Re: [EM] MMPO(IAMPO) (was IA/MMPO)

2013-10-14 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,

I should say, it seems I went too far in describing the potential approval 
winner set idea. That idea is only descriptive for the ordinary Plurality 
criterion that is based on strict first preferences (because you can assume 
that the approvals for those candidates would still be there under an Approval 
election).

While the IA=MPO criterion is (I would say) sound, it is a bit harder to 
defend along the same lines, because the MPO could come from a candidate ranked 
relatively low.



 De : Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu
thanks for the insights and suggestions. It's kind of you to suggest my name, 
Jameson, but I would rather something more descriptive similar to the 
potential approval winner set of Chris and Kevin or more public relations 
friendly like the Democratically Acceptable Set.  My original motivation (that 
eventually led to IA/MPO as an approximate solution) was to find a candidate 
most likely to win two approval elections in a row (going into the second 
election as front runner) without a change in sincere voter preferences, but 
with an opportunity to adjust their ballot approval cutoffs.


And also maintain monotonocity and/or FBC, I suppose? Otherwise, it wouldn't be 
so hard.




Personally, I still prefer IA-MPO over MMPO[IA=MPO] because of the superior 
participation properties, but I recognize the importance of the Majority 
Criterion in public proposals.  Ironically, in reality Approval satisfies the 
ballot version of the Majority Criterion, while IA-MPO does not, yet in the 
face of disinformation or other common sources of uncertainty IA-MPO is at 
least as likely to elect the actual majority favorite as Appoval is.


Well personally, I would want to keep the IAMPO name but apply it to 
MMPO[IA=MPO] since the latter is not pronounceable. Or else maybe a name for 
the set is really needed. It's up to you of course. But, I don't really like 
marketing-oriented names like DMC. I feel like you'll end up in situations 
where you have to answer e.g. what is DMC and why is it good while never 
using the D, the M, or the C in your answer because they're not really that 
relevant to the concept.

Too bad, that appealing yet descriptive names are so hard to find.

Kevin Venzke

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MMPO(IAMPO) (was IA/MMPO)

2013-10-13 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,

I read your first message: At first glance I think the new method (elect the 
MMPO winner among those candidates whose IA=MPO) is good. It doesn't seem to 
gain SFC, which is actually reassuring, that this might be a substantially 
different method from others. It seems like it is mainly an MMPO tweak (since 
the MMPO winner usually will not be disqualified) with corrections for 
Plurality and SDSC/MD.

Off the top of my head I can't see that anything is happening that would break 
FBC.


 De : Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 12 octobre 2013 13h58
Objet : Re: MMPO(IAMPO) (was IA/MMPO)
 

Kevin,

In the first step of the variant method  MMPO[IA = MPO] (which, as the name 
suggests, elects the MMPO candidate from among those having at least as much 
Implicit Approval as Max Pairwise Opposition) all candidates with greater MPO 
than IA are eliminated.

I have already shown that this step does not eliminate the IA winner.  Now I 
show that this step does not eliminate the Smith\\IA winner either:

Let X be the Smith candidate with max Implicit Approval, IA(X), and let Y be a 
candidate that is ranked above X on MPO(X) ballots.  There are two cases to 
consider (i) Y is also a member of Smith, and (ii) Y is not a member of Smith.


In both cases we have MPO(X) is no greater than IA(Y), because Y is ranked on 
every ballot expressing opposition of Y over X.


Additionally in the first case IA(Y) is no greater than IA(X) because X is the 
Smith\\IA winner.  So in this case MPO(X) is no greater than IA(X) by the 
transitive property of no greater than.


In the second case, X beats Y pairwise since X is in Smith but Y is not.  This 
entails that X is ranked above Y on more ballots than Y is ranked above X.  In 
other words, X is ranked on more ballots than MPO(X).  Therefore IA(X)  
MPO(X), 


In sum, in neither case is the Smith\\IA winner X eliminated by the first step 
in the method MMPO[IA=MPO].


We see as a corollary that step one never eliminates a (ballot) Condorcet 
Winner.  In particular, it does not eliminate a (ballot) majority winner.  And 
since MMPO always elects a ballot majority unshared first place winner when 
there is one, and MMPO is the second and final step of the method under 
consideration, this method satisfies the Majority Criterion.


Also worth pointing out is this: since step one eliminates neither the IA 
winner nor the Smith\\IA winner, if there is only one candidate that survives 
the first step, then the IA winner is a member of Smith, and the method elects 
this candidate.


I think this is right, though the method as a whole doesn't satisfy Smith, 
which is probably damning for one who finds it crucial.



Also in view of this result, I suggest a strengthening of the Plurality 
Criterion as a standard required of any method worthy of public proposal.


A method (involving rankings or ratings) satisfies the Minimum Ranking 
Requirement MRR if it never elects a candidate whose max pairwise opposition 
is greater than the number of ballots on which it is rated above MinRange or 
(in the case of ordinal ballots) ranked above at least one other candidate.


What do you think?


You could. Chris and I discussed a pairwise Plurality criterion by which a 
winner can't have MPO exceeding their maximum votes for in some pairwise 
contest. In contexts where one uses pairwise considerations to make proofs 
regarding Plurality, SDSC, or SFC etc., you're basically using a stronger, 
pairwise-based criterion anyway. Pairwise Plurality implies both Plurality 
and SDSC.


The motivation suggests to me a Potential Approval Winner criterion. 
Basically, the information on the cast ballots don't admit any interpretations 
by which the disqualified candidate(s) might have been the winner under 
Approval.




Also we need a nice name for the set of candidates that is not eliminated by 
step one.

Any suggestions?

If not the set then at least the combined method. I'm not sure how many uses 
the set has. I'll give the method some more thought.

Thanks.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MMPO(IAMPO) (was IA/MMPO) correction

2013-10-13 Thread Kevin Venzke
Mistake:



- Mail original -
 De : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
 À : Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu; em election-meth...@electorama.com
 Cc : 
 Envoyé le : Dimanche 13 octobre 2013 12h02
 Objet : Re: [EM] MMPO(IAMPO) (was IA/MMPO)
 
 Hi Forest,
 
 I read your first message: At first glance I think the new method (elect the 
 MMPO winner among those candidates whose IA=MPO) is good. It doesn't 
 seem to gain SFC, which is actually reassuring, that this might be a 
 substantially different method from others.

Actually it does satisfy SFC. That's fine too, I guess? So really, the method 
is a more ranking-sensitive version of MAMPO.

Suppose that SFC disqualifies B due to A. (There's an AB majority, but no 
majorities over A.) That means A's IA-MPO is positive. B's IA-MPO could be 
positive as well. But his MPO is 50% while A's is less. So, B won't win.

Kevin Venzke

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IA/MPO

2013-10-11 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,


 De : Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu

On Thu, Oct 10, 2013 at 9:23 AM, Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr wrote:

Hi Forest, 

Unfortunately, I realized that an SFC problem is possibly egregious:

51 AB
49 CB

B would win easily, contrary to SFC (which disallows both B and C). But more 
alarmingly it's a majority favorite problem.


So it is non-majoritarian in the same sense that Approval is.  In this case 
the count is too close for approval voters to drop their second preferences, 
so B will be the Approval winner.  Of course with perfect information, they 
would bullet, and A would win.  Philosophically, in this situation I 
sympathize with electing the candidate broader support (the consensus 
candidate) over the mere majority favorite, which is why Approval's failure 
of (one version of) the Majority Criterion has never bothered me.


Well, as an Approval scenario this is pretty inexplicable. It suggests to me 
that the pre-election polling is not working. There should generally be two 
frontrunners, but both A and C factions are voting as though their favorite is 
not one of the two. That's odd to the point that I don't know how to say who 
should win based purely on the ballots.

In a rank ballot setting, where you can see the majority, I think there's a 
risk of that majority complaining about the outcome and asking for a different 
method to be adopted.




Jobst and I have gone to a lot of trouble to contrive methods that make B the 
game theoretic winner in the face of such preferences.  I'm sure you remember 
his challenge to find a method that makes B the perfect information game 
theoretic winner when utilities are given by (say)


60 A(100), B(70)

40 C(100), B(50)


It seems that only lottery methods can solve this challenge in a satisfactory 
way.  We co-authored a paper with the double entendre title of Some Chances 
for Consensus on this topic for the benefit of people who take the tyranny 
of the majority problem seriously.


Yes, I read that paper. It was very interesting. It doesn't fit my perception 
of a proposable method, which is fine. It's just that IA/MPO, at first glance, 
seems pretty proposable. Not just the properties but the fact that the name is 
also the definition.




In light of this fact I propose the following variation on our method:


1. Eliminate all candidates that have higher MPO than IA.


2.  Elect the remaining candidate with the greatest difference between its IA 
and its MPO.


I like differences better than ratios in this context, but I used ratios in 
IA/MPO because I worried about people who couldn't easily agree that (25 - 30) 
  (72 - 90) , for example.  But now that we know eliminating all of the 
negative differences is possible without eliminating all of the candidates, 
let's switch to differences.


Well, if the elimination in step 1 recalculates MPO for step 2, you probably 
lose FBC.

Hrm. MDDA's approach (i.e. for satisfying Majority Favorite, and SFC more 
broadly) is that if your MPO .5 then you mostly can't win. MAMPO's approach is 
that if your IA is .5 then only your MPO is considered, not your IA. I wonder 
if there are any other options. Both of these approaches are kind of drastic, 
and I don't think a method needs to completely satisfy SFC.

Kevin Venzke

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IA/MPO

2013-10-10 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,

 De : Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mercredi 9 octobre 2013 19h51
Objet : Re: [EM] IA/MPO

Kevin,

thanks for working on the property compliances.

I agree that this method does satisfy the FBC, is monotone, and is at least 
marginally clone independent, like Score and ratings based Bucklin and MMPO.

I am not as expert as you in the various defense criteria.

My main focus so far is that the method seems to remedy some of the problems 
of Approval and some of the problems of MMPO.  


Unfortunately, I realized that an SFC problem is possibly egregious:

51 AB
49 CB

B would win easily, contrary to SFC (which disallows both B and C). But more 
alarmingly it's a majority favorite problem.

Approval has a problem with this (true preferences) scenario:


30 A
3 AC
15 CA
4 C
15 CB
3 BC
30 C

Of course, (under Approval voting) the two 15 member factions should, and 
would bullet C,  if they were sure of the numbers, but it is more likely that 
due to disinformation from the A and B parties (and other sources of 
uncertainty) they would not truncate their second preferences, so A and B 
would be tied for most approval.

Yes, Approval can't easily adjust on election day if polls were inaccurate or 
there is a sudden change of sentiment. It tends to settle on two frontrunners, 
and when it doesn't, the outcome is fairly arbitrary (which isn't better in my 
opinion).



However, IA/MPO robustly elects C.

Our friend MMPO has a problem with

19 ABC
18 BCA
18 CAB
15 DAB
15 DBC

15 DCA

electing the Condorcet Loser D, (unless some preferences are strategically 
collapsed).  But IA/MPO elects the right winner A, with no need to collapse 
preferences among members of the ABC clone set..

Can you think of any other examples where one or the other of IA or MMPO is by 
itself inadequate?  Does IA/MPO always improve the outcome in such cases?
Well, implicit approval as a method on its own wouldn't be proposable, I 
don't think, due to the majority favorite issue.

MMPO isn't fantastic at deterring burial, so I was hoping the IA might address 
that as in implicit Condorcet//Approval (though plain C//A is not great wrt 
FBC).


Kevin Venzke

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IA/MPO

2013-10-08 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,


 De : Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mardi 8 octobre 2013 16h59
Objet : [EM] IA/MPO

Kevin,

I'm afraid that IA/MPO does fail Plurality:

33 A
17:A=C
17:B=C
33 B

The IA/MPO ratio for both A and B is 50/50 = 1, while the ratio for C is 
34/33, which is greater than 1.

But this is about the worst violation posssible, and it doesn't seem too bad 
to me.

If equal top ranking were not allowed, then Plurality would not be violated.  
Or (in other words) the method satisfies a weaker version of Plurality that 
says if C is ranked on fewer ballots than X is ranked top but not equal to) C, 
then C cannot win.


I don't know if that is helpful.

Actually, we are OK here because Plurality only counts strict first 
preferences. This aspect is useful when trying to make proofs about it. In this 
particular case, I say that if Plurality disqualifies some candidate X to due 
another candidate Y, I know that pairwise opposition to X exceeds X's approval, 
so X's score is below 100%. (And the same sentence is true if you swap in 
SDSC/MD for Plurality.) Since we know somebody will have =100% as a score, X 
won't win.

I think the question for methods like this is how far away you can get from the 
ideal strategy resembling approval strategy. I feel optimistic because the role 
given to MPO is large. In MDDA and MAMPO majority threshold rules are 
hard-coded and key to seeing any ranking sensitivity. They satisfy SFC 
(basically a weak LNHarm) but I think IA/MPO is awfully close to satisfying 
that as well.


Basically:
Let a be the approval of candidate X
Let b be the approval of candidate Y and also Y's opposition to X
Let c be the maximum opposition to Y

Then IA/MPO violates SFC when a/b  b/c and a  b  0.5  c. Possible to do, 
but it would hardly ever happen, I think.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Try this method on your favorite election scenario

2013-10-07 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,



 De : Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Dimanche 6 octobre 2013 17h21
Objet : [EM] Try this method on your favorite election scenario

Ballots are ranked or rated.  If ranked, then equal ranking and truncation are 
allowed.
 
Let IA stand for Implicit Approval, which for any candidate X is the number of 
ballots on which X is ranked or rated above bottom, i.e. neither truncated nor 
rated at zero.
 
Let MPO stand for maximum pairwise opposition, which (for candidate X) is the 
maximum (as Y varies over the other candidates) of the number of ballots on 
which a strict preference of Y over X is indicated.
 
The winner of this method (IA/MPO) is the candidate with the highest ratio of 
IA to MPO.
 
Example
 
45 AB
35 BC
20 C
 
For A  IA is 45 and MPO is 55, so IA/MPO is 45/55 or 9/11.
For B IA is 80 and MPO is 45, so IA/MPO is 80/45 or 16/9.
For C IA is 55 and MPO is 80, so IA/MPO is 55/80 or 11/16.
 
The IA/MPO winner is B.
 
If, instead, the A faction votes 45 A, then the ratios become ...
 
For A  (the same) 9/11.
For B  IA is 35 and MPO is still 45, so the ratio is 7/9.
For C IA is still 55 and MPO is 45, so the ratio is 11/9.
 
This time C wins.

IA/MPO seems like a pretty good method. It seems to be guaranteed that at least 
one candidate will have a score = 100%. That's elegant. With that assumption 
it seems easy to demonstrate that the method satisfies Plurality and 
SDSC/Minimal Defense.

My guess is that it must satisfy FBC since the component scores each do, and 
the only processing is taking the ratio.

I suspect that we have lost SFC compared to MMPO (Strategy-Free: roughly, if 
A has a majority over B and there is no majority over A, B can't win), but it 
might be hard to contrive a failure scenario.

If it's right that IA/MPO satisfies FBC, MD, and Plurality, it's not in a 
crowded space... Though MAMPO satisfies those as well as SFC, it's probably 
less sensitive to the rankings. (MDDA has SFC but can fail Plurality.)

I should get my simulations running again. I seem to recall being disappointed 
with the performance of MDDA and MAMPO.


Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #8922] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,


(Benjamin wrote:)

On Mon, Jun 24, 2013 at 11:08 AM, Stephen Unger un...@cs.columbia.edu wrote:

Regarding the plurality criterion:

 The Plurality Criterion is: If there are two candidates X and Y so
 that X has more first place votes than Y has any place votes, then Y
 shouldn't win.

It is NOT worthy of  respect.
 Consider the following 2-candidate SV election.

#votes  C1  C2
51       9   8
49       0   9

C1 should win according to the Plurality Criterion, but obviously C2
is the people's choice. One of the advantages of SV is that it
properly handles cases like this.


Woodall (the inventor of the criterion) used a model in which all 
methods are rank methods (and optionally have the concept of truncation). If 
you want to use the criteria in other 
environments you just have to be consistent about how you extend it.

I would interpret 0 ratings as truncation and translate the above scenario to 
say:
51: C1C2
49: C2 (C1 has no votes)


So it is no violation of Plurality to elect C2, only a violation of Majority 
Favorite.

But you can change the scenario so that Plurality would be failed:

51: C1 rated 5, C2 unrated

49: C2 rated 10, C1 unrated


OK, SV=Score Voting, right?  Score voting doesn't have places, does it, as it 
is not a ranked based system? I agree with you that in the above election C2 
should win, of course - although some would not.

I dunno, maybe I don't under this, or maybe the Plurality is better defined 
without referring to first place or any place.

I guess that's my next question: is the Plurality relevant to non ranked 
systems? Is the Criterion used by experts (like you guys) to refer to C2 
winning about as failing the Plurality Criterion? Or is it only about things 
like Bucklin and IRV?


Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #8922] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-24 Thread Kevin Venzke


Hi Benn,


 De : Benjamin Grant panjakr...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 24 juin 2013 11h45
Objet : Re: [EM] [CES #8922] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically 
substantially different from Plurality?
 

On Mon, Jun 24, 2013 at 12:28 PM, Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr wrote:

But you can change the scenario so that Plurality would be failed:

51: C1 rated 5, C2 unrated

49: C2 rated 10, C1 unrated

Kevin


A little confused again.  What voting system are we using above? Lost track of 
that.


My assumption was that we were talking about Range, with blank ratings counting 
as zero.

Kevin


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #8922] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Benn,



 De : Benjamin Grant panjakr...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 24 juin 2013 12h11
Objet : Re: [EM] [CES #8922] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically 
substantially different from Plurality?

On Mon, Jun 24, 2013 at 12:50 PM, Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr wrote:


But you can change the scenario so that Plurality would be failed:

51: C1 rated 5, C2 unrated
49: C2 rated 10, C1 unrated

Kevin


A little confused again.  What voting system are we using above? Lost track 
of that.


My assumption was that we were talking about Range, with blank ratings 
counting as zero.

Kevin



If we are talking about Range and counting blank rating as zero, then this:


51: C1 rated 5, C2 unrated
49: C2 rated 10, C1 unrated

is really no different than this:


51: C1 rated 5, C2 rated 0
49: C2 rated 10, C1 rated 0

And I think, since plurality says If there are
two candidates X and Y so that X has more first place votes than Y has any 
place 

votes, then Y shouldn't win, then X and Y have the same number of any place 
votes, 

i.e., Range voting can NEVER fail plurality. Again, I can't imagine a decent 
system 

that would.

Woodall's framework involves a concept of voters explicitly acknowledging 
candidates on their ballots, and Plurality is based on this. It doesn't really 
matter whether being unrated or being rated 0 are treated the same by the 
method. Personally I think a 0 rating is about the same as not being 
acknowledged as having any value, but if instead we say that an explicit 0 
rating counts as the acknowledgment, then Plurality failures can be avoided as 
long as the voters put 0s instead of leaving candidates unranked.

Now if there was some functional difference between a 0 rating and no rating 
at all, 

we could examine that, I think.

The functional difference for Plurality relates to the input, not the result. 
Consider why this criterion should be of any interest in the first place. You 
seem to agree that it is not good to fail it.

In any case, with a Range/Score system that permits people to have a 
functionally 

different from zero no rating option, I still have an issue concluding the 
the 

Plurality criterion was failed.  Did C1 have more first place votes than C2? 
I 

don't think so.
...

What am I missing?  Or have I screwed up somewhere?


What first place votes means in the rank context is strictly ranked above 
all of the other candidates. Plurality is originally defined for rank methods. 
If you want to apply criteria for rank methods to some other kind of method, 
you have to explain how you can interpret the latter as a rank method. For 
ratings ballots I think it's easiest to say that you just extract the relative 
rankings from the ratings.

Kevin


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,


 De : Benjamin Grant
Cc : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 24 juin 2013 17h53
Objet : Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically 
substantially different from Plurality?
 

The only way to avoid this, I *think*, is with a system in which expressing a 
preference of A over B doesn't let C win - and such a system may well have 
worse flaws, possibly.

Right, you are here so close to IIA that you'd be stuck with random ballot or 
similar. FBC is sort of a next best. It's very close in spirit, only you're 
guaranteed to be able to vote A top and equal to B, but not necessarily 
strictly higher. Otherwise, we might create conflicting entitlements.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Associated Student Government at Northwestern University uses Schulze Method

2013-04-20 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,

It's true that *with the ballots as cast* any Condorcet-compliant method would 
have
worked identically. What you don't know until you try it, is whether voters 
would
actually cast those ballots, given the incentives created by the method. That 
said,
I don't see an obvious reason why Tideman or MinMax would have gone differently.

Kevin





 De : r...@audioimagination.com r...@audioimagination.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 20 avril 2013 13h20
Objet : Re: [EM] Associated Student Government at Northwestern University uses 
Schulze Method
 




 since there was no cycle, any Condorcet compliant work have worked 
 identically.  if it had a cycle, since there were only three candidate 
 tickets, Schulze, Tideman, and MinMax would still have performed identically.
 
oops.  i realize that there were 4 candidate tickets and then 6 pairwise 
elections.
 
still doesn't change that, with a Condorcet winner, it made no difference.  if 
there was a 4-way cycle, perhaps Schulze would choose a different winner than 
the other
methods.
 
also was going to mention that i had attended Northwestern during the Reagan 
years.  was a PhD student but left ABD.
 
r b-j
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] The successful repeal of Approval by the Dartmouth Board of Trustees

2013-01-29 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,





 De : Gervase Lam gervase@group.force9.co.uk
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Dimanche 27 janvier 2013 16h49
Objet : [EM] The successful repeal of Approval by the Dartmouth Board of 
Trustees
 
I was looking through the Approval Voting article and noticed that it
mentioned that in 2009 the Dartmouth Board of Trustees had Approval
successfully repealed.

It quotes an article in the web saying: When the alumni electorate
fails to take advantage of the approval voting process, the three
required Alumni Council candidates tend to split the majority vote,
giving petition candidates an advantage.


I think that quote states the issue exactly.



There is a link to the article.

http://thedartmouth.com/2009/04/03/opinion/verbum/

Can anybody give any further background on this?  The details in the
article look a bit sparse.

I think that the reason for the Approval failure was due to the three
required Alumni Council candidates.  But I don't really know.

Can somebody comment in further detail on why Approval was unsuccessful
in this case?


I don't have any knowledge of this outside the article but it sounds like voters
are either not adequately informed about candidate viability or weren't using
ideal strategies.

The fact that they had to nominate a minimum number of candidates should
not pose a problem for Approval provided that voters are informed and use
good strategy.

To be more specific, it sounds like those not voting for petition candidates
had no idea they needed to be concerned about them winning. If among the
three nominated candidates nobody was even getting majority approval 

from among non-petition candidate voters then most likely that also reflects
badly on the strategies voters used.

But that depends on an issue space assumption (or something similar)... If
there is no issue space and everyone just voted for their favorite, it could be 
bad
information, but it could also simply be something that can happen under 
Approval,
that nobody feels it's worth propping up one's second choice.


It does sound like the Board of Trustees did not like the winners, but I
certainly don't get the impression that the winners were good ones. If 
Approval
doesn't work in some setting then I guess you have no choice but to not use
it.


Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Symmetrical-IC-Beatpath(lv)?

2012-12-28 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,

It's been quite awhile, but when I was trying to devise new FBC methods, I got
a strong sense that any kind of path tracing wasn't going to prove compatible
with FBC. The consequences of tracing effects through multiple candidates seem

too unpredictable to offer the guarantee, that you will never want to position
your favorite candidate insincerely.


ICA and ICT are two-step methods where the second step obviously satisfies
FBC, and the first step is just carefully excluding some candidates in a way
that doesn't disrupt the FBC compliance. If the second step didn't satisfy
FBC I don't think Improved Condorcet would mitigate the issue. IC just refrains
from doing something harmful of its own.

The other Condorcet or Condorcet-like FBC methods are based on MinMax, which
doesn't use paths either. So, I'm pessimistic that it can be done.

Kevin



- Mail original -
 De : Michael Ossipoff email9648...@gmail.com
 À : election-meth...@electorama.com
 Cc : 
 Envoyé le : Jeudi 27 décembre 2012 22h01
 Objet : [EM] Symmetrical-IC-Beatpath(lv)?
 
 What if, in Symmetrical ICT, the top-count were replaced with Beatpath(lv)?

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-16 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Juho,



- Mail original -
 De : Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
  Plurality is just a description that is convenient for discussion on the
  EM list. Ranking above last place isn't a concept that 
 exists (until 
  someone feels it would aid their position to bring it up).
 
  It just takes someone (could be an IRV advocate) to say this many voters 
  ranked this candidate first and this candidate second, and didn't rank 
  anyone else, etc. If this, without bringing up any criteria, doesn't 
  raise an awful lot of eyebrows, then I'm wrong about Plurality. But if 
  it does raise eyebrows, then it is up to the pro-margins crowd to explain 
  to the public that their mistake is that they believe in implicit 
 approval
  (without having ever heard of it) and that they should stop, because it
  (you will say) encourages harmful strategy.
 
 Ok, it seems that we are moving in the direction of marketability of the 
 methods.

I was always talking about that as I said it was DOA as a proposal.

 All methods can be attacked based on some of their properties. And in 
 most cases voters are quite unaware of any of those properties, until someone 
 builds such (usually negative) marketing messages and starts using them.
 
 Sometimes the marketing messages might be based on what actually happened in 
 the 
 election. In Burlington 2009 mayoral elections people were told that IRV 
 failed 
 to elect the Condorcet winner. But it seems that people didn't pay much 
 attention to that failure. Sometimes the marketing stories are based just on 
 what might happen in theory. It may be that we are talking more 
 about the psychology of the politicians and lobbyists here, and less about 
 the 
 psychology of the actual voters, or the concerns of the election method 
 experts.

I claim the Plurality failure will be relatively easy to depict as
damning since it doesn't need explanation.

Your defense of margins (below) is apparently that the Plurality 
failure is justified because margins makes so much sense. I don't
know how strong that is.

  And I want note again that virtually every proposed method satisfies 
  Plurality aside from margins and MMPO. So if Plurality is the cause of 
  some harmful strategy, your offered alternative must be something really
  fantastic.
 
 I guess Condorcet methods can't ever be successful since they fail such 
 terrible criteria as favourite betrayal and 
 burial. ;-) 

That example doesn't make sense. At least the FBC part doesn't.

 I mean that whatever method you want to promote, there 
 are some nasty negative marketing pitches that you must be ready to answer. 
 I'm not sure if Plurality is the most difficult one. One reason is that even 
 experts need to read the definition twice before they properly understand 
 what 
 the idea is and what the implications of the criterion might be.

That's why I said I don't believe the criterion needs to be 
introduced and the failure doesn't need to be explained. Only the 
scenario itself needs to be shown in my opinion.

  Ok. In the context of margins' proposability and Plurality I don't 
  actually think it matters how people would vote under it. (Though I'm 
 sure
  it would come up. Ahaha.)
 
  However, even without stategy and property discussions, some voters may 
 be 
  tempted to truncate just because they get the idea (maybe from their 
 traditional 
  voting methods) that marking some candidate on the ballot will give him 
 some 
  points. But that would be based on lack of understanding 
 and not on 
  the properties on the method in question.
 
  Right. And when you advocate margins you get the job of convincing 
  everybody that they're wrong to think this way. (I do think they think 
  this way, and I don't think anyone can change it.)
 
 Most ranked methods lose a considerable part of their benefits if people 
 generally truncate. In the worst case the behaviour of the methods starts to 
 resemble plurality. It is quite common that the opposite side will 
 win, and then one's vote is wasted unless one tells which one of 
 the opposite side candidates is best. I believe that many enough 
 people will learn not to truncate, to make the results of the election 
 meaningful and fair.

You're writing this an example of what you would say to a skeptical 
public?

 Btw, I think that in some sense margins are easy to advocate. The reason is 
 that 
 there is one simple answer that, if you want, can be used to answer to most 
 attacks against Minmax(margins). The idea is roughly that you thwart all 
 attacks 
 on detais by repeating that the method will elect the candidate who needs 
 least 
 additional votes to beat all others. That is a simple and quite 
 understandable 
 rule that makes sense, not a complex algorithm, and any deviation from that 
 simple rule can be presented as violation of the basic principles of the 
 election. We may thus accept that there are some theoretical cases of burial 
 etc., but we can say that 

Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-13 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Juho,



- Mail original -
 De : Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
  I don't believe the public needs to understand the terms 
 plurality criterion
  or implicit approval or even strategy to find the 
 scenario problematic.
 
 I guess people need to understand what ranking candidates in general or 
 ranking 
 them above the last place means, and that such an act is supposed to mean 
 something when they vote, if they have an opinion on the Plurality criterion 
 (or 
 on examples that demonstrate the impact of the Plurality criterion). Or do 
 you 
 mean that the Plurality criterion example would be presented and explained to 
 the public, but assuming that they don't understand what ranking or not 
 ranking some candidate means?

Plurality is just a description that is convenient for discussion on the
EM list. Ranking above last place isn't a concept that exists (until 
someone feels it would aid their position to bring it up).

It just takes someone (could be an IRV advocate) to say this many voters 
ranked this candidate first and this candidate second, and didn't rank 
anyone else, etc. If this, without bringing up any criteria, doesn't 
raise an awful lot of eyebrows, then I'm wrong about Plurality. But if 
it does raise eyebrows, then it is up to the pro-margins crowd to explain 
to the public that their mistake is that they believe in implicit approval
(without having ever heard of it) and that they should stop, because it
(you will say) encourages harmful strategy.

And I want note again that virtually every proposed method satisfies 
Plurality aside from margins and MMPO. So if Plurality is the cause of 
some harmful strategy, your offered alternative must be something really
fantastic.

  That's why I see it as such a show-stopper.
  I wonder if the voters should be told about the Plurality criterion or 
 if that
  should be hidden from them (to avoid them rankig only those candidates 
 that 
  they approve / want to promote). In some startegies that information 
 may be 
  useful to them. But losing information because of truncation (in an 
 election 
  that has no meaningful strategy problems) is harmful.

  Do you think that if you permit IRV voters to know that IRV satisfies
  Plurality, they will truncate more often (assuming the rules allow them 
  to)?
 
 Depends on how different properties are presented and advertised. If 
 Plurality 
 would be presented as an important feature of Condorcet methods, some people 
 might take that seriously and vote accordingly (e.g. rank only those 
 candidates 
 that they approve). That could be relevant in IRV too, if someone would start 
 merketing IRV using the Plurality criterion.

I can't imagine that anyone would use Plurality to promote a method, 
since even FPP satisfies it. I can only see using it to oppose a method,
and even then it seems unnecessary to put a name to the problem.

 But in general I lean in the direction that in most cases (e.g. in 
 Burlington) 
 people will use ranked methods in some quite sincere way and they do not 
 worry 
 about the details, like IRV strategies or Plurality criterion.

Ok. In the context of margins' proposability and Plurality I don't 
actually think it matters how people would vote under it. (Though I'm sure
it would come up. Ahaha.)

 However, even without stategy and property discussions, some voters may be 
 tempted to truncate just because they get the idea (maybe from their 
 traditional 
 voting methods) that marking some candidate on the ballot will give him some 
 points. But that would be based on lack of understanding and not on 
 the properties on the method in question.

Right. And when you advocate margins you get the job of convincing 
everybody that they're wrong to think this way. (I do think they think 
this way, and I don't think anyone can change it.)

 I think the correct message to voters 
 in most ranked method based elections is to encourage them not to truncate 
 but 
 rank all ralevant (good and less good) candidates sincerely.

I actually don't understand the meaning of this kind of statement. Who 
is in the position of sending messages to voters? I think the political 
players will tell their supporters whatever they think is most advantageous,
and no one will consult the EM list.

  The thought that Plurality itself (satisfaction of it, or failures of it) 
  can be exploited by voters is strange to me.
 
 Pluraity criterion can at least play a role in some strategies. Sincere 
 rankings 
 are 49:A, 48:BC, 3:CB. If the three C supporters truncate, Plurality 
 criterion says that (former Condorcet winner) B can not win any more. 
 Plurality 
 criterion does not say that C must win, but if it does (as in some Condorcet 
 methods), then those three CB voters have a working strategy.

Ok.
 
 Also the wording and intent of Plurality criterion may lead people to think 
 that 
 by not ranking some candidates at all, they can decrease the chancs of those 
 candidates to win 

Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-12 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Juho,


Kevin Venzke wrote:

Margins, it seems to me, is DOA as a proposal due to the Plurality criterion.
That 35 AB, 25 B, 40 C would elect A is too counter-intuitive.

I agree. For those who don't know, the Plurality criterion says that if  X is 
ranked
strictly above all other candidates on more ballots than Y is ranked above 
any candidates,
then Y must not win. 


Plurality criterion assumes implicit approval (given any preference) of 
ranked
candidates (definitions above have some differences). In that sense it adds 
something
extra to pure ranking.

I don't believe the public needs to understand the terms plurality criterion
or implicit approval or even strategy to find the scenario problematic. 

That's why I see it as such a show-stopper.
I wonder if the voters should be told about the Plurality criterion or if that
should be hidden from them (to avoid them rankig only those candidates that 

they approve / want to promote). In some startegies that information may be 

useful to them. But losing information because of truncation (in an election 

that has no meaningful strategy problems) is harmful.
Do you think that if you permit IRV voters to know that IRV satisfies
Plurality, they will truncate more often (assuming the rules allow them 

to)?

The thought that Plurality itself (satisfaction of it, or failures of it) 
can be exploited by voters is strange to me.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Chris,


 De : Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au

Say there are 3 candidates and the voters have the option to fully rank them,
but instead they all just choose to vote FPP-style thus:
 
49: A
48: B
03: C
 
Of course the only possible winner is A. Now say the election is held again 
(with
the same voters and candidates), and the B voters change to BC giving:

49: A
48: BC
03: C

Now to my mind this change adds strength to no candidate other than C, so the 
winner 
should either stay the same or change to C. Does anyone disagree?

I'm tempted to. I'm not sure Later-no-help is inherently valuable. But even
if it is, many methods sacrifice it to accomplish something else.

Margins, it seems to me, is DOA as a proposal due to the Plurality criterion.
That 35 AB, 25 B, 40 C would elect A is too counter-intuitive.
Kevin


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MJ rules expressed in Bucklin terminology

2012-07-21 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,

[1] In fact, there aren't too many well-defined methods among the median-based 
ones. Bucklin
is really just an ill-defined soup. 

Why do you say that Bucklin is an ill-defined soup? Because there are several 
ways to treat
(or not accept) equal rankings?

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Nontechnical words for cardinal and ordinal categories?

2012-06-21 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,


Why do I think new terms are worthwhile? I think that choosing the right term 
is 

an important part of activism. Neither pro-life nor pro-choice activists are 

satisfied with the more-descriptive anti-abortion or abortion rights. 
Similarly, 

Republicans made no headway against the inheritance tax until they termed it 
the 

death tax. And FairVote has done very well with instant runoff.

Do you really want to advocate a ballot format, instead of a specific method? Or
is it a tool to help advocate Range (which will be a seemingly redundant name
once you've made the effort to separately explain what ratings ballots are)


Cardinal/Ordinal: yes, I know that pretty much everyone learns these terms 
somewhere 

around 2nd grade. But then they don't really use them again. Imagine you didn't 
know 

anything about voting theory, and you heard just one of the terms; cardinal 
voting or
ordinal voting, but not both. For me at least, these would be meaningless 
jargon. 

Cardinal, in isolation, is more likely to mean principal than on an 
absolute 

scale; and even ordinal, which has no other confusing meaning, takes some 
thought 

to relate to voting; you have to translate the adjective to a verb in your head.

I never use cardinal/ordinal when talking to non-EM people. Only rankings and 
ratings.
The only confusion I recall is when they are familiar with the idea of 
specifying
numbers in order to indicate a ranking, and seem unsure that this isn't also 
rating.


Ranked/rated: To me, these work fine as neutral terms. But they're not so good 
for 

activism. Again, if I heard the term rated voting for the first time, I'd 
have to 

think a bit to understand what it meant. Has the voting process itself been 
rated, 

or does it involve using ratings? What would it be like to use ratings to vote? 
None 

of these leap to mind; they must be explained.

That's why I like evaluative/comparative. Just hearing the words already puts 
you 

into the process of casting a ballot.

I find those names less descriptive than rank/rate of what you are actually 
doing.
I think they could describe almost any method. I also don't like how 
evaluative
seems to presuppose what one is using the ballot to do. But if the activist's 
goal is
a specific method then I guess that makes sense.

Comparative makes me think of comparing two options at a time. Because I'm 
familiar
with pairwise matrices, that makes sense for ranking. Would it make any 
intuitive
sense to someone familiar with IRV? I'm not too sure. I can't though, for the 
life
of me, imagine Condorcet or IRV advocates thinking they will get an advantage 
out of
using that term over, say, preferential.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Election-Methods Digest, Vol 96, Issue 22

2012-06-13 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,

- Mail original -
 De : Nicholas Buckner nlbor...@gmail.com
 À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Cc : 
 Envoyé le : Mercredi 13 juin 2012 3h39
 Objet : Re: [EM] Election-Methods Digest, Vol 96, Issue 22
 
 Actually, on a weird second thought, wouldn't a method that refused to
 identify a winner in a three-way tie (Condorcet paradox) be compatible
 with both? It would be I guess case 5 (A, B, C, D, no winner). It
 wouldn't be a very practical method, as we need our voting methods to
 decide ties, but isn't deciding the tie what breaks the Participation
 criterion? My voting method only made the mistake of picking a winner
 in the first place (a mistake I'd happily do again).

Besides what Jameson said, criteria usually are (or should be) 
defined for some framework which includes a definition of what an 
election method is. I don't know of any use of a framework that
allows no winner, as I suppose it becomes unclear how the criteria
should work within it (related to Jameson's point).

If you declare a massive tie and resolve it randomly, you will get
the same problem, since Participation should at least say that the
win odds of the favorite should not decrease, yet Condorcet demands
100% win odds for its winner.

Kevin


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Herve Moulin's proof not really a proof

2012-06-12 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Nicholas,

At no point is he adding simultaneously different groups of voters.
He is reaching conclusions about one group and then modifying it
to get the new group, but the modification is always relevant to
Participation.

Let me try to understand which stage exactly it is that you do not
agree with. Again let me start with the idea that you believe that
the winner of the first election (the one with four voting groups)
can only be A, in order to satisfy Condorcet and Participation.

Step 0: Assume A must win (everybody agrees nobody else is possible)
Case 1: proved that D cannot win (you agree with this)
Case 2: proved that B cannot win (you agree with this)
Case 3: proved that C cannot win (you agree with this)
Case 4: proved that either A or C must win in this election:
3 voters vote A  D  C  B.
3 voters vote A  D  B  C.
5 voters vote D  B  C  A.
4 voters vote B  C  A  D.
4 voters vote C  A  B  D.
Do you disagree with that? The new voters are CA voters so the
new winner cannot be anybody worse than A, because we know that
A was previously winning.

I will wait to continue until you say whether you agree that the 
winner of that five-faction election must be A or C.

Kevin


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Herve Moulin's proof - maybe I see the thought

2012-06-12 Thread Kevin Venzke
 Mail original -
 De : Nicholas Buckner nlbor...@gmail.com
 À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
 Cc : 
 Envoyé le : Lundi 11 juin 2012 16h47
 Objet : Re: [EM] Herve Moulin's proof not really a proof
 
 No, it is a logical fallacy, since the original scenario is
 3 voters vote A  D  C  B.
 3 voters vote A  D  B  C.
 5 voters vote D  B  C  A.
 4 voters vote B  C  A  D.
 Only if adding votes here with A  candidate X where X goes onto win
 would Moulin prove anything. He changes the electorate, the control
 group long before that though.

Actually, I think maybe I see what you're seeing.

You think he's trying to prove that A can't win in the original four-
faction scenario. Actually, he never directly does that. Instead, he
shows that *if* A wins in the original scenario, there will be an
unsolvable problem.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Herve Moulin's proof not really a proof

2012-06-11 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Nicholas,

You seem to agree in your paper that Moulin's proof shows that in the
original scenario, the winner can only be A. If that is granted, then
we can simplify the proof by removing what we don't need.

Initial scenario (from case 4):

3 voters vote A  D  C  B.
3 voters vote A  D  B  C.
5 voters vote D  B  C  A.
4 voters vote B  C  A  D.
4 voters vote C  A  B  D.

Either A or C is elected (we agree on this yes?)

Step 2:
Say that A wins in the initial scenario.
Now add 6 voters for A  C  B  D.

Now C would be the Condorcet winner, do you agree?

So A cannot be the winner in the original scenario.

Step 3:
Say instead that C wins in the initial scenario.
Now add 4 voters for C  B  A  D.

Now B would be the Condorcet winner, do you agree?

So C can't be the winner in the original scenario, either.

No design can make it work.

Kevin


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Throwing my hat into the ring, possibly to get trampled

2012-06-10 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Nicholas,



- Mail original -
 De : Nicholas Buckner nlbor...@gmail.com
 À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
 Cc : election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com
 Envoyé le : Samedi 9 juin 2012 20h23
 Objet : Re: [EM] Throwing my hat into the ring, possibly to get trampled
 
T hank you for the article, as it was informative. It is very true that
 Elimination methods tend to eliminate candidates who could go onto
 become winners.

That's not what I'm saying; I'm saying elimination of candidates helps
and hurts the non-eliminated candidates in unpredictable ways.

 QLTD doesn't have a single loser to eliminate (it doesn't mention
 losers much either). In fact I worn against first-past-the-post
 methods (vanilla QLTD) (that's why I go with the converse 
 way--the
 elimination way), as they are susceptible to Burying mentioned here
 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Tactical_voting

When you add elimination to a method, it often makes it better, but it
also tends to break some criteria.

 what I think the original article
 (http://www.mcdougall.org.uk/VM/ISSUE6/P4.HTM) tries to show is QLTD
 has a problem with a subset criterion to monotocity he called
 mono-add-top (which is very close to the Participation criterion).

 My method doesn't have that problem.  Let me use his example (though I
 have some mild problems with the Droop Quota now, I'll still use it
 for these calculations).

I am sure it does have that problem. Say that the candidates are X Y Z
and X is eliminated and then Z wins. It seems quite possible that you
could add ZX ballots that cause Y to be eliminated instead of X, in 
which case Z will still be elected only if he beats Y head-to-head as 
well as X.

That's the unpredictability I'm talking about: The ZX voter would want
Z to continue to win, but the method may use the voter's X preference
to eliminate Y instead of X, causing Z to lose.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Throwing my hat into the ring, possibly to get trampled

2012-06-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Nicholas,

I think that your basic method (page 2 of html version) is the same as 

QLTD:
http://www.mcdougall.org.uk/VM/ISSUE6/P4.HTM

I say this because the multiplier is expressed in terms of ranking slots
and a candidate is allowed to win with only part of a subsequent slot
instead of only in increments of entire slots.


So your full method is what I would call QLTD elimination because you
repeatedly eliminate the QLTD loser. (Hopefully I haven't misunderstood 

the definition.)


Elimination+Recalculation methods are bad for monotonicity because the 

way information can be used for or against candidates is usually not 

predictable. It would need to be quite clear how other candidates will 

fare when another candidate is eliminated.

Participation is satisfied by simple point scoring methods. I doubt it is
compatible with elimination+recalculations. The problem is that you need
to guarantee each voter that information will only work in certain ways,
but eliminations tend to have chaotic results.


__
 De : Nicholas Buckner nlbor...@gmail.com
À : Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com 
Cc : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 9 juin 2012 4h04
Objet : Re: [EM] Throwing my hat into the ring, possibly to get trampled
 
Thank you for that information. I thought IIA referred to adding of
irrelevant alternatives, not removing them. As a consequence I didn't
look as strongly at criterions I thought were incompatible, from the
Condorcet criterion group.

Basically adding them is a problem if removing them is. If there are only two
candidates A and B and you add a new candidate C, and change the winner from 

A to B, then you could also take the new situation, and remove C from it, and
thereby change the winner from B to A.

You wrote originally I developed an alternative method that takes the 

Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives path over the Condorcet path. Do you
know that we don't have *any* serious rank methods that satisfy IIA? For
example, STV doesn't satisfy it either.

Kevin


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] FBC vs Condorcet's Criterion

2012-05-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Kristofer,


De : Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com
À : Michael Ossipoff email9648...@gmail.com 
Cc : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mercredi 9 mai 2012 9h54
Objet : Re: [EM] FBC vs Condorcet's Criterion


On 05/08/2012 08:46 PM, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 Since Richard wants to make a which one wins comparison between
 FBC and Condorcet's Criterion (CC), then I'll remind him that, when
 FBC failure sufficiently makes its problem, CC compiance becomes
 quite meaningless and valueless. And there is good reason to believe,
 as described in my previous post, that Condorcet's FBC failure _will_
 fully make its problem in our public elections.

I'll get to your larger post later, but it seems what need isn't FBC as such, 
but rather u/a FBC.

Here's a Condorcet method I think meets u/a FBC: Each voter submits a ranked 
ballot with an Approval cutoff. The most Approved candidate in the Smith set 
wins.

If everybody ranks Approval style, then this becomes Approval. So let's see if 
there's any reason to favorite betray instead of ranking Approval style.

If there is no cycle, then you can't make an acceptable have a greater chance 
of winning over an unacceptable by ranking Compromise over Favorite versus 
ranking Favorite over Compromise.

If there's a cycle and Favorite is in the Smith set, but Compromise is not, 
then the only reason for getting Compromise into the Smith set would be to 
defend against an unacceptable candidate winning. However, you can do that by 
just voting Approval style. Since Smith set members are only beaten by other 
Smith set members, Favorite vs Compromise doesn't enter into it as long as 
you put both above the cutoff and all the unacceptables below it.

If there's a cycle and Compromise is in the Smith set, but Favorite is not, 
then because this is an u/a election, it doesn't matter. You'll still get an 
acceptable.

If there's a cycle and neither Compromise nor Favorite is in the Smith set, 
then voting Approval style will make Compromise and Favorite both maximally 
work to push the unacceptables out of the Smith set.

Hence it seems that the method above meets u/a FBC. By the time people get 
past u/a, they'll no longer be overcompromising and so proper FBC failure 
doesn't matter. So Condorcet can meet u/a FBC.

I'm not saying Smith,Approval is necessarily a good method, but I only have to 
show a single method to disprove that u/a FBC and Condorcet is incompatible.

Did you cover the scenario where both Favorite and Compromise are in the Smith 
set? If not, is there some reason
for u/a FBC (whose definition I don't actually know) why this scenario doesn't 
matter?

In general the way C//A methods fail FBC is by creating incentive to make 
Compromise beat Favorite because Worst
will win the approval tiebreaker.

Thanks.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] ICT definition. Presumed Kemeny definition.

2012-04-23 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,



ICT definition:

(as described by Chris Benham, unless I've made an error)

Iff the number of voters ranking X over Y, plus the number of voters 
equal-top-rating X and Y, is greater than the 
number of voters ranking Y over X, then X beats Y. 

Of course that's a very weak meaning for beat, and it's possible for X and Y 
to both beat eachother in that sense. Of course, when
I say beat (with or without the quotes), I mean it in the above-defined 
sense.

If there's exactly one beats-all candidate (candidate who beats all of the 
others), then s/he wins.

If not, then the winner is the beats-all candidatate who is ranked in 1st 
place on the most ballots.

[end of ICT definition]

As I said, ICT meets FBC, and is defection resistant. Maybe so 
defection-resistant as to be called defection-proof.

If Kevin /or Chis are listening right now, I have a question:

What if, instead of defining beat as above, I said:

X is unbeaten by Y iff the number of voters ranking X over Y, plus the number 
of voters equal-top-ranking X and Y, is at least equal
to the number of voters ranking Y over X.

If there is exactly one candidate not beaten by anyone, then s/he wins.

Otherwise, the winner is the unbeaten candidate who is ranked in 1st place on 
the most ballots

[end of questioned alternative definition of ICT]

Would that still meet FBC and be defection-resistant? Would it lack some other 
desirable property,
or acquire some undesirable property?

I haven't looked at ICT really. But your revised wording is how ICA is worded. 
It directs you to look
for a single unbeaten candidate. I think it sounds better to say you're picking 
the winner from among the
undefeated candidates, than from among the candidates who defeated everybody 
including each other.

I'm pretty sure your definitions are identical... Unless I'm missing something 
really obvious.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] ICT definition. Presumed Kemeny definition.

2012-04-23 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Kristofer,


De : Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com
À : Michael Ossipoff email9648...@gmail.com 
Cc : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 23 avril 2012 16h00
Objet : Re: [EM] ICT definition. Presumed Kemeny definition.


On 04/23/2012 10:32 PM, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 ICT:
 
 Kevin Venzke proposed ICA. Improved-Condorcet-Approval.
 
 ICA  passes FBC. The part of ICA that ICT uses is the Improved Condorcet
 part. But instead of completing IC with
 Approval, it completes it by electing the IC winner ranked top on the
 most ballots.
 
 ICT was introduced by Chris Benham. He gave it a longer name with longer
 abbreviation-initials. I'm calling it ICT,
 consistent with Keven Venzke's naming of ICA.

What's the advantage of ICT over ICA?

I'm pretty sure Mike judges ICT to be defection-resistant while ICA isn't.

Maybe predictably, I am a bit afraid of ICT because I don't think it's good for 
voters to be
able to thwart another candidate's CW status, by ranking candidate Z over him, 
without the
voter having to support Z in some sense during the cycle-breaker.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Newbie to the list here

2012-03-12 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Peter,

3. I think that plurality is the worst possible of the voting systems 
that do not involve randomness, except for antiplurality voting.
 
Nice, I got as far as I think that plurality is the worst 
possible... before thinking to myself I have antiplurality performing
worse, and what do you know, you thought of that. And random methods
are a pretty good exception too.
 
4. I have been checking in the electowiki archives once in a blue 
moon for some time, and finally decided to subscribe.
7. I have not seen any (not that I have looked for it all that 
studiously) FAQ being reposted. What is the best way of knowing 
whether a topic has been flogged to death before one posts on it 
yet again?
 
Since it seems that you know about the archives I don't think there
is anything else you can consult. There is no gospel truth on this
list... We have total agreement on very little.
 
It would be interesting to come up with a FAQ that outlines the 
various positions people take on age old issues. But I guess a
lot of perspectives could be attributed to exactly one person each.
And I'm not sure a collaborative approach would ever complete a 
version that everybody would be happy with...
 
Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Obvious Approval advantages. SODA. Approval-Runoff.

2012-03-11 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,


De : Abd ul-Rahman Lomax a...@lomaxdesign.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr; election-methods 
election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 10 mars 2012 8h30
Objet : Re: [EM] Obvious Approval advantages. SODA. Approval-Runoff.


While discussion of strategies whereby a political party might attempt to 
manipulate Bucklin/runoff is interesting, we should be careful not to treat 
these hazards as if they were facts, unless there are facts to back them.

I'm assuming the question is more is this a method that would be good to spend 
effort advocating not
is this a good method if we can magically just have it implemented.

It is a fact that the method's logic makes no effort to pick a representative 
final pairing. It's quite possible
for the final round to be meaningless to most voters. In the method's defense 
one can speculate that
it would probably never be an issue. But the thing is that I don't think that's 
a very strong defense, particularly
considering that (as far as I can see) there's no strong reason to use this 
specific method.

It sounds like you somehow view this as a free reform. If you know how to 
enact this method for free
then by all means, give it a try.

Personally I don't care for it because it doesn't seem anyone knows what it 
would be, or is supposed to be.
I understand that in theory you're taking standard Approval and adding a step 
to the end. But in practice that 
isn't what you have, because the first round of the runoff doesn't have the 
same incentives as Approval. The 
incentive to get it as right as possible in one round doesn't necessarily 
exist. That's the incentive that drives 
Approval's outcomes towards the center. I'm concerned that the runoff, similar 
to a standard runoff, will
pick its finalists too arbitrarily.

This is *not* a major problem in real elections. Ties occur for other reasons, 
i.e., factions in the electorate are divided. It's the opposite of cloning. 
It's not a major problem because political forces don't favor it. True clones 
will have the same set of supporters, largely, and those supporters will select 
one of them. If the clones fight each other and don't cooperate, then they 
aren't clones, and the supporters will take one side or another. (And weaken 
the faction's power. This narrow selfishness has natural consequences.) The 
political forces favor complete cooperation, and it won't be done by fielding 
both candidates in the public election, when that choice can be made much more 
efficiently and effectively within the faction.

In real elections we generally have the sense not to enact methods that 
encourage cloning. I agree there are 
some inherent disadvantages to deliberate cloning, but I wouldn't assume that 
these disadvantages will outweigh
any other incentive we can come up with. For instance, I don't think a Borda 
proposal will ever get off the 
ground.

 
 Number three. The strategy assumes that there will be no rivalry between the 
 two candidates. Even if they are in cahoots, their supporters may not be.
 
 
 You'd pick a second candidate who doesn't have supporters.

Who therefore doesn't have a prayer. Put them on the ballot, supporters will 
appear. The original candidate, through this silly strategy, has split his own 
party. Brilliant. Next case.

 
 
 Number four. Who gets the campaign funds?
 
 
 It's a single campaign, so it doesn't matter. Presumably the serious nominee 
 gets them.

Single campaign? No, there are two candidates. Sure, they could share ads. 
I'm running for dogcatcher, but I'd also like to recommend my friend, here, 
Ralph. Ralph, would you like to say a few words about how we are equally 
qualified for the job, and would you like to ask the public to vote for both 
of us?

As a voter, I'd think, these guys are nutty. If they are both equally 
qualified, why didn't they just decide which one of them should run. Toss a 
coin or something, and spare us the election process.

Remember, if both these guys make it into the runoff, they have wasted the 
city's money on a useless runoff election. Sorry, this strategy is a blatantly 
losing one. Political suicide, like a lot of theoretical methods of 
manipulating voting systems.

The main candidate doesn't attempt to claim that his companion is also running 
for the job. He says vote for us so
that I can win, in place of risking losing in a runoff. His companion doesn't 
claim to be trying to win.

You speculate put them on the ballot, supporters will appear. Well, I do 
believe that e.g. Huntsman and Perry 
received a few votes in Ohio recently, but at least they had hoped to win in 
the past.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Obvious Approval advantages. SODA. Approval-Runoff.

2012-03-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,


De : Abd ul-Rahman Lomax a...@lomaxdesign.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr; election-methods 
election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 9 mars 2012 17h04
Objet : Re: [EM] Obvious Approval advantages. SODA. Approval-Runoff.


At 07:36 PM 3/8/2012, Kevin Venzke wrote:
 Hi Mike,
 
 I don't think Approval-Runoff can get off the ground since it's too
 apparent that a party could nominate two candidates (signaling that one
 is just a pawn to aid the other) and try to win by grabbing both of the
 finalist positions. If this happened regularly it would be just an
 expensive version of FPP.

Number one. This objection does not apply to nonpartisan elections.

Not sure why it couldn't. You just wouldn't have a party, as such, executing 
the strategy.

Number two. The strongest factor in elections is positive name recognition. 
That's become obvious. By running two candidates, you are diluting name 
recognition. If you have one, you might win. With two, quite possibly not. 
Risky strategy.

Possibly true.

Number three. The strategy assumes that there will be no rivalry between the 
two candidates. Even if they are in cahoots, their supporters may not be.

You'd pick a second candidate who doesn't have supporters.



Number four. Who gets the campaign funds?

It's a single campaign, so it doesn't matter. Presumably the serious nominee 
gets them.



Number five. Others can play the same game, if it's a real strategy. I don't 
think it is.

I was actually assuming everybody (at least major candidates) would play the 
same game. The problem 
is that the second round doesn't play the role it was supposed to if this 
happens.



Number six. If this is a partisan election, who gets the party slot? The 
strategy could badly backfire, as supporters of the non-party candidate decide 
not to support the official party candidate, after all, the party made a bad 
choice. No, the tradition is strong, and there are strong reasons for it, that 
a party unites on a candidate. It's more powerful.

This seems to be the same as number three.



Number seven. If both candidates make it into the runoff, very good chance one 
of them would win anyway. This means that they are top two, really. If this is 
nonpartisan, very difficult to reverse that.

The intention of the first round is to pick two finalists who are likely to be 
the best winner. So if one finalist
gets both positions by running a weak clone, his odds of being the one who 
would have won anyway are 
probably better than half, yes. The criticism is that the second round serves 
little purpose if that's what is
happening.

Number eight. You might be able to figure out a scenario where this makes some 
sense.

Now, compare that scenario with the real and known hazard of center squeeze.

And where should that lead me? You know that nobody is backed into a corner 
where they have to
advocate either an approval runoff or nothing.


Besides, once we are Counting All the Votes, a ranked version of approval 
becomes far better.

My simulations do often find that specific rank/approval hybrids are the best 
wrt minimizing insincerity and
electing sincere CWs and utility maximizers. It depends on the scenario, but 
JGA's Approval-Weighted
Pairwise is often the best Condorcet method and my various Single Contest 
methods are usually the
best non-Condorcet ones (especially wrt sincerity).

Single Contest methods are actually like an instant approval runoff, except 
the finalists are the two 
candidates who together minimize the number of voters who approved neither of 
them.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Obvious Approval advantages. SODA. Approval-Runoff.

2012-03-08 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,
 
I don't think Approval-Runoff can get off the ground since it's too
apparent that a party could nominate two candidates (signaling that one
is just a pawn to aid the other) and try to win by grabbing both of the
finalist positions. If this happened regularly it would be just an 
expensive version of FPP.
 
SODA actually does allow you to not delegate via checking a box. But
a version that required delegation might be interesting because it
wouldn't require an approval plus checkbox ballot, it would just need
a vote-for-one ballot.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] correction

2012-03-08 Thread Kevin Venzke



De : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
À : election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Jeudi 8 mars 2012 18h36
Objet : Re: [EM] Obvious Approval advantages. SODA. Approval-Runoff.



Hi Mike,
 
I don't think Approval-Runoff can get off the ground since it's too
apparent that a party could nominate two candidates (signaling that one
is just a pawn to aid the other) and try to win by grabbing both of the
finalist positions. If this happened regularly it would be just an 
expensive version of FPP.
 
Actually, it would be an expensive version of Approval.
 
Still, I am not sure why it would be any easier to propose an approval
runoff vs. plain approval.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Kevin: FBC deleted from electowiki?

2012-03-05 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,

De : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com
À : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 5 mars 2012 15h19
Objet : [EM] Kevin: FBC deleted from electowiki?


Kevin:

You wrote:

Did they use a special term for this property?We used to have an FBC page on 
Wikipedia, based on content from Russ' site I believe, but eventually this was 
removed

[endquote]

Yes, that's why I don't have much use for electowiki. Something that I put up 
can later be modified or deleted
by anyone.
 
I'm referring to Wikipedia itself, not the Electowiki. An article surely
is still available on Electowiki.
 

You continued:


 since the notability is unclear. 
[endquote]


What is notability?

On Wikipedia they remove articles if you can't show sources to argue that
the topic is important enough to have an article.
 
Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Kevin: My failure scenario was erroneous for ABucklin

2012-03-03 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,


De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com 
Cc : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 2 mars 2012 13h13
Objet : Re: [EM] Kevin: My failure scenario was erroneous for ABucklin



Also, since ABucklin is in all significant regards identical to MJ, Balinski 
and Laraki's proof that MJ meets FBC works verbatim for ABucklin. 


Jameson

Did they use a special term for this property?

We used to have an FBC page on Wikipedia, based on content from Russ' site I 
believe, but eventually this
was removed since the notability is unclear.

The big difference between ABucklin and MJ is that in the former, raising and 
lowering a candidate can alter
the stage at which other candidates attain majority.

It occurred to me that it could happen that if you change
ABCDE
to
A=DBCE

This could probably move the win from B to C or E. But then you could 
just top-rank B to prevent it.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Better Approval-voting option? Could ABucklin fail FBC?

2012-03-01 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,


De : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com
À : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Jeudi 1 mars 2012 15h55
Objet : [EM] Better Approval-voting option? Could ABucklin fail FBC?


But could this happen?:

If you rank your favorite, F,  in 1st place, s/he gets a majority, even though 
s/he doesn't win, because someone else has a higher
majority. 

A number of people rank F, and, if you help F get a majority, then they won't 
give a vote to their next choice.

That's regrettable, because their next choice could win with those votes, 
while F can't win. And when their next choice doesn't win,
someone worse than s/he (as judged by you) wins.

You got a worse result because you didn't favorite-bury.

So maybe, even if that scenario is merely possible, I shouldn't propose 
Stepwise-to-Majority unless it turns out that the FBC-failure scenario
can't happen.

But more worrying is the fact that one could tell that same story about 
ABucklin (the ER-Bucklin defined at electowiki).

Of course a vague verbal scenario like the above might not have an actual 
numerical example that can carry it out. There might
be some reason why such an example couldn't work. Still, it's worrying.

Does anyone know if there's actually a proof that ER-Bucklin meets FBC?  

Can it be shown that the verbal FBC-Failure scenario described above couldn't 
really happen?

Might ABucklin fail FBC?

I want to help but I'm not sure I understand the failure scenario you
described.

With three candidates ER-Bucklin(whole) gives the same results as MCA.
There can't be much doubt that MCA satisfies FBC. But maybe you have in
mind a scenario with more than three candidates?
 
Off the top of my head I would argue that ERBW satisfies FBC because
when you raise your favorite to equal-top, this can only delay the
reception of votes for candidates that you like less than your top
candidates (because it's only on your own ballot that this has an 
effect). You aren't doing anything to delay acquisition of votes by
your top-ranked compromise choice from other voters.

Any thoughts?

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] An interesting scenario (spoilers, utility)

2012-02-29 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hello,

I have been adding some code to help investigate cases where Approval
shows greater perception of spoiler than, say, IRV. To make the 
scenarios easier to visualize I just allocated six voting factions 
proportionately along 1D, positions ranging from -1 to 1.
 
I found an interesting case with the candidate positions:
.939, 0.333, -.06  (call them A, B, C)
 
Approval showed perception of spoiler as 27%, whereas IRV, TTR, and FPP
showed none. So I checked to see if it was consistent and what was 
happening.
 
With six blocs the scenario looks roughly like this (with the pipe
indicating the location of average utility for the bloc):
~3 CB | A
~1 BC | A
~1 BA | C
~1 A | BC
 
Under IRV, all votes were sincere. Under FPP and TTR, the lone A bloc
was compromising and voting for B. The result was that the sincere CW
(either C or B) was always winning and no one perceived spoilers.
 
Under Approval, the CB voters bullet-voted, the two B blocs voted for
their top two candidates, and the A bloc bullet-voted.
 
(A much rarer outcome had the BC faction bullet-voting, with the BA
and A factions voting for both A and B, giving the same result as the
other three methods. I think it's clear that this outcome was rarer
because the BC voters are happier with settling for C than the A 
voters are with settling for B.)
 
The result of this is that Approval was only electing the sincere CW
half the time. Instead of alternating between C and B winning, C won by
far the most often. B or A won rarely (and, I'd say, largely thanks
to the AI confusion that results from one candidate winning most of
the time).
 
Note that C is easily the closest candidate to the median. Even when 
B has a majority win over C, B is still not likely to be the utility 
maximizer. Approval's success rate at electing the utility maximizer 
was thus nearly perfect (instead of 50%).
 
I'm not sure what I think of this personally. I'm sure this scenario
isn't any kind of general rule for Approval, but suppose that it was?
Would it be a viable trade-off, to elect the utility maximizer more
often, in exchange for more complaints about spoiled elections?
 
Kevin Venzke

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] The oldest bad-example trick in the book

2012-02-29 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,

Personally I don't think anyone is wronged in the MMPO example.
I just don't think voters would accept it, and it would be difficult
to advocate. People will ask how the outcome can possibly make sense
and I don't think you can reassure them by asking who's wronged.

The issue isn't really favoriteness but the near lack of any votes
at all. Most people expect winning candidates to have their own
positive support, not just lack of opposition.

That said, the voters could see themselves as wronged if they felt
it was strategically advisable under the method to truncate. You
suggest that if the A voters really preferred B (the other big
candidate) to C (tiny candidate) then they should have voted for A
and B? I for one can't see myself doing that. The apparent front-
runners are A and B and I wouldn't vote for the worse frontrunner 
under MMPO. It makes more sense to try to deter burial attempts than
to defend against an extremely unlikely C victory.
 
But I don't want to discourage you from supporting MMPO. The first 
method I ever invented was in effect MMPO on approval ballots. I 
have a soft spot for this mechanic.
 
Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] C/D is persistent. Another Approval C/D mitigation. IRV and sincerity.

2012-02-28 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,


De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com 
Cc : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mardi 28 février 2012 15h29
Objet : Re: [EM] C/D is persistent. Another Approval C/D mitigation. IRV and 
sincerity.


(Though I'd still really appreciate it if you made quick electowiki pages for 
all of that, because I'd bet that nobody but you actually knows what every one 
of those means, and it would be considerate of you not to ask us to 
continually look up all the definitions and redefinitions in the archives).


Jameson


2012/2/28 MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com

The methods that I've been suggesting, to get rid of the C/D problem--I'll 
refer to those as 
defection-resistant methods. They include AOC, MTAOC, MCAOC, AOCBucklin, 
AC, MTAC,
MCAC, ACBudklin, MMT, GMAT, and ICT.


Also, if any good ones need to be tested for FBC compliance, my sim is
pretty accurate at finding this via its percentage of voters deciding to
compromise statistic. FBC methods tend to show zero.

It doesn't provide anything that could be used as a proof though.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Kevin V, Richard F., Raph F

2012-02-21 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi David,





 De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 20 février 2012 13h18
Objet : Re: [EM] Kevin V, Richard F., Raph F
 


From: Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
To: election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com
Cc: 
Date: Mon, 20 Feb 2012 03:01:06 + (GMT)
Subject: Re: [EM] Kevin V.
Hi David,

KV:The similarity is that with SODA, you (and like-minded candidates) get a 
benefit even if you don't
win. Under normal methods you have the inherent pressure against running 
clones (that I think we both
agree exists) with little possible benefit in nominating them.

dlw: What is the benefit?  You might get lucky?  There'd be pressure in real 
life against clones running
regardless and so the strength of the effect is still an empirical 
question.  
 
The benefits are
1. to the candidate: still gets to influence the result even if he loses
2. to the voter: greater chance of having somebody palatable to vote for 
without wasting the vote
3. to the candidate's party: the candidate can attract voters that might not 
have bothered voting if there
had only been one nominee.



dlw: If it's really a clone then 2 seem like a stretch.   For 1 and 3, why not 
just hire more campaign staff to GOTV?  

They're clones in the sense that they come from the same party and are 
expected to transfer votes to each other
once they lose.

I don't understand how you're responding to 1. That point is saying that even 
if I only get 5% of the vote I still
have some influence in who will win.

Regarding 3: This is related to 2. If the voter likes Cain and hates Gingrich 
you can't simply hire more staff to make 

him like Gingrich instead.




 
The main factor working against nominating clones in most methods is that it 
risks dividing up the voters
such that they refuse to vote for all the like-minded candidates. If voters 
actually delegate power to a candidate
(which is a little uncertain) the risk of this is reduced.



dlw: It also imposes higher costs on voters in terms of getting to know the 
candidates and figuring out that so-and-so are clones... 

Yes, under most methods it does, because the voters would have to list all the 
clones for it to count.




 
By difficult to tabulate I was talking about IRV itself. But no matter:

dlw: Maybe that's why I'm pushing IRV+???
 
Ok, maybe I should take that literally, that you want to use an approval 
filter because it makes IRV easier
to tabulate. I don't know what else the lack of example scenarios could mean.



My motivation is pragmatic, or problem-solving driven, rather than based on 
stylized hypotheticals.. 

Ok. In reference to the approval component I can believe that.





KV:Ok, so you are married to IRV or variants because of its first mover 
status. Then my question switches
to how the approval rule helps it. Do you have a scenario on-hand that 
shows your method doing something
preferable to what IRV normally would do? I can't think of what the 
expected difference would be, except
when somehow the second-place (on first preferences) candidate isn't among 
the top three approved. Are
you thinking of a Chirac/Jospin/Le Pen scenario (2002 French presidential 
election)? Though that would
not even have happened under IRV.

dlw: Speeding up the election and simplifying the use of IRV are enuf to 
justify the use of IRV+ over IRV,
especially for bigger elections.  It doesn't matter how often it'd get a 
different outcome.  There'd be no recursion
in the explanation of how it'd work and that'd be one less arg that 
opponents of electoral reform could use
against it.  
Plus, almost all of the args used by advocates of Approval Voting against 
IRV would get watered down...,
cuz the simple fact of the matter is that IRV works best with only 3 
candidates.  

I don't buy that second paragraph at all. Contrived IRV bad examples usually 
don't need more than three.
Do you know one that requires four?



dlw: Well, it's the least important for me personally of the args, hence why 
it's listed last.
It's easiest to give bad egs with 3 candidates.  That doesn't mean they don't 
also exist for more than 3.  

If you know of examples where order of elimination matters in a cascading 
fashion then that'd make a great example for IRV+.   
As for IRV working best with only 3 candidates, the pathological examples 
emerge only in the relatively rare case of competitive 3 way elections
and those are relatively rare and not stable so the use of less ranking info 
by IRV relative to Condorcet methods would be less important w. only 3 
candidates and so on...

Ok.

I'm not too sure what else can be said, if you're mainly trying to simplify a 
method that you see yourself as forced to pick.


I don't think that any parties so at odds with the Democrats or Republicans
that they can't run under those labels, are the parties we are looking for.
 
I think that if, under whatever rules were in place

Re: [EM] Conditionality-by-top-count probably violates FBC

2012-02-19 Thread Kevin Venzke
Does anyone understand why the DH3 concept exists? Why envision three major 
blocs, instead of two major blocs plus the small bloc belonging
to the pawn candidate? That doesn't require four candidates and more closely 
resembles how burial problems are usually considered...


Kevin




 De : Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com
À : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com 
Cc : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com; election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Dimanche 19 février 2012 7h48
Objet : Re: [EM] Conditionality-by-top-count probably violates FBC
 
On 02/15/2012 06:08 PM, Jameson Quinn wrote:
 But conditionality-by-mutuality violates later-no-help, and as such,
 raises the spectre of a DH3 http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/DH3-like
 scenario.

I think you can have burial in methods that pass LNHelp too, unless the method 
also passes LNHarm. LNHelp-complying methods could still reward a move from, 
say, ABC to ACB (where the point would be to keep B from winning more than 
to get A to win).

See, for instance, Kevin Venzke's post: 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2011-February/027098.html
 , or James Green-Armytage's: 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2011-February/027091.html
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] (Kevin Venzke) and Richard Fobes.

2012-02-19 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi David,




 De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 18 février 2012 16h58
Objet : Re: [EM] (Kevin Venzke) and Richard Fobes.
 
 
That doesn't make much sense to me. The election method is a part of the system 
and it has an obvious effect on how
many candidates could run.


dlw: It depends on the size of the effect of the election method.  There still 
are cost-benefit rationales that would keep the number of serious candidates 
down, depending of course on the size and importance of the election.  Ceteris 
paribus, to have a party institution behind you will make a difference 
regardless of what election method gets used.  

Well, in SODA's case, I think the size of the effect is probably massive. It 
reminds me of the open party list in Brazil.


dlw: Aye, but that's multi-winner.  Multi-winner vs single-winner is a major 
effect.  We were talking amongst single-winner election rules.  

The similarity is that with SODA, you (and like-minded candidates) get a 
benefit even if you don't win. Under normal methods you have the inherent 
pressure
against running clones (that I think we both agree exists) with little possible 
benefit in nominating them.










 
and so what relative advantages there are of SODA over IRV will be less, 
which then makes the first-mover marketing problem more significant, 
especially if IRV can be souped up with the seemingly slight modification of 
the use of a limited form of approval voting in the first stage.


dlw
 
If I remember correctly your idea is to use approval to pick finalists. I 
don't think this is a good idea because it breaks
clone independence, which is an IRV selling point. 


But does it break it strongly?  Let there be A, B, and C.  Let BB be a B clone.
The field is split 30.1-40-29.9.  Normally B wins.  If BB enters then either B 
or BB gets eliminated in the first round but then their votes transfer to 
whoever remains and so the outcome wouldn't change.  You'd need to have a 
crowded field so that an original finalist and their clone would both get 
eliminated.  If either the original winner and clone(s) got eliminated, which 
would be harder, in all likelihood, or you might change the order of 
elimination in the 2nd round so that there'd be a different winner. 

I don't think you get the concern. It's not clone-winner, it's clone-loser. 
Suppose the original winner was 3rd place on approval. Then clone one of the 
other two candidates to 
shut out the original winner. 

[sarcasm]That sounds realistic.[/sarcasm]  You realize that the approval 
votes are just the number of (up to 3) rankings a candidate receives?  How 
often do you think you can clone one of the other 2 and thereby shutout the 
winner?  I'd love to see an example of that.  If the winner is preferred to the 
top-2 ranked-vote getters then if they were cloned, it'd not be the eventual 
winner who'd lose out on approval votes.  

I didn't know you could only have three rankings. I agree it is difficult to 
construct the scenario where it actually works.


 
They don't even need to know whether 3rd place was going to win, it should just 
be the standard nomination strategy. If you nominate three, you 
could even win the entire race just on
 approval. There's some risk to this strategy (voters may not agree to approve 
everyone their party wants), but if a party so much as tries
to use this strategy the method will look dumb. You should be really clear on 
what you're trying to do if you want to tell people to use a mechanic that 
looks manipulable.


If you can give me a robust example of this, ie one that's not on a knife edge, 
I will abandon the idea.  
JQ tried to do this a while back for a slightly different matter and it was 
very hard to do and he eventually agreed that it worked, except for how it 
tended to reenforce the 2-party domination thing that he believes (along with 
others) is the bane of democracy.   


Well, I don't understand how you see it aiding anything. If you place third or 
worse on first preferences you will almost certainly lose. It doesn't really 
matter if
every voter approved you.





 


For me, I think there are real world safeguards against clones in politics and 
so to be 100% clone independence is not important.  

I kind of agree with that, but only for cloning winners.


I'm not worried about cloning non-winners.   

In your method or in general?? I don't see how it can be denied that parties 
would nominate many candidates for a single seat if that was the best strategy 
for
winning. We can find examples of parties using the electoral method in 
unexpected ways (Taiwan and Italy occur to me), and we also have the open party 
list
tactic of nominating more candidates than there are even seats to be won.





 
If your goal is to e.g. not elect Condorcet winners who place third,


I don't think my goal is not to elect CW's who get 3rd amount of top

Re: [EM] Conditionality-by-top-count probably violates FBC

2012-02-19 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,





De : Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Dimanche 19 février 2012 15h28
Objet : Re: [EM] Conditionality-by-top-count probably violates FBC

On 02/19/2012 09:37 PM, Kevin Venzke wrote:
 Does anyone understand why the DH3 concept exists? Why envision three
 major blocs, instead of two major blocs plus the small bloc belonging
 to the pawn candidate? That doesn't require four candidates and more
 closely resembles how burial problems are usually considered...

If there are just two blocs, then the DH3 scenario never gets off the ground. 
Say you have a nobody, Z, and two viable candidates (A and B). Then say the 
honest ballots are something like:

53: A  B  Z
46: B  A  Z
1: Z  A = B

Then the B-supporters can't get the ball rolling, at least not in Condorcet, by 
burying A. Even if they do so, A will win by first preferences alone.

Technically speaking, it takes three viables to make a cycle, and you need 
cycle-making/turning strategy to make DH3 work in Condorcet. In Borda, you 
could do a sort of DH3 with only two blocs, but that's because Borda doesn't 
satisfy Majority.


Yes, I don't understand why it would be viewed this way. I.e. why would one 
assume that two major blocs means one bloc is a majority. I think a
pawn could have 10% or even more of the votes. It's as though one wants to be 
sure to be able to say that absolutely nobody likes the pawn.

I think that if DH3 could ever actually happen it would be better news than 
bad, just because it would mean we are able to have three blocs like that!

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] élection de trois élection de trois

2012-02-19 Thread Kevin Venzke
They are quirky because of IIA. The papers on this are from the 1970's. Quote 
Wikipedia:
 
The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem, named after Allan Gibbard and Mark 
Satterthwaite, is a 
result about the deterministic voting systems that choose a single winner using 
only the preferences 
of the voters, where each voter ranks all candidates in order of preference. 
The Gibbard–Satterthwaite 
theorem states that, for three or more candidates, one of the following three 
things must hold for every 
voting rule:
1. The rule is dictatorial (i.e., there is a single individual who can 
choose the winner), or 
2. There is some candidate who can never win, under the rule, or 
3. The rule is susceptible to tactical voting, in the sense that there 
are conditions under which a voter 
with full knowledge of how the other voters are to vote and of the rule being 
used would have an incentive to vote in a manner that does not reflect his 
preferences. 
 
I do wish we only posted in text. If I quote an html email as text I don't get 
any  symbols anymore to mark
what the other person said. And if I quote it as html, I have to supply my own 
indentation and still don't get 
any marker next to the quoted text.
 
Kevin
 
 

De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com 
Cc : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Dimanche 19 février 2012 19h53
Objet : [EM] élection de trois élection de trois


It seems quite a few election rules get quirky in one way or the other with a 
3-way competitive election.

That might be a point worth considering in the abstract in a paper or 
something why are 3-way single-winner elections quirky? 

dlw


On Sun, Feb 19, 2012 at 5:31 PM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com wrote:

..., cuz the simple fact of the matter is that IRV works best with only 3 
candidates.  


2.5, actually.

Jameson 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] (Kevin Venzke) and Richard Fobes.

2012-02-19 Thread Kevin Venzke
(I've figured out how to quote since my last comment on that. I have no idea
why quoting a message is merely an option...)

- Mail original - (Richard wrote)
 Unfortunately none of the third parties in the U.S. are understanding this 
 opportunity.  The leaders at the top of those third parties are more 
 concerned about maintaining their control than representing frustrated voters.

I don't think that any parties so at odds with the Democrats or Republicans
that they can't run under those labels, are the parties we are looking for.
 
I think that if, under whatever rules were in place, there were room for three
contenders in an election, you would find not-too-unfamiliar-looking candidates
taking the third spot and trying to beat the Ds and Rs. With this situation, it
is at least possible that a general viewpoint (about as coherent as those of
the Ds and Rs) would come together and allow a third party including a label
for it.

It isn't obvious that a three-way race will still fight over the center though.
I am interested to study this, but it seems very hard to study voter strategy
and nomination strategy at the same time.

If party discipline were strengthened (though I can't imagine how that would
happen) I expect it would force some current Ds and Rs to leave and form new
minor parties. But I don't think this in itself would benefit voters much. I
think it would mean for many that there is even less of a real choice.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] (Kevin Venzke) and James Gilmour.

2012-02-18 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi David,





De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 18 février 2012 14h10
Objet : Re: [EM] (Kevin Venzke) and James Gilmour.


You are supposed to get the EM list to agree first, before writing Soros 
directly.


If there were such a pot at the end of the rainbow then maybe the EM list would 
have an incentive to agree.   

I like to think we don't agree because we think other people are mistaken. But 
if there were incentive to compromise I could see writing more posts on the 
subject of
reaching one.


 
But in the context of a 2-party dominated system, there aren't as many 
serious candidates 
 
 
That doesn't make much sense to me. The election method is a part of the 
system and it has an obvious effect on how
many candidates could run.

dlw: It depends on the size of the effect of the election method.  There still 
are cost-benefit rationales that would keep the number of serious candidates 
down, depending of course on the size and importance of the election.  Ceteris 
paribus, to have a party institution behind you will make a difference 
regardless of what election method gets used.  

Well, in SODA's case, I think the size of the effect is probably massive. It 
reminds me of the open party list in Brazil.






 
and so what relative advantages there are of SODA over IRV will be less, which 
then makes the first-mover marketing problem more significant, especially if 
IRV can be souped up with the seemingly slight modification of the use of a 
limited form of approval voting in the first stage.


dlw
 
If I remember correctly your idea is to use approval to pick finalists. I 
don't think this is a good idea because it breaks
clone independence, which is an IRV selling point. 

But does it break it strongly?  Let there be A, B, and C.  Let BB be a B clone.
The field is split 30.1-40-29.9.  Normally B wins.  If BB enters then either B 
or BB gets eliminated in the first round but then their votes transfer to 
whoever remains and so the outcome wouldn't change.  You'd need to have a 
crowded field so that an original finalist and their clone would both get 
eliminated.  If either the original winner and clone(s) got eliminated, which 
would be harder, in all likelihood, or you might change the order of 
elimination in the 2nd round so that there'd be a different winner. 

I don't think you get the concern. It's not clone-winner, it's clone-loser. 
Suppose the original winner was 3rd place on approval. Then clone one of the 
other two candidates to 
shut out the original winner. They don't even need to know whether 3rd place 
was going to win, it should just be the standard nomination strategy. If you 
nominate three, you 
could even win the entire race just on approval. There's some risk to this 
strategy (voters may not agree to approve everyone their party wants), but if a 
party so much as tries
to use this strategy the method will look dumb. You should be really clear on 
what you're trying to do if you want to tell people to use a mechanic that 
looks manipulable.

 


For me, I think there are real world safeguards against clones in politics and 
so to be 100% clone independence is not important.  

I kind of agree with that, but only for cloning winners.


 
If your goal is to e.g. not elect Condorcet winners who place third,

I don't think my goal is not to elect CW's who get 3rd amount of top-rankings 
among the three finalists.   I think the goal is to reduce the distance between 
the de facto center and the true center, 
while allowing that we don't know the true changing center and don't want to 
chase it too easily.  

That's a pretty unusual goal that I still don't quite get. (Why do you pick the 
terms de facto and true? Wouldn't it be anticipated vs. actual or 
something? If the true
changing center is the actual location of the median voter, how on earth does 
de facto contrast with this?)



 
I think you should use the Approval-IRV hybrid that eliminates the least 
approved candidate until there is a majority 
favorite. I call it AER... I think Woodall called it Approval AV.

dlw: IRV+ is easy to tabulate at the precinct level.  One could get the 3 
finalists on election night.
The next day the votes can be sorted into 10 categories, once again at the 
precinct level, and the results used to find the winner.  
This is  more important than clone independence, cuz the true winner(for normal 
irv) would be more immune to the existence of clones than other finalists.
I wish I understood what you feel makes IRV good and how you are trying to 
improve it. I'm pretty sure that if those were nailed down, you could find 
something easier and
better. Using approval you are already discarding the LNHarm guarantee. Why 
stick to something relatively difficult to tabulate? I don't think you can ride 
IRV's coattails if you 
won't keep the (demonstrable) properties of it. And picking finalists

Re: [EM] STV vs Party-list PR, could context matter?

2012-02-18 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Richard,





De : Richard Fobes electionmeth...@votefair.org
À : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 18 février 2012 14h47
Objet : Re: [EM] STV vs Party-list PR, could context matter?
 
I do favor having more than two parties, but I don't see how three (or more) 
strong parties can be accommodated until after Congress and state legislatures 
use voting methods that are compatible with more than two parties.

Do you have real world examples in mind here? Have you looked at assemblies, to 
which no executive is responsible, that are elected by party list or that
for some other reason have multiple parties?

I have trouble imagining that this is a major issue. Congressional rules based 
on the assumptions of there being two parties aren't in the U.S. constitution.
They can be changed. But they definitely won't see revisions until there is a 
need to revise them!

I think I might agree with you to some extent, in that I don't really care how 
many party labels there are. Whether there are two, three, ten, or zero, doesn't
tell me much of anything by itself.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Question about Schulze beatpath method

2012-02-17 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Robert,
 
Suppose there are four candidates ABCD. B beats A with strength of 10. C beats 
D with strength
of 20. With strength of 30, A beats C, B beats C, D beats A, and D beats B. 
Then every candidate
has a path to every other candidate, and the best path from A to B or from B to 
A involves traversing 
the CD win (which is the weakest link in those paths).
 
Kevin
 

De : robert bristow-johnson r...@audioimagination.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 17 février 2012 12h56
Objet : Re: [EM] Question about Schulze beatpath method

On 2/17/12 1:27 PM, Markus Schulze wrote:
 it can happen that the weakest link in the strongest path
 from candidate A to candidate B and the weakest link in the
 strongest path from candidate B to candidate A is the same link,
 say CD.

how can that be?  since a path is a *defeat* path.  you only traverse a 
beatpath from a candidate who beats the next candidate in the path.

is it that candidates C and D are exactly tied?  other than that, i cannot 
understand how the weakest link from A to B can be the same as *any* link from 
B to A.

-- 
r b-j                  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] JQ wrt SODA

2012-02-17 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi David,


De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 17 février 2012 13h37
Objet : Re: [EM] JQ wrt SODA


IRV's got a first mover advantage over SODA and to catch up you need to 
convince someone like Soros to help you market it.  It wouldn't matter if you 
got the whole EM list to agree with you that it was hunky-dory.  

You are supposed to get the EM list to agree first, before writing Soros 
directly.


But in the context of a 2-party dominated system, there aren't as many serious 
candidates 


That doesn't make much sense to me. The election method is a part of the system 
and it has an obvious effect on how
many candidates could run.

and so what relative advantages there are of SODA over IRV will be less, which 
then makes the first-mover marketing problem more significant, especially if 
IRV can be souped up with the seemingly slight modification of the use of a 
limited form of approval voting in the first stage.


dlw

If I remember correctly your idea is to use approval to pick finalists. I don't 
think this is a good idea because it breaks
clone independence, which is an IRV selling point. If your goal is to e.g. not 
elect Condorcet winners who place third,
I think you should use the Approval-IRV hybrid that eliminates the least 
approved candidate until there is a majority 
favorite. I call it AER... I think Woodall called it Approval AV.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
Just a few thoughts.

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com; electionsciencefoundation 
electionscie...@googlegroups.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 17 février 2012 9h20
Objet : [EM] SODA arguments


For those who feel that Bayesian Regret is the be-all-and-end-all measure of 
voting system quality, that SODA's BR for 100% strategic voters will beat all 
other systems, including Range/Approval. 

I guess you will have a hard time arguing this, especially if you have multiple 
audiences. For instance, whether Range/Approval
are even all that great is controversial. But if you're an anti-majoritarian 
type or think it's unfair/unrealistic to propose that voters
are strategic, I guess that SODA looks like a step down.

Didn't you post an example where SODA declined to elect a weak CW that you 
said was actually a good thing? If that's
true, I guess some people won't agree with that.

It seems to me that there would be a lot more candidates under SODA. It's 
pretty hard to spoil the race and there is benefit to
be had in receiving some votes. It seems parliamentary that way. How many 
supporters is too few to consider running?

(I have a simple rule for cutting down the number of candidates. I don't think 
I've ever mentioned it because I know how 
idealistic you all are. Just say that the first-preference winner auto-wins if 
he has more first preferences than second and third
place combined. This can make it risky even to compete for third place. The 
idea is that voters should definitely then realize
which candidates are the top three in their race, which could amount to a 
viability/visibility boost for #3. My rule assumes 
there's no equal-ranking, but I bet something could be devised for other 
ballots.)

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 


De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 17 février 2012 19h53
Objet : Re: [EM] SODA arguments




 
For those who feel that Bayesian Regret is the be-all-and-end-all measure of 
voting system quality, that SODA's BR for 100% strategic voters will beat 
all other systems, including Range/Approval. 

I guess you will have a hard time arguing this, especially if you have 
multiple audiences. For instance, whether Range/Approval
are even all that great is controversial. But if you're an anti-majoritarian 
type or think it's unfair/unrealistic to propose that voters
are strategic, I guess that SODA looks like a step down.


I'm not sure that's true. Clay and Warren are the most hard-core BR 
advocates, and probably I should let them speak for themselves, but... I 
think their attitude is not that strategy is evil or Range voters will be 
100% honest, but rather, Some fraction of voters will be honest under 
range, and that's good, so why not use range and let them? In that case, the 
fact that range voting is strictly better (by BR, and for a pre-chosen 
arbitrary strategic percentage) than [IRV, Condorcet, MJ, etc], is an 
important foundation of their argument. Finding a system which, while it is 
worse than range for 100% honest, is actually better than it in some cases 
(100% strategy, and presumably 99%, who knows where it stops), is an 
important qualitative difference in the situation.

Alright. I guess I'll let them make their own arguments if they are so inclined.


Didn't you post an example where SODA declined to elect a weak CW that you 
said was actually a good thing? If that's
true, I guess some people won't agree with that.


Yes. The basic setup is two major candidates and a weak centrist. The weaker 
of the two majors gets to decide which of the other two wins. So if the weak 
CW is truly a CW, they will be preferred by the weaker major, and thus win; 
but if they are more weak than CW, then the weaker major would rather allow 
the stronger major to win than stake their reputation on electing the weak CW.


So in the end, it's more a question of giving a last chance to realize that 
someone isn't really the CW, rather than not electing someone who is the CW.


Concerns me a little. I'm not sure candidates would do the thing their 
supporters would want (or even that they themselves feel is 
best) due to pressures like staking their reputation. For instance, I can see 
a moderate liberal giving his votes to a more extreme
liberal even when he himself prefers a moderate conservative. A voter whose 
personal ranking crosses the line like that might
want to avoid delegating.




It seems to me that there would be a lot more candidates under SODA. It's 
pretty hard to spoil the race and there is benefit to
be had in receiving some votes. It seems parliamentary that way. How many 
supporters is too few to consider running?


Well, there is the 5% cutoff, below which your votes are automatically 
assigned for you.


That's not really a punishment though. The candidate will probably get what 
they would've done anyway.

I really think this is an issue that might need a rule of some kind. Why 
nominate one when you can nominate five? Anybody
who appeals to some segment of the electorate could help bring in votes. Can 
you imagine if, for example, the Republicans
were able to nominate every single one of their hopefuls for the presidency, 
with the knowledge that in the end all their votes
would probably pool together? You don't have to like Gingrich, you can vote for 
Cain. And maybe your vote will end up
with Gingrich, but without Cain you might not have cast it at all.
 



(I have a simple rule for cutting down the number of candidates. I don't 
think I've ever mentioned it because I know how 
idealistic you all are. Just say that the first-preference winner auto-wins 
if he has more first preferences than second and third
place combined. This can make it risky even to compete for third place. The 
idea is that voters should definitely then realize
which candidates are the top three in their race, which could amount to a 
viability/visibility boost for #3. My rule assumes 
there's no equal-ranking, but I bet something could be devised for other 
ballots.)


That rule doesn't sound too bad to me. Most of the time, there'd be no risk 
of it applying; but I think it would still be a gentle pressure in the 
intended direction. Still, I think it should be considered separately from 
SODA per se.
Maybe it would be gentle if you expect a lot of candidates but in general I 
don't think it is very gentle. For example, 
this election:

49 A
44 B
4 CB
3 DB

Would qualify, and auto-elect A.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] i don't get why mixed member rules use FPTP???

2012-02-14 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi David,


De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 13 février 2012 20h41
Objet : [EM] i don't get why mixed member rules use FPTP???



It seems like the awesomeness of using PR for part of the seats somehow makes 
up for the lousiness of FPTP for the rest of the seats. 


But why not use IRV+ for the rest?  I mean it's not unlike FPTP in how it 
tends to favor bigger parties.  According toGeorge Eaton, it
still lets there popular parties get a disproportionately large portion of 
the seats, but only when they're truly popular.


So why couldn't Germany replace FPTP for its single-member seats with IRV?


I got on this rant because I learned of the DPR approach to foster 
multi-party system in the UK.


I don't see any reason why 4-seat super districts that use 3-seat LR Hare and 
IRV+ wouldn't suffice?
Maybe the use of PR might get more folks excited about the electoral reform 
this time...
dlw


I don't think there is much to be gained from doing that in Germany. My 
understanding is that in practice voters
vote the single-winner ballot according to party, and then the PR part 
basically overrules anomalies as well. What
I mean is, suppose you used Condorcet and some minor party won a ton of 
single-winner races. Despite this, the
PR would adjust it so that the relative winnings are proportional to the party 
list vote. So the unexpected results
on the single-winner ballot result in almost nothing.

I think this would probably still be a problem in a setting with weak party 
discipline...

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #4445] Re: Looking at Condorcet

2012-02-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Robert,


De : robert bristow-johnson r...@audioimagination.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Jeudi 9 février 2012 10h07
Objet : Re: [EM] [CES #4445] Re: Looking at Condorcet

On 2/8/12 1:25 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 8.2.2012, at 7.33, robert bristow-johnson wrote:
 
 ...
 if it's not the majority that rule, what's the alternative?
 I'm not aware of any good alternatives to majority rule in competitive 
 two-candidate elections (with some extra assumptions that rule out random 
 ballot etc.).
 
 Juho

thank you Juho, for stipulating to the obvious.  i will confess that i am 
astonished at the resistance displayed here at the EM list to this obvious 
fact.

Nobody on EM said anything contrary to Juho's statement. I agree with Juho. And 
Bryan said something similar at the end of his post.

With two candidates, most of us agree that you have to use majority rule. That 
doesn't mean it gives perfect answers according to some ideal. If your ideal is 
maximum utility, then it's pretty clear majority rule isn't always giving the 
correct answer. Not because the ballots make it clear that this is happening, 
but because almost any model of voter preferences will lead to this 
conclusion. It would be frankly bizarre, if fairness and utility always gave 
the same answers.

(Your idea of all the utilities being 0 or 1 can't even be made to work as a 
model, I don't think, unless voters really only have two stances toward 
candidates. Because what happens when you introduce a third candidate that some 
people like even better? Utilities don't change based on who else is in the 
race, they are supposed to represent in absolute terms the benefit from a 
candidate being elected.)

When you try to make an argument for Condorcet and 3+ candidate scenarios, 
based on the inevitability of using majority rule with two candidates, you will 
fail to convince an advocate of utility, because an advocate of utility 
probably doesn't think the method options are as limited anymore, once you have 
3+ candidates. The majority rule procedure with two candidates may be necessary 
(Clay may even disagree with that though), but that doesn't mean it was always 
doing the right thing.

Is this clear enough? I understand you want to make a fairness argument in 
favor of majority rule with two candidates, and then build off of that. But a 
utility advocate may reject fairness and prefer utility, even without offering 
a different method that could be used with two candidates. (He may perceive 
that there is no utility improvement to be had by doing something else.) So 
even if you attack Range as silly in the two-candidate case, you're not making 
the point that fairness is paramount over utility.

I'd note also that utility goes far beyond the question of whether Range is a 
workable method. A utility advocate is free to leave Range in the trash-bin 
while seeking to maximize utility under other methods that you might recognize 
as less prone to exaggeration strategies.
 
And from your last mail to me:
 
 It could be true if it so happens that nobody wants to vote truthfully under
 Condorcet methods, while Approval in practice never has any bad outcomes, 
 etc.

it could be true that hundreds of people who have testified to such have 
actually been abducted by extraterrestrial aliens who poked needles into them 
and did experiments on human subjects.  but it's an extraordinary claim that 
requires extraordinary evidence.
 
Yes, you're right. However, the important point here is just that it could be 
true. More Condorcet than Condorcet isn't inherently nonsense. You just have 
to read it as better sincere Condorcet efficiency than under Condorcet 
methods. Such a thing is possible.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Kevin V

2012-02-08 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi David,
 

De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : step...@yahoo.fr; EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mardi 7 février 2012 16h17
Objet : Re: Kevin V


dlw: I argue that the strength of the US presidency and regular presidential 
elections has the effect of building up our two-party system.  

This is why I take as a given that there tend to be 2 bigger major parties 
and not as many serious candidates in single-winner elections.  This in 
turn tends to 
reduce the import of the diffs among the wide variety of single-winner 
elections.  

I think it works like this:
President isn't responsible to or chosen by Congress -
There is not that much prize for having a majority of a house -
Weak party discipline (because of less focus on party: a candidate can get 
reelected even if his peers are unhappy) -
If you are a viable candidate, there is no need for you to carve out a new 
party. There is only room for two contenders per
race (under FPP), and there are two parties that will take you as long as you 
can win for them.


dlw: Aye, but the prez election itself and its potential for coat-tails and 
the reward from capturing one or both of the US legislatures
does build up the parties who can afford to run a serious prez election race. 
 I think some of the weak party discipline is also due to the restrictions on 
donations to parties in the 1974 FEC act.
Our system wd function better if there was more intra-party discipline and 
the donations flowed thru the relatively transparent venue of the party. 

Personally I prefer weak party discipline. I like candidates to have 
independence, with the decision-making power
less concentrated. And I'm suspicious of what party policies designed at the 
national level would look like.




KV: I think we could have three parties (if not a much greater variety of 
viewpoints) with the right method. I wouldn't care
if they are actually parties or just a higher number of real choices, on 
average, in a race.


dlw:Would it make a diff if our two major parties became two different major 
parties, bridging the gap between the de facto center and the true center?
If American forms of PR were adopted so that there'd still be 2 major parties 
per area, they wouldn't be the same 2 parties for all regions, which would 
then enable minor parties 
to contest the duopoly.  And if this got complemented by a host of LTPs(with 
coalitions)  that specialized in contesting more local elections and voting 
strategically together in less local elections, 
along with other acts that hold elected officials accountable to their 
promises then we'd have better quality choices, even if the quantity is less 
than we'd prefer.

Yes, I think it would be useful if we could increase the incentive to stand at 
the median, even if two parties maintained
their grip on things.

I don't find PR very interesting personally. It can be its own goal, but it 
doesn't seem useful for the things I'm concerned
about.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #4445] Re: Looking at Condorcet

2012-02-08 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Robert,
 
I would +1 to Bryan Mills' post.
 
in the two-candidate case, you would have to assume unequal treatment for 
voters
 
Yes, utility inherently does this. It's trying to maximize happiness which is 
a different ideal from giving
everyone equal weight (e.g. even people who don't have a strong opinion).
 
but when Clay says that Score or Approval is better at picking the Condorcet 
winner than is a 
Condorcet-compliant method, *that* is no tautology is obviously controversial, 
since it says that there is 
a number closer to 3 than the number 3 itself.
 
What Clay means is that score/Approval are better at picking the *sincere* 
Condorcet winner. Yes, that's
obviously controversial. It could be true if it so happens that nobody wants to 
vote truthfully under
Condorcet methods, while Approval in practice never has any bad outcomes, etc.
 
if it isn't 0 (for when you don't get who you voted for) and 1 (for when your 
candidate is elected), then 
some voter is diluting their utilities and i think it's pretty useless and in 
bad taste to ask voters to do that 
explicitly with a Score ballot.
 
Utilities refers to what voters actually feel, not what they are putting on 
the ballot.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #4445] Re: Looking at Condorcet

2012-02-07 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Robert,
 
I think that the basic claim of Condorcet doesn't necessarily pick the option 
whom the elecotorate prefers (in terms of
total utility) won't be too controversial. Any kind of model usually assumes 
internal utilities (such as based on distances in
issue space) because we need these to figure out how voters prioritize. One 
could try to assume that some set of
internal utilities might have some absolute, aggregable value. In that case it 
is really easy to produce a scenario where the
majority favorite isn't the utility winner. All you need is one case and you 
get Clay's not necessarily.
 
You ask how we can decide, then, not to elect voted majority favorites. 
Assuming voters are strategic I don't know
of a good answer to this.
 
You suggest a model where there are only two candidates and the 
voter-for-candidate utilities are all either 0 or 1. If 
that's an accurate model then Clay's claim doesn't work. But with virtually any 
other model it will be true sometimes
that the voted majority favorite isn't the utility maximizer.
 
Kevin
 
 
 

De : robert bristow-johnson r...@audioimagination.com
À : election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 6 février 2012 21h31
Objet : Re: [EM] [CES #4445] Re: Looking at Condorcet


one thing i forgot to mention...

On 2/5/12 5:07 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 On 02/04/2012 06:14 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote: 
...
 that is not well defined. given Abd's example:
 
 2: Pepperoni (0.61), Cheese (0.5), Mushroom (0.4)
 1: Cheese (0.8), Mushroom (0.7), Pepperoni (0)
 
 who says that for that 1 voter that the utility of Cheese is 0.8?
 
 The voter does. In this thought experiment, one simply assumes the 1-voter's 
 utility of Cheese is 0.8 so as to show the point. The point is that there may 
 be situations where utilitarian optimization and majority rule differs.
 
so my question, when running simulations or trying to construct a quantitative 
case of maximizing utility, it depends of course on how utility is 
quantitatively defined.  and we understand that the aggregate utility is some 
combination of every voter's individual utility, and, for the sake of argument 
(and because it sounds reasonable), we'll say that the metric of aggregate 
utility is equal to the sum of the individual metrics of utility.  so 
maximizing the sum is the same as maximizing the mean.

but there is still no model of individual utility other than one simply 
assumes.  how can Clay build a proof where he claims that it's a proven 
mathematical fact that the Condorcet winner is not necessarily the option whom 
the electorate prefers?  if he is making a utilitarian argument, he needs to 
define how the individual metrics of utility are define and that's just 
guessing.  when you guess at a model that is part of your proof, it doesn't 
make for a very rigorous proof.  a *real* proof is that the Devil hands you the 
model (that's within the domain of possible models) and you make your proof 
work anyway.  *you* don't get to cook up heuristics like the utility to voter 
X that Candidate A is elected is equal to 0.8.

now, with the simple two-candidate or two-choice election that is (remember all 
those conditions i attached?) Governmental with reasonably high stakes, 
Competitive, and  Equality of franchise, you *do* have a reasonable assumption 
of what the individual metric of utility is for a voter.  if the candidate that 
some voter supports is elected, the utility to that voter is 1.  if the other 
candidate is elected, the utility to that voter is 0.  (it could be any two 
numbers as long as the utility of electing my candidate exceeds the utility of 
not electing who i voted for.  it's a linear and monotonic mapping that changes 
nothing.)  all voters have equal franchise, which means that the utility of 
each voter has equal weight in combining into an overall utility for the 
electorate.  that simply means that the maximum utility is obtained by electing 
the candidate who had the most votes which, because there are only two 
candidates, is also the majority
 candidate.

if Clay or any others are disputing that electing the majority candidate (as 
opposed to electing the minority candidate) does not maximize the utility, can 
you please spell out the model and the assumptions you are making to get to 
your conclusion?

sorry that i am belaboring what i would have thought were simple axioms, but i 
can't tell that they are widely accepted and i want to probe how they are not 
widely accepted.  how can it be that when Candidate A gets more votes than 
Candidate B (and they are the only choices) that anyone would advocate awarding 
office to Candidate B?  something has to be anomalous to come to such a 
conclusion.  perhaps the votes for Candidate B count more than the votes for 
Candidate A (violating one person, one vote).  perhaps we introduce a goofy 
rule such as tossing in a random variable (like draw two non-negative random 
integers within some given 

Re: [EM] Re Raph Frank wrt 3-seat LR Hare and RV for US Senators by proxy.

2012-02-07 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,
 

 
De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com; EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mardi 7 février 2012 13h20
Objet : Re: [EM] Re Raph Frank wrt 3-seat LR Hare and RV for US Senators by 
proxy.

dlw: I argue that the strength of the US presidency and regular presidential 
elections has the effect of building up our two-party system.  

This is why I take as a given that there tend to be 2 bigger major parties and 
not as many serious candidates in single-winner elections.  This in turn 
tends to 
reduce the import of the diffs among the wide variety of single-winner 
elections.  

I think it works like this:
President isn't responsible to or chosen by Congress -
There is not that much prize for having a majority of a house -
Weak party discipline (because of less focus on party: a candidate can get 
reelected even if his peers are unhappy) -
If you are a viable candidate, there is no need for you to carve out a new 
party. There is only room for two contenders per
race (under FPP), and there are two parties that will take you as long as you 
can win for them.

I think we could have three parties (if not a much greater variety of 
viewpoints) with the right method. I wouldn't care
if they are actually parties or just a higher number of real choices, on 
average, in a race.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #4445] Re: Looking at Condorcet

2012-02-04 Thread Kevin Venzke




 De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : electionscie...@googlegroups.com 
Cc : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 3 février 2012 22h06
Objet : Re: [EM] [CES #4445] Re: Looking at Condorcet
 



Condorcet systems fundamentally try to maximize the wrong thing. They try to 
maximize the odds of electing the Condorcet winner, even though it's a proven 
mathematical fact that the Condorcet winner is not necessarily the option whom 
the electorate prefers.


Trouble is that the ballots ARE the voters' statements as to which candidate IS 
the CW.  The above paragraph seems to be based on the ballots sometimes not 
truly representing the thoughts of the voters voting them.



No, he's saying that when the CW and the true, honest utility winner differ, 
the latter is better. I agree, but it's not an argument worth making, because 
most people who don't already agree will think it's a stupid one.

From my perspective the trouble with the top statement is that sincere 
Condorcet efficiency and utility performance seem to be correlated. I don't 
know any way
to design a method to specifically perform better at utility, assuming 
strategic voters.

Note that, if you try to take this issue back to Warren's sims, 
strategically-voted Condorcet methods within his framework have not just bad 
utility but bad sincere
Condorcet efficiency as well. (I don't know the numbers but it's impossible to 
believe they are any good.) So I don't know where one could look to argue that 
maximizing sincere Condorcet efficiency vs. utility performance can be done.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Sparring over AV vs IRV at Least of All Evils...

2012-02-03 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi David,
 
I'm trying to make sense of this as an anti-Approval argument, since you say we 
don't want people to pursue the
center too doggedly. Did you explain what bad consequence follows from 
pursuing the center doggedly, though?
I thought I understood your post as an IRV is not so bad argument, until I 
reached this line.
 
Kevin
 

De : David L Wetzell wetze...@gmail.com
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Jeudi 2 février 2012 22h12
Objet : [EM] Sparring over AV vs IRV at Least of All Evils...


http://www.blogger.com/comment.g?blogID=7696446405100112491postID=7962761243854932802
 

Dale Sheldon Hess has provoked me to explain my views about IRV wrt to a 1-d 
politics game.  

Here's what I wrote, 
DSH:Place a party directly in the center. Now, if I can place two more 
parties, I can always make your centrist lose. ALWAYS. And you can't move 
more-centrally to do anything about it (I can actually make it so that you can 
still win by moving AWAY from the center; how's that for perverse incentives!)

dlw: Ah, but in this example, the two biggest parties are in fact close to the 
center(as I predicted)... and so the fact that the most centrist party doesn't 
win is relatively small potatoes. 

And as for the 3rd party candidate winning by going way from the center, that's 
a curiosity due to the uniform dist'n of voter preferences. That isn't 
realistic...

I've played with Yee's voteline thingy. The issue is with the uncertainty as to 
what is the center, since it's something that's dynamic. 

That's why I downplay the import of center squeeze. The center can't be 
cordoned off by anyone and so to pick a rule based on how it pins down the 
center is like chasing after the wind. 

With both IRV and FPP, there's pressure to move twds the center by the biggest 
parties, it's stronger with IRV. Thus, the de facto center ends up becoming 
more closely tied to the true center.

Let's say a shift in voter preferences has D and R at the 70 and 71 penny marks 
and G sets up shop at 35. G wd win with both FPP and IRV, but both D and R get 
to move again. But there are rigidities that prevent them from moving too much 
too fast. And so the D's move to 55 and the R's to 56. And then G still wins if 
it's FPP, but with IRV then R wins. 

But what if D moves and R (perhaps stuck in FPP thinking) doesn't move, so the 
positions are 35, 55 and 70? In that case, G would win. 
Tragedy, right? But it can be expected that the next election will change 
things further so that the G's must move to the right(or merge w. the Ds) and 
the R must move to the L or merge with the Ds. 

The moral of the story is that parties are like the people groping around in 
the dark in Socrates' cave. They cannot choose exactly where on the spectrum 
they will be. But IRV helps us to adjust and makes the outcome closer to the 
center than o.w. with FPP. 

If Approval Voting had been used then D would have won by moving to 64. In fact 
all the parties wd be strongly encouraged to beeline for whatever the center 
seemed to be and with a shifting center, they'd all stumble and bump together 
in the dark. 

Whereas, the Gs by taking a stand at 35 at least they succeed in moving things 
to the left or maybe they'll get lucky... 

It's not an exact science, which is what it should be. We want people to pursue 
the center, but not too doggedly...

Sorry if that's fuzzy, but I think that's closer to real life...

dlw 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Majority-Judgement. Condorcet.

2012-02-03 Thread Kevin Venzke
Personally I don't understand why one would want to spend time on a method that 
you have to defend by saying
it might work anyway, even if as built the incentives are wrong.
 
I like the idea of being able to test things, so I may be biased here.
 
It's taking a shot in the dark. How fantastic must this method be, for that to 
seem like a good idea? It's hard to
believe one couldn't go back and work out something that more reliably does 
whatever you were going for.
 
Also, if MJ is a serious proposal it should be called median rating and use 
the Bucklin tiebreaker. You'd have
a name that means something and a tiebreaker that isn't a pain to solve.At the 
top rating (the one we all agree
might matter) the rules aren't even different.
 
The name is so bad. Imagine you hear that on the news and are trying to figure 
out what it means. Majority
doesn't tell you that much (IRV already does majorities and they didn't even 
need to put it in the name) and
judgment refers to what? The voting. They're calling it judgment though. 
Puke. So dramatic and it doesn't
even say anything.
 
The tie-breaker is the same thing really. It sounds neat and fair to pull out 
median votes one by one, but in
practice that isn't the methodology, you really should use math. Try coding MJ 
and then see how much code you
could delete, how much less thought it would've taken you, if you just wanted 
the Bucklin tiebreaker instead.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-02 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mercredi 1 février 2012 18h35
Objet : Re: [EM] SODA criteria





In 
your criteria list you had Majority but for that you must actually be 
assuming the opposite of what I am trying, namely that
*everyone* is delegating, is that right?


Everyone who votes for the majority candidate is either delegating to them, 
or voting them above all other alternatives - that is, approving only them 
but checking do not delegate. This is the standard meaning of the majority 
criterion. For instance, by this meaning, approval meets the majority 
criterion.


For MMC, everyone in the mutual majority is either delegating to one of the 
candidates, or approving all of them and nobody else.

Oh, I missed that the voter can't rank at all. So you are good with FBC. But I 
don't regard Approval as satisfying what I
call MF and Woodall's Majority. It's possible to say it satisfies MF, but I 
prefer Woodall's treatment. (The criteria framework
I use doesn't have any way to say that Approval satisfies MMC. You can equate 
approval with equal-top, above-bottom, or
call it something external, but I can't say that voters stick to a limited 
number of slots. I understand the meaning of two-slot 
MMC or voted MMC but I see these as inferior versions.)

In response to your last line, if the majority set involves more than one 
candidate, the delegating voters are never part of it
and are unnecessary in getting one of these candidates elected. (I'm using your 
treatment that voters only have two rank 
levels.) If you don't agree, I'd like to hear how you are interpreting MMC, 
because I can't think of how else it would work.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-02 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,


De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Jeudi 2 février 2012 11h35
Objet : Re: [EM] SODA criteria









In 
your criteria list you had Majority but for that you must actually be 
assuming the opposite of what I am trying, namely that
*everyone* is delegating, is that right?


Everyone who votes for the majority candidate is either delegating to 
them, or voting them above all other alternatives - that is, approving 
only them but checking do not delegate. This is the standard meaning of 
the majority criterion. For instance, by this meaning, approval meets the 
majority criterion.


For MMC, everyone in the mutual majority is either delegating to one of 
the candidates, or approving all of them and nobody else.

Oh, I missed that the voter can't rank at all. So you are good with FBC. But 
I don't regard Approval as satisfying what I
call MF and Woodall's Majority. It's possible to say it satisfies MF, but I 
prefer Woodall's treatment.


I don't know what MF stands for. I agree that it fails Woodall's majority, 
though not in the unique strong Nash equilibrium.

(The criteria framework
I use doesn't have any way to say that Approval satisfies MMC. You can 
equate approval with equal-top, above-bottom, or
call it something external, but I can't say that voters stick to a limited 
number of slots. I understand the meaning of two-slot 
MMC or voted MMC but I see these as inferior versions.)


voted, because delegation means there's sometimes effectively more than two 
slots. 


In response to your last line, if the majority set involves more than one 
candidate, the delegating voters are never part of it
and are unnecessary in getting one of these candidates elected. (I'm using 
your treatment that voters only have two rank 
levels.) If you don't agree, I'd like to hear how you are interpreting MMC, 
because I can't think of how else it would work.


10: A(BC?...)
10: B(CA?...)
10: C(AB?...)
21: ABC
49: 


One of A, B, or C must win.

MF is Majority Favorite.

If I understand you correctly, you're treating voters as casting either an 
approval ballot, or else one of the predeclared
preference orders. I guess that makes sense though it's quite tricky to 
analyze. If a voter is counted as voting ABC, it's
not possible to raise C above only B. But when I analyze this, it has to result 
in something consistent with the desired ranking
unless that's completely impossible. I guess that could only be A, AC, or ACB 
approval ballots. I think that would result in 
some criteria problems. For instance, suppose that ABC elects C, but A=C=B 
elects B. Since I look at how the voter 
wanted to rank, and not the options the method made available, I would call 
that a Mono-raise failure.

You might think that's unfair, but I don't know what framework you can suggest 
that will be more apparent and also allow
you to fairly evaluate something like Mono-raise.

Personally I think it would be easier to assume voters have no idea what 
candidates predeclare. In that case MMC doesn't
apply in your scenario above.

Granted, this might make it hard for criteria that are supposed to deal with 
optimal strategy assumptions or equilibrium.
I just don't worry about those criteria because I don't know how to evaluate 
them.

I also wanted to note, here instead of in a separate post, that I wonder about 
the FBC. I was thinking it must satisfy
it because you could cast an approval ballot, but that's not good reasoning 
(see: any Condorcet method). What if it
is possible to get a superior result by delegating your vote to someone other 
than your favorite? It's not clear to me
that this is impossible.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-01 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
I expect that unpredictability (whatever there may be) of candidates' decisions 
can only hurt criteria compliance.
At least with criteria that are generally defined on votes, because with such 
criteria you usually have to assume
the worst about any other influences incorporated into the method.
 
So I wonder, can you suggest a deterministic version of SODA, where the 
negotiations of SODA are instead
calculated directly from the pre-announced preferences of the candidates? And 
if so, does it satisfy the same
criteria in your view?
 
I can say I would be skeptical of how a criterion is being applied, or how 
clearly it is being defined, if the 
satisfaction of it *depends* on the fact that candidates have post-voting 
decisions to make.
 
Kevin
 
 

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mardi 31 janvier 2012 20h50
Objet : [EM] SODA criteria


SODA passes: 

Majority
MMC (as voted)
Condorcet (as voted, and in a strong Nash equilibrium as honest)
Condorcet loser (ditto)
Monotone
Participation (with the fix that delegation can be any fraction)
IIA (delegated version - that is, if a new candidate is added, the winner is 
either the same, or someone higher on the new candidate's delegation order.)
Cloneproof
Polytime (there is no guarantee that optimal delegated assignment strategy is 
polytime calculable, but it will be in any real case, and anyway, candidates 
can just choose some near-optimal strategy.)
Resolvable
Summable
Allows equal rankings
FBC

So, of the criteria in the wikipedia voting systems table, the only ones it 
out-and-out fails are:
Consistency (though it comes damn close)
Later-no-harm and later-no-help (though it does satisfy LNHarm for the one 
(two) candidate(s?) with the most voted approvals, and for other 
candidates, adding later preferences is probably strategically forced; so I'd 
say it fulfills the spirit of both of these. Similarly, it satisfies LNHelp for 
the last-to-delegate candidate, and nearly so for other late-delegating 
candidates, and the point of LNHelp is to prevent a weak candidate from winning 
through clever bottom filling, so again it satisfies the spirit.)
Allows later preferences (though delegation substitutes for this affordance in 
some cases.)

If we could just get some wikipedia-notable mention of SODA, we could put it in 
the table, and I think it would graphically stand out as the most 
criteria-compliant method there.

I'm working on an academic article on SODA, which would not be focused on these 
criteria or even on SODA, but would quickly state the above. But if anyone can 
make an article happen in a wikipedia reliable source, that would be great.

Jameson


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : Majority Judgement

2012-01-30 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,
 
In my simulations MJ and Bucklinesque methods usually show similar strategy 
patterns to Approval. (Though so
does Range.)
 
If there are three candidates, you can rank them ABC and get protection for A 
from the B preference if you
believe that A's viability depends on A having a top-slot majority. If you 
think that A could still win with, say, a
49% plurality, it doesn't make a lot of sense to give a preference to B (unless 
B is about as good).
 
In constructed scenarios it's not hard to imagine situations where this could 
be a useful guarantee. You can
easily make a situation where if A only gets 49%, it must be that opposing 
candidates and voters made up the rest,
in which case it's safe to give the second preference, because A definitely 
lost.
 
But in real elections I would be concerned by the fact that a narrow majority 
can be thwarted just by adding in
a few ballots for non-contenders.
 
If you go lower in the rankings (e.g. consider safety of 2nd preference from 
the specified 3rd preference) I think
the numbers just get more and more unclear as to whether you stand to 
gain anything for the risk you definitely
take.
 
By the way, I agree that AERLO methods probably violate FBC. The effects are 
too unpredictable.
 
Kevin
 

De : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com
À : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Lundi 30 janvier 2012 15h09
Objet : [EM] Majority Judgement



Does anyone here know the strategy of MJ? Does anyone here know what valid 
strategic claims can be made for it? How would one maximize one’s utility in an 
election with acceptable and completely unacceptable candidates who could win? 
How about in an election without completely unacceptable candidates who could 
win?

And no, I don't mean refer to a website. The question is do YOU, as an MJ 
advocate, know what MJ's strategy is?

Of course, if anyone here advocates MJ, then they, themselves, should know MJ’s 
strategy, and its advantages and disadvantages, and be able to state them here.

I’m just guessing, but isn’t MJ’s strategy the same as that of RV? (Maximum 
rating for candidates you’d vote for in Approval, and minimum points for 
candidates you wouldn’t vote for in Approval).

And surely the u/a strategy of MJ is to max-rate the acceptables and min-rate 
the unacceptables.

But of course MJ differs from RV in the following way: In RV, if you rate x 
higher than y, you’re reliably, unquestionably, helping x against y. In MJ, of 
course that isn’t so. In fact, if you like x and y highly, and at all 
similarly, and rate sincerely, then you’re unlikely to help one against the 
other, at all.

Another difference is that, in MJ, even if you correctly guess that you’re 
raising a candidate’s median, you can’t know by how much.

Suppose x is your favorite. y is almost as good. Say the rating range is 0-100. 
You sincerely give 100 to x, and 90 to y.

Say I prefer y to x, and, as do you, I consider their merit about the same. If 
I rated sincerely, I’d give y 100 and x 90.

But, unlike you, I don’t vote sincerely. Because x is a rival to y, and maybe 
also because I expect you to rate sincerely, I take advantage of your sincerity 
by giving y 100, and giving x zero.

Because different people have different favorites and near-favorites, your high 
rating of x and y is probably above those candidates’ median ratings. So you’re 
raising the medians of both candidates, with no particular reason to believe 
that you’re raising one’s median more than that of the other.

In our above-described example, that’s what you’re doing: Raising the medians 
of x and y. Probably by about the same amount. I, however, am raising y's 
median and lowering x's median. You’re raising my candidate’s median, and I’m 
lowering your candidate’s median. You aren’t helping x against y. I’m helping y 
against x.

You’ve been had. 

At least in RV, you’d have reliably somewhat helped x against y.

There's something familiar about that strategy situation :-)  MJ fully has the 
co-operation/defection problem.

Discussion of a method’s strategy shouldn’t have to come from someone who 
doesn’t advocate that method.

A tip: Don’t have confidence in a method whose advocates evidently don’t know 
its strategy.

Another thing: Just as one example, try MJ on the Approval bad-example. What 
you thereby find out is that, to be usable, MJ needs bylaws and patches, such 
as to make it too wordy and elaborate (and arbitrary?) to be publicly 
proposable. 

Mike Ossipoff
 




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] An ABE solution

2011-11-27 Thread Kevin Venzke
Mike,


De : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com
À : election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Samedi 26 Novembre 2011 13h39
Objet : [EM] An ABE solution


This was answered in the first part of the paragraph that you're quoting. What 
Woodall calls a preferential
election rule is by definition a rank method.

Kevin


Kevin said:

By definition an election method doesn't use
approval ballots. 

[endquote]

Whose definition? 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Re : An ABE solution

2011-11-27 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
 
My perspective is the following:
1. Most real-world elections will have a sincere CW, although that might not 
be visible from the ballots.
1a. Those elections without a sincere CW don't really have a wrong answer, 
so I don't worry as much about the pathologies in that case.
2. Therefore, we can divide FBC-violating strategies into two (overlapping) 
classes: those which work when there is not a CW among the other voters, 
which I will call offensive strategies, and which usually work by creating 
a false cycle; and those which work when there is no CW among the other 
voters, which I will call defensive.
3. I consider that a method with no offensive FBC violations is good 
enough. That's why I've used those labels: why would defensive strategies 
be a problem if offensive ones weren't?


Having some problems understanding where you're coming from. A defensive 
FBC-violating strategy isn't likely going to be 
provoked by an offensive FBC-violating strategy. I would expect it to be 
provoked by the truncation of other voters.

If you want to say that it's enough for methods to not be suspectible to 
strategies that would necessitiate defensive compromise
from other voters, then I might agree, but that is almost the same thing, in 
practice, as saying the method should satisfy FBC.


Kevin, I suspect that you're probably closer to the truth than I am on this, 
because you have more experience twiddling the knobs on your simulator. But 
your brief assertions here don't really give me enough fodder for me to 
understand why I'm wrong, if I am.


Do you agree with me that lack of a sincere CW will be rare? Do you agree 
with me that some methods have strategic possibilities which are irrelevant 
as long as there is a sincere CW who is known as such by most voters? Do you 
agree that some FBC violations fall into that category? 


Apparently you do not agree that all FBC violations which start from a non-CW 
scenario fall into that category; and apparently this is because 
non-FBC-violating truncation strategies could cause the non-CW scenario. If 
I've read you correctly on this, you may well be right, but I don't follow 
all the logic. But even if I have and you are, the questions in the preceding 
paragraph are more important for the big picture.


Jameson
 

I suspect I don't understand you more than that I think you are wrong. My best 
guess as to what you are saying involves trying
to interpret the thought behind your rhetorical question (why would defensive 
strategies be a problem if offensive ones weren't)
which seems to me to assume that defensive FBC-violating strategies depend on 
there being offensive FBC-violating strategies.

Let's grant that we only care about the situation that there is a sincere CW. 
I'm not sure how to answer your other questions in the 
second paragraph. Maybe I'll understand their importance after another 
exchange.

I would like to understand what you are referring to when you talk about an 
offensive FBC-violating strategy. You say this strategy
usually creates a false cycle. Does this strategy also directly betray one's 
favorite? Or what do you mean by FBC-violating here?
If it does betray the favorite, then you seem to be describing a strategy 
where some voters bury their favorite in order to create 
a false cycle (probably by creating a pairwise defeat over that favorite, or 
something comparable in effect) that achieves something 
preferable. But if this was creating a cycle then I have to wonder who was the 
preexisting winner? Surely it would have been the 
favorite?

I hope you see where I am coming from. As far as I can understand, the 
offensive FBC-violating strategy is a strange idea, so I
can hardly see it as the obvious thing to blame for provoking defensive 
FBC-violating strategies.

My impression of what provokes defensive FBC-violating strategies is not based 
on sims. It's just based on asking the question,
if there is a sincere CW but not a voted one, what kind of inaccuracies might 
exist on the cast votes? It could be many things
besides offensive compromise.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : An ABE solution

2011-11-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Chris,


De : Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au
À : fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu 
Cc : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mercredi 23 Novembre 2011 7h08
Objet : [EM] An ABE solution

It is certainly a clear proof of the incompatibilty of  the Condorcet criterion 
and Kevin's later
suggested variation of  the FBC, Sincere Favorite:
 Suppose a subset of the ballots, all identical, rank every candidate in S 
(where S contains at least two candidates) equal to each other, and above 
every other candidate. Then, arbitrarily lowering some candidate X from S on 
these ballots must not increase the probability that the winner comes from S.
A simpler way to word this would be: You should never be able to help your 
favorites by lowering one of them.
 
http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/#critfbc

I can't see any real difference between this and regular FBC, which probably 
partly explains
why it didn't catch on.
 
Sincere Favorite is supposed to be a votes-only translation of FBC. It should 
clarify what I am doing when I
check whether a method satisfies FBC. It's possible that a method can satisfy 
FBC without satisfying Sincere
Favorite, but it would be hard to design a method to do so, I think.
 
Besides the issue you mention, there are also the facts that I rarely use the 
sincere favorite name myself and 
that the SF acronym would be confusing given the Strategy-Free criterion with 
the same initials.
 
Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : An ABE solution

2011-11-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au 
Cc : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com; fsimm...@pcc.edu 
fsimm...@pcc.edu; em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mercredi 23 Novembre 2011 4h18
Objet : Re: [EM] An ABE solution




 
My perspective is the following:
1. Most real-world elections will have a sincere CW, although that might not 
be visible from the ballots.
1a. Those elections without a sincere CW don't really have a wrong answer, 
so I don't worry as much about the pathologies in that case.
2. Therefore, we can divide FBC-violating strategies into two (overlapping) 
classes: those which work when there is not a CW among the other voters, 
which I will call offensive strategies, and which usually work by creating 
a false cycle; and those which work when there is no CW among the other 
voters, which I will call defensive.
3. I consider that a method with no offensive FBC violations is good 
enough. That's why I've used those labels: why would defensive strategies 
be a problem if offensive ones weren't?


Having some problems understanding where you're coming from. A defensive 
FBC-violating strategy isn't likely going to be 
provoked by an offensive FBC-violating strategy. I would expect it to be 
provoked by the truncation of other voters.

If you want to say that it's enough for methods to not be suspectible to 
strategies that would necessitiate defensive compromise
from other voters, then I might agree, but that is almost the same thing, in 
practice, as saying the method should satisfy FBC.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Re : Votes-only criteria vs preference criteria. IRV squeeze-effect. Divulge IRV election specifics?

2011-11-18 Thread Kevin Venzke
Jameson/Mike,
 

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Jeudi 17 Novembre 2011 12h48
Objet : Re: [EM] Re : Votes-only criteria vs preference criteria. IRV 
squeeze-effect. Divulge IRV election specifics?




2011/11/17 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
..In practice [preference-mentioning criteria] usually have to be translated 
into votes-only criteria in order to figure out how to use or test them.
Yes, this is another (better?) way of putting what I said about Criteria 
which apply to ballots and mention preferences.

Jameson



 
Well, in my mind a votes-only criterion is independent. Usually the two 
versions aren't quite equivalent or can't be easily proven to be equivalent.

I think part of the disagreement on this issue is based on who the audience 
is. On this list we don't generally have problems with most people using an 
implied Woodall-ish conception of methods and criteria. If someone wanted to 
argue that FPP actually does satisfy Condorcet we would just tell them they're 
doing it wrong and shrug them off, no big deal. Mike seems to be paranoid 
about people understanding criteria contrary to their original intention.

The inconvenient thing about e.g. SDSC is mostly the should have a way of 
voting wording. In practice this way of voting is almost always truncation 
(which definitely is possible to define within Mike's scheme, as he doesn't 
consider truncation of two candidates to be voting them equal). Mike's wording 
does allow a method to satisfy the criterion alternatively using an explicit 
approval cutoff or something. So I recognize that he is getting something 
additional, that is not useless, from his choice of wording.

I wonder if SDSC can really be seamlessly applied to any ballot format though. 
Mike seems to assume it is unambiguous what it means to vote a candidate above 
or equal to or below another candidate. If he has a definition for these I 
imagine it's based on some very specific test that wouldn't necessarily 
reflect general method behavior. For example, what if under some method the 
majority preferring A to B can make B lose by ranking B top? One could say 
(see definition below) that this is no good, because B is being ranked over 
A. But how do we know whether that's over? Based on this one very 
counterintuitive result, it doesn't look like over.

What if voters can vote cycles? What if they put candidates in color-coded 
buckets and the outcome is determined by even vs. odd vote counts? I think at 
some point, any criterion scheme has to say use your head, you know what I'm 
trying to say, and where it says that is mostly a matter of taste.

For reference, this is SDSC:
If a majority of all the voters prefer A to B, then they should have a way of 
voting that will ensure that B won't win, without any member of that majority 
voting a less-liked candidate equal to or over a more-liked candidate.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : Votes-only criteria vs preference criteria. IRV squeeze-effect. Divulge IRV election specifics?

2011-11-17 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,
 

De : MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com
À : election-meth...@electorama.com
Envoyé le : Mercredi 16 Novembre 2011 11h32
Objet : [EM] Votes-only criteria vs preference criteria. IRV squeeze-effect. 
Divulge IRV election specifics?


I don't object to such criteria. I just prefer not to use them. In practice 
they usually have to be translated into votes-only criteria in order to figure 
out how to use or test them.

You say it is inelegant to specify assumptions about methods to which criteria 
apply. But your alternative is criteria that have to discuss not just sincere 
preferences but also the degree to which voting may be insincere. And you need 
to define these concepts in a universal way, irrespective of ballot format. I 
don't feel this is more elegant. Possibly better-defined (if done well), but 
not more elegant.

Kevin



Votes-only criteria vs preference criteria:


Kevin, you objected to my preference-mentioning criteria on the grounds that no 
one knows what the voters'
true preferences really are. But so what?
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : [Off Topic] Banning those Me-Tooing like brain-dead AOLers [/Off Topic]

2011-11-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
 De : ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wala...@macosx.com
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Envoyé le : Mercredi 9 Novembre 2011 22h10
Objet : [EM] [Off Topic] Banning those Me-Tooing like brain-dead AOLers [/Off 
Topic]

    ¡Hello!

    ¿How fare you?

    Lately, some unnamed members have been metooing like brain-dead AOLers.  
Some others have complained about this.  Although I have not complained, it 
irks me.  I have a simple solution:

    If someone metoos like a brain-dead AOLers, direct the pffender to read 
this primer about posting protocol:

    
http://web.archive.org/web/20080113211450/http://www.greenend.org.uk/rjk/2000/06/14/quoting.html

    If the offenders continues to metoo like a brain-dead AOLer, an admin 
should banner the offenders immediately.  If an offender tries to rejoin under 
a different name, I see no alternative other than summoning “Weird Al” 
Yankovic for permanently dealing with the trouble maker:

    “¡And postin’, ‘¡Me Too!’, like some brain-dead AOL-er!”
    “¡I should do the world a favor and cap you like Old Yeller!”
    “¡You’re just about as useless as JPEGs to Hellen Keller!”


This is a pretty stupid post. Worse than the one where you suggested 
some readers should kill themselves. I couldn't even tell what this one was 
talking about until I followed the link.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : Re : Toy election model: 2D IQ (ideology/quality) model

2011-11-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
 
De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com
Envoyé le : Mercredi 9 Novembre 2011 2h06
Objet : Re: [EM] Re : Toy election model: 2D IQ (ideology/quality) model




2011/11/8 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

Speaking of quoting messages, I have to admit I don't understand how it is 
even supposed to be done under Yahoo. I can indent the message, and I used to 
be able to correctly quote plain text messages. But usually when I try to 
quote an html message I just end up destroying the formatting somehow.
 
Anyway, to Jameson:
 

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : kathy.d...@gmail.com
Cc : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Envoyé le : Dimanche 6 Novembre 2011 20h23
Objet : Re: [EM] Toy election model: 2D IQ (ideology/quality) model




 3. It is therefore reasonable to hope for a voting system that tends to
 elect centrists, but slightly less so than a Condorcet system.

Why would utility be considered more important than centrist?  Or would it?



Utility is the goal, almost tautologically. I mean yeah, there's plenty of 
ways you could criticize the model, or even the idea that the votes have 
anything at all to do with the utility that the voters will gain from a 
given candidate winning; but until someone comes up with something better, 
for democracy at least, utility is the best paradigm we have.



I don't think I agree. Utilities are everpresent in simulations because they 
are a convenient way to represent the priorities of the voters. They can 
easily be generated from distances in space. But, it's not obvious that 
these priorities need to be aggregable (we could use a system where the 
addition of different voters' priorities isn't even a straightforward 
task) and it's not obvious that maximizing the aggregation should even be a 
goal. You don't need to do it. 


I know there are proofs for a single agent that something equivalent to 
utility is the only way to have consistent priorities and avoid being money 
pumped. (You have A? OK, will you trade that and $1 for B? Now will you 
trade that and $1 for C? OK, now will you trade that and $1 for A? Heh heh 
heh, you just gave me $3 for nothing, fool.) I suspect you could prove 
something similar for aggregate agents (societies). Basically, utilities are 
the only way to avoid the Condorcet paradox.


I understand what you're saying about being money pumped, though I don't see 
how a similar thing would work for societies. Utility does give you a result 
when Condorcet doesn't, but I'm not sure this is a huge problem unless your 
scenario is mostly generating scenarios where Condorcet or say Schwartz isn't 
making any distinctions.


I do not think that this means that utilities are somehow real. I do think 
that it is a pretty good argument for using a utility-based model.

I've said before that I prefer to look at sincere Condorcet efficiency and 
strategic incentives. 


While I'm advocating using utilities, I must say that we could do a lot worse 
than your plan. In particular, as I've said elsewhere, using utilities is no 
substitute for looking at strategic incentives.

So you don't get one clean number from me, sorry. But I think it may be less 
artificial than aggregated utility.

Furthermore I doubt that aggregate utility is likely to get you anywhere 
unique. Electorates in practice try to get sincere CWs elected. If someone 
ever pointed to a simulation and a scenario and a rule and said, here is a 
concrete method by which we can favor higher utility candidates over sincere 
Condorcet efficiency my intuition would be that their tools are 
underestimating the voters. When the sincere CW loses, it represents an 
error from the standpoint of what the electorate was trying to do. I think 
it would take some genius work to capitalize consistently on such errors, 
and gain more than is lost.


I suspect that Majority Judgment does exactly that. My evidence? B+L's study 
that shows that MJ is the only system which does not elect almost solely 
centrists nor almost solely extremists, in a model based on 2007 France. That 
is to say, where Condorcet elected centrists, MJ sometimes elected 
extremists. And in my toy model, that is sometimes the right answer.

Well, I believe you that you have read this study and that's what it said. That 
result of the study doesn't make a lot of sense to me though. As I suggested, I 
would guess that if I read what their model was, I would feel that it's 
underestimating the voters' motivation or ability to strategize.







All that said, I would be interested to hear if someone has made an argument 
that majority rule, as a sensible principle, depends on some other more 
fundamental principle.


OK, here goes: utility is happiness and is the true goal. Majority rule is 
just the most strategy-proof principle which tends to agree with maximum 
utility. 


That wasn't too hard.

Well, for this to work your

[EM] Re : (no subject)

2011-11-08 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,
 
{quote}
Kevin--
You wrote:

ER-IRV(whole) doesn't satisfy FBC. You may need to demote your favorite in order
to get a preferable elimination order.
 
[endquote]

How? Say that there's a particular candidate whom you need to have win. 

You can give him a vote by downrating your favorite in order to get hir 
eliminated soon,
so that your ballot will give a vote to the compromise. But you could also just 
give the
compromise an immediate vote, by ranking hir in 1st place. Why would you need 
to do otherwise
in order to help hir win?
{end quote}
 
Because your compromise's ability to win may depend on which candidates were 
eliminated and when. By downranking your favorite you can affect that.
 
{quote}
What do you mean when you say even when the scenario isn't S?  If S 
represents a scenario 
meeting the stipulations of the criterion's premise, then the criterion only 
makes a requirement
when those stipulations are met. It says nothing about any other scenario. 
That's true of all
criteria, not just mine.

No criterion, including mine, says anything about what should happen when the 
scenario described
by its premise-stipulagions doesn't happen.
{end quote}
 
This is a difference of theory and practice. In theory a criterion only 
addresses the sincere 
scenarios in mentions. In practice it will have broader implications. That's 
all it is.
 
{quote}
You _weren't_ right Bucklin(= whole simultaneous)
not meeting FBC, because you were thinking that FBC requires that no one need 
to 
vote someone equal to their favorite. Actually, FBC requires only that
no one need to vote someone _over_ their favorite.
{end quote}
 
I erroneously claimed ERBucklin(whole) failed monotonocity, because I 
misunderstood how
the method worked. I don't remember ever saying ERBW failed FBC.

{quote}
Yes, SFC protects sincere CWs. Do SFC complying methods protect other 
candidates who don't
have a majority defeat (and, in that way look like sincere CWs)? Sure. What's 
the problem
with that?
{end quote}

There's no problem with that. It's just an observation that a criterion like 
SFC may have
implications beyond the scenarios it purports to deal with.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : Toy election model: 2D IQ (ideology/quality) model

2011-11-08 Thread Kevin Venzke
Speaking of quoting messages, I have to admit I don't understand how it is even 
supposed to be done under Yahoo. I can indent the message, and I used to be 
able to correctly quote plain text messages. But usually when I try to quote an 
html message I just end up destroying the formatting somehow.
 
Anyway, to Jameson:
 
De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : kathy.d...@gmail.com
Cc : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Envoyé le : Dimanche 6 Novembre 2011 20h23
Objet : Re: [EM] Toy election model: 2D IQ (ideology/quality) model



 3. It is therefore reasonable to hope for a voting system that tends to
 elect centrists, but slightly less so than a Condorcet system.

Why would utility be considered more important than centrist?  Or would it?



Utility is the goal, almost tautologically. I mean yeah, there's plenty of ways 
you could criticize the model, or even the idea that the votes have anything at 
all to do with the utility that the voters will gain from a given candidate 
winning; but until someone comes up with something better, for democracy at 
least, utility is the best paradigm we have.



I don't think I agree. Utilities are everpresent in simulations because they 
are a convenient way to represent the priorities of the voters. They can easily 
be generated from distances in space. But, it's not obvious that these 
priorities need to be aggregable (we could use a system where the addition of 
different voters' priorities isn't even a straightforward task) and it's not 
obvious that maximizing the aggregation should even be a goal. You don't need 
to do it. I've said before that I prefer to look at sincere Condorcet 
efficiency and strategic incentives. So you don't get one clean number from me, 
sorry. But I think it may be less artificial than aggregated utility.

Furthermore I doubt that aggregate utility is likely to get you anywhere 
unique. Electorates in practice try to get sincere CWs elected. If someone ever 
pointed to a simulation and a scenario and a rule and said, here is a concrete 
method by which we can favor higher utility candidates over sincere Condorcet 
efficiency my intuition would be that their tools are underestimating the 
voters. When the sincere CW loses, it represents an error from the standpoint 
of what the electorate was trying to do. I think it would take some genius work 
to capitalize consistently on such errors, and gain more than is lost.

All that said, I would be interested to hear if someone has made an argument 
that majority rule, as a sensible principle, depends on some other more 
fundamental principle.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Strategy and Bayesian Regret

2011-10-28 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
I am a little short on time, to read this as carefully as I would like, but if 
you have a
moment to answer in the meantime:

--- En date de : Ven 28.10.11, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com a écrit :
voting is best. But how do you deal with strategy? Figuring out what strategies 
are sensible is the relatively easy part; whether it's first-order rational 
strategies (as James Green-Armytage has worked out) or n-order strategies under 
uncertainty (as Kevin Venzke does) 
 
3. Try to use some rational or cognitive model of voters to figure out how much 
strategy real people will use under each method. This is hard work and involves 
a lot of assumptions, but it's probably the best we can do today.
 

As you might have guessed, I'm arguing here for method 3. Kevin Venzke has done 
work in this direction, but his assumptions --- that voters will look for 
first-order strategies in an environment of highly volatile polling data --- 
while very useful for making a computable model, are still obviously 
unrealistic.
 
[end quotes]
 
I am very curious if you could elaborate on my assumption that voters will 
look for
first-order strategies in an environment of highly volatile polling data. I'm 
not totally
sure what you mean by first-order vs. n-order strategies, and whether your 
criticism
of unrealism is based on voters will look for... part or on the highly 
volatile polling 
data part. I wonder if this volatility is a matter of degree or a general 
question of 
approach.
 
I want to note in case it's not clear that when I talk about what strategies 
voters are
using, that is just a reporting mechanism that has awareness of the relationship
between voters' sincere preferences and how they actually voted. The voters have
no idea what they are doing in strategic or sincere terms.
 
Thanks.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] New Criterion: The Co-operation/Defection Criterion

2011-10-26 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,

--- En date de : Lun 24.10.11, MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com a écrit :
 You wrote:
  
  Basically A will have a majority over B
  
 endquote
  
 Not necessarily. A will certainly have a pairwise win over
 B. When the non {A,B} 
 candidates lose, and MMPO is applied to its A,B tie, that
 pairwise win will mean
 that B has a greater pairwise opposition than A does.

Thanks for the correction.

So, when I reduce this to pairwise terms (which I do for convenience)
I see this criterion in effect:

If some candidate A has simple pairwise wins over every candidate in
a set of candidates B and has no majority pairwise losses to any
candidate in a set of candidates C, and every candidate in the set
C has a majority pairwise loss to every candidate in set B, then
candidate A must win.

If it wasn't already clear, this definitely won't be compatible with
the Plurality criterion. I know that won't bother you though.

As far as methods that will satisfy it, we at least have some clumsy 
ones. Any Condorcet method used to complete majority-defeat-
disqualification or CDTT (i.e. Schwartz set that replaces sub-majority
wins with ties) will do the trick. These methods would also satisfy
SDSC fully.

I am not sure that MMPO as you propose it actually does the trick.
It seems to depend on the A-B tied score which I'm not sure is 
guaranteed. Particularly if C is multiple candidates.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Let MMPO solve its ties. It elects A in the example. The simplest is the best

2011-10-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,

--- En date de : Sam 22.10.11, MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com a écrit :


De: MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com
Objet: [EM] Let MMPO solve its ties. It elects A in the example. The simplest 
is the best
À: election-meth...@electorama.com
Date: Samedi 22 octobre 2011, 15h42





Kevin--
 
You wrote:
 
What do you make of this example under MMPO:
 
49 A
24 B
27 CB
 
There is no CW. Standard MMPO returns a tie between B and C. If you remove A,
C is both the CW and MMPO winner. Do you think this can be accepted?
 
[end quote]
 
Yes. Because, as I define it, MMPO chooses C.  I define MMPO as solving its own 
ties. I suggest that
MMPO's ties be solved by MMPO.

Yes, but what will you say when someone asks how it can possibly be that C is
a better winner than A? A has more first preferences, and neither has any lower
preferences. The only difference is that C voters listed a second preference.
 
Is it better to elect a weak candidate, over a majority-defeated one? (I call C 
weak
because C apparently could never win the Approval version of this election.)
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Let MMPO solve its ties. It elects A in the example. The simplest is the best.

2011-10-20 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,
 
What do you make of this example under MMPO:
 
49 A
24 B
27 CB
 
There is no CW. Standard MMPO returns a tie between B and C. If you remove A,
C is both the CW and MMPO winner. Do you think this can be accepted?
 
Thanks.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Methods

2011-10-16 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,
 
--- En date de : Dim 16.10.11, MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com a écrit :
I had several FBC-complying methods that I liked very much, with such names as 
MMC, MAMPO, MDDB, SR...etc.

I haven't been able to find what MDDB and SR were. Or MAMPO either.
 
Can anyone tell me, or tell me where I can look it up? 
 
I proposed MDDA and MAMPO as methods that satisfy FBC, SDSC, and SFC.
MDDB was a variant you made, but I don't remember how it was defined.
 
With MDDA you will eliminate all candidates with a majority pairwise loss, 
unless that
would eliminate everyone. Of remaining candidates, elect the approval winner.
 
With MAMPO you elect the approval winner unless more than one candidate has
majority approval. In that situation, among those candidates elect the one with 
the best
MMPO score. But no eliminations are done: Pairwise opposition from sub-majority-
approved candidates may be decisive.
 
MDDA can violate Plurality. That means it is possible for X to be elected when 
X's
total preference count is less than some other candidate Y's first preference 
count.
 
I hope that's helpful...
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Single-winner method with strong winners (was: Poll for favorite single winner voting system with OpaVote)

2011-10-16 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Juho,
 
Sorry in advance if I didn't read your message carefully enough, but I think I 
probably
did:

--- En date de : Dim 16.10.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :






Use a Condorcet method to elect the winner among the most approved candidate 
pair and those who are at least as approved as the less approved of those two.
- a pair of candidates is approved by a voter if she approves at least one of 
those candidates


This method is summable. One should sum up information about pairwise 
comparisons, pair approvals and individual approvals.


20: A1  A2 
15: A2  A1 
33: B  C
32: C  B



In this example we have three major parties, A, B and C. Or alternatively we 
have four parties. In that case parties A1 and A2 are ideologically close to 
each others.


This method elects B since pair A1, B (or A2, B) is the most approved pair 
(approved by 68 voters), A2 is more approved than B, and B beats both A1 and A2 
in pairwise comparison.


 
 


Use of approvals typically requires a (sincere) strategy. In this method the 
voters should try to impact on which two candidates will be at least as 
approved as the most approved pair of candidates. That means that it would make 
sense to approve at least one candidate with reasonable chances to be among the 
most approved candidates (and not to approve too many of the candidates).


Does this method work well enough? Are this kind of methods useful methods in 
general?
 
 
 
I think that your method is similar to my single contest method. I believe you 
determine
the critical pair of candidates in exactly the same way. However, while my 
method just
has an instant runoff between those two candidates, you are possibly letting in 
some 
other candidates.
 
I don't think there is a big problem on paper... It's quite likely that I 
tested in my sim
some methods very similar to your proposal, and didn't report on them just 
because I
found them to be less than the best.
 
What I found to be of interest, of course, is that very little strategy 
remained on the
ranking side of the method, since its main purpose was to resolve a two-way 
race.
Your method will compromise on that a bit...
 

Do you have majority favorite covered...?
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Methods

2011-10-16 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,

--- En date de : Dim 16.10.11, matt welland m...@kiatoa.com a écrit :
  It has been shown, here, and in journal articles, that
 Approval will
  soon home in on the CW. After a few
  elecions. But a few elections can be a decade or
 more. We'd like
  better results before that, and so
 
 Does this prediction of a few elections account for polls
 typically
 done over and over prior to the election also being done
 with approval?
 My hunch is that Approval would have an immediate
 disruptive (in a good
 way) impact if the accompanying polls were also approval.

I completely agree with that. Swap a few elections with a few 
polling iterations and you should be where you wanted.

Approval's weakness is that it has to decide where the main contest is
prior to the vote. If there are few good options (i.e. any pair of
frontrunners leaves a large percentage of voters approving neither) or 
too many good options (i.e. several likely candidates for sincere CW) a
rank method, with its higher resolution, may be able to fish out a
better result.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Comments on the declaration and on a few voting systems

2011-10-14 Thread Kevin Venzke

Hi Mike,
 
Nice to see you back.

--- En date de : Ven 14.10.11, MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com a écrit :





 Venzke's MMPO example

  A  B = C
    1 A = C  B
   1 B = C  A
  B  A = C
.
 and C wins. That seems quite counterintuitive.
.
.
Yes. C is the Condorcet loser.
 
But is Kevin sure that C wins in that example?
 
MMPO isn't usually defined as a Condorcet method, though it is very nearly one.
From the criteria standpoint, MMPO was attractive because it satisfied weak FBC
as well as Later-no-harm. It also satisfies SFC, and in the three-candidate 
case,
it won't fail SDSC.
 
I think there are two main bad things about the basic method:
1. The Plurality criterion failure (which is on display above)
2. Although it satisfies LNHarm, the defensive truncation strategy is still 
viable and
recommended (by me, anyway).
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Comments on the declaration 2

2011-10-14 Thread Kevin Venzke
Juho,
 
Truthfully my damning MMPO scenario is meant to show a Plurality failure, so the
last-preference rankings that Kristofer lists as equal are meant to be 
truncated.
In other words, candidate C receives acknowledgement from TWO voters.
The appalling thing is not meant to be that the winner primarily has lower 
preferences.
We would be able to choose from very few methods if that were the problem.
 
Kevin

--- En date de : Ven 14.10.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :


De: Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
Objet: Re: [EM] Comments on the declaration and on a few voting systems
À: Election Methods election-meth...@electorama.com
Date: Vendredi 14 octobre 2011, 15h11




If that one example set of votes is bad enough for MMPO, then how about this 
example for PC(wv)?


49 A
48 B  C
03 C


Juho
 
 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #3845] condorcet range voting -- which one yields more condorcet winners?

2011-10-13 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,

--- En date de : Mer 12.10.11, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com a écrit :




 

Maybe you should do sims first, emit flames second.


That's a fair criticism, and one I continue to violate in this message. I 
wonder if Kevin Venzke has any sims which speak to this question.
 
 
Thanks for remembering me. The question is sincere Condorcet efficiency between 
Range and something like MCA? I have three scenarios on-hand (two 1D, one
spectrumless, all three-candidate) and MCA is a bit better than (four-slot) 
Range in
all three. But it is rare that either method has the efficiency of a Condorcet 
method.
 
My sims use 100% strategic voters and polling by the way.
 
A few comparisons.
Spectrumless (blocs have random preferences):
IRV 92.2% (of trials with a CW)
WV 91.7%
MCA 90.6%
Range 90.3%
Approval 88.4% (note that Range doesn't quite become Approval due to the voters
being divided into a fairly small number of strategizing blocs)
FPP 84.8%
 
1D with random candidate positions:
WV 99.1%
IRV 98.4%
MCA 97.9%
Range 97.6%
Approval 96.5%
FPP 84.0%
 
1D with random candidate positions but distance from center halved 
(center-heavy):

WV 97.8%
IRV 97.3%
MCA 96.9%
Range 95.7%
Approval 93.2%
FPP 76.6%
 
Note that the voters have the ability to get what they want a high percentage 
of the
time no matter the method. But they may have to compromise or use other 
strategies
in order to do it. For instance...
 
Here are the percentage of elections in which at least a quarter of the voters 
ended up
compromising (favorite betrayal). The three figures follow the order of the 
scenarios 
above.
 
WV 0.4%, .02%, 0% of elections
IRV 9.3%, 4.6%, 5.7%
MCA 0%, 0%, 0%
Range 0%, 0%, 0%
Approval 0%, 0%, 0%
FPP 17.4%, 17.3%, 18.7%
 
I could have produced other figures as well, such as the rather alarming burial 
rate
under WV. But the point is just that the Condorcet efficiency with strategic 
voters,
this single figure, doesn't tell a complete story.
 
Another point is that I'm not using one cookie-cutter strategy for all methods 
here.
The voters' strategy is deduced by AI, not by me.
 
I do realize I need to get around to making more of my work available.
 
Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] condorcet range voting -- which one yields more condorcet winners?

2011-10-11 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,

--- En date de : Mar 11.10.11, Warren Smith warren@gmail.com a écrit :
 I've done sim experiments indicating that range voting
 finds
 honest-voter Condorcet winners
 more often than Condorcet methods do, if the voters are
 strategic.

Though you have to be careful what you mean by strategic.

My own recent sims use an apples-to-apples method to determine strategic
voting under each method (with all voters being strategic). I don't find
Range/Approval/MCA/whatever to be relatively strong at sincere Condorcet
efficiency most of the time.

It's not that I don't find strategic voting to varying degrees under
rank methods. (Although I see extremely few disaster scenarios, as 
voters, observing polls, seem to have no qualms about compromising to
avert them.) It is probably due to this difference:

In a left/right/center scenario it is completely possible that on 
election day, any one of those three candidates could be the sincere 
Condorcet Winner and be correctly elected under Condorcet or some other
methods. But Approval, at least experimentally, can't handle three
frontrunners on a spectrum. Either left or right is likely to lose
their exclusive supporters, so that only two of the three candidates
can actually win on election day.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [CES #3834] condorcet range voting -- JQ

2011-10-11 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,

--- En date de : Mar 11.10.11, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com a écrit :


 
Note that the more Condorcet-like than Condorcet is only true for Range if 
voters are strategic and somewhat knowledgeable about the polls. 
 
I'm curious whether you believe the more Condorcet-like than Condorcet claim 
based on Warren's IEVS work, or for some other reason. Because in IEVS, the 
polls, 
if we call them polls, provide arbitrary data. Nobody is actually polled.
 
What do you say happens if Range voters are strategic but *not* knowledgeable?
Does that mean they place their approval cutoffs potentially arbitrarily?
 
If so, I think that would still beat all the rank methods with strategic but 
not-
knowledgeable voters. In that situation every ballot's first preference could 
be nearly
arbitrary, because in IEVS strategic rank voters *always* use compromise.
 
Kevin Venzke
 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Viewable Interim results with permitted vote changing

2011-09-25 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Toby,

--- En date de : Dim 25.9.11, Toby Pereira tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :


De: Toby Pereira tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk
Objet: [EM] Viewable Interim results with permitted vote changing
À: electorama list election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Date: Dimanche 25 septembre 2011, 12h13



This may well have been discussed before, and it wouldn't really be practical 
for parliamentary elections, but could be used in other situations. You allow a 
certain period for voting to take place (say a week), and when you cast your 
vote (logging into a computer with a password), it tells you the current 
result. Votes can be changed as many times as you want until the voting 
deadline. This would possibly be a little bit like SODA except that voters 
aren't putting delegation in the hands of the candidates, but do it all 
themselves.
 
I think it would potentially remove problems where weak winners get in - 
candidates that people rank/rate highly thinking that they will never get in, 
perhaps to put a gap between theit favourite and their perceived nearest rival.
 
As for what sort of ballot you'd use with this, I would suggest something 
simple. First Past the Post probably wouldn't be too horrific with this sort of 
voting, but I would suggest probably Approval.
 
This is basically what pre-election polling is supposed to do. With FPP you will
have the same problem that once you have two frontrunners, the winner will
almost certainly be one of those two, with little likelihood of the 
frontrunners 
changing. You might prevent some spoiled outcomes though.
 
Kevin
 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] the meaning of a vote (or lack thereof)

2011-08-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,

It seems to me all Warren is saying is that a more practical definition
of meaning would be a practical one. Arrow doesn't care about whether
the definition is practical, and as you'd then expect it doesn't happen
to be all that practical.

The Arrow/Tideman view doesn't even care what the election method is.
With the minimal assumption of top = good you can aggregate the data
on claimed relative preferences. When you have data that can't be 
interpreted even across two ballots (beyond they chose to vote like 
this), and it is proposed to use that data to pick the winner, that 
feels unpleasant.

I'd be the first to say that every election method is basically just a
game. But if it comes in a box with plastic pieces and a spinner, the
electorate may not be willing to try it. The will of the people, and
democratic legitimacy, is serious business.

Everybody's right, basically.

I'd note though that I've never seen a simulation or estimation of
utility that attempted to incorporate any factor other than how happy
people were with the winner. So even if we agree with the primacy of
BR as an EM criterion, we don't really know what this advises us to 
do.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [RangeVoting] Re: Range Voting As an Issue

2011-08-09 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
Just passing through at the moment. I read this though and wanted to
comment.

--- En date de : Ven 5.8.11, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com a écrit :
In the end, I definitely sympathize with Warren that BR is the best
measure of results ...

I am finding myself looking at utility less because it doesn't appear
to me that any methods are very good at maximizing it, or differ all 
that much in this respect. In that case perhaps one would do better to
focus on something that methods do differ at, which seems to have a
clear value, instead of fighting for the last tiny scrap of utility in
the odd belief that simulated utility numbers will take anything else
of worth into account! Even if that's theoretically true, we're nowhere
near to possessing such numbers.

I haven't seen BR results for MJ, but based on its similarity to 
Range and MCA, I'd suspect MJ clearly beats Condorcet by this measure.

If BR means shortfall from the best outcome that was possible then I
want to note, that in 1D simulations, I find all of the Approval-ish
methods to be rather poor. But again, the difference is so small, it 
may not matter.

It is hard to gauge what one unit of regret means. In the sims I'm
looking at at the moment, the top method (of over 50) had 25% less
regret than Approval, which was the 3rd worst method. How can I tell if
25% is a lot, and something to be concerned about?

The two methods' rates of electing the utility maximizer were 89% to 
87%. Now it doesn't seem like that much of a difference, does it...?

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Correction on BPW cyclebreaker (Stensholt's method)

2011-07-27 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,

The BPW (= Beats Plurality Winner) method is a cyclebreaker proposed
by Eivind Stensholt that he found to be resistant to burial. When there
is a cycle among three candidates, you elect the one who defeats the
first preference winner. (It's unknown how to define the method for 
more than three.) I coded it (incorrectly) and probably commented that 
I wasn't impressed.

However, having fixed the error, I feel the need to say I was wrong and
that it is quite good at what it does. I tried it in three scenarios
(aspectral, 1D, and center-heavy-nomination 1D) and in all three it
either had the lowest burial rate for a Condorcet method, or (in one 
case) was beaten slightly by Condorcet//King of the Hill.

The compromise and truncation incentives are pretty mediocre (i.e. 
highish) though. There's also a little pushover incentive. (I didn't 
allow compression due to the nature of the method.)


I'm planning to compile some stats from my sim to put in an Excel file
that people can download and look through on their own... That way
I won't have to type everything up and people can sort as they wish
and such.

There is probably also a need to distribute method source code so that
if I have implemented a method incorrectly (as in this case) it may be
spotted someday...

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Single Contest Method

2011-07-27 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,

--- En date de : Mer 27.7.11, fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu a écrit :
 Andy's chiastic method is a way of
 utilizing range ballots that has a much more mild incentive
 than 
 Range itself to inflate ratings.  He locates the
 method in a class of methods each of which is based on a 
 different increasing function f from the interval [0,1 ]
 into the same interval:
 
 Elect the candidate with the highest fraction q such that
 at least the fraction f(q) of the ballots rate the 
 candidate at fraction q of the maxRange value (assuming
 that minRange is zero).

Hmmm. So, noting that I cannot test more than 4 slots due to the design
of the simulation, I want to take each candidate and ask:
Did 100% of the voters rate him 3/3?
Or else did 67+% of the voters rate him 2/3 or higher?
Or else did 33+% of the voters rate him 1/3 or higher?
And then the last possible question is trivial.

That I believe is if f(q)=q. So what I want is this:

f(q)=q/2, and f(q)=(q+1)/2,

So the first one asks:
50% rated 3? 33.3% rated a 2+? 16.7% rated a 1+?

It is curious to me that the 50% figure should decrease.

I'm not really sure how to interpret the second one. I was interpreting
the range of q to be 0-100%. I guess I will interpret (q+1) for a
four-slot ballot to mean 133.3%. So then I get:
66.7% rated 3? 50% rated 2? 33.3% rated 1+?

I must not have this correct, because isn't the first test strictly
harder than the second? What is an example where you win on the first
method but not the second?

Thanks.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Single Contest Method, never mind

2011-07-27 Thread Kevin Venzke
Er...

--- En date de : Mer 27.7.11, Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr a écrit :
 So the first one asks:
 50% rated 3? 33.3% rated a 2+? 16.7% rated a 1+?
 
 four-slot ballot to mean 133.3%. So then I get:
 66.7% rated 3? 50% rated 2? 33.3% rated 1+?
 
 I must not have this correct, because isn't the first test
 strictly
 harder than the second? What is an example where you win on
 the first
 method but not the second?

What I was thinking when I asked this was that if you got 33.3%+ 2+
ratings, you also necessarily got 33.3% 1+ ratings. So, if I understand
things, the way to not win on the second method is if somebody else
has fewer 2+ ratings than you but more 1+ ratings than you.

So the combined method is something like identifying the ambiguity
between two Bucklin-like levels and having a pairwise contest to
resolve it.

Honestly I don't how well that is going to work... It seems to me it's
the better bet to try to avoid having the pairwise contest.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Automated Approval methods (was Single Contest)

2011-07-25 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Rob,

--- En date de : Lun 25.7.11, Rob LeGrand honky1...@yahoo.com a écrit :
  Yes, but if it were strategy-free somehow, I think it
 would be worth
  it. Real life isn't monotone. I don't imagine that all
 the prettier Yee
  diagrams would really look like that if voters were
 using information
  and strategy!
 
 I may be missing something, but I don't see how you can
 have a
 nonmonotonic method that is strategy-free.

Well, there aren't technically any (serious) strategy-free methods. I'm
referring more to a method not having obvious strategic incentives, or
at least not having a lot of a single type of strategic incentive, so 
that everybody knows that in method X you should use Y strategy all 
the time etc.

  For any example of
 nonmonotonicity, you should be able to find a single voter
 that triggers
 it--say, if that focal voter votes ABXC, then X
 wins, but if they vote
 AXBC, then X loses.  Whoever wins when X
 loses, manipulability pops up:

Yes, I don't disagree with that.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] PR for USA or UK

2011-07-25 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Toby,

--- En date de : Lun 25.7.11, Toby Pereira tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
But to summarise a 
possibility - everyone submits their range ballots. Then the computer
calculates what would be the winning set of candidates under these 
votes. Then each ballot is looked at again by the computer and it 
works out the optimum vote for each voter on the basis of what 
everyone else has done. These new votes are then submitted. 
Obviously everyone's changes at once so the goalposts move. But 
they could be recalculated a few times, and it might approach some 
form of equilibrium. But I'm not entirely sure at the moment how you
would decide the optimum vote for someone based on the current 
situation. I'll think about it though.

Actually we are discussing this sort of thing in the automated approval
posts.

The problem (if it is a problem) is that if this method does a good 
job, you will (in the single-winner case) get a Condorcet method, or 
very close. Because, even if you only like a candidate 3/10, if that 
is the best candidate you can hope for, the method will still decide
that you should get behind that candidate and help him win.

Really, I think Approval and Range work this way anyway, just without
a computer.

What I like about the range ballot here is that it sets out in 
advance each voter's preference for whole sets of candidates. It 
would work on the basis that how a voter rates a set of candidates is 
realted to their total score given to them. So if there are two to be 
elected then two candidates they give 5 out of 10 to is the same 
as a 10 and a 0. I would set that out as how the scores are 
essentially defined. With ranks I don't know if 1st and 4th is 
better or worse than 2nd and 3rd.

Yes, that's nice. There are Condorcet methods that use this data to
resolve cycles and deter certain strategies. But I don't know of a
method that uses this data, in an effective way, to elect candidates
who are somehow different in quality from Condorcet winners.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Automated Approval methods (was Single Contest)

2011-07-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Kristofer,

--- En date de : Dim 24.7.11, Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com a 
écrit :
  I also tried implementing the most obvious (I suppose)
 method: Take the
  ratings and conduct simulated approval polling, either
 for some
  determined or semi-random number of iterations, or
 until someone wins
  twice in a row. This doesn't test as well as I thought
 it would though.
 
 What Approval strategy do you use?

I always use better than expectation when it is allowed to assume the
voters know the method is approval. (Which is just to say that the main
sim, when during pure Approval, can't use better than expectation.)

I put a tiny amount of average utility of all candidates into the
expectation just to try to avoid the situation where your favorite won
all the polls so therefore you don't approve him.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] PR for USA or UK

2011-07-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Toby,

--- En date de : Dim 24.7.11, Toby Pereira tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
Strategy-resistant systems do have certain advantages as you say, 
but in the single-winner case it would end up reducing range to a 
Condorcet method, which arguably isn't as good, and ends up pushing 
out a better-liked candidate for one that strictly more people 
prefer. And this is what I like about range - it's not just about 
which candidates you prefer to which other ones, but by how much. 

I think the Range method itself is pretty incapable of this, but you
could do it either with rated ballots or with a rank ballot that has
truncation incentive.

And as long as strategy isn't performed better by voters of some candidates 
than others, the fact that there would still be some 
honest voters would mean that the advantages of range would still 
remain to an extent, meaning that overall better-liked candidates 
stand a better chance, and it therefore reflects better the overall
preferences of the electorate!

That paragraph makes sense if you're comparing Range to Approval, but 
not Range to anything else. If large numbers of voters use strategy in
Range (and I'm pretty sure they would be encouraged to; personally I
wouldn't need any encouraging) this will destroy so much information 
that the only way Range will win out is if the rank methods you compare
it to contain even more destructive incentives than Range has.

[begin quote]
On my website I give an example where party A has 68% of the support 
and party B 32%. There are two seats and so each party fields two 

 Of course party A voters could 
coordinate themselves and split into two factions of 34% to take both 
seats, but this would be very hard for them to achieve. STV (Droop 
quota anyway) would transfer the votes above the quota accordingly 
so that party A would win both seats, and give what I would regard 
as the less fair result.

Ok, but it's not obvious that it is less fair. You are according a
privilege to the weaker party just because it is a different party.

I'm not according them a privilege because they are a different party, but 
because I would see it as logical and fair that 75% is a reasonable cut-off. If 
a system made the cut-off at 80%, I'd argue that it was unfair in favour of the 
smaller party.

[end quote]

Can you explain your position without saying party? Because if you 
didn't see the parties, and only saw voters, it would be indefensible 
to give a seat to the 32%. There would be nothing special about that 
group.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] PR for USA or UK

2011-07-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Toby,

--- En date de : Dim 24.7.11, Toby Pereira tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
[begin quote]
Strategy-resistant systems do have certain advantages as you say, 
but in the single-winner case it would end up reducing range to a 
Condorcet method, which arguably isn't as good, and ends up pushing 
out a better-liked candidate for one that strictly more people 
prefer. And this is what I like about range - it's not just about 
which candidates you prefer to which other ones, but by how much. 

I think the Range method itself is pretty incapable of this, but you
could do it either with rated ballots or with a rank ballot that has
truncation incentive.
 
Is a range ballot not a rated ballot?
[end quote]

Sorry, I mean, I don't believe it is hopeless to try doing what you
want with a rated ballot. Range does use a rated ballot. Off the top
of my head I don't have any really great method suggestions here,
because it seems to me to be extremely difficult to design a method so
that it maximizes utility. If the method is strategy-proof, it will
tend to elect the sincere Condorcet winner. If it's not strategy-proof,
you can't fully trust the information you collect. Something in-between
seems to be needed, but I would bet nobody will feel very happy with 
whatever is invented.

[begin quote]
And as long as strategy isn't performed better by voters of some candidates 
than others, the fact that there would still be some 
honest voters would mean that the advantages of range would still 
remain to an extent, meaning that overall better-liked candidates 
stand a better chance, and it therefore reflects better the overall
preferences of the electorate!

That paragraph makes sense if you're comparing Range to Approval, but 
not Range to anything else. If large numbers of voters use strategy in
Range (and I'm pretty sure they would be encouraged to; personally I
wouldn't need any encouraging) this will destroy so much information 
that the only way Range will win out is if the rank methods you compare
it to contain even more destructive incentives than Range has.
 
With a single-winner election, the full strategy option is to vote approval 
style, but I'm not sure if this is as clear for PR.

[end quote]

No, I have no comment on any PR versions. I wouldn't assume any 
similarity.

You say you wouldn't need any encouraging to vote strategically -
I wouldn't either to be honest - but what is the optimal strategy?

I have heard and tend to agree with approve everyone better than what
you expect on average the outcome to be. If there are two frontrunners
with perceived-to-be equal odds of winning, that would mean approving
every candidate better than the average of the two.

Experimentally there usually are two frontrunners that emerge from
pre-election polling.

In my own simulations, the ideal strategy is determined by the voters
within the specific situation they find themselves in. So it's not
easy to describe what strategy they are choosing, but it must be 
something close.

In any case, if range does turn out to be problematic, proportional
approval voting would be my next choice. I don't like ranked ballots
because you don't know how much the voter actually likes each 
candidate or whether they like them at all.

Generally I have liked rank methods where voters are not thought to be
supposed to rank candidates they don't really like. This may start to
turn it into Approval, but with some ranking information retained.

Can you explain your position without saying party? Because if you 
didn't see the parties, and only saw voters, it would be indefensible 
to give a seat to the 32%. There would be nothing special about that 
group.

Candidates A and B are both fairly similar and 68% of voters vote 
for both of these approval-style and no-one else. Candidates C and 
D are also similar to each other and 32% of voters vote for both 
of these approval style and no-one else. That's the example set out 
without parties.

Ok. It sounds like you want to represent more types of voters. The
68% cannot have both seats because they're the same type. If they were
different types then it would be OK.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [COVoterChoice] RB gives an equal chance of winning to not just all parties, but all combinations of programs,

2011-07-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi,

--- En date de : Dim 24.7.11, Dave Ketchum da...@clarityconnect.com a écrit :
 De: Dave Ketchum da...@clarityconnect.com
 Objet: Re: [EM] [COVoterChoice] RB gives an equal chance of winning to not 
 just all parties, but all combinations of programs,
 À: electionscience Foundation electionscie...@googlegroups.com
 Cc: preferentiality preferential...@gmail.com, EM 
 election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Date: Dimanche 24 juillet 2011, 19h42
 I assume this is from Colorado, and
 have no idea who else has seen it.
 
 I see it as worth considering the thinking, although I AM
 NOT signing on as backing any of it.

I have trouble finding any description in the post. I wonder if RB is 
intended to mean Random Ballot (RB) as the message subject would
almost make sense in that case.

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Automated Approval methods (was Single Contest)

2011-07-24 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Forest,

--- En date de : Dim 24.7.11, fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu a écrit :
 This kind of approach has been experimented with for a long
 time by Rob LeGrand, and there doesn't 
 seem to be any good way to make it monotone.

Yes, but if it were strategy-free somehow, I think it would be worth it.
Real life isn't monotone. I don't imagine that all the prettier Yee
diagrams would really look like that if voters were using information
and strategy!

No time to say more...

Kevin Venzke


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


  1   2   3   4   5   >