Clark, list,

Sorry, I got busy for a while.

Immediate objects may have averageness but the averageness seems not definitive of them, and Peirce never makes it so. They may also have distinctiveness; an unusual characteristic, perhaps displayed at an unusual moment, might be a prominent part of the immediate object, as a result of a single prior experience. Also, immediate objects may be both simplified, e.g., a practical "essence" consisting in a rule for mentally re-constructing the object, and complicated, as in the way that Tom Wyrick discussed or as, when one hears the word "copula," one may think of a vaguely structured jumble of things such as a copula instanced in a grammar book, the copula as an abstract conceptual relation, and so on. Consider what are immediate objects of "animal" and "triangle" in universal statements about them. "Every animal is a eukaryote." "Every (Euclidean) triangle's angles sum to 360 degrees." In each case it can seem as if there were a horde of objects competing to serve as the immediate object.

If, as you consider doing, we take "average" loosely in the sense of "truth in the main" and use that idea of the average to distinguish the cenoscopic (philosophical) inquirial goal from the idioscopic (physical, psychological, etc.) inquirial goal, it brings us back to Peirce's definitions of cenoscopy, e.g., in his 1904 intellectual autobiography wherein he defines (cenoscopic) philosophy as logical analysis (by which Peirce in other writings indicates he means _/phaneroscopic/_ analysis) of that sort of common experience that people cannot seriously doubt. The truth of such experience is not even a question (or serious question) for (cenoscopic) philosophy, since, after all, one cannot seriously doubt it. Peirce wrote:

   Philosophy merely analyzes the experience common to all men. The
   truth of this experience is not an object of any science because it
   cannot really be doubted. All so-called 'logical' analysis, which is
   the method of philosophy, ought to be regarded as philosophy, pure
   or applied.
   [End quote]

I don't think that an immediate object _/automatically/_ has either that undoubtability of such common experience or the kind of truth-in-the-main (figured as averageness or otherwise) that is based upon it.

Furthermore, if such truth-in-the-main as goal distinctive of cenoscopy is a kind of _/average/_, but is not a deductive probability, or even a deductive fuzzy probability, then it seems to consist in a _/verisimilitude/_, in Peirce's sense, a likeness to experience as embodied in premisses of an inductive inference. http://www.commens.org/dictionary/term/verisimilitude .

   1910 | Note (Notes on Art. III) [R] | ILS 123-4; CP 2.663

   I will now give an idea of what I mean by _/likely/_ or
   _/verisimilar/_ . [—] I call that theory _/likely/_ which is not yet
   proved but is supported by such evidence, that if the rest of the
   conceivably possible evidence _/should/_ turn out upon examination
   to be of a _/similar/_ character, the theory would be conclusively
   proved. Strictly speaking, matters of fact never can be demonstrably
   proved, since it will always remain conceivable that there should be
   some mistake about it.
   [End quote]

There's another quote at the link, and that second quote is part of a longer passage (c. 1910, Letters to Paul Carus, ILS 274-5; CP 8.222-4) in which he elsewhere ascribes verisimilitude to induction. Peirce means that a good induction, one with verisimilitude, is that which is commonly called an inductive generalization; Peirce doesn't call it that, because by "generalization" Peirce means a notably selective generalization, decreasing the comprehension while increasing the extension, whereas (at least in the early years, in the JSP papers) induction keeps the comprehension the same while increasing the extension.

Using such an idea of _/verisimilitude/_ to _/distinguish/_ cenoscopy rather suggests that cenoscopy would be the science that draws inductive conclusions, and that inductive inference in idioscopy would ipso facto be applied cenoscopy - things that Peirce never (so far as I know) said, and that I think he would not say, although I would say them.

Maybe the immediate object usually has some sort of verisimilitude, if not always of a pure cenoscopic kind (if one accepts that idea of cenoscopy at all), insofar as, even if deduced as an average (or a distribution of probabilities, or whatever), it is not merely that deductive result but instead is its inductive extension to stand as the object as represented in a new sign. An immediate object that focuses on the distinctiveness of the object might have a verisimilar distinctiveness, and so on. Still, if one does not have previous experience with the object of the sign, the immediate object might be marked more by (attempted) plausibility, in Peirce's sense of natural simplicity, than by verisimilitude. I also wonder whether an immediate object could be marked by deductive novelty or nontriviality.

Best, Ben

On 6/24/2016 2:47 PM, Clark Goble wrote:

On Jun 23, 2016, at 12:14 PM, Benjamin Udell <baud...@gmail.com > wrote:

Peirce somewhere talks about taking a companion's experience as one's own, say, if the companion has better eyesight. The companion reports discerning a ship on the horizon, while one sees just a blurry patch there, which one lets count as the object in question. There's an idea of the commind floating around there. Anyway, Peirce didn't always use the narrowest interpretation of the word "experience." Still, the less direct an experience, the less experiential it seems.

>[CG] It’s worth going even farther than that. All experiences are themselves mediated. The phenomena you present above is just one example of a mediated experience. Yet mediation is always occurring and mediation entails transformation in various ways. An obvious example is memory where my experience during the events is always different from my memory of the events as an experience of the original events. History itself is a classic example of that kind of mediation.

The example of everydayness I gave from Peirce the other day of erroneous views of Richard III really is just this. A kind of low level often extremely fallible kind of indirect experience we draw upon for intelligibility in communication. It’s an average not in the sense of mean but in the sense of including quite a lot in a more kind of sea of chaos as a source of meanings to draw from.

>>[BU] I remember years ago Joe Ransdell posted a message "What 'fundamenal psychological laws' is Peirce referring to?" (22 Sept. 2006) https://www.mail-archive.com/peirce-l@lyris.ttu.edu/msg01394.html . Joe wrote:

    In "The Fixation of Belief" Peirce says that

        "a man may go through life, systematically keeping out of
        view all that might cause a change n his opinions, and if he
        only succeeds -- basing his method, as he does, on two
        fundamental psychologicl laws -- I do not see what can be
        said against his doing so".

    [End quote of Joe & Peirce]

As I recall, people in reply agreed that one of the laws that Peirce had in mind must have been the law of association, but then what would the other law be?

>[CG] I just reread part of that thread. That’s fascinating and I somehow had zero memory of it. One of Joe's initial thoughts is worth quoting.

    I was thinking of the argument one might make that social
    consciousness is prior to consciousness of self, and the method of
    tenacity seems to me to be motivated by the value of
    self-integrity, the instinctive tendency not to give up on any
    part of oneself, and one's beliefs are an important aspect of what
    one tends to think of when one thinks of one's identity.  Losing
    some beliefs e.g. in religion, in one's parents, in the worthiness
    of one's country, etc., can be experienced as a kind of
    self-destruction and people often seem to demonstrate great fear
    of that happening to them.  But this sense of self-identity could
    be argued to be a later construct than one's idea of the social
    entity of which one is a part.   (Joe Ransdell 9/23/06)

>[CG] Something else that came up in that discussion is what Peirce means by psychologizing here. Again let me quote from Joe, as I think it has direct bearing on the notion of “average” or “everydayness.”

    In the terminology Peirce adopted from Jeremy Bentham, we should
    distinguish between a COENOSCOPIC  sense of "mind" or "thought" or
other mentalistic term and an IDIOSCOPIC sense of such terms.. The former is the sense of "mind" or "thought" which we have in
    mind [!!] when we say something like "What are you thinking
    about?",  "What's on you mind?", "He spoke his mind", and so
    forth, as distinct from the sense which is appropriate for use in
    the context of some special scientific study of mind.

    To understand what is meant by the word "mind" as used in
    scientific psychology, let us say, we have to find out what people
    who have established or mastered something in that field
    understand by such terms since the meaning of such terms in that
    context is a matter of what the course of special study of its
    subject matter has resulted in up to this point. That is the
    idioscopic sense of "mind", "thought", etc.  But long before there
    was anything like a science of psychology and long before we were
    old enough to understand that there is any such thing as
    psychology we had already learned in the course of our ordinary
    dealings with people something about the nature of mind in the
    "coenoscopic" sense of the term. For we all learn early on, as
    small children,  that we have to figure out what people are
    thinking in order to understand what they are wanting to say, for
    example; we learn that people can be sincere or insincere, saying
    one thing and thinking another; we learn that they sometimes lie,
    pretending to think what what they do not actually think or
    believe; people change their minds; they tell us what is on their
    minds; and we learn also that they believe us or doubt us, too,
    when we say something, and so forth.  We become constantly -- I
    don't mean obsessively but just as a mater of course -- aware of
    that sort of thing in any conversation we have or any
    communications we read.  In other words it is just the plain old
    everyday understanding that is indispensable for ordinary life,
    which may be shot through with contradiction and incoherence
    but,.for better or worse,  is indispensable nonetheless

>[CG] He then quotes Peirce on something I think /extremely/ pertinent to our notion of average. (Emphasis mine)

    Now it is a circumstance most significant for the logic of
    science, that this science of dynamics, upon which all the
    physical sciences repose, when defined in the strict way in which
    its founders understood it, and not as embracing the law of the
    conservation of energy, neither is nor ever was one of the special
    sciences that aim at the discovery of novel phenomena, but merely
    consists in the *analysis of truths which universal experience has
    compelled* every man of us to acknowledge. Thus, the proof by
    Archimedes of the principle of the lever, upon which Lagrange
    substantially bases the whole statical branch of the science,
    consists in showing that that *principle is virtually assumed in
    our ordinary conception* of two bodies of equal weight. *Such
    universal experiences may not be true to microscopical
    exactitude*, but that *they are true in the main* is assumed by
    everybody who devises an experiment, and is therefore more certain
    than any result of a laboratory experiment. (CP 8.198, CN3 230 — 1905)

>[CG] I think this notion of “true in the main” is more or less what average means relative to the immediate object. It’s not really average in the sense of mean in its strict mathematical sense. Rather it’s the distinction between what Peirce calls the coenoscopic and idioscopic senses of such terms.

-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to