so compelling, why does the statute allow an employer
to
ignore it -- to avoid having to pay for prescription contraceptives --
simply by dropping all prescription drug coverage? (Catholic Charities
could
have done so, but it believed that it had a religious duty to provide
quality health insurance to its employees; thus it was unwilling to drop
prescription drug coverage from its health insurance plan. In fact it
viewed
that duty as a stronger duty than the duty not to pay for prescription
contraceptives.)

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law
 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:34 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

I don't think that the constitution requires the state to bankrupt
itself
for fear of offending the Religion Clauses.  There has to be some play
in
the joints, and some concern, however slight, for the poor taxpayers.

Why isn't the interest compelling?  There is a variety of public health,
fiscal, financial, psychological and other reasons to support the claim
that
the state has a compelling interest in the matter.  But, of course,
these
reasons are progressive or -- gasp! -- liberal.

I am not arguing for or against an exemption. My point is simply that
there
is a good reason for the interference or intrusion that Mark finds
troubling.

 


-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 1:16 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

If the state's interest is simply in satisfying the
contraceptive
needs of its residents, why isn't providing contraceptive insurance
directly
-- whether to all residents, employed or not, to all residents who
aren't
already covered, or to all residents who lose coverage as a result of an
exemption -- a less restrictive means of serving that interest?  Or is
it
the case that any time an alternative would require spending some more
money, it doesn't count as a prospective less restrictive alternative?

On the other hand, if the state's interest is in enforcing an
employer's supposed obligation to its employees, the law here would be
well-tailored to that interest; but why is that interest so compelling?

I don't think this means that a religious exemption is mandated
-- under Smith, it wouldn't be (unless a court finds impermissible
religious
discrimination, which presumably wouldn't be constitutional in any event
absent some very strict scrutiny, stricter than the feeble
Sherbert/Yoder-era scrutiny).  But if strict scrutiny is really the
right
regime, I'm not sure that the interest in helping residents get
contraception is sufficient to justify the law.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom 
 Michael
 Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:07 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to 
 ContraceptionLaw
 
 
 I think that the state has a strong, and perhaps compelling, interest 
 in the contraceptive needs of employers.  Starting from that position,

 it is easy to justify the intervention, at least as an initial 
 proposition. In other words, I find this problem to be extremely 
 difficult, put perhaps not troubling, at least so far.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Scarberry, Mark [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Sunday, January 15, 2006 8:48 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics '
 Subject: RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to 
 ContraceptionLaw
 
 In response to Marty:
 
 First, one might ask what interest of the state in providing for 
 contraceptive needs of employees, or what part of the merits of 
 providing the employer with an exemption, is implicated by the section

 of the Internal Revenue Code chosen by the organization under which it

 receives its tax exempt status. That was never clear to me.
 
 Second, suppose the inappropriate criterion were as follows: 
 No social services group associated with the Roman Catholic Church 
 shall qualify for the exemption. Wouldn't such a criterion show that 
 the statutory scheme was designed to discriminate against a particular

 religious group because of its religion? And wouldn't such proof be 
 fatal to the scheme?
 
 The targeting of Catholic Charities by way of the four criteria in the

 statute -- including the impermissible ones
 -- is nearly as clear

RE: School District drops Intelligent Design Class

2006-01-18 Thread Newsom Michael








How do we make sure that we have teachers
who think teaching the controversies is more important than guaranteeing that the
students adopt a particular substantive resolution?











From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, January 18, 2006
3:46 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: School
 District drops Intelligent Design Class







Okay,
there are problematic facts which makes this case of poor example of the point
I'm advocating. However, I think it's a positive good to have the hot-buttons
issues, creationism, ID, the problem of evil, and other arguments against the
plausibility and even intelligibility of the existence of the Abrahamic God,
and a host of other issues taught in a fair and balanced manner in high school.
Because some people want to use these issues to indoctrinate (I believe
this is the class that the Lord wanted me to teach.), is no reason not to
expose adolescents to these controversies taught by teachers who think teaching
thecontroversies is more important than guaranteeing that the students
adopt a particular substantive resolution.











Bobby

Robert Justin Lipkin
Professor of Law
Widener University School
of Law
Delaware








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Evaluation of people's religious beliefs

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael
Protestantism is clearly the point of departure.  There can be no
reasonable argument against that fact because virtually everybody who
has taken a serious look at America's religious history reaches the same
conclusion, and, of course, I think that they are right.  The point is
that Protestant norms help define the mainstream, a concept that is
meaningless without context.

My point is as much pragmatic as it is principled, and, on the normative
question, I think that courts would make the distinction precisely
because of the fact that Protestantism is the point of departure in
establishing the norms that guide pragmatic judgments.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Saturday, January 14, 2006 4:58 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Evaluation of people's religious beliefs

I don't quite see how Protestantism as such has much to do with
this.  My guess is that, descriptively, the line is between mainstream
beliefs and weird beliefs.  Mainstream Protestant, Catholic, and in
some measure Jewish assertions about supernatural events largely
overlap, but when there are differences, I doubt that these differences
would end up being descriptively relevant:  A court would be as
troubled, I think, by an employer's failing to hire someone because of
that someone's quintessentially Catholic belief in intercession in
temporal matters by saints or the Virgin Mary, as by an employer's
failing to hire someone because of that someone's more broadly Christian
belief in the virgin birth.

Yet this leaves the normative question:  *Should* courts act
differently when (1) a government employer refuses to hire someone
because the employer thinks that someone's mainstream religious belief
bespeaks irrationality or craziness (i.e., I don't want to hire this
person, because he [Catholic/Protestant/Orthodox/other Christian]
believes in the Virgin Birth) than when (2) a government employer
employer refuses to hire someone because the employer thinks that
someone's weird religious belief bespeaks irrationality or craziness
(i.e., I don't want to hire this person, because he believes that God
told him about space aliens / werewolves / the end of the world coming
in 3 years)?

Eugene



 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Friday, January 13, 2006 1:43 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Evaluation of people's religious beliefs
 
 
 Eugene, I think that the real-world answer is your #4.  I 
 think that the law contains some normative propositions about 
 religious belief.  You know that I start from the Protestant 
 Empire premise.  But you don't have to agree with me as to 
 the continued existence of the Protestant Empire (I know that 
 we will soon have a right-wing Catholic majority on the 
 SCOTUS, but that is really another discussion) to agree that the
 *origins* of these propositions rest in evangelical 
 Protestantism of the British sort.  In your hypo, the beliefs 
 are so far removed from the core normative propositions and 
 any reasonable variations on their thematic content as to put 
 them, literally, beyond the pale, in my opinion.  (I don't 
 know whether in your hypo this is a good or a bad result, 
 although I lean to the former over the latter for entirely 
 pragmatic reasons in part having to do with something 
 resembling a concern for social order, or at least wear and 
 tear of the social fabric.  When it comes both to children 
 and the workplace, don't we tend to have reasonable concerns 
 and worries about whackiness?) 
 
 (I might add by way of a belated response to Perry's 
 interesting analysis of line-drawing, (I love the parsonage 
 example) that the problem of neutrality/equality flounders on 
 the shoals of these normative propositions that have the 
 effect or redesigning the playing field in such a way that 
 neutrality/equality often goes by the boards. For what it is 
 worth, Catholics are not the only ones who essentially 
 require that clergy live in church-provided housing.  Many 
 Episcopalian parishes come remarkably close to this 
 bottom-line result. Other Protestant groups may do so as 
 well.  And, regarding the priest-penitent privilege, my 
 recollection is that the early American courts may have had 
 some difficulty in accepting or recognizing the privilege, 
 or, if they accepted it, saw virtue and utility in it for 
 Protestants as well.  But on this I could be wrong.)  
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Friday, January 13, 2006 1:44 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Evaluation of people's religious beliefs
 
   Thinking some more about my First Amendment / child 
 custody paper brought me to this question:
 
   Government officials in various situations have to 
 evaluate people's overall

RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael


-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Sunday, January 15, 2006 8:48 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics '
Subject: RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

In response to Marty:

First, one might ask what interest of the state in providing for
contraceptive needs of employees, or what part of the merits of
providing
the employer with an exemption, is implicated by the section of the
Internal
Revenue Code chosen by the organization under which it receives its tax
exempt status. That was never clear to me.

Second, suppose the inappropriate criterion were as follows: No social
services group associated with the Roman Catholic Church shall qualify
for
the exemption. Wouldn't such a criterion show that the statutory scheme
was
designed to discriminate against a particular religious group because of
its
religion? And wouldn't such proof be fatal to the scheme?

The targeting of Catholic Charities by way of the four criteria in the
statute -- including the impermissible ones -- is nearly as clear as if
the
statute had included that hypothetical language. Floor statements of
California legislators also make it clear that they did not like the
Church's position on contraception and that the statutory scheme was
designed specifically to force the Church to violate its precepts. After
all, as the legislators stated, you could be a good Catholic without
following the Church's teaching on contraception. 

That religious intervention by the state is deeply troubling to me, as I
believe it should be to other members of the list.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Marty Lederman
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Sent: 1/15/2006 4:24 PM
Subject: Re: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

Alan writes that having one or more inappropriate criterion taints the
entire accommodation provision.
 
Why?
 
Let's say, as apparently was the case in the Catholic Charities case,
that the requirement of specified tax status would, standing alone, be a
perfectly permissible criterion, and the plaintiffs do not satisfy that
criterion.  That disqualifies them for the exemption right there.  Why
should the outcome change just because another of the criteria --
superfluous for an employer who doesn't qualify under the tax-status
criterion -- would be unconstitutional standing alone? 

[snip]
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael
I think that the state has a strong, and perhaps compelling, interest in
the contraceptive needs of employers.  Starting from that position, it
is easy to justify the intervention, at least as an initial proposition.
In other words, I find this problem to be extremely difficult, put
perhaps not troubling, at least so far.

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Sunday, January 15, 2006 8:48 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics '
Subject: RE: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

In response to Marty:

First, one might ask what interest of the state in providing for
contraceptive needs of employees, or what part of the merits of
providing
the employer with an exemption, is implicated by the section of the
Internal
Revenue Code chosen by the organization under which it receives its tax
exempt status. That was never clear to me.

Second, suppose the inappropriate criterion were as follows: No social
services group associated with the Roman Catholic Church shall qualify
for
the exemption. Wouldn't such a criterion show that the statutory scheme
was
designed to discriminate against a particular religious group because of
its
religion? And wouldn't such proof be fatal to the scheme?

The targeting of Catholic Charities by way of the four criteria in the
statute -- including the impermissible ones -- is nearly as clear as if
the
statute had included that hypothetical language. Floor statements of
California legislators also make it clear that they did not like the
Church's position on contraception and that the statutory scheme was
designed specifically to force the Church to violate its precepts. After
all, as the legislators stated, you could be a good Catholic without
following the Church's teaching on contraception. 

That religious intervention by the state is deeply troubling to me, as I
believe it should be to other members of the list.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Marty Lederman
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Sent: 1/15/2006 4:24 PM
Subject: Re: N.Y. Court Rejects Employers' Challenge to ContraceptionLaw

Alan writes that having one or more inappropriate criterion taints the
entire accommodation provision.
 
Why?
 
Let's say, as apparently was the case in the Catholic Charities case,
that the requirement of specified tax status would, standing alone, be a
perfectly permissible criterion, and the plaintiffs do not satisfy that
criterion.  That disqualifies them for the exemption right there.  Why
should the outcome change just because another of the criteria --
superfluous for an employer who doesn't qualify under the tax-status
criterion -- would be unconstitutional standing alone? 

[snip]
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael








There is a way of testing what is happening
here: why not have the state acquire the property and then rebuild the
structure and maintain it as some sort of museum? (The state could, of course,
seek contributions from private individuals and groups to help meet the costs
of rebuilding.) The Turks have done something like that, I think, with Hagia
Sophia. I have been in Hagia Sophia and my recollection is that the structure
is now essentially a museum, neither a basilica nor a mosque. If the state of Illinois rejects this
solution, then maybe there is a serious EC problem here. 











From: David E. Guinn
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Sunday, January 15, 2006
9:41 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Pilgrim Baptist
 Church







You wrote:











Nevertheless, even if the sort of
formal neutrality rule espoused in Thomas's Mitchell
plurality becomes the governing doctrine, as I think it will, these cases are
still difficult, because there's nothing neutral, or objective, about the
decision to fund the rebuilding of the Pilgrim Baptist
 Church. Illinois presumably does
not rebuild all buildings destroyed by fire, or all community
services buildings, or all churches, for that matter. The decision
to rebuild this particular structure is very subjective, and
discretionary. I suppose it's possible that the decision to fund would be
made completely without regard to the building's status as a church, but that
seems unlikely, no?: Isn't it at least a strong possibility that the
state would not pledge a million dollars if the building had never been a
synagogue and church? And if its religious status is part of
the reason for the pledge, isn't that a form of religious favoritism that is
problematic under the EC, even if the Thomas view prevails? 

















I agree that this may be classified as
discretionary. However, I do not necessarily believe that it is driven
strictly out of concern for the fact that it is a church or synagogue. Illinois -- and Chicago
in particular -- is very attentive to its architectural heritage. In this
case, the Church not only has cultural significance to the religious community,
but it is also valued for its connection with Adler and Sullivan. Louis
Sullivan is a particularly revered architect here in Chicago. I do believe that the state
has funded renovation and reconstruction costs for building by Frank Lloyd
Wright, Sullivan and other famous architects.











I think the equal protection argument
lies in the fact that this building is valued according to secular standards by
people independent of the the church as a architectural gem worthy of
protection. One may or may not add its historical relevance to Chicago to the judgement.











David



































- Original Message - 





From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 





To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 





Sent: Sunday, January 15, 2006 8:09 PM





Subject: Re: Pilgrim
 Baptist Church













The case I've seen cited
on this issue is Committee
for Public Ed.  Religious Liberty v. Nyquist, 413
U.S. 756, 777 (1973) which says:











If the State may not erect buildings in which
religious activities are to take place, it may not maintain such buildings or
renovate them when they fall into disrepair.
Full text at:











http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/cgi-bin/getcase.pl?navby=casecourt=usvol=413invol=756#777











See also Tilton v. Richardson, 403 U.S. 672, 678
(1971) available at:











http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/cgi-bin/getcase.pl?navby=casecourt=usvol=403invol=672#678

















For a Bush Administration view, see the
2003 DOJ memo titled AUTHORITY OF THE DEPARTMENT OF THE INTERIOR TO
PROVIDE HISTORIC PRESERVATION GRANTS TO HISTORIC RELIGIOUS PROPERTIES SUCH AS
THE OLD NORTH CHURCH, at:











http://www.usdoj.gov/olc/OldNorthChurch.htm











Hope that helps











Allen Asch











In a message dated 1/15/2006 3:56:48 PM
Pacific Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:





I trust that many members of the list may
have heard about the tragic fire 
at the Pilgrim Baptist Church.
The church, designed by the firm of Adler 
and Sullivan, started life as a major synacoge on the South side of Chicago 
that was eventually taken over by the Pigrim Baptist Congration. 
Interestingly, the new congregation did not strip the decorative features of 
the synagogue but instead simply added christian decorative features.

The church became a leading institution within the Black community in 
Chicago and was
the birth place of gospel music. It has also become a 
significant stop on the many archetectural tours that Chicago is famous for. 
The attached link describes the virtues of the building and the need to 
rebuild.
http://www.chicagotribune.com/news/opinion/chi-0601150287jan15,1,4394171.story?coll=chi-opinionfront-hed

You may have also heard about the controversy. As the news reports puts
it: 
Gov. Rod 

RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael
Doesn't Boerne answer the question posed in your second paragraph?

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, January 16, 2006 11:59 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

Marty makes an excellent point here.  I think (though I'm not sure
that Marty does) that it would be outrageous if, when a state *does*
rebuild all buildings, or help rebuild them, or provides other services
short of rebuilding (e.g., taxpayer-paid internal sprinkler
installation, partly subsidized earthquake retrofitting, etc.), it
nonetheless excluded churches, synagogues, homes that are used for
regular synagogue meetings or Bible study, and the like.  Yet surely
there is a risk here that the state is indeed preferring religious
buildings; even if there's no deliberate desire to help religion because
religion is somehow good, many people who are trying to evaluate a
building's historic status may well be understandably influenced by
that building's being religious, since religious buildings are often
seen as especially important to a community and to the community's
history.

Yet would this go the other way, too?  Would landmarking ordinances
that *burden* the property owner, by barring it from reconstructing the
building, thus be per se unconstitutional under the Free Exercise Clause
when applied to churches and the like, on the theory that there's no
neutrality here?

Eugene



Marty Lederman writes:

Nevertheless, even if the sort of formal neutrality rule espoused in
Thomas's Mitchell plurality becomes the governing doctrine, as I think
it will, these cases are still difficult, because there's nothing
neutral, or objective, about the decision to fund the rebuilding of the
Pilgrim Baptist Church.  Illinois presumably does not rebuild all
buildings destroyed by fire, or all community services buildings, or
all churches, for that matter.  The decision to rebuild this particular
structure is very subjective, and discretionary.  I suppose it's
possible that the decision to fund would be made completely without
regard to the building's status as a church, but that seems unlikely,
no?:  Isn't it at least a strong possibility that the state would not
pledge a million dollars if the building had never been a synagogue and
church?  And if its religious status is part of the reason for the
pledge, isn't that a form of religious favoritism that is problematic
under the EC, even if the Thomas view prevails? 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael
You may be right, in a technical sense.  The Court limited itself to the
RFRA claim.  But the case suggests to me that the Court would probably
not be receptive to a claim on the (landmarks preservation) merits made
by the Church.  I am not remembering the aftermath of the case very
well, but it seems to me that the Church basically lost, on the merits.
Finally, if I am remembering the cases correctly, objections to
landmarking by churches usually fail, even though landmarking imposes
burdens on the churches. 

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 1:26 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

I'm not sure I quite understand -- why would it answer that
question?  If I recall correctly, this issue wasn't passed on by the
Court.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:18 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
 
 
 Doesn't Boerne answer the question posed in your second paragraph?
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Monday, January 16, 2006 11:59 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
 
 Marty makes an excellent point here.  I think (though I'm 
 not sure that Marty does) that it would be outrageous if, 
 when a state *does* rebuild all buildings, or help rebuild 
 them, or provides other services short of rebuilding (e.g., 
 taxpayer-paid internal sprinkler installation, partly 
 subsidized earthquake retrofitting, etc.), it nonetheless 
 excluded churches, synagogues, homes that are used for 
 regular synagogue meetings or Bible study, and the like.  Yet 
 surely there is a risk here that the state is indeed 
 preferring religious buildings; even if there's no deliberate 
 desire to help religion because religion is somehow good, 
 many people who are trying to evaluate a building's 
 historic status may well be understandably influenced by 
 that building's being religious, since religious buildings 
 are often seen as especially important to a community and to 
 the community's history.
 
 Yet would this go the other way, too?  Would landmarking 
 ordinances that *burden* the property owner, by barring it 
 from reconstructing the building, thus be per se 
 unconstitutional under the Free Exercise Clause when applied 
 to churches and the like, on the theory that there's no 
 neutrality here?
 
 Eugene
 
 
 
 Marty Lederman writes:
 
 Nevertheless, even if the sort of formal neutrality rule 
 espoused in Thomas's Mitchell plurality becomes the governing 
 doctrine, as I think it will, these cases are still 
 difficult, because there's nothing neutral, or objective, 
 about the decision to fund the rebuilding of the Pilgrim 
 Baptist Church.  Illinois presumably does not rebuild all 
 buildings destroyed by fire, or all community services 
 buildings, or all churches, for that matter.  The decision to 
 rebuild this particular structure is very subjective, and 
 discretionary.  I suppose it's possible that the decision to 
 fund would be made completely without regard to the 
 building's status as a church, but that seems unlikely,
 no?:  Isn't it at least a strong possibility that the state 
 would not pledge a million dollars if the building had never 
 been a synagogue and church?  And if its religious status is 
 part of the reason for the pledge, isn't that a form of 
 religious favoritism that is problematic under the EC, even 
 if the Thomas view prevails? 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, 
 see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, 
 see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot

RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael
I don't think that your analogy holds up.  It is one thing for the state
to regulate, and quite another to spend money.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 1:48 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

I don't think Boerne can be read as even implicitly passing on
this question.  But if courts do end up rejecting these objections to
landmarking, then my point (a response to Marty's point about
neutrality) is that the same should apply to objections to government
repair assistance.  The mere risk that landmarking decisions might end
up burdening religious institutions because of their religiosity (since
maybe the authorities would be less likely to see a building as a
landmark if it weren't a church) doesn't justify treating all such
decisions as presumptively religiously discriminatory.  Likewise, the
mere risk that landmark repair assistance decisions might end up
benefiting religious institutions because of their religiosity (since
maybe the authorities would be less likely to repair a building as a
landmark if it weren't a church) doesn't justify treating all such
decisions as presumptive religious favoritism.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:43 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
 
 
 You may be right, in a technical sense.  The Court limited 
 itself to the RFRA claim.  But the case suggests to me that 
 the Court would probably not be receptive to a claim on the 
 (landmarks preservation) merits made by the Church.  I am not 
 remembering the aftermath of the case very well, but it seems 
 to me that the Church basically lost, on the merits. Finally, 
 if I am remembering the cases correctly, objections to 
 landmarking by churches usually fail, even though landmarking 
 imposes burdens on the churches. 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 1:26 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
 
   I'm not sure I quite understand -- why would it answer 
 that question?  If I recall correctly, this issue wasn't 
 passed on by the Court.
 
   Eugene
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
  Newsom Michael
  Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:18 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
  
  
  Doesn't Boerne answer the question posed in your second paragraph?
  
  -Original Message-
  From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
  Sent: Monday, January 16, 2006 11:59 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
  
  Marty makes an excellent point here.  I think (though I'm
  not sure that Marty does) that it would be outrageous if, 
  when a state *does* rebuild all buildings, or help rebuild 
  them, or provides other services short of rebuilding (e.g., 
  taxpayer-paid internal sprinkler installation, partly 
  subsidized earthquake retrofitting, etc.), it nonetheless 
  excluded churches, synagogues, homes that are used for 
  regular synagogue meetings or Bible study, and the like.  Yet 
  surely there is a risk here that the state is indeed 
  preferring religious buildings; even if there's no deliberate 
  desire to help religion because religion is somehow good, 
  many people who are trying to evaluate a building's 
  historic status may well be understandably influenced by 
  that building's being religious, since religious buildings 
  are often seen as especially important to a community and to 
  the community's history.
  
  Yet would this go the other way, too?  Would landmarking
  ordinances that *burden* the property owner, by barring it 
  from reconstructing the building, thus be per se 
  unconstitutional under the Free Exercise Clause when applied 
  to churches and the like, on the theory that there's no 
  neutrality here?
  
  Eugene
  
  
  
  Marty Lederman writes:
  
  Nevertheless, even if the sort of formal neutrality rule
  espoused in Thomas's Mitchell plurality becomes the governing 
  doctrine, as I think it will, these cases are still 
  difficult, because there's nothing neutral, or objective, 
  about the decision to fund the rebuilding of the Pilgrim 
  Baptist Church.  Illinois presumably does not rebuild all 
  buildings destroyed by fire, or all community services 
  buildings, or all churches, for that matter.  The decision to 
  rebuild this particular structure is very subjective, and 
  discretionary.  I suppose it's possible that the decision to 
  fund would be made completely without regard to the 
  building's status as a church, but that seems unlikely,
  no?:  Isn't it at least

RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

2006-01-17 Thread Newsom Michael
The analogy is too sweeping.  Even if one tried to limit it by reference
to a non-discrimination principle, I am not sure that the principle is
(1) correct or (2) workable.  There is no textual warrant for reducing
the Religion Clauses to a non-discrimination principle, and there is no
principled basis, short of a careful and honest consideration of
history, experience, and context, for determining what constitutes
permissible or impermissible discrimination.

Once again, we reach the core of that which divides the two of us.
Perhaps it is enough to note that fact and move on.
  

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 2:24 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church

Of course the two are in a sense different things.  But they're
also similar in that (1) they are both generally unconstitutional when
done in a way that discriminates based on religion or religiosity, amd
(2) by hypothesis, both are constitutional when done in an evenhanded
way.  Recall that Marty suggested that even if one adopts the Mitchell
plurality's evenhanded aid is OK principle, the *risk* of
discrimination may suffice to invalidate the aid program; that's what I
was responding to.

So the question is whether, despite these similarities, they
should be treated differently in that the *risk* of discrimination would
suffice to invalidate the discretionary aid program but *not* the
discretionary regulatory program.  It seems to me the answer is no.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:52 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
 
 
 I don't think that your analogy holds up.  It is one thing 
 for the state to regulate, and quite another to spend money.
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 1:48 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
 
   I don't think Boerne can be read as even implicitly 
 passing on this question.  But if courts do end up rejecting 
 these objections to landmarking, then my point (a response to 
 Marty's point about
 neutrality) is that the same should apply to objections to 
 government repair assistance.  The mere risk that landmarking 
 decisions might end up burdening religious institutions 
 because of their religiosity (since maybe the authorities 
 would be less likely to see a building as a landmark if it 
 weren't a church) doesn't justify treating all such decisions 
 as presumptively religiously discriminatory.  Likewise, the 
 mere risk that landmark repair assistance decisions might end 
 up benefiting religious institutions because of their 
 religiosity (since maybe the authorities would be less likely 
 to repair a building as a landmark if it weren't a church) 
 doesn't justify treating all such decisions as presumptive 
 religious favoritism.
 
   Eugene
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
  Newsom Michael
  Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:43 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
  
  
  You may be right, in a technical sense.  The Court limited
  itself to the RFRA claim.  But the case suggests to me that 
  the Court would probably not be receptive to a claim on the 
  (landmarks preservation) merits made by the Church.  I am not 
  remembering the aftermath of the case very well, but it seems 
  to me that the Church basically lost, on the merits. Finally, 
  if I am remembering the cases correctly, objections to 
  landmarking by churches usually fail, even though landmarking 
  imposes burdens on the churches. 
  
  -Original Message-
  From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
  Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 1:26 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
  
  I'm not sure I quite understand -- why would it answer
  that question?  If I recall correctly, this issue wasn't 
  passed on by the Court.
  
  Eugene
  
   -Original Message-
   From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
   [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
   Newsom Michael
   Sent: Tuesday, January 17, 2006 10:18 AM
   To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
   Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
   
   
   Doesn't Boerne answer the question posed in your second paragraph?
   
   -Original Message-
   From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
   Sent: Monday, January 16, 2006 11:59 AM
   To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
   Subject: RE: Pilgrim Baptist Church
   
   Marty makes an excellent point here.  I think (though I'm not 
   sure that Marty does) that it would be outrageous if, 
 when a state 
   *does* rebuild all

RE: Evaluation of people's religious beliefs

2006-01-13 Thread Newsom Michael
Eugene, I think that the real-world answer is your #4.  I think that the
law contains some normative propositions about religious belief.  You
know that I start from the Protestant Empire premise.  But you don't
have to agree with me as to the continued existence of the Protestant
Empire (I know that we will soon have a right-wing Catholic majority on
the SCOTUS, but that is really another discussion) to agree that the
*origins* of these propositions rest in evangelical Protestantism of the
British sort.  In your hypo, the beliefs are so far removed from the
core normative propositions and any reasonable variations on their
thematic content as to put them, literally, beyond the pale, in my
opinion.  (I don't know whether in your hypo this is a good or a bad
result, although I lean to the former over the latter for entirely
pragmatic reasons in part having to do with something resembling a
concern for social order, or at least wear and tear of the social
fabric.  When it comes both to children and the workplace, don't we tend
to have reasonable concerns and worries about whackiness?) 

(I might add by way of a belated response to Perry's interesting
analysis of line-drawing, (I love the parsonage example) that the
problem of neutrality/equality flounders on the shoals of these
normative propositions that have the effect or redesigning the playing
field in such a way that neutrality/equality often goes by the boards.
For what it is worth, Catholics are not the only ones who essentially
require that clergy live in church-provided housing.  Many
Episcopalian parishes come remarkably close to this bottom-line result.
Other Protestant groups may do so as well.  And, regarding the
priest-penitent privilege, my recollection is that the early American
courts may have had some difficulty in accepting or recognizing the
privilege, or, if they accepted it, saw virtue and utility in it for
Protestants as well.  But on this I could be wrong.)  

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, January 13, 2006 1:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Evaluation of people's religious beliefs

Thinking some more about my First Amendment / child custody
paper brought me to this question:

Government officials in various situations have to evaluate
people's overall rationality and sensibleness.  The most common
situation, I think, has to do with employment -- if we're considering
hiring someone (whether a faculty member or a staff employee), and we
learn that the person believes some really zany, improbable stuff (e.g.,
that aliens are talking to him, or that there are werewolves
congregating outside his house, or even that his house is haunted by
ghosts), we might not hire him.  This is true even if werewolf studies
are outside his job description -- we might just think that he's foolish
or crazy, and likely to do some dumb things in other contexts.  Another
situation, I take it, has to do with child custody; when courts are
deciding parental fitness they sometimes have to consider indicators of
how sane or reasonable a parent is (though I realize that here this
factor would and likely should be more controversial than in the
employment context).  Another might have to do with adoption.

Yet I take it that government officials ought not deny a person
employment or child custody because of that person's religious views,
including religious assertions about physical events that nonbelievers
might see as pretty implausible -- miracles, the existence of angels,
even (to take a less mainstream belief) that the earth was created 6000
years ago.

So here's the question:  Say you're a government employer, or a
family court judge, and you're considering the merits of a job applicant
or a prospective custodial parent.  You start talking to him and hear
what strike you as some zany, irrational, factually unsound beliefs,
e.g., aliens are talking to me, werewolves hang out in the woods outside
my house, and the like.  You're tempted to stay away from this person,
and keep the child as far from this person as possible -- but then he
says I know all this because God told it to me.  That makes his
beliefs pretty clearly religious.  Must you then decline to take those
beliefs into account?

Here are a few possible answers:

1.  Yes; government actors must ignore people's religious
beliefs about facts, regardless of how strange, irrational, or possibly
borderline insane they may seem to them (at least unless the beliefs are
specifically tied to the person's job description, and aren't just
evidence of overall sensibleness).

2.  Same as 1, but as to all beliefs, religious or not.

3.  No; government actors may view people's religious beliefs
about facts as evidence of the person's overall lack of rationality or
even mental problems, whether the beliefs are about werewolves or
angels, aliens talking to him or the 

RE: Law Religion Section Announcement, including request for citations to works you may have published in 2005

2005-12-30 Thread Newsom Michael








Mark, Happy New Year!



I do have an article that came out in 2005:
Michael deHaven Newsom, Some Kind of Religious Freedom: National Prohibition
and the Volstead Acts Exemption for the Religious Use of Wine, 70
Brooklyn L. Rev. 739 (2005).



Thanks, Michael









From: Scarberry, Mark
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, December 30, 2005
12:49 PM
To: 'Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: Law  Religion
Section Announcement, including request for citations to works you may have
published in 2005





Below you will find an announcement with regard to the Law 
Religion Section of the Association of American Law Schools. As many of you
will know, the AALS annual meeting will be held Jan. 3-7 in D.C. The Law 
Religion Section is presenting two programs and cosponsoring a third, as
described in the announcement. 



In addition, in late January or early February I will be mailing out
the Section newsletter, which will include notices of relevant upcoming conferences
and citations to books and articles on law and religion published during 2005.
As the announcement indicates, I will do my best to include all relevant
conferences and publications, but if you want to be sure that yours is included
please e-mail me with the citation. If you are not a member of the Section but
would like to receive the newsletter, please send me your e-mail address and I
will send it to you electronically. (I suppose even Section members who prefer
to receive the newsletter electronically can send me their e-mail addresses.)



Whether or not you will be attending the AALS annual meeting, you may
want to know that many of the annual meeting sessions (including, I hope, the
Law and Religion Section sessions) will be recorded and then made available
free as podcasts. See http://www2.cali.org/index.php?fuseaction=pages.news.




I thought this would be of general interest to many members of both the
religionlaw and conlawprof lists. My apologies to those who are members of both
lists for the cross-posting.



Mark S. Scarberry

Pepperdine
 University School
of Law







Section
on Law and Religion

at the 2006 AALS
Annual Meeting



This year the Section on Law and Religion is presenting two programs
and cosponsoring another:



On Wednesday, January 4, from 9:00am to noon, the
Section will cosponsor a program presented by the Section on Professional
Responsibility, Professional Responsibility and the Religious
Traditions, in Maryland Suite A  B (Lobby Level of the Marriott
Wardman Park). Greg Randy Lee (Widener) and Irma S. Russell (Memphis) will moderate. Speakers will be
Anthony E. Cook (Georgetown), Moushumi Khan (Khan Law Offices, NYC), Samuel J.
Levine (Pepperdine), Nancy B. Rapoport (Houston), Thomas L. Shaffer (Notre
Dame), and Rodney K. Smith (Pres., Southern Virginia University). The
commentators will be Robert F. Cochran, Jr. (Pepperdine), Bruce A. Green
(Fordham), Susan R. Martyn (Toledo),
and Russell G. Pearce (Fordham). The program will be published in the Journal of Law and Religion.



On Friday, January 6, from 3:30 to 5:15pm, the Section
will present The (Re)Turn to History in Religion Clause Law and
Scholarship, in Delaware Suite A (Lobby Level of the Marriott Wardman
 Park). Lee J. Strang (Ave
Maria) will moderate a panel comprising Noah R. Feldman (NYU), Steven K. Green
(Willamette), Marci A. Hamilton (Cardozo), Douglas Laycock (Texas), and Steven
Douglas Smith (San Diego). The program will be published in the Notre Dame Law Review. The Section's
business meeting will be held at the end of this program.



On Saturday, January 7, from 9:00 to 10:45am, the
Section will present Religion, Division, and the Constitution, in
the Wilson A room (Mezzanine Level of the Marriott Wardman
 Park). Richard W. Garnett
(Notre Dame) will moderate a panel comprising David Campbell (Dept. of Poli.
Sci., Notre Dame), Stephen M. Feldman (Wyoming),
Frederick Mark Gedicks (BYU), and Lawrence B.
Solum (Illinois).
The program will be published in the William
 Mary Bill of Rights Journal.



*
* *



The Section newsletter will be mailed to Section members in late
January or early February 2006. It will include (1) citations to books and
articles on law and religion published during 2005 (and to any that were
published during 2004 but not included in last year's newsletter) and (2)
notices of relevant conferences. I will do my best to include every appropriate
publication and conference, but if you wish to be sure that yours is included,
please e-mail me at [EMAIL PROTECTED].




Mark S.
Scarberry

Co-Chair
Elect

(and
thus Co-Secretary)

Pepperdine








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages 

RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

2005-12-02 Thread Newsom Michael
I agree that there is a standard.  I just don't find it in the
Declaration.  I find the hypocrisy of Jefferson just too much to
stomach.  I can't take him seriously.  And I don't.  Sometimes the
messenger is the message.  I'll leave it at that.

-Original Message-
From: Francis Beckwith [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, December 02, 2005 11:37 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

Michael:

The Declaration of Independence is merely a document that is intended to
convey what its authors believed are truths eternal in their patrimony.
You are correct that these truths were not applied justly. However, the
failure of mortals to live up to these standards does not diminish the
value or truth of these standards.  Being short-changed at the grocery
store does not diminsh the truth of mathematics. If anything, it
demonstrates it. In the same way, the fact that we can make the judgment
that the declaration's principles were not appropriately deployed to
protect all human beings under its authority ironically relies on the
veracity of those very principles. After all, to say that someone
entitled to justice was denied it, assumes the truth of the justice one
was denied. To say someone does not measure up, implies that there is a
standard by which we can make the measure. 

Frank

 
On Friday, December 02, 2005, at 10:23AM, Newsom Michael
[EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:


Original Attached___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.



--
Francis J. Beckwith, MJS, PhD
Associate Professor of Church-State Studies
Associate Director, J. M. Dawson Institute for 
 Church-State Studies, Baylor University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://francisbeckwith.com
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

2005-12-02 Thread Newsom Michael
I don't accept your premises.  I said that sometimes the message and the
messenger are essentially the same.  My position, given that, is
entirely logical.

-Original Message-
From: Ed Brayton [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, December 02, 2005 1:00 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

Newsom Michael wrote:

I agree that there is a standard.  I just don't find it in the
Declaration.  I find the hypocrisy of Jefferson just too much to
stomach.  I can't take him seriously.  And I don't.  Sometimes the
messenger is the message.  I'll leave it at that.


I find this highly illogical. Let's say you have Principle X. It is a 
principle advocated and accepted by two people, Person A and Person B. 
Person A advocates Principle X, but applies it in an inconsistent and 
even hypocritical manner. Person B advocates Principle X, but does so 
consistently, always putting it into practice whenever reason demands 
it. By your reasoning, it seems that you would say that if someone knows

Person A, then Principle X is false, while if someone knows Person B, 
then Principle X is true. But that's not logically tenable. Principle X 
is either true or false, regardless of whether someone who advocates it 
follows it consistently or not, and certainly regardless of whether 
someone who's been dead for 180 years followed it consistently or not.

More importantly, as Frank Beckwith pointed out, you cannot make the 
argument that failing to follow Principle X consistently is wrong 
without first accepting that Principle X is valid.You cannot logically 
demand that Principle X be followed consistently unless you, wittingly 
or unwittingly, endorse Principle X as true.

Ed Brayton
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Christianity as taint

2005-12-01 Thread Newsom Michael
But you have made a distinction which, for you, has constitutional
significance.  But I am not sure that it is a valid distinction.  But
assuming, arguendo, that the distinction has some value, there is still
the matter of its application.  The answer as to the proper
classification of a Christmas tree cannot turn on your say-so or mine.
So it would seem that my questions remain.

By the way, your examples demonstrate the inaptness of your distinction.
There may be a need to make a distinction, but it has to rest on
different grounds (and at this point Doug's view becomes very important
and powerful).

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, November 30, 2005 2:14 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Christianity as taint

Well, I'm happy to hear how various Christians understand the
meaning of Christmas trees.  For purposes of the constitutional
analysis, though, it seems to me not enough that some people view the
tree as a religious symbol.

Otherwise we'd be paralyzed:  After all, I'm pretty sure that
some people understand the removal of Christmas items (whether trees or
creches) as symbolic of hostility to Christianity, whether or not that's
the intention of those who would remove the items.  Likewise, that some
people see Graeco-Roman religious imagery as a live religious symbol, as
opposed to a cultural allusion, surely shouldn't be enough to require
that the government never use such imagery (e.g., in a goddess of
Justice standing outside courthouses).  We could add to the list
indefinitely:  Consider the Sangro de Cristo Mountains, Santa Fe, Corpus
Christi (whether the city or the submarine, about which I'm told there
was indeed controversy), Thanksgiving, and the like.  That some people
see these as live religious symbols ought not, it seems to me, render
their use unconstitutional (or even improper).

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Wednesday, November 30, 2005 10:49 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Christianity as taint
 
 
 
 With respect, Eugene, doesn't it make sense to find out how 
 various Christians understand the meaning of Christmas trees 
 before leaping to a categorical acontextual conclusion as to 
 its meaning for Christians?
 
 While I am not sure that I completely agree with Doug on the 
 question of the display of Christmas trees, surely a possible 
 basis for Doug's view is that Christmas trees are religious 
 symbols.  If, in fact, that is what they are, or at least 
 some reasonable number of Christians so believe, then isn't 
 Doug right, or at least very close to being right? (If I 
 disagree with Doug, it is because I am still attracted, 
 perhaps irrationally so, to the notion that the government 
 can properly express support and appreciation for our various 
 forms of diversity, including religious diversity.  Although 
 I would be the first to argue that the devil is in the 
 details, and I might, for prudential reasons, want to be 
 cautious in approving such expressions.)  
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Tuesday, November 29, 2005 1:47 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Christianity as taint
 
   Doug's response assumes, it seems to me, that a 
 Christmas tree is an issue of religion (as opposed to 
 abortion, which is treated as not an issue of religion).  
 Michael (see below) suggests that it is, because there's not 
 much of a distinction between religious symbols and symbols 
 associated with religious holidays; but I don't think that's 
 right:  Egg nog, Easter egg hunts, the Easter bunny, and for 
 that matter the Winter holiday gift-giving tradition in the 
 U.S. are all associated with religious holidays, but they do 
 not themselves carry a religious message, or (to use the 
 modern Establishment Clause test) a message that endorses a 
 particular religious viewpoint.  The Christmas tree, it seems 
 to me, fits within the same category.
 
   Finally, Marty asked, near the start of the thread, 
 Does any of us 'complain[] about publicly displayed 
 Christmas trees'?  It seems to me that some recent posts 
 make clear that the answer is yes.  The complaints are 
 often quite thoughtfully expressed (as Doug's are), but they 
 certainly are there.
 
   Eugene
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, 
 see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others

RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

2005-12-01 Thread Newsom Michael








And, I assume, others are free to reject
your claims about the Declaration of Independence. (I reject them because the
supposed rights laid out therein did not apply to my African and
African-American ancestors. I look elsewhere for instruction on the matter of
human rights.) Dont you think that your position might be construed as
hegemonic?











From: Ed Brayton [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, November 30, 2005
2:30 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Swedish Pastor Beats
Hate Crime Rap





Newsom Michael wrote: 

Shouldnt
we be careful in applying American notions of free speech to other cultures and
traditions? Sweden
may have had good and sufficient reasons for taking a different position on the
question. I would be curious to know if the Swedish Court relied at all on American
cases.













Quite frankly? No, I don't think we should be careful
about applying American notions of free speech to other cultures and
traditions. I take seriously the supposition found in the Declaration of
Independence that we are all endowed with unalienable rights that precede the
institution of government, that governments are instituted in order to secure
those rights, and that it is unjust for any government to violate them. I have
no problem whatsoever applying that principle universally, whether it indicts
my own government or another government. 

Ed Brayton






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

2005-12-01 Thread Newsom Michael
Maybe the answer lies in a different understanding of homosexuality, and
perhaps a different set of experiences.  I do recall, by the way, that
the Nazis killed homosexuals (the pink triangle).

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, November 30, 2005 2:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

I've certainly heard the argument that Western democracies with
histories of Nazism or Communism might be justified in suppressing Nazi
or Communist speech even if the U.S. might not be; I think I understand
the argument, though I find it unpersuasive.  But I'm puzzled why some
democracies' cultures and traditions (and in particular Sweden's) should
justify suppression of criticism of homosexuality while other
democracies' cultures and traditions (such as America's) does not.  It
seems to me that both the religious freedom arguments and the free
speech arguments -- and the counterarguments -- would be quite similar
in both.  (I'm speaking of course of the substantive arguments, not just
the precedential arguments, which would naturally differ.)

Eugene


-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Ed Brayton
Sent: Wednesday, November 30, 2005 11:30 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap


Newsom Michael wrote: 
Shouldn't we be careful in applying American notions of free speech to
other cultures and traditions?  Sweden may have had good and sufficient
reasons for taking a different position on the question.  I would be
curious to know if the Swedish Court relied at all on American cases.




Quite frankly? No, I don't think we should be careful about applying
American notions of free speech to other cultures and traditions. I take
seriously the supposition found in the Declaration of Independence that
we are all endowed with unalienable rights that precede the institution
of government, that governments are instituted in order to secure those
rights, and that it is unjust for any government to violate them. I have
no problem whatsoever applying that principle universally, whether it
indicts my own government or another government. 

Ed Brayton
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

2005-12-01 Thread Newsom Michael








Free speech may be a human right,
universal or not, but surely you dont contend that the right is utterly
absolute without any limit whatsoever, do you? Is there an absolute right
to cry fire in a crowded theater?



I will leave it to others to defend
bullies like the good reverend.











From: Brad M Pardee
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, November 30, 2005
2:45 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Swedish Pastor Beats
Hate Crime Rap






I was under the
impression that free speech was considered a universal human right, not merely
an American notion, regardless of whether governments acknowledge it as such or
not. 

And I cannot even begin to
conceive of a good and sufficient reason for putting people in jail
because they have expressed the teachings of their faith about what behaviors
are right and what behaviors are wrong. 

Brad 

Michael Newsom wrote: 
Shouldnt
we be careful in applying American notions of free speech to other cultures and
traditions? Sweden
may have had good and sufficient reasons for taking a different position on the
question. I would be curious to know if the Swedish Court relied at all on American
cases. 






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Swedish Pastor Beats Hate Crime Rap

2005-11-30 Thread Newsom Michael








Shouldnt we be careful in applying
American notions of free speech to other cultures and traditions? Sweden may have
had good and sufficient reasons for taking a different position on the question.
I would be curious to know if the Swedish Court relied at all on American
cases.











From: Ed Brayton [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Tuesday, November 29, 2005
3:42 PM
To: Law
  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Swedish Pastor Beats
Hate Crime Rap





Rick Duncan wrote: 



This
just in from ADF:











In a
unanimous 5-0 decision, Sweden's
Supreme Court today acquitted a pastor of a hate crime for
presenting the biblical view of homosexual behavior in a sermon. 



Well I certainly hope that we can all, regardless of
our religious views or opinions about homosexuality, cheer that decision. You
will find no stronger advocate of gay rights than yours truly, but give me
freedom above all else, including the freedom to disagree with me.
Indeed, one cannot coherently argue for gay rights without also
supporting the right to speak out against homosexuality, whether that is in the
US, in Sweden as in this particular case, or in Canada with the
Stephen Boissoin case (another minister up on charges for writing an anti-gay
letter to a newspaper). 

Ed Brayton






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

  1   2   3   >