Re: [EM] Sociological issues of elections

2013-09-01 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.9.2013, at 16.57, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 To answer your question Juho, «When you wrote about a form of
 government that is elected by the people, did you mean that voters
 should have more say on what the government (coalition) will be like?»:
 My intention behind that statement was purely that the government should
 still be voted in by the population, not be decided by any other means,
 such as electing people based on skill and knowledge (i.e. technocracy).

I tried to outline some scenarios where the voters could more or less directly 
determine the composition of the coalition. I guess this is too dynamic for 
you, and you actually like the current Norwegian practice where there are two 
rather fixed government alternatives, and voters know exactly which coalition 
each candidate/party belongs to?

That approach is good in the sense that people know exactly what they will get. 
There are however also some possible problems. If there are only two possible 
alternatives, the dynamics of the system might approach the dynamics of a two 
party system. The problem is that voters may not be able to influence all the 
topics but only on some selected or most popular topics.

I mean that if grouping A says yes to X  and Y (two continuously popular 
questions), and grouping B says no to X and Y, then there may be third 
questions that will never be solved. Maybe both groupings say yes to Z (e.g. 
yes to money coming to the parties from some dubious sources) although voters 
do not like Z. The voters can not vote no to Z. A multiparty system is however 
better than a two-party system in this respect since it is possible that 
grouping A has party A1 that actually would not like to promote Z, but uít has 
to since other parties in grouping A do. In this case voters may one day 
influence on Z by first giving party A1 sufficient support so that A1 gains 
majority within grouping A.

The point thus is that voters may have more influence on what direction the 
country will take if there are more than 2 main groupings, and voters can 
decide which ones will be in power next time. If all parties that do not like Z 
(and who will sincerely announce their preferences before the election) will 
get more votes, those parties are likely to be in the government, and the 
country is likely to oppose Z (those parties may come from left, right and 
elsewhere). Of course this approach has the problem that the exact policy and 
parties that will be included in the government are not known before the 
election (unlike in the fixed groupings approach). The formation of the 
government and its policy may can however be guessed quite well, if 
large_and_rising_parties will form the govrnment, and all parties have clearly 
stated their opinion on X, Y, Z etc. More votes to no Z parties is likely to 
lead to a no Z government in these or next elections.

Different approaches have different benefits. One just needs to estimate how 
well these properties meet the needs of the country in question.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Sociological issues of elections

2013-09-01 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.9.2013, at 22.02, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 On Sun, Sep 01, 2013 at 07:05:12PM +0300, Juho Laatu wrote:
 I tried to outline some scenarios where the voters could more or less 
 directly determine the composition of the coalition. I guess this is too 
 dynamic for you, and you actually like the current Norwegian practice 
 where there are two rather fixed government alternatives, and voters know 
 exactly which coalition each candidate/party belongs to?
 
 I apologize for answering so briefly on your message.


 I find the idea that letting the voters vote for their preferred
 coalition quite interesting

I agee with interesting. But probably they are not very pracical, and probably 
will not be used. I just wanted to analyze the prospects a bit further on the 
path taht you seemed to point out. :-)

 And I can't fully
 visualize how such an election would work, and it seems to me that this
 may quickly become a fairly complex system?

Yes. Even the simplest approaches could get quite complex since one can not 
allow a mechanical algorithm to determine the coalition anyway. Maybe the 
parties will not agree, and it is not easy to agree what coalition size is 
optimal etc. So, maybe voter opinions would be used olny as one input in the 
negotiations.

We can see the sizes of the parties after the election anyway, and we can see 
which parties lost votes and which ones gained new votes. Based on this we can 
quite well already see which coalitions are the favourite ones. Explicit voter 
given information on different coalitions could be just additional opinion poll 
style information. Maybe a Condorcet poll where different coalition core 
partner combinatons are listed as candidates. Maybe a poll on one's favourite 
party and one's favourite second party for the coalition. The latter example is 
easier since it is easier to agree what the candidates are. But the additional 
information that these polls would offer is not very essential anyway.

 I don't know how common this is, but before elections in Norway most
 media create tests where the user is presented with several questions
 they answer with how much they agree with, and at the end they're
 presented with which party they agree the most with.

This kind of web services are popular in Finland too.

 If this was how
 people voted for parties then you would effectively eliminate much
 fearmongering and charisma-votes, but you'll also introduce several
 other issues (the ideology of the party is lost, and you'll greatly
 simplify problems that may be very complex in nature).

The key problem that I see in the question based polls is that it is very 
difficult to formulate neutral questions, to find a well balanced set of 
questions, and also to evaluate the level of agreement and weight of each 
question. I typically also miss some key questions that I would have liked to 
answer and hear candidate opinions. Such questionnaires can offer useful 
additional information to the voters, but I would not pick any single one of 
them as an election method that does good enough job in analyzing which 
candidates the voters want to elect. This kind of questionnaires can also be 
(at least in principle) used to mislead the voters by focusing on certain 
matters, and making biased questions and answer options (like giving a sunny 
picture and forcing candidates and voters to agree with topic X, and reverse 
treatment for topic Y).

 I know the questions is vague and broad, but I hope the issues I'm
 trying to point out is something the readers of this list can relate to.

Questions like how to arrange an election so that voters will get best possible 
information and where parties can not present too biased views to the voters 
are very relevant at least to me. One topic that I have sometimes played with, 
and that has something to do with this discussion is how to complement the 
quick and vague TV debates with some more concrete questions and answers. One 
approach is to allow each party to present some written questions to other 
parties and force the other parties to answer these questions. That alone would 
give the voters some idea on what the current key differences between different 
parties are. Just a scratch, but the point is that we could force the 
discussions to be more exact, not only marketing stuff, and not only kind of 
enetertaining first shooter games on TV.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Sociological issues of elections

2013-08-31 Thread Juho Laatu
On 31.8.2013, at 15.24, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 This may be a bit outside what is usually discussed here, but I'll give
 it a shot and if someone know of some resources I should check up on
 then please let me know.
 
 I've not followed this list for a long time, but my impression is that
 the main focus is on the technical or mathematical properties, and less
 on the sociological issues.
 
 For instance, when voting for persons then candidates with high
 popularity and charisma are likely to win more votes than less
 charismatic candidates, despite the less charismatic candidates being
 far more suited for the task (more knowledge, experience, talent, etc.).
 In the Norwegian system where we got multiple parties, but two blocks
 (left and right), we also see that some people vote for their second
 preference rather than the first, because the first is in the wrong
 block or intend to cooperate with another party which the voter dislike
 the most.
 
 If it is within the scope of this list, what are your thoughts on the
 subject?

In my opinion this is very much in scope. And from technical or mathematical 
properties point of view, these considerations may well have an impact on what 
kind of techniques one should use.

I'd try to solve the problem of charismatic candidates by offering more 
information about the candidates to the voters, and allowing all candidates 
equal amount of publicity (visual, non-visual, real time, offline, net). What 
more could we do? Voters must anyway find out themselves which candidates are 
really good despite of not so good charisma, and which ones have nice charisma 
but nothing behind the charisma. The system can not make these evaluations for 
them, so we just need to increase the openness and informativeness of the 
system.

Then the problem of people not voting for otherwise good candidates that have 
bad ideas like cooperation with unwanted parties, or who are from the wrong 
bock. I think also here voters should decide how much weight they put on 
different topics. If cooperation and correct wing are important, then that 
candidate really is bad and the voter should not vote for him.

I guess here we come also close to the problem of voters being unable (e.g. in 
traditional list based systems) to give support to some selected set of 
candidates that come from multiple parties, but not to the other candidates of 
those parties. Typically voters can also give their vote to one candidate only, 
and that vote might end up supporting wrong candidates (if the favourite 
candidate will not be elected).

 Alternatively:
 Assuming the perfect election system where voting any different than
 your real preference would only hurt your preference, how would you
 design a form of government that is elected by the people, but is
 resistant to sociological issues that can't be prevented by the election
 method (such as the examples mentioned above)?

I think we would first have to agree what kind of a government is a good 
government. There can be many opinions, and for different kind of political 
systems the choice may be different.

From a traditional multiparty perspective a good government might be one that 
represents majority of the voters but not if we want to have an opposiition 
too. (this is just one option)

Traditionally we want there to be static parties (other options possible too). 
The government would typically consist of multiple parties. A typical approach 
is that voters must choose their party and some preferred candidate(s) within 
that party. (Alternatively voters could indicate support also to good 
candidates from multiple parties.)

Traditionally governments are formed only after the election, which means that 
the voter will not vote for a government coalition but that parties will build 
the coalition by themselves. It is however also quite common that possible 
government coalitions are quite well known and fixed already before the 
election (I guess Norway is closer to this). (It would be possible to have also 
elections where voters will decide what kind of government to form, but I guess 
this approach is not in use anywhere.)

When you wrote about a form of government that is elected by the people, did 
you mean that voters should have more say on what the government (coalition) 
will be like? I.e. do you dislike both the approach of two fixed alternatives 
and the approach of parties negotiating the coalition structure after the 
election?

Anyway, whether decided by the voters or by the parties (/ elected 
representatives) after the election, a good government coalition might be one 
that has proportional representation of all those parties that will form the 
government.

Within those parties one has different options on how to pick the ministers. 
The ministers could be representatives that got a lots of support from the 
voters. Or alternatively the ministers could be ones that have support from the 
representatives (this approach alloas also 

Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-22 Thread Juho Laatu
On 22.7.2013, at 16.43, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 On Sun, Jul 21, 2013 at 04:04:03PM +0300, Juho Laatu wrote:
 Yes, it is possible and even typical that many small parties get their best 
 results in the same district. One simple fix (and one step more complex 
 algorithm) is to allocate full quota seats first and fractional seats only 
 after them. This means that the results can be off only by less than one 
 quota for each party in each region. (Also other more ideal methods can be 
 developed.) I wonder if accuracy of one quota would be sufficient.
 
 I may misunderstand you here, but I'm confused as of what would be the
 fractional seats. Using Sainte-Laguë there's no quota and thus no
 fraction.

The simplest quota is Hare quota (= allVotes / allSeats). If a party gets 3.4 
quotas of votes in some district, then it has three full quotas and one 
fractional quota of votes. In the algorithm above that would mean three certain 
full quota seats and one uncertain fractional seat. That approach is closer to 
quota style thinking than to divisor (e.g. Sainte-Laguë) style thinking, but it 
can be used in in divisor based methods too. The fractional seats will just be 
allocated using either a largest remainder method or a divisor method. With 
Sainte-Laguë one could use also Droop quota instead of Hare quota if one finds 
that more appropriate, or whatever quota is considered best (and is not too 
generous in the sense that it would grant too many seats).

 Is your idea to apportion seats by first using a quota (quota = votes /
 seats), then apportion the remaining seats (sequentially giving out
 seats to party A, party B, party C, ...) as described earlier in this
 thread?

Yes, in the description above the intention was to allocate the remaining seats 
first to the smallest party, then to the next smallest etc.

 That might produce a sensible result, I'll see if I can modify the code
 to do something like this.

I think that approach is at least quite easy to explain and justify to the 
voters. A full quota is something that looks pretty much like a certain seat, 
and quota fractions look like possible seats.

Juho


 Let me know if this is not what you meant.
 
 
 -- 
 Regards,
 Vidar Wahlberg
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-22 Thread Juho Laatu
On 22.7.2013, at 23.50, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 07/22/2013 05:37 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 22.7.2013, at 16.43, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:
 
 That might produce a sensible result, I'll see if I can modify the
 code to do something like this.
 
 I think that approach is at least quite easy to explain and justify
 to the voters. A full quota is something that looks pretty much like
 a certain seat, and quota fractions look like possible seats.
 
 Yes, a quota is easier to explain. Just consider my attempts at divisor-based 
 STV analogs vs STV itself: the latter is far easier to understand.
 
 On the other hand, quota-based systems have some peculiar properties. In 
 party list, if you're using a quota method, it might happen that party X 
 gains support while party Y loses support, yet Y gains more seats than X.

Yes, the paradoxes may complicate things 
(http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Apportionment_paradox). Some of the peculiarities 
can however be quite acceptable and even wanted. We discussed earlier for 
example the possibility that some seats would go to Condorcet style centrists. 
Let's say we have three parties, large Left, large Right and small Centre. If 
there is only one seat, we might give that to the centrist party (since it may 
be a clear Condorcet winner). But if there are two seats we might give them to 
Left and Right. And we get Alabama paradox style behaviour (where the centrist 
party loses a seat when the number of seats grows).

The benefit of divisor methods is that they give a clear order of allocation. 
The quota methods rather focus on minimizing the lost votes. Both have their 
benefits, and their problems, both from the point of view of who should 
actually be elected, and from the point of view how to explain the behaviour of 
the methods to the audience.

 
 I guess that for party list, you could explain a divisor method pretty easily 
 as well -- or rather, the Webster variant (multiply and round) would be 
 fairly easy to explain:
 
 We would like each party to get a proportional share. So we divide each 
 party's number of votes by some constant to get the sum to equal the number 
 of seats in parliament.
 But this will give fractional results, so we have to round the results since 
 there's no such thing as a tenth of an MP.
 But now the sum of seats may not add up to the number of seats in parliament. 
 So we adjust the divisor.
 
 In other words, it's the least possible change from the ideal situation, 
 given that we can't have fractional MPs.
 

I'd like to test and try fractional MPs too :-).

I note that generally voters need a simple and credible explanation. Very few 
voters actally understand how the most common divisor methods lead to 
proportional representation. Some of them may know how to use the algorithm, 
but I guess most are just happy to have a vague understanding that the used 
algorithm is most likely ok since people say it is proportional and experts, 
media and one's own party do not complain about it.

The algorithm may thus be complex and it may contain paradoxes as long as there 
is a consensus that it works well enough. Or the algorithm may simple to help 
calculations and understanding. Nowadays simple calculations are no more a 
requirement, but computerized counting may sometimes be presented as a 
potential source of fraud (not often in real life though, if the calculations 
can be independently checked).

I note that it is quite common that claimed problems emerge when some interest 
group wants to attack a method  that is for some reason not beneficial to the 
interest group. Often the identified flaws are just clever propaganda, not so 
much about actual meaningful flaws of the system. It is also possible that 
flaws are real in a situation where someone proposes a biased system that would 
serve the interest of some interest group (e.g. to keep the current strong 
parties in power).

After saying all this, I note that the most common divisor and largest 
remainder methods tend to give very proportional results when compared to what 
kind of systems are on average used globally. I think they are also all simple 
enough and easy enough to justify (not to all voters but to many enough experts 
and politicians to get the consensus that they work fine). Often the 
vulnerabilities are vulnerabilities to negative marketing, not really 
vulnerabilities in the actual use of the system.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-21 Thread Juho Laatu
On 20.7.2013, at 13.07, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 07/19/2013 11:50 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 19.7.2013, at 10.18, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 
 In such cases, I would also suggest a few of the seats of the
 parliament be given by a centrist- or minmax-based method (e.g.
 Condorcet, CPO-SL with few seats, or possibly even minmax approval
 or something like it). The idea would be that there shouldn't be
 any kingmakers, but if there's a near-tie, that tie is broken by a
 moderate group.
 
 In proportional systems one should distribute most of the seats
 directly to different parties without seeking for compromise
 candidates. I mean that also extreme parties should get their
 proportional share of the seats. Only in the allocaton of the very
 last seats (=last seats at national level) one can take the second
 preferences of the voters into account. The second preferences often
 point to compromise oriented candidates (by definition). The idea of
 favouring compromise candidates thus means taking the second
 preferences of the voters into account when allocating the very last
 seats.
 
 Sometimes the voters may prefer giving the last seat to a compromise
 party (with only a small fraction of quota of first preference votes
 supporting this decision) to giving it to one of the main parties
 (that might have close to 0.5 quota of first preference votes left
 supporting their candidate). The CPO approach is a good way to
 estimate which allocation of seats would get wide support among the
 electorate.
 
 I was more thinking of doing so as a way of heading off the kingmaker 
 objection. The objection goes something like: we need to have a threshold, 
 because otherwise a very small party might be in position to make or break a 
 coalition and so would get undue power. A threshold is an absolute way of 
 avoiding this unless the party is at least to some extent large enough, but 
 one could also avoid it by giving the tiebreaker spot to a centrist or broad 
 appeal group. If complexity is not an issue, having a centrist tiebreaker 
 group might even be preferable, since a threshold is indiscriminate about 
 where it gives that tiebreaker power: a medium sized party could still become 
 kingmaker were it lucky enough, given a threshold.

If new mechanisms are needed in order to avoid using some more problematic 
mechanisms (like a high threshold), then such mechanisms are needed. But if not 
absolutely needed, my preference is to go for full proportionality, allowing 
compromise candidates instead of ones with most unused support (fractional 
quota) left only when allocating the very last seats. Also in those cases 
allocation of last seats to compromise candidates would be based on vote 
transfers (of still unused fractional votes) that give the compromise candidate 
more support than all extreme candidates have.

One reason for this approach is that voter opinions and majortity are such a 
strong concepts that one should avoid breaking such majorities. Let's say we 
have four parties, big left, big right, small extreme left, and small modeate 
right. L + EL have 51% majority. EL is now a kingmaker in the sense that its 
support gives majority strength to L. MR is a compromise party in this scenario 
(preferred over the other big party by many voters). If we give more power to 
MR (since it is a compromise party, or since it is more moderate than the other 
small party) would change the left wing majority to a right wing majority. I'm 
sure this would also not look good in the eyes of the voters and media.

Parties of different size may have disproportional voting power with certain 
distribution of strength among the parties. But I rather see that as a 
mathematical phenomenon that is natural in the sense that if majorities are 
that way, then they are that way. It would be difficult to say that some 
majority grouping does not deserve its majortity status.

I already noted few mails back that at least in Finland I don't see the 
kingmaker effect giving too much power to the small parties. Typically 
government coalitions have more than one small party, if one small party would 
be in a kingmaker position. And generally small parties rather respect the 
opinions of the big parties. This is because they want to continue co-operation 
with other parties also in the next governments, and because they probably made 
some agreements (you get this, I get that, other topics will be decided by 
majority within the government) when the government was formed.

I thus believe that in many (maybe most) countries the kingmaker position would 
not be a major problem. But if it causes problems in the discussion, then some 
modifications may be needed to defend agaist the threat, or the threat of not 
making any progress otherwise.

 
 Now that I think about it, that might be a way to improve the inequality 
 between proportional representation and coalition voting power. This could be 
 done in one of two ways

Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-21 Thread Juho Laatu
Some random notes. Please treat them as such. Just trying to point out what PAL 
representation looks like from different angles.

I guess the key feature of PAL representation is the dynamic size of the 
districts. In this thread one central theme has been practical reforms in the 
Norwegian (or similar) system. Therefore of course one starts from districts 
that are similar to the current ones. But I think it could be possible that 
also a working and very accurately proportional multiparty system would use PAL 
representation like dynamic districts one day. (For current single member 
district based systems the promise of PAL representation is of course quite 
different, and the reasons to support or oppose it are quite different.)

I note that the linked PAL representation article recommends use of 
super-districts. This means that voters would be (almost) forced to vote for 
the candidates of their own region (as in typical multiwinner systems force 
voters to do today). There was also the write-in option (to support the 
traditions of the USA I guess). If such write-in votes are rare, then they have 
also only small impact on the results. If they are common, then candidates of 
large centres would probably get more votes, and that would reduce regional 
proportionality somewhat.

If some party gets only one seat (nationally), then I wonder if that seat would 
go to the biggest super-district. Is that how the system works? I guess the 
candidates of the biggest super-district typically delegate votes to each 
others. I wonder if they are allowed to delegate to others too (which might 
mean delegation to some central places, central figures, and that migh distort 
regional proportionality to some extent). I also note that the negotiation 
process of candidate vote delegation might be a complex one, possibly even 
involving money and party coercion.

In large parties that will get several seats in each super-district this system 
could lead to more accurate regional representation than in traditional 
multimember district based systems. The problem of voters voting for the most 
central candidates of their (super-)district however remains (= makes the 
regional representation less proportional). Same with candidate delegation.

One alternative to this kind of dynamic district oriented approach to providing 
good regional proportionality are e.g. ranked votes that allow voters to 
support all the candidates of their own sub-district (if they so wish), but 
just let the representatives represent whatever they do represent (region or 
ideology). I note that one key idea behind the PAL representation approach to 
districts is to follow the traditional single member district idea as closely 
as possible (maybe partly for marketability reasons, partly to guarantee good 
regional proportionality). This may be important in current single member 
district countries. When one looks at the system from current multmember 
district country point of view, the super-districts seem to correspond to the 
current districts. Then the question is, how much more will the dynamic 
districts offer when compared to traditional bullet votes to a party or to a 
candidate withins a (super-)district, or to a ranked vote based system (that 
allows voters to vote in terms of smaller sub-districts, but does not force 
them to do so (like super-districts do not force voters to vote locally)).

One more topic in my mind is the distribution of candidates to the atomic 
districts. I guess in PAL representation it is possible that representatives of 
all (dynamic) districts that cover one particular atomic district may come from 
that single atomic district. Each atomic district thus gets its own nominated 
representative (for each party) but it is possible that the geographical 
distribution of the candidates is not very balanced.

I guess that's enough (maybe even too much :) for now.

Juho


On 20.7.2013, at 17.40, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 I have kept up with this thread only intermittently. It seems to have strayed 
 significantly far away from its subject line, and while I've been interested 
 in some of the points that have been made, it's hard to summarize the thread 
 as a whole.
 
 There is one point I've wanted to make, which seems a bit off-topic, but no 
 more so than the rest of the thread. That is that a least remainders approach 
 is not the only way to get something biproportional. You can also approach 
 that ideal through delegation. Asset, for instance, is arguably perfectly 
 proportional in all salient dimensions. And PAL representation is a 
 biproportional system that works with a simple vote-for-one ballot. I 
 encourage the people to follow that link because I think that the ideas in 
 that system might enrich the conversation in this thread.
 
 Jameson


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-21 Thread Juho Laatu
On 21.7.2013, at 14.42, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 On Fri, Jul 19, 2013 at 08:23:04AM +0300, Juho Laatu wrote:
 I do feel that distributing first seats to small parties first makes
 more sense, especially considering that certain small parties (such as
 Rødt) got a lot of support in districts with large cities, but nearly
 no support in other districts. They should be guaranteed to receive
 their won seats in the districts where they got most support.
 
 I think it is ok to simply distribute first all seats of the smallest party, 
 then all seats of the next smallest party etc. This is to avoid any weird 
 results where some parties got seats in districts where they had relatively 
 small support. Large parties do have strong candidates in every district, so 
 leaving the rounding errors to them causes least harm.
 
 I actually tried something not too far from this, I distributed one and
 one seat to each party, i.e. in a election where 3 parties won seats:
 party A gets a seat
 party B gets a seat
 Party C gets a seat
 Party A gets a seat
 ...
 When a party had no more seats they were of course skipped. What
 happened was that certain districts got very peculiar results for the
 large parties. For example in Oslo all the small parties got one or more
 seats, leaving few seats left for the largest party, who got half the
 amount of seats you'd expect compared to their vote percentage in that
 district.

Yes, it is possible and even typical that many small parties get their best 
results in the same district. One simple fix (and one step more complex 
algorithm) is to allocate full quota seats first and fractional seats only 
after them. This means that the results can be off only by less than one quota 
for each party in each region. (Also other more ideal methods can be 
developed.) I wonder if accuracy of one quota would be sufficient.

 This is why I went for the slightly more complex way of distributing
 seats in the reversed order the seats were won. It does mean that both
 small and large parties suffer rounding errors, but it's more evenly
 spread, and with a slight advantage to smaller parties.
 
 
 The biproportional apportionment system Kristoffer linked to is very
 interesting. It is slightly more complex and I fear it may be too
 complex for common people to understand (which will make it difficult to
 gain support for it), and I wonder if it may end up with exceptionally
 long calculation time when there are many districts and many parties.

Yes, it has some complexity problems. Of course the benefit is that the results 
will follow some ideal definition. I guess the society and politicians have a 
lot to say on what approach is best.

 Especially in Norway where amount of seats in a district may be
 radically different from the amount of votes cast in that district.
 Finnmark is a such example, which got a low population and few voters,
 but a large area, giving them relatively many seats (calculated by
 population and area) compared to amount of votes. As I've understood the
 algorithm so far it'll calculate how many seats each party wins in a
 district purely based on percentage of the votes cast there, then later
 adjusted up or down to match the real amount of seats that should be won
 in the district. Due to the low amount of votes in this district it's
 likely that only about 1-2 seats will initially be won there, meaning
 you'll have to weight up the votes in Finnmark and weight the votes down
 in another district.
 
 I'd like to try implementing it, but I don't fully grasp all of it yet
 and most of my spare time ran out, so it might take a while.

It would be good if there was an EM algorithm library somewhere. This has been 
discussed also before. I guess the rich environment of languages and platforms 
is one key reason why such nice library culture does not exist (not in EM, not 
much elsewhere either). Hoping for a better future with ability to communicate 
also easily implementable algorithms.

Juho


 
 
 -- 
 Regards,
 Vidar Wahlberg
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-19 Thread Juho Laatu
On 19.7.2013, at 10.18, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 In short, multiple constraints might mean that the results over here 
 depends on what happens over there in a way that's not easy to understand. 
 And the more constraints you add, the harder it could get.

One could estimate the level of confusion caused by those properties of the 
method that are not very easy to explain by studying the complex properties of 
the current system. In Norway the leveling seats are one potential topic. Could 
a discussion on the leveling seats go like this? Why do we have leveling 
seats? To make the results more balanced. Ok. If this is plausible, and if 
people thus accept the current level of complexity in the rules, then people 
could accept same level of complex rules also in the new system. The 
acceptable explanation could refer to the algorithm itself or to the design 
principles behind the algorithm.

 In such cases, I would also suggest a few of the seats of the parliament be 
 given by a centrist- or minmax-based method (e.g. Condorcet, CPO-SL with few 
 seats, or possibly even minmax approval or something like it). The idea would 
 be that there shouldn't be any kingmakers, but if there's a near-tie, that 
 tie is broken by a moderate group.

In proportional systems one should distribute most of the seats directly to 
different parties without seeking for compromise candidates. I mean that also 
extreme parties should get their proportional share of the seats. Only in the 
allocaton of the very last seats (=last seats at national level) one can take 
the second preferences of the voters into account. The second preferences often 
point to compromise oriented candidates (by definition). The idea of favouring 
compromise candidates thus means taking the second preferences of the voters 
into account when allocating the very last seats.

Sometimes the voters may prefer giving the last seat to a compromise party 
(with only a small fraction of quota of first preference votes supporting this 
decision) to giving it to one of the main parties (that might have close to 0.5 
quota of first preference votes left supporting their candidate). The CPO 
approach is a good way to estimate which allocation of seats would get wide 
support among the electorate.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-18 Thread Juho Laatu
On 18.7.2013, at 14.15, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 the percentage of the votes the party received in the
 district that plays a role

This expression is actually ambigious. It could mean percentage of the votes of 
the district votes or percentage of the votes of the party votes.

 It could be an idea to implement an algorithm that tries to minimize
 partySeatsInDistrict / seatsInDistrict - partyPercentageInDistrict for
 all parties in all districts, but I believe this is a fairly difficult
 problem to solve, and the algorithm would likely be complex.

Algorithms that aim at ideal results may be complex. Simpler approximate 
algorithms may give almost identical results. Ideal algorithms have the benefit 
of being provably ideal in some sense. Simple algorithms have the benefit of 
being understandable to the voters (and of course also easy to use and verify).

 I do feel that distributing first seats to small parties first makes
 more sense, especially considering that certain small parties (such as
 Rødt) got a lot of support in districts with large cities, but nearly
 no support in other districts. They should be guaranteed to receive
 their won seats in the districts where they got most support.

I think it is ok to simply distribute first all seats of the smallest party, 
then all seats of the next smallest party etc. This is to avoid any weird 
results where some parties got seats in districts where they had relatively 
small support. Large parties do have strong candidates in every district, so 
leaving the rounding errors to them causes least harm.

 and I believe it's
 important that the method is so simple that most people can easily grasp
 it.

Yes, this is quite important. Although I note that also the philosophy of a 
complex algorithm that aims at ideal results (in some mathematical sense) may 
sometimes be easy to explain to the voters, although the actual algorithm might 
be very complex.

Most voters will not learn how to count the results anyway, but most of them 
like the system more if they at some level can trust that it is fair. This 
could mean exparts saying that it is good, media and friends saying that it is 
good, or simply nobody complaining that it has some bad features (like 
paradoxical results or a complex algorithm that may hide something).

 I think you may have misread the line you quoted.

Yes, that was just confusion and being too quick to push the send button.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-18 Thread Juho Laatu
On 18.7.2013, at 21.13, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 For each district and each party, calculate the quotient.
 Quotient = partyDistrictVotes / (2 * partyDistrictSeats + 1)

In the category of simple and straight forward algorithms, here is one approach.

- first use SL to determine at national level the number of seats that each 
party gets
- then allocate all seats of the smallest party so that it gets it seats in 
districts where it has full nationalQuota of votes, or largest fractional 
nationalQuota of votes
- continue with the next smallest party etc.
- nationalQuota = nationalVotes / nationalSeats
- after all seats of some district have been allocated, that district will be 
ignored when counting the rest of the results
- if some party doesn't have sufficient number of candidates in some district, 
restart the algorithm but reduce the number of seats of this party by one

I think the last row where a party loses a seat if it doesn't have sufficient 
number of candidates in all districts is fair since it is usually a mistake of 
the party if it does not nominate many enough candidates. (In the recent 
proposal in Finland they did some backtracking in such cases, but to me that 
seemed like adding unnecessary complexity to the method without getting any 
real benefits.)

(One could also adjust the use of nationalQuota in the districts so that the 
impact of different voting activity in each district is cancelled = 
districtQuota = districtVotes / districtSeats, or maybe even something more 
complex (and possibly more fair).)

 it's possible to keep the
 modified Sainte-Laguë (first divisor is 1.4 instead of 1) if one so
 desires

I note that in addition to being a threshold to small parties, divisor 1.4 can 
be also used to avoid strategic splitting of a small party to two even smaller 
parties to get two seats instead of only one. Generally I don't like thresholds 
at all since they make the results less proportional, but I can accept this one 
if the risk of startegies is real.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-18 Thread Juho Laatu
On 18.7.2013, at 23.36, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 (And now that I think about it: if it's desired, it should be possible to 
 make n-proportional apportionment methods for n2 -- e.g. a method that tries 
 to balance regional representation, national representation, and 
 representation of minorities according to their share of the population. The 
 greater n is, though, the less intuitive the results will be.)

I think any number of such (voted or static) proportionalities could be used. 
To me the biggest problem is that the rounding errors will increase, and as a 
result we will get also some strange results. That means some less intuitive 
results as you say, but maybe also more intuitive/fair in the sense that all 
groups will be fairly represented.

With voted and static proportionalities I refer to e.g. percentage of votes 
to women vs. percentage of women in the society.

In real life having political and regional proportionality may be enough for 
most countries, but I can see that in countries where the balance betheen 
different groups of the society is critical, also other proportionalities can 
be useful. This would allow e.g. different ethnic groups to work within one 
(ideological) party instead of being split in separate ethnic parties.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-17 Thread Juho Laatu
On 18.7.2013, at 3.11, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

   so the party gets
   the seat in the district with the highest:
   partyVotePercent / (2 * partyDistrictSeats + 1)

Will the size of the district impact the results? (i.e. 20% of the votes in a 
district that has 6 seats altogether should always give that party at least one 
seat, but if that district has only 3 seats, getting a seat would not be 
certain)

 Once a district received all its seats, it's of course excluded from
 receiving any more seats.

I guess the same applies to districts. Once all the seats of a district are 
gone, the remaining (party) seats will be allocated in other districts.

 I'd like to hear your thoughts on this method.

I like the simplicity of the method. And despite of its simplicity I expect the 
results to be pretty accurate.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] EM list problems?

2013-07-11 Thread Juho Laatu
This message (that was sent by me) was not properly delivered to me. Did 
someone else have similar probelms or was it only me?

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2013-July/032170.html

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 7.7.2013, at 23.49, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 But this raises the question of where the regional MPs should reside.

Two approaches (just thinking out loud). 1) One could have multiple layers from 
single member districts to counties etc. I recommend natural historical 
borderlines, not newly generated random borderlines, since it is important that 
people see the regions and their representatives as their own, representing 
some identifiable group with similar needs and targets. 2) Each party could 
have their own districting that spreads their representatives over all 
districts (smallest parties with one representative would have one district 
that covers the whole country).

I note that in order to keep good geographical balance, one would have to take 
into account where each representative comes from, and not let their 
distribution become too unbalanced (e.g. one bottom level district gets 
representatives at all levels and another one only at the bottom level). This 
seems to get quite complex.

 And yes, when one adjusts local outcomes to get greater national 
 proportionality, that means that someone who shouldn't have won on the 
 local level nevertheless does win. Hopefully the difference won't be as great 
 as to make the voters complain! Perhaps this is part of the point of leveling 
 seats: they start off not being owned by anyone, so giving them out to party 
 members may not seem as much a way of overruling the local result as if one 
 started with all seats filled and *then* adjusted.

Yes, it is important to give also a good impression of how the system works.

I think people are quite ok with the idea that there will be some randomness in 
the allocation of the last seats, since that is the case anyway in most 
methods, and since those candidates are anyway close to having vs. not having 
sufficient support. Better luck next time for those candidates that didn't make 
it this time.

I note also that one easy trick to get accureate proportionalities (national 
political, regional political and geographic) is to have representatives with 
different weight (different voting weight while in the parliament). But usually 
people do not fancy this kind of solutions.

I'll outline also one sketch of a simple non-backtracking algorithm, just for 
reference. 1) Allocate (number of) seats to parties at country level, 2) in 
each district, allocate those seats that are supported by full quota of party 
votes, 3) allocate the remaining seats to parties, starting from the smallest 
party, so that each party gets its seats in regions that still have unallocated 
seats left and where the party has highest support, 4) allocate the seats of 
each party in each district to their candidates. Point 3 is the critical one. 
The idea is simply that small parties better be handled first since large 
parties have probably good candidates with reasonable amout of support in each 
district, and they can therefore be allocated last (without causing strange 
results). The result may not be ideal, but probably good enough, and acceptable 
since the algorithm is simple and straight forward.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-07 Thread Juho Laatu
On 7.7.2013, at 16.16, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 On Fri, Jul 05, 2013 at 11:37:55PM +0200, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 The argument then
 is that if you add in lots of very small parties, any of them might
 become a kingmaker and so get extremely disproportional amounts of
 power.
 
 While I see the point, I think this may be a bit too simplified. Where
 as small parties in Norway possibly do have more influence than their
 size dictates, they arguably do not have the same power as the larger
 parties.

Let's say we have two left wing parties and one right wing party.
46% L1
5% L2
49% R

Should we redulce the number of seats of L2 so that it would not get too much 
power. By doing so we would change the left wing majority to a right wing 
majority. Small parties can be needed to build up majorty coalition 
governments. I think it is fair to give them their proportional number of 
seats. At least in Finland small parties have much smaller role in the 
coalition governments than the largest parties have. It is also typical that 
large parties collect so many small parties in the govenment that even if one 
of them would leave the government, the government would still have majority. 
This guarantees that no single small party can blackmail the government. The 
small parties need to consider also what would happen at the next time if they 
try to play bigger role in the government that their size is.

 Alternatively, instead of running Sainte-Laguë in each county, you could
 run SL on the national result (distributing all 169 seats), something
 which would produce a representation percentage very close to the actual
 result, and then distribute the seats to the parties in the different
 counties (keeping the same amount of seats in each county).

I think this makes sense if you do not like the leveling seat style of building 
proportionality at national level. The last seats will be distributed pretty 
much in the same way anyway, but in this approach all seats are in principle 
seen as equal. The algorithm may either aim at some ideal allocation, or be a 
practical algorithm that just finds a good enough result.

If we want full proportinality, then proportionality should thus be counted at 
national level. Another reason why national level votes should be used to count 
the number of seats for each party is that one should guarantee that it makes 
sense to vote for the small paries also in the smallest counties. If there is 
no such prcedure or leveling seats or some other national level leveling 
algorithms in place, it would not make sense to vote for small parties in the 
small counties. this would reduce the support of the smallest parties already 
before the votes are counted.

This kind of balancing mechanisms will lead to electing a representative of the 
small party at least in some county, or maybe in this voter's own county, even 
if the number of votes would not be sufficient to win any of the seats, if 
seats would be allocated independently in each county.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-05 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.7.2013, at 21.39, Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 that we're using 1.4 as the first divisor in Sainte-Laguë
 is what's making it difficult for smaller parties to get a foothold

I can see the followig factors that influence the ability of the smallest 
parties to get seats:
- constituencies / counties with small number of seats (problematic to parties 
below 4% national support)
- thresholds are bad to the small parties
- Sainte-Laguë is very fair to the small parties
- 1.4 vs. 1 as the first divisor (divisor 1 for the leveling seats helps small 
parties above 4%)
- vote to a party can be lost if the vote can not be inherited by the second 
best party (hurts large parties as well, but may be psychologically more 
difficult to the small party voters)

 I favour systems that are so simple that regular voters can easily 
 understand how they work.
 
 Even though I'm a fan of Ranked Pairs  Condorcet methods, I too share
 this sentiment.

One can see also ranked methods also as simple methods in the sense that voters 
can easily understand what ranking means. And if there is also no need to 
consider and plan strategies but to just rank some candidates sincerely, then 
we could say that voting is easy for the voters. We would thus not require them 
to be able to tell how the algorithm works internally, but just to have a good 
understanding on how to vote, and that the method seems to be a fair.

 Another argument could be that voters probably would be
 wary of drastically changing the existing voting system.
 In the Norwegian voting system, changing it by removing election
 threshold, increase seats in each county by 1 and remove leveling seats,
 and possibly reduce the first Sainte-Laguë divisor slightly, say 1.3,
 while making it possible for voters to rank parties, could greatly
 help prevent the fear of wasting ones vote. Using the counting method
 mentioned earlier (exclude party with fewest votes, rerun Sainte-Laguë
 until all remaining parties got at least 1 seat), it's arguably easier
 to explain than the current one with the leveling seat algorithm.

Just be careful that, when getting rid of the leveling seats, you don't end up 
in a situation where all the counties would elect their representatives 
independently of each others. Because of the small number of seats per county, 
that would effectively limit the chances of small parties to get seats in the 
small counties.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
Some late comments follow.

Vidar Wahlberg wrote:

 The short answer to why not vote directly for persons? would be that
 in Norway there's more focus on the goals of a party rather than the
 goal of its politicians, and some may argue that the extra abstraction
 layer is a good thing, as well as I'd like an alternative that won't be
 completely alien to the common people. I'm hoping that any discussion
 that may arise won't focus on this aspect, though.

Open lists would be one easy modification, but I note that you prefer ranked 
ballots, so let's skip open lists. Ranked ballots can also provide better party 
internal proportionality (between different sections of the party or between 
different parts of the districts) than basic open lists.

 I don't have any proof that it will degenerate into a populist
 competition, but I do see the potential that it will, when you vote
 directly for a person rather than a party.


In principle ability to vote for persons helps populist candidates. My best 
understanding is that in Finland, that uses open lists, well known candidates 
(from sports, TV etc.) probably have slightly better chances to win a seat when 
compared to countries using closed lists, but that difference is not big. Also 
closed lists can be populated with well known figures to get populist votes 
(in addition to nominating experienced politicians).

Also campaining could in principle be more populist in open lists, but I don't 
see big difference here either. In FInland the level of populism differs more 
between parties than between the candidates of a single party.

All in all, I believe the risk of excessive populism is not big in ranked 
methods either.

 The leveling seat algorithm is... peculiar.

You said that you don't like methods that lead towards a two/three party 
system. In other words the method should allow also small parties to survive. I 
note that typically small districts are one key reason why small parties do not 
get any seats. If you e.g. have a district with 3 seats, it is obvious that 
only two/three largest parties can win there. The leveling seats (that are 
allocated based on support at national level) could fix that problem, but I 
understood that n Norway they don't apply to the smallest parties. Therefore 
the 5% threshold probably effectively reduces the chances of the smallest 
parties to get their proportional share (at national level) of the seats. It 
does not make sense to the voters to vote for parties that most likely will not 
get any seats in their district anyway.

I don't know what the situation in Norway actually is today. My comments here 
are thus just general comments on how multi-winner election methods usually 
work.

 I'd like to get rid of both leveling seats and
 election threshold.

If you want to achieve exact proportionality (also for small parties) I think 
it is important that proportionality will be counted at national level. Also in 
ranked methods it is not enough if each district does its best alone since the 
small number of seats per district will distort proportionality at national 
level. From this point of view the leveing seats (or any construction that aims 
at providing proportionality at national level) is good, and thresholds are bad.

- - -

I note that you can achieve national level proportionality in list based 
methods also without leveling seats. In Finland there was a proposal that was 
alrady once accepted by the parliament but then cancelled by the current 
government. This proposal counted the proportionality first at national level, 
and then allocated a predetermined number of seats to each district so that at 
the same time also the calculated national proportionality numbers were met. 
This means that the last seats in some districts were slightly forced to 
correct parties, to meeth the national proportionality target. All methods that 
try to reach multiple targets, like political proportionality and geographic 
proportionality at the same time will have some rounding errors. In the 
Finnish proposal those rounding errors were thus solved by slight distortion in 
who and which party wins the last seat in each district, instead of using e.g. 
leveling seats to capture the rounding errors.

- - -

You had interest in guaranteeing that the lost votes of small parties will go 
to parties that are similar-minded. If one counts exact proportionality at 
national level the number of lost votes will be quite small. That alone might 
be enough for some needs. The traditional way of voting for one party or one 
candidate only could thus be enough, and there would not be need to have ranked 
votes for this reason. (Ranked votes could be there for other reasons, like to 
support party internal proportionality.)

Ranked methods may also be quite heavy for the voter if there anre tens of 
candidates to rank. For the needs of Finland I have been interested in methods 
that would combine lists and ranked votes in another way. 

Re: [EM] Quotaless STV-PR suggestion

2013-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.7.2013, at 6.57, Chris Benham wrote:

 STV meets Later-no-Harm because lower preferences only count after the
 the fate (elected or definitely eliminated) of more preferred candidates has
 been set.
  
 My suggestion doesn't because by not truncating a voter could have their
 ballot count towards the election of a non-favourite in an early round (and
 a candidate that might have won anyway), and so be reduced in weight and
 then not be heavy enough to elect the voter's favourite in a later round
 (when it would have been if the voter had truncated).


It seems that your suggestion reduces the weight of a vote when it contributes 
to electing someone at the first time. Another approach would be to try to 
reduce the weight of a vote based on the most preferred candidate that is about 
to be elected. Can you elaborate why you prefer to do it this way (to help me 
to understand why your suggestion is what it is).

Another question. How about using Condorcet to elect the winner at each round 
instead of doing it in IRV style (top-ranked on the highest number of 
ballots)?

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.7.2013, at 13.55, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 07/04/2013 08:55 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 
 In principle ability to vote for persons helps populist candidates.
 My best understanding is that in Finland, that uses open lists, well
 known candidates (from sports, TV etc.) probably have slightly better
 chances to win a seat when compared to countries using closed lists,
 but that difference is not big. Also closed lists can be populated
 with well known figures to get populist votes (in addition to
 nominating experienced politicians).
 
 Also campaining could in principle be more populist in open lists,
 but I don't see big difference here either. In FInland the level of
 populism differs more between parties than between the candidates of
 a single party.
 
 All in all, I believe the risk of excessive populism is not big in
 ranked methods either.
 
 Both closed list and open (and ranked) methods have their failure modes. 
 Closed list fails when the party leadership becomes unaccountable and 
 insulates itself, and then the voter is forced to either vote my way or the 
 highway - i.e. to accept the leadership's ranking or to not vote for the 
 party. Person-based methods fail when it produces an incentive to be 
 excessively populist.
 
 In a way, that's a mirror of the general balancing act of democracy. If it is 
 too representative as opposed to direct, then the powerholders might just 
 run away with the power and mockingly say to the voters that they have no 
 choice but to vote for one of the powerholders. If it's too direct, then it 
 can amplify too much and oscillate around various policies if not 
 degenerating entirely to populism.
 
 I suspect that the solution to this particular problem lies not in getting 
 the balance right, but somehow setting up the right feedback system so that 
 public discussion and opinion convergence can move beyond populism. That 
 said, I think I favor ranked multiwinner methods if I have to choose: the 
 populist objection seems to be employed to exaggerate the negative results of 
 giving the people more choice.

Your expression representative vs. direct captures the small difference 
between multi-winner methods that allow parties vs. voters to decide which 
candidates of each party will be elected. Most democracies are representative 
democracies, so there will be some level of representative isolation between 
voters and decision making. One just has to decide how much direct power to 
give to the voters, and how much one expects them to be capable of making 
decisions themselves.

In closed lists it is also important that the party structure can change. If 
the system is parameterized so that the old parties will stay in power forever, 
we may be in trouble. But if the system allows parties to grow, emerge and 
diminish depending on what kind of candidates each party puts on the list, then 
we are ok.

 
 The leveling seat algorithm is... peculiar.
 
 You said that you don't like methods that lead towards a two/three
 party system. In other words the method should allow also small
 parties to survive. I note that typically small districts are one key
 reason why small parties do not get any seats. If you e.g. have a
 district with 3 seats, it is obvious that only two/three largest
 parties can win there. The leveling seats (that are allocated based
 on support at national level) could fix that problem, but I
 understood that n Norway they don't apply to the smallest parties.
 Therefore the 5% threshold probably effectively reduces the chances
 of the smallest parties to get their proportional share (at national
 level) of the seats. It does not make sense to the voters to vote for
 parties that most likely will not get any seats in their district
 anyway.
 
 I don't know what the situation in Norway actually is today. My
 comments here are thus just general comments on how multi-winner
 election methods usually work.
 
 The Norwegian threshold is at 4%. If parties get sufficient local support, 
 they still get seats; the 4% only regards leveling seats.
 
 As a concrete example, in the 2009 parliamentary election, the Liberal Party 
 (Venstre) achieved a support result of 3.9%, just below the threshold of 
 4%. In the previous election, their support reached 5.9%. As a consequence of 
 going below the threshold, the party lost 8 of its 10 MPs.

The Norwegian system has thus two levels that determine how many seats the 
smallest parties will get. Here is a list of constituencies of the 
parliamentary election (taken from Wikipedia).

County Seats
Østfold 9
Akershus 16
Oslo 17
Hedmark 8
Oppland 7
Buskerud 9
Vestfold 7
Telemark 6
Aust-Agder 4
Vest-Agder 6
Rogaland 13
Hordaland 15
Sogn og Fjordane 5
Møre og Romsdal 9
Sør-Trøndelag 10
Nord-Trøndelag 6
Nordland 10
Troms 7
Finnmark 5
Total 169

If a voter expects some party not to reach the 4% threshold, then voting for 
such party makes sense only in the largest districts, e.g. in Oslo that has 17 
seats

Re: [EM] Before Voting Methods and Criteria: Outcome Design Goals (long)

2013-07-02 Thread Juho Laatu
On 30.6.2013, at 23.19, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 I’ve been coming at understanding better the options and choices, merits and 
 flaws of various approaches to holding votes – mostly with the kind (and 
 sometimes not-so-kind) help of the people on this list.
  
 However, a (I assume) basic thought occurred to me, which may be so obvious 
 no one need ever discuss it, but I want to double check my thinking on some 
 of this.
  
 The rest of this post will NOT be concerned with any one particular voting 
 method or criteria.  Instead I will be comparing different scenarios of voter 
 preference with thoughts about who “should” win. If I am not making sense 
 quite yet, come along and hopefully it will make more sense in practice. If 
 not, you can ask me questions or delete the post.
  
 Let’s assume that we have a magical gift – a super power, if you will.  We 
 can know exactly what each voter thinks about each candidate.  Now, because 
 this comes from magic, it cannot unfortunately be used as a part of the 
 election process, but it will be useful for our examination of attitudes of 
 the voters.
  
 So as we turn our power on a random voter, we can pick (on a scale of 0 to 
 100) how they feel about each candidate.  A 0, in this case, indicates that 
 the voter is absolutely against the candidate winning the election, and will 
 vote however he must to stop that from happening, whereas a 100 indicates the 
 reverse: that the voter is absolutely for this candidate’s victory, and will 
 give it everything he can at the ballot box. 50 indicates a sort of “meh” 
 reaction – doesn’t hate them, doesn’t love them – or possibly the voter has 
 some aspects of the candidate he really likes, but some other aspects that he 
 is less than thrilled with.
  
 So, using this power, we can know absolutely on a scale of 0 to 100 what each 
 voter thinks of each candidate. Using that knowledge, we ought to be able to 
 say who “should” win – which I will return to in just a moment.
  
 First, each candidate’s support by the voters can be noted on a graph, with 
 the X axis denoting the scale of 0-100 Favorability, and the Y axis denoting 
 the percentage of voters who hold that exact opinion.
  
 So, for example, on a graph like this, you might find that 12% rate a certain 
 candidate at 0F – they *hate* this guy.  Another 14% may rate this candidate 
 at 100F – these are his loyal base. Most people fall somewhere in between.
  
 To keep things simple, I’m going to talk about candidates as if their voters 
 clump at certain points, instead of spreading more fuzzily. I think the core 
 questions become no less valid and no less worth thought.
  
 I am going to posit a series of two candidate comparisons, and ask who 
 “should” win. The point here is to ignore the methods for a bit, and just see 
 what our gut says, given the absolutely magically accurate information we 
 have about the voter’s preferences.

An exact definition of which candidate is best can be used also as a definition 
of the method (assuming that the preferences can be expressed on the ballot and 
the expressed opinions are sincere enough). I mean that you can also proceed by 
defining the ideal outcome first and then declaring that exact definition to be 
the algorithm, instead of defining an algorithm first and then checking what 
kind of candidates that algorithm will elect.

  
 To start with, let’s imagine one candidate with 51% of the voters giving him 
 an 80F, and 49% giving him a 0F. Another candidate has a 63% of the voters 
 giving an 80F (with the remaining 37% giving 0F.) Which candidate ought to 
 win?
  
 Unless I miss something, this one is an easy one. Both candidates have the 
 same level of favorability but one has greater breadth than the other. It 
 seems self-evident to say that when the favorability is identical, but the 
 breadth is not, greater breadth should win.
  
 Likewise, if instead our election has one fellow with 51% @ 80F and another 
 at 51% @ 100F, the second ought to win, since he has the same breadth, but 
 higher favorability, right?
  
 (Note, if I say that a candidate has 51% @ 80F, not only does that mean 51% 
 of the voters find him at an 80 Favorability, but that all other voters 
 omitted (the 49%) find him at 0F.  Additionally please note that these are 
 NOT elections or election methods, just questions about who we feel “should” 
 win given different circumstances of voter sentiment.)
  
 So, when one candidate has equal or better breadth and/or favorability, it 
 makes sense to our sense of fairness that they ought to win.  Now let’s 
 examine the more complex and fun situation of unequal aspects – with one 
 candidate with a better breadth, but his competitor with a better 
 favorability.
  
 This time, we have a candidate named Wilson who manages to get 51% @ 100F. 
 His competitor Franklin gets 80% @ 90F.
  
 In this circumstance, I think a lot of us would prefer that Franklin win. 
 Sure, 51% of the 

Re: [EM] Discourse

2013-07-02 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.7.2013, at 23.12, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 Thanks for everyone's candor and feedback. I can certainly appreciate how
 annoying it is to deal with someone like myself that 1) is often asking
 questions that everyone else had heard many times before and knows the
 answer by heart, and 2) someone who may not be able to understand the
 explanations when they are given.
 
 I am running into #2 a lot, so much that I am wondering if this list is
 really mostly for people who are already trained, steeped, and comfortable
 with concepts like utlity and Batesian regret, with high level math and set
 theory, and so on.

Some people are very kowledgeable here, some less. That's no problem as long as 
the discussions are good. There are many kind of people on the EM list. Some 
have academic interests in this area, some are active on practical reforms, 
some promote their own favourite methods and criteria, some are just interested 
in following the discussions. The language on this list is sometimes polite, 
sometimes not. Your mails have certainly been better than many others. Welcome 
to the list. It is no problem if you don't know all the used terminology yet. 
Because of the multitude of topics and writers of this list, people are already 
used to reading and answering those mails that they are interested of and skip 
the rest. Despite of all the quarreling and messy posts, I think the EM list is 
a well working mailing list that has also lots of good content for various 
needs. Hopefully for you too.

Juho



 
 It may simply require more time and effort than I have to give to understand
 the answers to these questions, I certainly do not have the option presently
 to take courses in these advanced subjects. I was hoping there would be a
 more down-to-earth way to get this stuff, but whether there's no way to
 dumb this stuff down, or whether it's just not something that people here
 are interested in, either way I can appreciate it.
 
 Finally, while I was surprised that erudition didn't eliminate the
 churlishness, my best approach to that fact is probably to get a thicker
 skin. I'm not promising to be a punching bag, mind you, but I can probably
 be a little less sensitive and just assume that these groups are more
 pugnacious than I had imagined.
 
 Thanks everyone. I'm going to keep my subscription to these groups for now
 (if I may), and I will try to be mindful of all of the above if and when I
 continue interacting with them.
 
 -Benn Grant
 eFix Computer Consulting
 b...@4efix.com
 603.283.6601
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] irv and the politics of electoral reform.

2013-06-27 Thread Juho Laatu
On 26.6.2013, at 22.48, David L Wetzell wrote:

 This is in response to an earlier post by Juho where he speculates that IRV 
 is the preferred reform by politicians in the two major parties who want to 
 accommodate change that does the least harm to the status quo.  I think it's 
 useful to consider the ideas of the politics of electoral reform by Alan 
 Renwick, as reviewed by Patrick Dunleavy.  Renwick breaks electoral reforms 
 into two categories, ‘majority elite imposition and elite-mass 
 interactions.  The first is a faux reform pushed by the elites to increase 
 their control.  The latter is a reform pushed by the masses on the elites 
 whereby both sides accommodate each other some to give way to a new political 
 equilibrium with a different system for the circulation of the elites.  

This sounds like a tug of war between elite and masses. Makes sense.

(Maybe the elite wins the tug of war when it gets rid of democracy, and the 
masses win when they get rid of the elite. The democratic ideal seems to be to 
seek a balance where the rope is loose and the power is as close to the masses 
as they can steer the system.)

 
 I think the reform in the US that wins the majority elite imposition prize 
 is top two primary.  It certainly improves on fptp the least of all 
 possible reforms and removes a lot of important voices in the final round.  

Yes, top two primary would be a simpler modification. Its dynamics differ 
somewhat from the dynamics of IRV. I'm not sure which one would defend status 
quo better in a typical two-party environment.

 
 I see IRV as an elite mass interaction.  It doesn't end the tendency to a 
 two-party dominated system, but it does change the nature of that two-party 
 dominated system so that both must hew more to the center and new ideas or 
 frames for wedge-issues can be brought up by outsiders.  

In traditional two-party countries this kind of electoral reforms may have far 
reaching influences. One should be ready to discuss also possible changes in 
other areas of the political system that is typically built around the basic 
idea of having two alternating parties in power, or alternating presidents / 
governments from one of the two leading parties. Or maybe the target is just to 
open up the possibility of electing sometimes independents or representatives 
of small parties, just to remind the big parties that they must listen to the 
voters and not just keep running their own (maybe hidden) agenda and rely on 
winning 50% of the elections forever anyway. That would be a two-party system 
with reminders. I guess this is close to what you meant.

Transition from FPTP towards IRV looks like a typical elite mass interaction 
since that modification increases the power of the masses, and works against 
the status quo that the elite is expected to maintain.

 
 I also see that FairVote's proposed upgrade of top two primary to that a 
 top four primary is essentially trying to coopt the momentum such a false 
 reform has gotten for disingenuous reasons so that it'd actually be useful.  
 It also solves some of the problems with IRV by limiting the number of 
 candidates in  the final election to four.  There are only 41 ways to rank up 
 to 3 of four candidates and so it'd be feasible to sort ballots into these 
 forty-one categories at the precinct level.  
 
 This fits with my proposal to rally around IRV and then if or when IRV proves 
 dysfunctional, using IRV to proffer alts to IRV.  If we make IRV+ American 
 forms of PR in more local elections the progressive-centrist consensus for 
 reform then it'll pave the way for further experiements down the road that'll 
 give some of the ideas this list focuses a lot on more opportunities.

In politics one must be prepared to make lots of compromises. That means that 
if a reform will be made, it will probably be very different from the first 
(mathematically clean) proposals, and therefore maybe not very pretty. This 
means that one should have a clear understanding on what direction one wants to 
take, and accept all reasonable steps in that direction.

Juho


 
 dlw
 
 
 dlw
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Is it professional?

2013-06-26 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.6.2013, at 12.13, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 06/25/2013 09:17 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 25.6.2013, at 1.25, Benjamin Grant wrote:
 
 On Mon, Jun 24, 2013 at 6:19 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
 km_el...@lavabit.com mailto:km_el...@lavabit.com wrote:
 
Scenario 1: Voters don't rank now, but will rank when they see
it's worth it. Here IRV will eventually crash but BTR-IRV is,
well, better.
 
Scenario 2: Voters rank, contrary to your assumptions (but
suggested by international evidence). Again, BTR-IRV does better.
 
Scenario 3: Voters don't rank and never will. BTR-IRV is here no
worse than IRV.
 
Under what scenario does BTR-IRV *lose* against ordinary IRV?
 
 
 I am quite interested in the answer to this as well, as I imagine that
 whatever the answer is is a defining advantage, should any exist.
 
 One can see this problem from two quite different points of view.
 
 One approach is that BTR-IRV is simply an improved version of IRV that
 it avoids some of the key problems of IRV. Therefore it could be
 straight forward to get also BTR-IRV accepted if the society accepts IRV.
 
 Another approach is to have a more political power oriented viewpoint.
 IRV tends to favour major parties. If the incumbent strong parties (that
 do have a lot to say on what route the politics take) may well count
 their chances in each proposed method. This might lead to favouring
 methods like IRV that still allow the largest parties to take a lion's
 share of the victories.
 
 Right. I've heard this argument from others: that IRV, favoring the large 
 parties, will get greater support from them. But the problem with that 
 argument is that on the face of it, it seems to apply just as well to 
 Plurality.

The rule may apply to all political parties with ability and interest to plot 
and plan and be power hungry or be afraid that other parties are power hungry. 
That is thus a considerable temptation to all parties in all competitive 
political systems.

Some political forces might think that if reform is imminent, then one should 
pick a method that causes least harm. Adoption of IRV (replacing plurality) 
might lead to further reforms and therefore this path is risky to the incumbent 
major parties, but other methods might be even more dangerous to them. In that 
situation IRV may be the least threatening one of the proposed changes.

From this point of view a good reform might be one that will cause so many 
problems that it wll be soon cancelled. I note that in Burlington the reform 
was cancelled. The reasons behind the cancellation are probably quite complex, 
but in real life political situations also fake reforms and watered down 
reforms are quite common.

My theory thus is that in all organizations (not just in politics) people tend 
to maintain and increase their own power and position. In this situation, and 
if someone understands the dynamics of the election methods well enough, also 
reforms may proceed on such paths that are most useful and least harmful to the 
ones that are in power right now. For example in the USA Plurality (and the 
whole political system around it) may thus be the most popular approach to the 
incumbents. IRV might be one of the least harmful reforms, and at least less 
harmful than e.g. Condorcet.

 The ones who already have power, have power to some degree because of the 
 imbalances in the power allocation system.

Yes. I think in most systems also the initiatives and alternative proposals 
come from the ones that already have power. Therefore already the concrete 
proposals are usually filtered by them in some suitable way.

 Therefore, they'll be disinclined to switch the power allocation system or 
 parts of it, for something that will distribute power away from them. Or to 
 be more direct: the people who are in power because of Plurality would see no 
 need to advocate IRV unless they would also be in power under IRV -- and if 
 they already have power, why take the chance?

Yes. In all political systems those who were elected in the previous election 
tend to dislike electon method reforms since it was the old method that elected 
them. In this situation any changes in the method carry a risk of not electing 
the same candidates next time.

On the other hand it is the job of the politicians to make changes in the 
society and thereby market themselves as active politicians. Sometimes the 
discussion goes also on the (unwanted) election method reform track, and 
sometimes that even leads to something. In that situation some watered down 
reform (or a reform that improves the chances of the politician / party in 
power) is the favourite one.

 
 I think the argument would be better if adapted to a sort of internal 
 discontent scenario. For simplicity's sake, say you have a 1984-like 
 structure with three classes:
 
 - The upper class wants to stay in power,
 - The middle class wants to switch places with the upper class,
 - The lower class

Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-26 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.6.2013, at 11.57, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 06/25/2013 09:00 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 25.6.2013, at 1.06, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 
 Remember that criterion compliances are absolute. So a method may
 fail a criterion yet be perfectly acceptable in real elections.
 
 I just want to support this viewpoint. It is not essential how many
 criteria a mehod violates. It is more important how bad those
 violations are, i.e. if the method likely have serious problems or
 not. The best method might well be a method that violates multiple
 criteria, but manages to spread the  (unavoidable) problems evenly so
 that all of them stay insignificant.
 
 In a sense, it's like certain kinds of mathematical tests. There are 
 primality tests that return either this number is definitely a prime or 
 this number might be prime or might be composite. If you get the former 
 result, you know you're dealing with a prime, but if you get the second, you 
 don't know whether you're dealing with a prime or a composite number.
 
 Criterion compliances are similar. If something passes IIA, you don't have to 
 worry about candidates being added or removed as long as the voters don't 
 alter their votes when the candidates are being added/removed. Whatever the 
 dynamics might be on the nomination side, IIA secures the method. On the 
 other hand, if something fails IIA, then you have the might be scenario. 
 The method might fail IIA in blatant ways, or it might fail it where it 
 doesn't really matter. You don't know.

Yes. Often you also know that although some method violates some criterion in 
practice it will (almost or completely certailnly) not cause any problems. We 
may also have a balance of benefits and problems where the benefits the 
problems so that e.g. trying some theoretically possible stratgy simply does 
not makes sense (= is more likely to cause damage than benefits). In this case 
there is no compliance but there is a strong understanding that there will be 
no problems. In the EM list discussions people often do not keep the difference 
of theoretical vulnerabilities and practical vulnerabilitis (in real life 
elections, maybe in some given political environment) clear enough.

 
 In my case, I do like the certainty that criterion compliance provides, but 
 sometimes, it just isn't available.
 
 There is, though, one situation where criterion compliances go both ways. The 
 method might produce a result that goes so completely against common sense 
 that opponents can use it to argue against the method, even if that result 
 itself only would appear very rarely. Perception does matter; and it's 
 reasonable that it does, because sometimes the bizarre failure is symptomatic 
 of a method that behaves strangely under pressure in general. That is not 
 true all the time, though.
 

It is good to handle both concerns. I like to discuss first about the 
properties of each method at abstract / technical / theoretical level, and then 
give also some consideration to how such methods would fit and could be 
marketed in some given political environments.

What I don't like is method and criteria names that have been chosen to be as 
good for positive or negative marketing as possible. In the theoretical 
discussions the ugly and pretty names should have no meaning (except to idetify 
a criterion or method).

Condorcet methods are an interesting example since in many cases their 
violations deal with situations where opinions are cyclical. In real elections 
sincere top level cycles are not very common, and artificially generated cycles 
(as a result of successfully implemented strategies) may also be difficult to 
generate and may easily lead to unwanted results from the strategists' point of 
view. The problem thus is that marginal violations (that voters actually need 
not worry about at all) will be marketed as major flaws that make it impossible 
to use the method in all real elections. Failing to meet FBC does not mean that 
voters are expected to betray or should always seriously consider betraying 
their favourite. Strategy never betray your favourite or always vote 
sincerely may lead to better results and may well be the best strategy for the 
voters (of all opinion groups) to follow.

One can compare the vulnerabilities of the election methods also to security 
systems. In that area one often says that a system is as strong as its weakest 
link. Also in election methods one could optimize the system based on how 
strong the weakest link is. That means (roughly) that we need not worry how 
many flaws the stronger links have as long as those links are still stronger 
than the weakest link (and if weakening a strong link allows us to make a weak 
link stronger).

In summary, I want to clearly separate discussion on the theoretical properties 
of the methods, on the practical properties of the methods (in real life 
elections), and on the marketability of the methods (to the politicians, media

Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-26 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.6.2013, at 18.00, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 On Tue, Jun 25, 2013 at 2:53 AM, Juho Laatu juho.la...@gmail.com wrote:
 On 24.6.2013, at 16.06, Benjamin Grant wrote:
 
 So, as far as *I* can see, this converts Score Voting into Approval voting.  
 The only people who would bother to vote sincerely are:
 1)  Those who truly prefer Gore highest and Bush lowest (or vice versa), 
 because there’s no strategic downside.
 
 
 You seem to assume that voters with opinion 'Gore:75, Nader: 90, Bush: 10’ 
 are not strategic when they vote 'Gore:75, Nader: 100, Bush: 0’. There are 
 thus two possible levels of sincereness, either people who think that all 
 candidates are about equally good should vote that way, or if they should 
 exaggerate and tell that the worst one of them is worth 0 points and the best 
 one is worth 100 points.
 
 But in the instance where someone's highest priority is to stop Bush, and a 
 distant second level priority is to see Nader elected over Gore, it seems 
 unavoidable to admit that if they vote 'Gore:75, Nader: 100, Bush: 0’ they 
 will be harming their first priority by withholding support from Gore. Isn't 
 this correct?

Yes. Those voters already have some strategic thoughts like I must maximize 
the power of my vote. If they sincerely feel strongly that way (Bush is worth 
0 points etc.), this can be classified as sincere voting. But if they think 
that all politicians are actually quite equal, maybe they should vote sincerely 
'Gore:75, Nader: 80, Bush: 70’.

 So then that is a non-strategic vote in comparison to 100/whatever/0, yes?

I guess whether we call some vote strategic or not depends also on what the 
voters were requested to do. If they were requested to evaluate candidates so 
that 0 points means worst imaginable and 100 points means perfect, then 0 
points should be reserved for Hitler and Stalin and similar. Bush is certainly 
above that level for most voters. But if they were asked to spred the 
candidates on a scale from 0 to 100, then voters should use also numbers 0 and 
100. (The latter approach of course has problems like someone nominating a 
Republican candidate that is much worse than Bush and thereby lifts Bush to at 
least 25 points in all ballots.)

 
 That's what makes strategic voting different from sincere voting, isn't it: 
 that strategic voting has a greater chance of creating a more preferred 
 outcome?

The voters can either try to influence the outcome of the election as much in 
their own favour as possible, or they can simply indicate their opininion 
sincerely, as requested by the election organizers. In competitive elections 
(e.g. political elections) voters tend to adopt the first approach. I some more 
peaceful elections and polls they may adopt the second approach.

 So long as the strategic vote and the sincere vote are not the same, a 
 sincere vote is a vote against your preferences.

If the election is not competitive, then your sincere votes is also ideal for 
you, even if you caould change the result to better from your point of view by 
falsifying your preferences. A typical example situation could be e.g. a vote 
within a family on what food to make today. In such environments the voters 
typically want to seek a balanced result rather than get their own preferences 
implemented every day by using some strategic tricks. Political elections are 
of course usually more competitive.

 That is why it seems so important to me to favor system where those two kinds 
 of voting coincide as often as possible, right?

Yes. It is one of the key targets to find an election method that would 
sufficiently discourage strategic voting. In some methods like Approval people 
(on the EM list) usually expect voters not to vote sincerely (= approve those 
that you approve) but to cast their best strategic vote, which typically 
includes approving some of the frontrunners and not approving some of the 
frontrunners. From this point of view there are at least two categories of 
practical methods 1) methods where people are expected to express their sincere 
opinions on the ballot and 2) methods where all voters are expected to follow 
some strategy that is available to all and that least to balanced results 
despite of all being strategic. In both cases we want to avoid situations where 
some voters can cast a stronger strategic vote than others, and where strategic 
voting would somehow make the end result bad, or make the election more random, 
or allow the plotters to win, or make it difficult for the regular voters to 
vote.

  
 It’s days like these that I feel that there *is* no way to elect people that 
 is fair and right. L
 All methods have some problems. But the problems are not always so bad that 
 they would invalidate the method. I'd propose to study also the Condorcet 
 compliant methods. I note that they already popped up in the later 
 discussions and you more or less already promised to study them.
 
 When compared to Range style

Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-26 Thread Juho Laatu
On 26.6.2013, at 13.31, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 06/26/2013 11:24 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 
 On 25.6.2013, at 18.07, Benjamin Grant wrote:
 
 Now there are some criteria that aren't important to me at all, that I
 do not value what the try to protect - and those I factor out.
 
 I think I don't have any criteria that I'd absolutely require.
 
 How about unanimity? :-)

Ok, that comes close. However, an otherwise excellent method with 1/100 
random probability of not meeting unaminity, giving victory to some almost 
equally good candidate, would maybe be a stupid method, but still maybe 
acceptable. I.e. I could accept it if other alternatives are worse. :-)

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-25 Thread Juho Laatu
On 24.6.2013, at 16.06, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 So, as far as *I* can see, this converts Score Voting into Approval voting.  
 The only people who would bother to vote sincerely are:
 1)  Those who truly prefer Gore highest and Bush lowest (or vice versa), 
 because there’s no strategic downside.


You seem to assume that voters with opinion 'Gore:75, Nader: 90, Bush: 10’ are 
not strategic when they vote 'Gore:75, Nader: 100, Bush: 0’. There are thus two 
possible levels of sincereness, either people who think that all candidates are 
about equally good should vote that way, or if they should exaggerate and tell 
that the worst one of them is worth 0 points and the best one is worth 100 
points.

 Am I substantially wrong about any of this?

I think you are generally very right about this.

 It’s days like these that I feel that there *is* no way to elect people that 
 is fair and right. L

All methods have some problems. But the problems are not always so bad that 
they would invalidate the method. I'd propose to study also the Condorcet 
compliant methods. I note that they already popped up in the later discussions 
and you more or less already promised to study them.

When compared to Range style utility measuring style Condorcet methods take 
another approach by allowing majorities to decide. With sincere (Range) 
preferences 55: A=100 B=90, 45: B=100 A=0 majority based methods allow A to 
win. Althoug B has clearly higher sum of utiliy, it is also a fact that if one 
would elect B, B would be opposed by 55% majority. A would be supported by 55% 
majority. Not a pretty sight to watch, but that's how majority oriented systems 
are suposed to work. Maybe the majority philosophy is that you will get a ruler 
that can rule (and there is no mutiny), instead of getting a ruler whose 
proposals would be voted against every time by 55% majority in the parliament 
or in public elections.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-25 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.6.2013, at 1.06, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Remember that criterion compliances are absolute. So a method may fail a 
 criterion yet be perfectly acceptable in real elections.

I just want to support this viewpoint. It is not essential how many criteria a 
mehod violates. It is more important how bad those violations are, i.e. if the 
method likely have serious problems or not. The best method might well be a 
method that violates multiple criteria, but manages to spread the  
(unavoidable) problems evenly so that all of them stay insignificant.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Is it professional?

2013-06-25 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.6.2013, at 1.25, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 On Mon, Jun 24, 2013 at 6:19 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm 
 km_el...@lavabit.com wrote:
 Scenario 1: Voters don't rank now, but will rank when they see it's worth it. 
 Here IRV will eventually crash but BTR-IRV is, well, better.
 
 Scenario 2: Voters rank, contrary to your assumptions (but suggested by 
 international evidence). Again, BTR-IRV does better.
 
 Scenario 3: Voters don't rank and never will. BTR-IRV is here no worse than 
 IRV.
 
 Under what scenario does BTR-IRV *lose* against ordinary IRV?
 
 I am quite interested in the answer to this as well, as I imagine that 
 whatever the answer is is a defining advantage, should any exist.

One can see this problem from two quite different points of view.

One approach is that BTR-IRV is simply an improved version of IRV that it 
avoids some of the key problems of IRV. Therefore it could be straight forward 
to get also BTR-IRV accepted if the society accepts IRV.

Another approach is to have a more political power oriented viewpoint. IRV 
tends to favour major parties. If the incumbent strong parties (that do have a 
lot to say on what route the politics take) may well count their chances in 
each proposed method. This might lead to favouring methods like IRV that still 
allow the largest parties to take a lion's share of the victories.

A classical example is one where there are two major parties and a smaller 
compromise party candidate between the lajor party candidates. Should the 
mathod allow that compromise candidate win? Condorcet compliant methods seem to 
think that the compromise candidate should win. (I also note that different 
political systems may have different needs. In some systems the strongest are 
expected to rule whil in others compromises are the default mode of operation.)

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-25 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.6.2013, at 1.06, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 So there are really three stages to a prospective new party or candidate 
 (like the Greens or Nader):
 
 1. the candidate is not competitive (e.g. fringe candidate).
 2. the candidate is competitive but either not strong enough to win, or 
 there's been a miscalculation by the voters.
 3. the candidate has taken over the position that would belong to a 
 competitor (e.g. Nader becomes the new Gore).
 
 I think Approval advocates argue that the relative share of approvals will 
 inform the voters of where they are. So the progression goes something like:
 
 In stage one, everybody who approves of Nader also approves of Gore.
 In stage three, the tables are turned: everybody who approves of Gore also 
 approves of Nader, but Nader still wins.
 
 Stage two and the transition to three is the tricky part. ... ... ...

One more approach to the problems of Approval is that it works fine as long as 
there are two potential winners. Then it is easy to approve the better one of 
those, and any additional candidates that one wants to promote.

It is much more difficult for individual voters to find a working voting 
strategy when there are three or more possible winners. One classical example 
is the one where one wing has two candidates that have about equal chances to 
win, and the other wing has just one candidate.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Participation Criteria and Bucklin - perhaps they *can* work together after all?

2013-06-18 Thread Juho Laatu
On 18.6.2013, at 4.24, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 From: Jameson Quinn [mailto:jameson.qu...@gmail.com] 
 Sent: Monday, June 17, 2013 3:14 PM
 Subject: Re: Participation Criteria and Bucklin - perhaps they *can* work 
 together after all?
  
 Unfortunately, Bucklin systems fail that one too.
  
 Hold on a sec. Let me think this through.  If we are using a Bucklin system, 
 perhaps a strictly ranked one, and X is currently winning.  Adding a single 
 ballot that has X ranked as the highest does two things: it changes the 
 threshold, and it awards one more vote to X.  The only way it can hurt X – 
 ie, cause X not to win, is if the harm in changing the threshold is greater 
 than the benefit of getting another first place vote.
  
 That’s the key to why Buckley keep failing Participation!!  I think I finally 
 grasped the essential Participation flaw with Buckley!!
  
 Each added ballot changes the threshold. Changing the threshold will either 
 have NO effect, or it will change how “deep” we have to go to find a winner.
  
 In this case, even if we know ALL the ballot we are adding have X at the top, 
 adding even a single on if it changes the threshold enough will suddenly 
 bring into your totals all the next place rankings for the existing ballots.  
 In other words, Buckley fails Participation because it is not a “smooth” 
 curve, it is a fragile one that can leap and lurch, if you see what I am 
 saying.
  
 In its own way, Buckley is as unpredictable as IRV.  Both have fractal 
 moments where a very small change can completely swamp the system and produce 
 a very different result.  Any system as – what’s the right word, jagged? 
 sensitive? fragile? is going to have one or more issues with appealing to our 
 common sense, because each has a point in which a tiny change can cause a 
 system wide shift.
  
 Am I right?

Yes. This is a good approach to describing the problem.

I tend to categorize different methods also as heuristic and more 
mathmatically exact methods that try to describe the outcome or wanted 
features of the winner more directly. IRV is a good example of a method that is 
based on an algorithms that makes pretty much sense to us, but that is anyway 
just an approximation of what we want. Also Bucklin is based on a similar kind 
of algorithm that does pretty good job, but still is just a serial stepwise 
approximation based on guesses on what direction we want to take (and which 
candidates might be bad enough so that we can eliminate them already at this 
step).

  
 I don’t know what this kind of trait is called, this oversensitivity, this 
 ability to suddenly shift from condition One to Condition Two with no smooth 
 transition points in between – but I think these kinds of systems will suffer 
 from problems like these.
  
 Now, for all I know ALL voting systems have this kind of issue – we’ll see.

I think out of the discussed methods at least Range does not really have this 
kind of randomness / fractal behaviour / oversensitivity / stepwise guesses 
based problems. It simply measures the quality of the candidates (=sum of 
utilities) and picks the best candidate as the winner. Range has other 
strategic problems in competitive environments, but that is due to strategic 
voting, not due to an oversensitive algorithm. Also FPTP is quite ok, if one 
assumes that all voters vote sincerely and we are supposed to elect the 
candidate that has highest first preference support.

According to my experience the most typical way to get an oversensitive method 
is to use some serial elimination based algorithm that makes serial (heuristic) 
guesses on which candidates are potential winners and which ones are not. Those 
methods can be good methods though, if the randomness caused by the algorithm 
causes less harm than the other properties of the method give us benefits.

If we want to avoid this kind of oversensitivity / randomness, one good 
approach is to simply define a (candidate quality) criterion that points out 
which one of the candiates is the best for our needs.

Juho


  
 -Benn Grant
 eFix Computer Consulting
 b...@4efix.com
 603.283.6601
  
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] List issues?

2013-06-18 Thread Juho Laatu
That has sometimes happened to me too.

Juho


On 18.6.2013, at 15.49, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 Well, I did put my computer consultant hat on (my day job) and this is what I 
 found:
  
 With regard to the 2 or 3 emails that showed up on the list archive page but 
 not in my inbox,
 1)  They did not show up in my inbox in Outlook
 2)  Nor did they show up in my webmail, since Outlook is configured to 
 leave a copy on the server
 3)  Nor are they in the Bulk Mail folder of my Webmail
  
 I am at a loss to come up with a plausible explanation of the above apart 
 from the idea that those emails were either never sent (list-serv issue) of 
 somehow were sent but didn’t make it to my mail server @ godaddy (no idea how 
 that might happen, I include it for the sake of completeness.)
  
 Anyways, just wanted the list-serv admins to know about this, will let you 
 guys know if I see any other strange behavior.
  
 -Benn Grant
 eFix Computer Consulting
 b...@4efix.com
 603.283.6601
  
 From: Jameson Quinn [mailto:jameson.qu...@gmail.com] 
 Sent: Tuesday, June 18, 2013 5:45 AM
 To: Benjamin Grant
 Subject: Re: [EM] List issues?
  
 I don't think it's a general problem. Perhaps it's something about your spam 
 filter or your mail client's threading algorithm.
 
 2013/6/17 Benjamin Grant b...@4efix.com
 I have noticed a few times, now, over the last several days where I have sent 
 something to the list, and I don’t receive a copy of my own email back from 
 the list.  Most of the time, I do – but on at least 2 or 3 occasions I have 
 written something to the list – and I can see it at least made it to the 
 archive here:
 http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2013-June/thread.html
  
 BUT I never get a copy of it in my inbox as I am supposed to.
  
 Is this a known issue with this list, that sometimes you don’t get copies of 
 the stuff you send?  Is it worse than that, do you sometimes not get copies 
 of the stuff *other* people send too?
  
 -Benn Grant
 eFix Computer Consulting
 b...@4efix.com
 603.283.6601
  
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
  
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MAV on electowiki

2013-06-18 Thread Juho Laatu
I quickly read the article. Here are some observations.

- Term Bucklin system has not been defined. I can guess that it probably 
refers to Bucklin style stepwise addition of new approvals, but that may not be 
as obvious to all readers. If there is no definition of Bucklin system, maybe 
one could say As in Bucklin instead of As with any Bucklin system.

- Sentence if there are more than one with a majority, the B votes are 
removed and the highest sub-majority wins is ambigious in the sense that it is 
not clear if highest sub-majority refers to all candidates or to candidates 
that had majority after adding the B votes.

- It is not quite clear what happens and if it is possible that there is no 
majority after the F votes have been counted.

- The grades could be letters or numbers, but they could also be e.g. columns 
without any letter or number. This part of text discusses what the ballots 
might look like. I'm not sure if ballot different ballot formats should be seen 
as an essential part of the method definition, or if the method should be 
defined abstractly without referring to what the actual ballots might look 
like. I tend to define the methods abstractly without assuming anything on the 
ballots, and then discuss possible ballot formats as a separate topic, but I'm 
not saying that's the only and best approach. The current text is thus ok. I 
just first read the grades of the definition as abstract grades, not as 
definitions on what would be written in the ballots.

- The linked definition of evaluatve says that ranked systems can not give 
same ratings to two candidates. I think that's confusing and wrong.

Juho


On 18.6.2013, at 23.44, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Majority_Approval_Voting
 
 Please help build up the article and work on the clearest consensus wording. 
 This article is all my own voice so far; my goal is for it not to be.
 
 Jameson
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Deconstructing the Majority Criterion

2013-06-17 Thread Juho Laatu
On 17.6.2013, at 18.26, Benjamin Grant wrote:

 Majority Criterion

My definition of Majority Criterion is simply something like if more than 50% 
of the voters prefer candidate A to all other candidates, then A shall win. 
There are methods that aim at respecting the wishes of the majority (majority 
oriented). Range/Score is not one of them. It rather aims at electing the 
candidate that has the highest sum of utility among the voters. This is a 
different need than the idea of letting the majority decide.

Majority oriented methods can give poor results from the range point of view. 
For example sincere votes 51: A=10, B=9, C=9 ; 26: B=10, C=9, A=0 ; 25 C=10, 
B=9, A=0 tell us that B and C have clearly higher average utility among the 
voters than A, although majority of the voters consider A to be the best 
candidate. A would not be a good winner according to the Range philosophy.

One could say that majority oriented methods are typically used in competitive 
environments since majority rule seems to make sense in environments where we 
expect voters to take position strictly in favour of their own candidate and 
against the other candidates and vote accordingly. In Range such thinking may 
lead to exaggeration. Maybe we will get votes like 51: A=10, B=0, C=0 ; 26: 
B=10, C=0, A=0 ; 25 C=10, B=0, A=0 although the sincere preferences are as 
above, With this kind of maximally exaggerated votes Range will also respect 
the majority rule (but it loses its expressiveness and its ability to elect the 
candidate that has highest sum of utility among the voters).

In summary, Range is not a majority oriented method, and not really a method 
for competitive environments (since it may become just approval with 
fractional votes). It should not follow the majority rule since that would 
ruin its intended other good properties. Majority oriented methods are often 
good for competitive environments. Range is good when the election organizer 
and the voters sincerely want to elect the candidate with highest sum of 
utility.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-11 Thread Juho Laatu
On 12.2.2013, at 0.33, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 I think it could be useful to quantify exactly what is meant by quoted-in 
 proportionality in the sense that the Czech Green Party desires it. Then one 
 may make a quota proportionality criterion and design methods from the 
 ground up that pass it.

My best understanding of the quoted-in related requirements is now as follows. 
The key idea is that if a seat is about to go to a candidate that is of wrong 
gender, then the fact that this seat must be given to some less liked 
candidate makes the seat in some sense less valuable to the grouping that 
supports these candidates. The rule is not exactly about one of the sexes since 
one (quoted-in) seat may be forced to go to a male candidate and another seat 
(of the same grouping) to a female candiate. The rule is not really about 
avoinding allocating more than one quoted-in seat to one grouping since 
sometimes the value of two (less valuable) quoted-in seats is the ideal way to 
balance the seats between the groupings (best proportionality). To my 
understanding there is also no requirement to have equal number of male and 
female representatives in each grouping (only a requirement to do so at top 
level, i.e. to make the proportinally ordered list balanced with respect to 
gender
 s).

Since there is also a general proportionality requirement in the traditional 
sense (each grouping to get a proportional number of representatives), there 
are two conflicting requirements, and therefore also a need to agree the 
correct balance between these two requirements (traditional proportionality and 
need to balance the allocated less valuable (quoted-in) seats). I mean that if 
the elected quoted-in candidate is 10 points worse than the candidate that 
would have been elected without the quoted-in rule, then that can be 
compensated by giving that grouping some fraction of a seat more seats (worth 
10 points). All groupings will thus not get all those representatives that they 
wanted (quoted-in rule), and they will also not get the proportionally correct 
number of representatives. There is thus a need to agree what the value of one 
seat is, and what the negative value of getting a quoted-in seat is. These 
weights must be determined by a political agreement.

Once the weights of these benefits have been determined, it should be a more 
exact task to determine what algorithm finds the best allocation of the seats. 
It is however quite difficult to estimate if some candidate that was elected as 
a quoted-in candidate would or would not have been elected also otherwise. And 
if not elected without the quoted-in rule, how much the opinions were violated 
in this particular change of representative. Some agreement is needed also here 
on how to measure these values. One may also follow some theoretical model that 
gives exact values to the quoted-in representatives (based on the preferences 
on the ballots). Or maybe there is just one constatnt value for all quoted-in 
seats.

What would the quota proportionality criterion be then? Based on this 
discussion one should first make some agreements on what the weights of 
different (conflicting) needs are. Once this has been agreed, and assuming that 
we have also a rule for determining the lost value of each quoted-in 
candidate, then the algorithm just needs to find the ideal allocation of the 
weighted seats (different representative sets may have different weights). And 
the criterion is just a mathematical proportionality criterion, based on the 
agreed (and/or calculated) weights. Is this close to what you want the 
criterion to be?

Juho


P.S. Personally I think this algorithm gets already quite complex, and there 
are also some arguments why there would be no need or why it would be harmful 
to compensate the quoted-in seats. So also a simpler proportional approach 
could do. But if the Czech Green Party says that the quoted-in seats shall be 
compensated, then let's try to find a good algorithm that will do the job (and 
the correct criterion).






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-11 Thread Juho Laatu
On 12.2.2013, at 1.24, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 2013/2/11 Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_el...@lavabit.com

 (Also, speaking of criteria: if I had enough time, I would try to find a 
 monotone variant of Schulze STV. I think one can make monotone 
 Droop-proportional multiwinner methods, since I made a Bucklin hack that 
 seemed to be both monotone and Droop-proportional. However, I have no 
 mathematical proof that the method obeys both criteria.)
 
 What does monotone even mean for PR? You can make something that's 
 sequentially monotone, but it's (I think) impossible to avoid situations 
 where AB were winning but changing CAB to ABC causes B to lose (or 
 variants of this kind of problem). That's still technically monotone, but 
 from a voters perspective, it's not usefully so.

I think monotonicity is sometimes an obvious requirement but not always. A 
ranked ordering (= monotonicity with respect to adding seats) may give 
different results than a proportional algorithm that just picks the agreed 
number of representatives (with no order). Sometimes a ranked ordering is 
needed (like in the Czech Green Party canddidate list), sometimes not. The need 
to establish a ranked order may make the proportionality of the results 
slightly worse.

I also like the Alabama paradox in the sense that one can as well consider such 
results the correct and exact outcome, not a negative paradox. All in all, 
both appraches are needed, for different needs.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 7.2.2013, at 20.43, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 At second sight, I think that giving different quota weights (V) to
 quoted-in candidates would lead to strategic voting leading to the
 weaker-gender candidates being placed at the end in order to be
 quoted-in, as you mention yourself.

Coming shortly back to this strategy.

Let's assume first that the genders are about equally strong across all 
groupings. One grouping recommends its supporters to rank all female candidates 
before the male candidates in this election. In the next election the order of 
the genders will be reversed. The grouping also recommends all its supporters 
to rank all the candidates of this grouping. The probablity of getting mostly 
female representatives increases, but in the next election the roles will be 
reversed. On average this strategy gives more representatives (if other 
groupings are sincere).

If one gender is known to be weaker, then that gender would be ranked last, as 
you said. If that gender is constantly weaker, this strategy will lead to a 
constant bias within this grouping to get candidates of the stronger gender. 
But average number of representetives would grow also in this case (if other 
groupings are sincere).

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-07 Thread Juho Laatu
On 5.2.2013, at 19.50, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 i] that the seats are quoted-in fairly proportionally between the
 voters (i.e. the same voters do not get both quoted-in seats) and at
 the same time

50: w1  w2  m1  m2
50: w3  w4  m3  m4

The first seat goes to w1 (lottery). The second seat goes to m3 (male 
representative needed).

I read the rule above so that the third seat should go to w3 (not to w2). The 
rule talks about getting both quoted-in seats, but I guess the intention is 
that already the first quoted-in seat is considered to be a slight disadvantage 
that shall be balanced by ranking w3 third. Is this the correct way to read the 
rule?

The fourth seat goest to w2.

1) If we read the rule above literally so, that one grouping should not get 
both quoted-in seats, the fifth seat goes to m1.
2) If we read the rule so that the quoted-in seats are considered slightly less 
valuable than the normal seats, then the fifth seat goes to m4.

Which one of the interpretations is the correct one? My understanding is now 
that there is no requirement concerning the balance of genders between the 
groupings, so allocating both male seats to the second grouping should be no 
problem. But is it a problem to allocate both quoted-in seats to it?

Is the second proportional ordering (  w1, m3, w3, w2, m4  ) above more 
balanced / proportional in the light of the planned targets than the first one 
(  w1, m3, w3, w2, m1  )?

(The algorithm could in principle also backtrack and reallocate the first seats 
to make it possible to allocate the last seats in a better way, but that 
doesn't seem to add anything useful in this example.)

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-07 Thread Juho Laatu
-in candidate a
 value of 1/2 or 2/3 of a seat for the quoted-in candidate could maybe
 be used.
 
 Maybe someone will propose a better formula to value the quoted-in candidate,
 which might (or might not) depend on the number of the seat being
 elected (i.e. it is worse to get seat no. 2 quoted-in, than seat no.
 5).
 
 P.
 
 2013/2/7 Peter Zbornik pzbor...@gmail.com:
 2013/2/7 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk:
 On 5.2.2013, at 19.50, Peter Zbornik wrote:
 
 i] that the seats are quoted-in fairly proportionally between the
 voters (i.e. the same voters do not get both quoted-in seats) and at
 the same time
 
 
 50: w1  w2  m1  m2
 50: w3  w4  m3  m4
 
 The first seat goes to w1 (lottery). The second seat goes to m3 (male
 representative needed).
 
 I read the rule above so that the third seat should go to w3 (not to w2).
 The rule talks about getting both quoted-in seats, but I guess the intention
 is that already the first quoted-in seat is considered to be a slight
 disadvantage that shall be balanced by ranking w3 third. Is this the correct
 way to read the rule?
 
 In a sense yes, but I haven't thought about the problem that way.
 The question is how to quantify the disadvantage, for instance if we
 had the votes 55 w1 w2 m1 m2 and 45 w3 w4 m3 m4, should we still rank
 w3 third, instead of w2?
 
 
 The fourth seat goest to w2.
 
 1) If we read the rule above literally so, that one grouping should not get
 both quoted-in seats, the fifth seat goes to m1.
 2) If we read the rule so that the quoted-in seats are considered slightly
 less valuable than the normal seats, then the fifth seat goes to m4.
 
 That is an interesting point. I guess both interpretations are valid.
 Personally, at first sight, I like the second interpretation.
 I have to think about that a little.
 
 
 Which one of the interpretations is the correct one? My understanding is now
 that there is no requirement concerning the balance of genders between the
 groupings, so allocating both male seats to the second grouping should be no
 problem. But is it a problem to allocate both quoted-in seats to it?
 
 Is the second proportional ordering (  w1, m3, w3, w2, m4  ) above more
 balanced / proportional in the light of the planned targets than the first
 one (  w1, m3, w3, w2, m1  )?
 
 (The algorithm could in principle also backtrack and reallocate the first
 seats to make it possible to allocate the last seats in a better way, but
 that doesn't seem to add anything useful in this example.)
 
 Juho
 
 
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-07 Thread Juho Laatu
On 7.2.2013, at 19.11, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 I think V should be 3/4 (if quoted-in) or 1 (if would have won that same seat 
 anyway).

Do yu mean that also the weight of a quoted-in seat should grow dynamically to 
1 if the algorithm finds out later that the quoted-in candidate would have been 
elected also at a later round without the quoted-in rules? That may add some 
complexity and inaccuracy to a sequential algorithm (but may still yield fairer 
results).

That leads to anouther topic. James Gilmour referred to one algorithm that 
fills the seats starting from the last seat. If one wants the proportionality 
to be ideal (but still use a sequential algorithm, not an exhaustive evaluation 
of all combinations), and one can estimate what the expected number elected 
representatives is, one could first find the ideal proportional set of that 
size, and then proceed from that point to larger sets by adding candidates (in 
the proportional order), and to smaller sets by dropping the candidates out one 
by one. This may be already too much fine-tuning and therefore not worth the 
trouble (even if the expected outcomes would be slightly more proportional).

Juho


(P.S. My wording on the mail below should be softened a bit = w3 could be 
automatically ranked third. That depends on the used algorithm.)


 Thus, the quota would be 2/11, and the leftover (unrepresented) quota at the 
 end would be between 1/11 (Hare-like) and 2/11 (Droop-like).
 
 Jameson
 
 2013/2/7 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 I try to address the targets one more round without taking position on how 
 the actual algorithm will work. From this point of view I start from the 
 question, what is the value of a quoted-in seat. Maybe we can use a constant 
 value (V) that is smaller that the value of a normal seat (1).
 
 One problem that we have is that although the value of a quoted-in seat is 
 smaller than 1, the final value of that representative may be equal to 1. I 
 mean that if we are electing members of a parliament, all elected candiates 
 will have one vote each in the parliament. Therefore, from political balance 
 point of view, every representative is equally valuable. The lesser value of 
 the quoted-in candidate refers only to the fact that some grouping did not 
 get their most favoured candidate throuh.
 
 If one tries to meet e.g. regional proportionality and political 
 proportionality requirements at one go simultaneously, the only erros are 
 rounding errors in the allocation of the last seats. The quoted-in 
 requirements and political proportionality requrements are however in 
 conflict with each others. One has to decide how much weight to put to the 
 need to elect the most liked candidate of a grouping vs. to give all 
 groupings equal weight in the parliament.
 
 In the example below, if we assume that five candidates (w1, m3, w3, w2, m4) 
 will be elected, and V = 0.5, the liked candidate points of the two groups 
 will be  2, 2  but the voting weights in the parliament will be  2, 3 . 
 What is the ideal outcome of the algoritms then? Should the algorithm make 
 the liked candidate points as equal as possible for all groupings, or 
 should the algorithm lead to a compromise result that puts some weight also 
 on the voting strengths in the parliament? I guess you can do this quite well 
 also by adjusting the value of V, e.g. from 0.5 to 0.75.
 
 So far my conclusion is that one could get a quite reasonable algorithm by 
 just picking a good value for V and then using some algorithm that optimizes 
 proportionality using these agreed weights (and the gender balance 
 requirements).
 
 - - -
 
 Personally I'm still wondering if the less liked candidate reweighting 
 rules are a good thing to have. One reason is the equal voting weight of the 
 elected representatives in the parliament. Sometimes the quoted-in candidates 
 could be elected also without the quoted-in rules (e.g. if the second set of 
 opinions was 50: w3  m3  w4  m4). The algorithm could thus not be accurate 
 anyway (could give false rewards). One could also say that if some of the 
 groupings doesn't have any good (= value very close to 1) candidates of the 
 underrepresented gender, it is its own fault, and that shoudl not be rewarded 
 by giving it more seats.
 
 One more point is that the algorithm might favour the quoted-in grouping also 
 for other reasons. I'll modify the example a bit.
 
 45: w1  w2  m1  m2
 05: w1  w2
 45: w3  w4  m3  m4
 05: w3  w4
 
 Here I assume that those candidates that are ranked lower in the votes will 
 typically get also less votes in general. Here all male candidates have only 
 45 supporters, while all female candidates have 50 supporters each. Here I 
 assume that voters do not generally rank all candiates or all candidates of 
 their own grouping (this may not be the case in all elections). Anyway, the 
 impact of this possible phenomenon is that at least w3 will be automatically 
 ranked third, also

Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-07 Thread Juho Laatu
On 7.2.2013, at 22.24, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 returning to your original example, again,  with slightly modified
 number of votes to avoid tie-breaking:
 Coalition 1 (C1) - 51: w1  w2  m1  m2
 Coalition 2 (C2) - 49: w3  w4  m3  m4
 
 Results:
 Seat number, candidate, coalition, quoted in
 1. w1, C1, no
 2. m3, C2, yes
 3. w2, C1, no
 4, w3, C2, no
 5. m1, C1, no
 
 There is no problem here, as C1 got the majority of candidates, and
 kept the constraints, so there was never any issue with
 proportionality of quoted-in candidaes.
 
 Here is an example to illustrate the problem:
 Coalition 1: 32: w1w4w3m3
 Coalition 2: 33: w1w3w4m4
 Coalition 3: 35: w2w5m1m2
 
 Apply top-down proportional ordering (Otten) for normal STV:
 Elect 1st seat - w1 (quota 50)
 Elect 2nd seat - m1 (quoted in instead of w2) (quota 33.4)
 3rd seat - w3 (quota 25)
 4th seat - w4 (quota 20)
 5th seat - m4 (quoted in instead of w5) (quota 16.7)
 
 This leads to the quoted-in candidates being disproportionally
 distributed in coalition 3.
 
 Thus, the right distribution, intuitively is:
 4th seat - m3
 5th seat - w5

The approach of giving less weight to the quoted-in candidates (= reduce less 
weight from the votes that supported the election of m1) could lead to the 
intended outcome here.

 
 Sorry to have bothered you with this, but on the other hand, I feel
 this is an important problem.

No problem. Actually I have personal interest in proportional methods with 
mutiple allocation criteria. So, thanks for taking this topic up and promoting 
this kind of advanced methods also in real life.

Juho


 
 Best regards
 Peter Zborník
 
 2013/2/7 Peter Zbornik pzbor...@gmail.com:
 Hi Juho,
 
 I have to think this through a bit.
 Thanks for the examples.
 At second sight, I think that giving different quota weights (V) to
 quoted-in candidates would lead to strategic voting leading to the
 weaker-gender candidates being placed at the end in order to be
 quoted-in, as you mention yourself.
 
 Best regards
 Peter Zborník
 
 
 2013/2/7 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk:
 I try to address the targets one more round without taking position on how 
 the actual algorithm will work. From this point of view I start from the 
 question, what is the value of a quoted-in seat. Maybe we can use a 
 constant value (V) that is smaller that the value of a normal seat (1).
 
 One problem that we have is that although the value of a quoted-in seat is 
 smaller than 1, the final value of that representative may be equal to 1. I 
 mean that if we are electing members of a parliament, all elected candiates 
 will have one vote each in the parliament. Therefore, from political 
 balance point of view, every representative is equally valuable. The lesser 
 value of the quoted-in candidate refers only to the fact that some grouping 
 did not get their most favoured candidate throuh.
 
 If one tries to meet e.g. regional proportionality and political 
 proportionality requirements at one go simultaneously, the only erros are 
 rounding errors in the allocation of the last seats. The quoted-in 
 requirements and political proportionality requrements are however in 
 conflict with each others. One has to decide how much weight to put to the 
 need to elect the most liked candidate of a grouping vs. to give all 
 groupings equal weight in the parliament.
 
 In the example below, if we assume that five candidates (w1, m3, w3, w2, 
 m4) will be elected, and V = 0.5, the liked candidate points of the two 
 groups will be  2, 2  but the voting weights in the parliament will be  
 2, 3 . What is the ideal outcome of the algoritms then? Should the 
 algorithm make the liked candidate points as equal as possible for all 
 groupings, or should the algorithm lead to a compromise result that puts 
 some weight also on the voting strengths in the parliament? I guess you can 
 do this quite well also by adjusting the value of V, e.g. from 0.5 to 0.75.
 
 So far my conclusion is that one could get a quite reasonable algorithm by 
 just picking a good value for V and then using some algorithm that 
 optimizes proportionality using these agreed weights (and the gender 
 balance requirements).
 
 - - -
 
 Personally I'm still wondering if the less liked candidate reweighting 
 rules are a good thing to have. One reason is the equal voting weight of 
 the elected representatives in the parliament. Sometimes the quoted-in 
 candidates could be elected also without the quoted-in rules (e.g. if the 
 second set of opinions was 50: w3  m3  w4  m4). The algorithm could thus 
 not be accurate anyway (could give false rewards). One could also say that 
 if some of the groupings doesn't have any good (= value very close to 1) 
 candidates of the underrepresented gender, it is its own fault, and that 
 shoudl not be rewarded by giving it more seats.
 
 One more point is that the algorithm might favour the quoted-in grouping 
 also for other reasons. I'll modify the example a bit

Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-06 Thread Juho Laatu
Is there a quota or gender requirement or both requirements?

- If we assume that the quota rules are not needed since both genders will get 
seats also otherwise, is it ok if one grouping gets 3 women and the other one 2 
men?
- Is it ok if the second seat goes to a male candidate of some grouping and the 
fifth seat goes to a female candidate of the same grouping?

Juho


On 6.2.2013, at 11.47, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 James, Jonathan,
 
 I need that the quoted-in people are quoted-in in such a way, that the
 proportionality of the election is not significantly disturbed.
 
 I think Rosenthiel's approach has the following insufficiencies:
 If I elect five women, and then increase the number of elected seats
 until two more men have been elected, then we might end up with a
 situation, where
 a] one coalition of voters get all the seats (the easiest example is
 when we elect two ordered seats, one man and one woman) - i.e. the
 resulting list is not a proportionaly ordered list
 b] one coalition of voters get all the qouted-in men - i.e. the
 resulting list has no proportionality between gender.
 
 Best regards
 Peter Zborník
 
 
 2013/2/6 James Gilmour jgilm...@globalnet.co.uk:
 Jonathan Lundell   Sent: Tuesday, February 05, 2013 6:40 PM
 There is, I think, an underlying misconception here, namely
 that STV order of election can be interpreted as a ranking of
 level of support. It's not, in the general case.
 
 Jonathan is absolutely right.  If you want lists ordered by relative 
 support, you need to adopt a procedure like that recommended by
 Colin Rosenstiel and used by some UK political parties when they have to 
 select ordered lists for closed-list party-PR elections.
 
 First you use ordinary STV-PR to elect the required total number of 
 candidates.  Then you conduct a series of STV-PR elections, each
 for one vacancy less than the preceding election.  The unsuccessful 
 candidate takes the lowest vacant place on the ordered list.
 Continue until you run-off between the top-two for the second-last place.
 
 For full details, see:
  http://www.crosenstiel.webspace.virginmedia.com/stv/orderstv.htm
 and
  http://www.crosenstiel.webspace.virginmedia.com/stv/ordstvdt.htm
 
 The second one includes a constraint for candidate's sex.
 
 James Gilmour
 
 
 
 
 ---
 avast! Antivirus: Outbound message clean.
 Virus Database (VPS): 130205-0, 05/02/2013
 Tested on: 05/02/2013 23:49:22
 avast! - copyright (c) 1988-2013 AVAST Software.
 http://www.avast.com
 
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] proportional constraints - help needed

2013-02-06 Thread Juho Laatu
On 6.2.2013, at 12.29, Juho Laatu wrote:

 - Is it ok if the second seat goes to a male candidate of some grouping and 
 the fifth seat goes to a female candidate of the same grouping?

Clarification: In the second and fifth seats the quota rule forced the sex to 
be changed.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] The Green scenario, and IRV in the Green scenario, is a new topic here. Hence these additional comments. Clarification of position and why.

2013-02-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.2.2013, at 15.40, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 Being a green party member (although a Czech one and not US), I would
 advocate only the top-two-run-off
 variant of IRV, i.e. elimination of the candidates and transfer of
 votes until two remain, no quota for election (or quota=100%) except
 for the case where one candidate has more than 50% of first
 preferences.
 
 The top two candidates would meet in a second round in IRV.
 A candidate would be elected if he/she would get more than 50% of the votes.
 
 Empty votes would count as  valid votes in both first and second round.
 
 If no candidate would be elected in second round new elections would take 
 place.
 
 The advantages of the proposed election system are
 1) the voters are given a chance to concentrate only on two candidates
 in the second round, and are thus allowed to change their preferences.
 2) blank votes together with IRV might make the candidates less
 polarized, as, given a large number of blank votes, the candidate with
 the highest number of votes in the second round would have to rely on
 the second preferences of the voters for the opposing candidate in
 order to get 50%+ votes.
 
 PZ

If one wants to guarentee sufficient support of the winner (50% in the 
description above), then one nice approach is to have an explicit approval 
cutoff in the ballots. By comparing each candidate to that cutoff one can count 
how wide support each candidate has. You can use that information also to 
determine if someone should win already based on the first round, or which 
candidates shoud go to the later rounds.

For example, if the winner of the first round (maybe using a Condorcet method) 
has 50% approval, elect him. Otherwise arrange a second round with the same 
rules, except that you may drop some of the candidates out (maybe all but two).

My point is just that this aproach is formally nice and it collects useful 
additional information that can be used in many ways, like making the decision 
already after the first round.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Proposed bullet-voting prohibition criterion

2013-02-03 Thread Juho Laatu
On 3.2.2013, at 13.13, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 01/30/2013 05:30 PM, Peter Gustafsson wrote:
 
 Kristoffer:
 
 Thanks for pointing out those possibilities for how a big party can
 instruct its voters on how to thwart the intent of this proposed
 criterion. Obviously, BVP is not sufficient to ensure the transition
 from a two-party environment to a multiparty environment. What are your
 ideas on how make a stronger set of criteria to that end?
 
 ...

One approach to this problem is that Proportional Representation is actually 
the criteron that defines multiparty systems (or at least the typical ones). 
This criterion may however not be a practical requirement in a two-party 
country since a jump to a PR system would be a very long jump. However, also 
two-party systems approximate PR roughly. One could therefore start from small 
steps like requiring more accurate PR for the leading two parties in those 
bodies where both parties are represented. After that a natural step might be 
to allow also some major third party to get some seats in areas where it is 
strong. And eventually one might in theory end up having PR for all opinion 
groups (or at least all those that have at least one quota of supporters).

In some sense plurality allows those parties that have 50% support to have 
seats while a good PR system allows all parties with at least one quota of 
support to have one seat. Single member districts are maybe the key problem and 
strong legacy that makes and keeps two-party systems two-party systems. It may 
be that a multiparty system that is based on single member districts is not 
viable (or does not properly meet the multiparty environment requirement). 
So, maybe one would have to break the single seat district tradition at some 
point in time. That's not an easy thing to do.

One more important trick might be to start the changes from smaller units like 
towns. I'm sure there must be one or two towns that would be interested in 
giving the multiparty approach try. If such trials are suucessful, that wolud 
surely influence thinking and decisions also at the higher levels.

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Request re. Acronym Use on this list

2013-01-21 Thread Juho Laatu
EM's own web site is also a good source of definitions for abbreviations that 
are often used in the EM discussions. 
(http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Special:AllPages)

But in general I too recommend writers to open all abbreviations that are not 
obvious to all. There is no point in making the messages more cryptic than they 
could be.

Juho



On 21.1.2013, at 19.54, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 On 1/21/13 9:31 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:
 I do not spend enough time following this subject to memorize all the 
 acronyms.
 
 Could posters to this list please make your emails comprehensible to
 someone like myself by spelling out the words comprising the acronym
 when it is first used in each and every email to the list?
 
 
 Kathy, i feel the same way.  sometimes Wikipedia (Voting systems) is helpful. 
  but it doesn't keep up.
 
 and i just confirmed, evidently a while ago i disabled the filter on my email 
 client regarding your posts to EM.  i forgot i did that.  hence i see the 
 post.
 
 -- 
 
 r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com
 
 Imagination is more important than knowledge.
 
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Majority-Judgement using adjectives versus alphabetical scales versus numerical ranges.

2012-12-06 Thread Juho Laatu
On 6.12.2012, at 23.54, ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wrote:

   ¡Hello!
 
   ¿How fare you?
 
   Yesterday, I noted that Majority-Judgements does not work if we have 
 too many adjectives because we have only so many adjectives and voters might 
 confuse adjectives too close in meaning..  ¿Would an alphabetical scale be 
 acceptable?:
 
   In the United States of America, we grade students using letters:
 
   A+
   A
   A-
   B+
   B
   B-
   C+
   C
   C-
   D+
   D
   D-
   F+
   F
   F-
 
   I have 2 questions grading candidates on this scale.  1 question is for 
 people not in the United States of America.  The other question is for 
 everyone:
 
   People outside the United States of America:
 
   ¿Do you Understand this Scale?

Very understandable. If some values should be considered unacceptable, then 
that category should be pointed out.

 
   For everyone:
 
   ¿Is this scale acceptable to you?
 
   Followup question:
 
   If this scale is not acceptable to you, ¿why is it not acceptable to 
 you?
 
   With 15 grades, this scale is not very different from the numerical 
 ranges of 0 to 9 or negative -9 to positive +9.  This raises the question:
 
   ¿Why not just use the ranges 0 to 9 or negative -9 to positive +9 
 instead?

Each country could use those values (letters or numbers) that people are most 
familiar with. If you want to have universal coverage, then numbers are good 
since they heve the same meaning and people are familiar with them everyehere.

It depends on the type of election if -n to +n is better than 0 to n or 1 
to n. If there is an approval cutoff or unacceptable values, then the 
scale can be from a to b to c (b can be 0 or a positive number). Since most 
number systems are based on 10, ranges that are in one way or another based on 
that number are good.

I guess low values are usually worse than high values, but one could also use 
ranking style values where 1 is the best value.

Juho


 
   ¡Peace!
 
 -- 
 
   “⸘Ŭalabio‽” wala...@macosx.com
 
 Skype:
   Walabio
 
 An IntactWiki:
   http://circleaks.org/
 
   “You are entitled to your own opinion, but you are not entitled to your 
 own facts.”
   ——
   Senator Daniel Patrick Moynihan
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Possibly more stable consensus government

2012-12-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 26.11.2012, at 0.03, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 You have a parliamentary system.
 Forming a government requires a supermajority (say 60%).

That says to me that the policy of the governmnet will be on average more 
centrist (averaged) than e.g. with 51% governmnets. Since the governments will 
be a combination of multiple interest groups, each party probably has to commit 
to supporting few topics that they actually don't like. And this means that the 
parties should have strict party discipline.

I'll use FInland as an example. In the recent years there have been three major 
parties. Any two of them can form the core of the government. In order to make 
the government stronger they invite also some smaller parties in the 
government. Those governments have been very stable (regularly from one 
election to the next election). It is normal that all parties in the government 
at least stay silent and vote as agreed when the government was formed, even if 
they disagree on the content in some questions. One reason is that the 
politicians love being ministers. Also the small parties tend to be loyal. One 
reason is that they want to be included in the next governments too (as loyal 
members of the government, with one or two own requirements that they want the 
government to support).

The Finnish system does not require 60% support, but in practice the three 
party system has thus led to a quite similar situation.

 However, all motions of no confidence have to be constructive, i.e. they have 
 to propose a new government and thus be subject to the supermajority rule.

In FInland the government usually has no problem making (practically) all their 
MPs support the government when the parliament votes on confidence in the 
government (and in other questions too).

 
 What kind of behavior would you see under such a system? One would ordinarily 
 consider parliamentary systems that require a supermajority for forming a 
 government to be very unstable, because it may take forever to get the 
 required majority, and in the meantime, a simple majority can tear down the 
 government that already exists.

In Finland the policy does not change very much between governments. It may be 
even so that the policy (or rhetorics) of that major party that move from 
government to opposition (or in the other direction) is the part that changes. 
There is thus no alternating government policy style behavour e.g. between the 
left and right wings. Nowadays there are also other factors in the political 
fiels than the traditional left vs. right battle. Also coopertion of the 
leftmost and rightmost large parties is no problem. They have other things in 
common (e.g. som more salary worker, industry and city orientation than the 
centre party has).

 
 But by insisting that all votes of no confidence are constructive, a simple 
 majority can't remove the government. Only a supermajority can, and then only 
 when it has a proposal for another government.
 
 So what we would expect to happen is that the government can stay in office 
 for a much longer time than would otherwise be the case. This, in turn, is 
 offset by the supermajority requirement for getting your particular 
 government proposal into the executive in the first place.

In Finland the political system has resembled this approach in the recent years 
although there are no specific supermajority requirements to form or to break 
governmnets. Having such rules could strengthen similar behaviour even more. 
Looking at the rules from a Finnish perspective, the supermajority rule to 
replace the current government could be too strong since it could make the 
maybe too stable system even more stable.

 
 Would that configuration weaken the consensus aspect of the system?

That doesn't seem to be the case in Finland.

One problem that I see is that the consensus may not be a true consensus of the 
voters. Sometimes it appears to be more a consensus of the professional 
politicians themselves, including their interest to stay in the government 
(higher salary, more power, more visibility). Sometimes it appears that the 
politicians agree what to do between themselves an tell to the media and voters 
only the official planned story (as agreed by the government parties).

 Perhaps a government that happened to have a supermajority at one point 
 outstays their welcome and gets increasingly unpopular until there's a 
 sufficient supermajority in the other direction, then that government gets 
 replaced by its opposite pole, and rinse and repeat.

Maybe in some other countries, but in Finland the party discipline or 
governmnet discipline tends to be quite strong.

 On the other hand, the opposition might try to appeal more broadly so that, 
 as the government gets less popular and the centrists previously aligned with 
 the government starts abandoning it, the opposition almost immediately has a 
 variant of the centrist policy ready to catch them so their 

Re: [EM] Possibly more stable consensus government

2012-12-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.12.2012, at 15.35, Raph Frank wrote:

 On Tue, Dec 4, 2012 at 10:21 AM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 In Finland the political system has resembled this approach in the recent 
 years although there are no specific supermajority requirements to form or 
 to break governmnets. Having such rules could strengthen similar behaviour 
 even more. Looking at the rules from a Finnish perspective, the 
 supermajority rule to replace the current government could be too strong 
 since it could make the maybe too stable system even more stable.
 
 Fundamentally, consensus by rules is different than consensus voluntarily.

Yes, e.g. in a country with two alternating 51% government alternatives these 
rules would make a dramatical difference.

 
 In the case you have, the lager parties benefit from having the
 smaller parties involved, but it isn't mandatory.  Making the smaller
 parties required would boost their negotiating power.

In Finland the governments typically have more than one small party. That means 
that no single small party is critical when forming the new government, nor 
after the government has been formed.

If there is a supermajority requirement for breaking the government, that could 
reduce the power of the small parties (inside the already formed government).

 
 This may lead to fragmentation of the larger parties.

I'm not sure since a large party would still have more power than its 
fragments. At least in Finland I'd expect large parties to agree and form the 
core of the government also if the supermajority rules would be in place.

 
 Maybe in some other countries, but in Finland the party discipline or 
 governmnet discipline tends to be quite strong.
 
 I think the parliamentary system, where being a minister requires
 loyalty to the party, discipline is easier.
 
 If you changed it so that members of the legislature couldn't be
 appointed to cabinet (or better couldn't stand for election to the
 legislature for the next election), then discipline would probably
 fall.

Such rules would seem to expand Montesquieu's separation of powers rules to new 
areas. In the current political system in Finland (and probably also in most 
other places) the politicians are very interested in becoming and staying as 
ministers. In the politics of the EU countries politics also ablity to 
influence in the EU machinery is a possible career target for the politicians. 
If those interests are too high, the political targets may become secondary 
targets. Even before proposing separation of the parliament and the government 
I might propose separation of political roles and business roles, separation 
from administration (e.g. reward jobs for the politicians), and setting 
stricter rules on how the political parties re funded. I believe most political 
systems would probably benefit of various additional separations of power.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Juho: Social Optimizations. The Sincere Ideal.

2012-11-15 Thread Juho Laatu
On 15.11.2012, at 18.00, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 If I ranked all of the candidates sincerely, the Democrat and the
 Republican would be at the bottom of that ranking. Even if they're
 winnable.
 
 So you can't say that not ranking unwinnable candidates allows you to
 vote a short ranking.

I said that not ranking unwinnable candidates does not cause very much harm. In 
your case I assume that your most preferred candiates can not win. Based on 
that you could leave them unranked, but you should rank at least one of the two 
winnable candidates.

That apprach will not change the result of the election (with high 
probability). This (focus on who wins) is the way we usually measure the 
performance of election methods and study the recommended voting practices for 
the voters. There could however be other resons why it would make sense to rank 
your favourite candidates. You could rank them at top to help them (or their 
party) to win at the next election. Or you could give them this way some 
encouragement and thumbs up, and you could increase their chances of becoming 
elected in some other important position. In order to get good information on 
the true preferences of the electorate (for statistics and studies) it would 
make sense for all voters to always rank as many candidates as possible. You 
may also have your personal reasons, like the feeling of ranking one of the 
frontrunners one but last (not first).

 Sure, there's a case for saying that people would enjoy indicating who
 is worst. I just don't think that the Democrats and Republicans
 deserve to be ranked at all. Not ranking them at all is better than
 dignifying them with rank positions--even last and 2nd-to-last.

That sounds like you are talking about implicit approval of all the ranked 
candidates. I prefer to see rankings as rankings, i.e. truncated vote AB means 
ABC=D=E, not ABC=D=E, if we talk about traditional Condorcet methods that 
usually treat truncations that way. But I guess you are talking about methods 
that intentionally want to use implicit approval.

I believe many people would be happy to tell who is worst. But it is not a good 
idea to allow them to vote ABall_othersYZ since that could lead to 
unexpected and bad results. Allowing them to rank ABCDYZ(all_others) is 
better since then they have to explicitly indicate that C and D are better than 
Y and Z.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-14 Thread Juho Laatu
On 14.11.2012, at 2.59, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 
 
 - Mail original -
 De : Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 I don't believe the public needs to understand the terms 
 plurality criterion
 or implicit approval or even strategy to find the 
 scenario problematic.
 
 I guess people need to understand what ranking candidates in general or 
 ranking 
 them above the last place means, and that such an act is supposed to mean 
 something when they vote, if they have an opinion on the Plurality criterion 
 (or 
 on examples that demonstrate the impact of the Plurality criterion). Or do 
 you 
 mean that the Plurality criterion example would be presented and explained 
 to 
 the public, but assuming that they don't understand what ranking or not 
 ranking some candidate means?
 
 Plurality is just a description that is convenient for discussion on the
 EM list. Ranking above last place isn't a concept that exists (until 
 someone feels it would aid their position to bring it up).
 
 It just takes someone (could be an IRV advocate) to say this many voters 
 ranked this candidate first and this candidate second, and didn't rank 
 anyone else, etc. If this, without bringing up any criteria, doesn't 
 raise an awful lot of eyebrows, then I'm wrong about Plurality. But if 
 it does raise eyebrows, then it is up to the pro-margins crowd to explain 
 to the public that their mistake is that they believe in implicit approval
 (without having ever heard of it) and that they should stop, because it
 (you will say) encourages harmful strategy.

Ok, it seems that we are moving in the direction of marketability of the 
methods. All methods can be attacked based on some of their properties. And in 
most cases voters are quite unaware of any of those properties, until someone 
builds such (usually negative) marketing messages and starts using them.

Sometimes the marketing messages might be based on what actually happened in 
the election. In Burlington 2009 mayoral elections people were told that IRV 
failed to elect the Condorcet winner. But it seems that people didn't pay much 
attention to that failure. Sometimes the marketing stories are based just on 
what might happen in theory. It may be that we are talking more about the 
psychology of the politicians and lobbyists here, and less about the psychology 
of the actual voters, or the concerns of the election method experts.

 
 And I want note again that virtually every proposed method satisfies 
 Plurality aside from margins and MMPO. So if Plurality is the cause of 
 some harmful strategy, your offered alternative must be something really
 fantastic.

I guess Condorcet methods can't ever be successful since they fail such 
terrible criteria as favourite betrayal and burial. ;-) I mean that 
whatever method you want to promote, there are some nasty negative marketing 
pitches that you must be ready to answer. I'm not sure if Plurality is the most 
difficult one. One reason is that even experts need to read the definition 
twice before they properly understand what the idea is and what the 
implications of the criterion might be.

 
 That's why I see it as such a show-stopper.
 I wonder if the voters should be told about the Plurality criterion or 
 if that
 should be hidden from them (to avoid them rankig only those candidates 
 that 
 they approve / want to promote). In some startegies that information 
 may be 
 useful to them. But losing information because of truncation (in an 
 election 
 that has no meaningful strategy problems) is harmful.
 
 Do you think that if you permit IRV voters to know that IRV satisfies
 Plurality, they will truncate more often (assuming the rules allow them 
 to)?
 
 Depends on how different properties are presented and advertised. If 
 Plurality 
 would be presented as an important feature of Condorcet methods, some people 
 might take that seriously and vote accordingly (e.g. rank only those 
 candidates 
 that they approve). That could be relevant in IRV too, if someone would 
 start 
 merketing IRV using the Plurality criterion.
 
 I can't imagine that anyone would use Plurality to promote a method, 
 since even FPP satisfies it. I can only see using it to oppose a method,
 and even then it seems unnecessary to put a name to the problem.
 
 But in general I lean in the direction that in most cases (e.g. in 
 Burlington) 
 people will use ranked methods in some quite sincere way and they do not 
 worry 
 about the details, like IRV strategies or Plurality criterion.
 
 Ok. In the context of margins' proposability and Plurality I don't 
 actually think it matters how people would vote under it. (Though I'm sure
 it would come up. Ahaha.)
 
 However, even without stategy and property discussions, some voters may be 
 tempted to truncate just because they get the idea (maybe from their 
 traditional 
 voting methods) that marking some candidate on the ballot will give him some 
 points. But that would be based on lack

Re: [EM] 3 or more choices-Condorcet

2012-11-14 Thread Juho Laatu
On 14.11.2012, at 15.21, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 There's no best winner. We've been over that. But, if you really
 want a best winner, then look at the significant social optimizations
 of Approval and Score.

There may be different elections with different needs. The society is free to 
decide what criterion to use for each need. If you want to elect a candidate 
that gets a high sum of ratings, why not use Score. If you want to elect the 
most approved candidate, use Approval. If you want to elect a candidate that is 
preferred over all others, use Condorcet. (Take also the nature of the society 
into account since the votes may not be sincre enough.)

 Maybe, then, people should reluctantly give up the
 elusive goal of electing the CW. That's my take. Just work on reducing
 strategy needs, eliminating the worst strategy needs.

I'm more optimistic. My guess is that in most societies voters are sincere 
enough.

 But, what if there are 20 or 30 candidates? Wouldn't you prefer a
 method that doesn't make you need to rank the unacceptables?

In methods with 20 or 30 candidates many of the candidates may be irrelevant 
either in the sense that they will certainly not win, or in the sense that the 
voter doesn't care which one of the remaining candiates wins. In those cases 
truncation is quite ok. No information lost. It would however be good if the 
voters would rank all but one of those unacceptables that are potential winners 
(if the voter has such preferences).

 if ranking unacceptables is distasteful to you (as it is to me)

You should think that you are telling that the worst candidate is even worse 
than the second worst. That's what Condorcet methods anyway typically do, i.e. 
focus on pairwise losses rather than wins. That could make ranking of the worst 
candidates a pleasant experience. :-)

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-13 Thread Juho Laatu
On 12.11.2012, at 17.59, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 
 Kevin Venzke wrote:
 
 Margins, it seems to me, is DOA as a proposal due to the Plurality 
 criterion.
 That 35 AB, 25 B, 40 C would elect A is too counter-intuitive.
 
 I agree. For those who don't know, the Plurality criterion says that if  X 
 is ranked
 strictly above all other candidates on more ballots than Y is ranked above 
 any candidates,
 then Y must not win. 
 
 
 Plurality criterion assumes implicit approval (given any preference) of 
 ranked
 candidates (definitions above have some differences). In that sense it adds 
 something
 extra to pure ranking.
 
 I don't believe the public needs to understand the terms plurality criterion
 or implicit approval or even strategy to find the scenario problematic.

I guess people need to understand what ranking candidates in general or ranking 
them above the last place means, and that such an act is supposed to mean 
something when they vote, if they have an opinion on the Plurality criterion 
(or on examples that demonstrate the impact of the Plurality criterion). Or do 
you mean that the Plurality criterion example would be presented and explained 
to the public, but assuming that they don't understand what ranking or not 
ranking some candidate means?

 
 That's why I see it as such a show-stopper.
 I wonder if the voters should be told about the Plurality criterion or if 
 that
 should be hidden from them (to avoid them rankig only those candidates that 
 
 they approve / want to promote). In some startegies that information may be 
 
 useful to them. But losing information because of truncation (in an election 
 
 that has no meaningful strategy problems) is harmful.
 Do you think that if you permit IRV voters to know that IRV satisfies
 Plurality, they will truncate more often (assuming the rules allow them 
 
 to)?

Depends on how different properties are presented and advertised. If Plurality 
would be presented as an important feature of Condorcet methods, some people 
might take that seriously and vote accordingly (e.g. rank only those candidates 
that they approve). That could be relevant in IRV too, if someone would start 
merketing IRV using the Plurality criterion.

But in general I lean in the direction that in most cases (e.g. in Burlington) 
people will use ranked methods in some quite sincere way and they do not worry 
about the details, like IRV strategies or Plurality criterion.

However, even without stategy and property discussions, some voters may be 
tempted to truncate just because they get the idea (maybe from their 
traditional voting methods) that marking some candidate on the ballot will give 
him some points. But that would be based on lack of understanding and not on 
the properties on the method in question. I think the correct message to voters 
in most ranked method based elections is to encourage them not to truncate but 
rank all ralevant (good and less good) candidates sincerely.

 
 The thought that Plurality itself (satisfaction of it, or failures of it) 
 can be exploited by voters is strange to me.

Pluraity criterion can at least play a role in some strategies. Sincere 
rankings are 49:A, 48:BC, 3:CB. If the three C supporters truncate, Plurality 
criterion says that (former Condorcet winner) B can not win any more. Plurality 
criterion does not say that C must win, but if it does (as in some Condorcet 
methods), then those three CB voters have a working strategy.

Also the wording and intent of Plurality criterion may lead people to think 
that by not ranking some candidates at all, they can decrease the chancs of 
those candidates to win (never mind if the voters are rational or not).

Juho



 
 Kevin
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-12 Thread Juho Laatu
On 11.11.2012, at 18.16, Chris Benham wrote:

 [robert bristow-johnson wrote:] the most realistic path to accomplishing 
 that is *not* to advocate a method 
 that cannot be explained to citizen-legislators.
 
 Yes, but it also helps to advocate a method that opponents can't  easily 
 ridicule
 with bad examples.

Which methods don't have any such bad examples that can be used for negative 
marketing? ;-)

Juho
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-11 Thread Juho Laatu
On 11.11.2012, at 18.33, Chris Benham wrote:

 Kevin Venzke wrote:
 
 Margins, it seems to me, is DOA as a proposal due to the Plurality criterion.
 That 35 AB, 25 B, 40 C would elect A is too counter-intuitive.
 
 I agree. For those who don't know, the Plurality criterion says that if  X is 
 ranked
 strictly above all other candidates on more ballots than Y is ranked above 
 any candidates,
 then Y must not win. 

Woodall says:  (in http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/ISSUE6/P4.HTM)
If some candidate x has strictly fewer votes in total than some other candidate 
y has first-preference votes, then x should not have greater probability than y 
of being elected.

Wikipedia says:
If the number of ballots ranking A as the first preference is greater than the 
number of ballots on which another candidate B is given any preference, then 
A's probability of winning must be no less than B's.

Plurality criterion assumes implicit approval (given any preference) of 
ranked candidates (definitions above have some differences). In that sense it 
adds something extra to pure ranking.

If one wants to have an approval cutoff in the ballot, an alternative approach 
is to have an explicit approval cutoff. Explicit cutoff allows voters to rank 
also candidates that they do not approve. Those explicit approvals would be 
taken into account when counting the results (maybe in the spirit of the 
Plurality criterion). Implicit cutoff (if voters know of its existence) may 
encourage truncation, which means losing some preference information.

Typically the definitions of winning votes based Condorcet methods do not 
contain any reference to implicit approval, and usually they don't have any 
specific emphasis on the last and one but last position. But of course, if they 
meet Plurality criterion, then they will respect rankings or rankings above the 
last position as described in the Plurality criterion.

In the given example there was an assumption (in the spirit of the Plurality 
criterion) that all voters who voted KL, did not approve M and N, and they all 
approved L. That may not be the case if voters are not aware that this is how 
their vote will be interpreted, or they may not follow this rule even if they 
knew it.

I wonder if the voters should be told about the Plurality criterion or if that 
should be hidden from them (to avoid them rankig only those candidates that 
they approve / want to promote). In some startegies that information may be 
useful to them. But losing information because of truncation (in an election 
that has no meaningful strategy problems) is harmful.

Juho



 
 http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Plurality_criterion
 I like a more general standard that says that if  X both pairwise beats Y and 
 positionally
 dominates Y, then Y mustn't win.
 
 Chris Benham
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Fwd: 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-09 Thread Juho Laatu
Resent. Also I seem to have some problems getting my mails through on the list.

Juho


Begin forwarded message:

 From: Juho Laatu
 Date: 8. 11 2012 20.32.01 UTC+2.00
 To: EM list
 Subject: Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet
 
 On 8.11.2012, at 18.55, Chris Benham wrote:
 
 Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (1 Oct 2012):
 
 my spin is similar.  Ranked Pairs simply says that some elections (or 
 runoffs) speak more loudly than others.  those with higher margins are 
 more definitive in expressing the will of the electorate than elections 
 with small margins.  of course, a margin of zero is a tie and this says 
 *nothing* regarding the will of the electorate, since it can go either way.
 
 the reason i like margins over winning votes is that the margin, in vote 
 count, is the product of the margin as a percent (that would be a 
 measure of the decisiveness of the electorate) times the total number of 
 votes (which is a measure of how important the election is).  so the 
 margin in votes is the product of salience of the race times how 
 decisive the decision is.
 
 Say there are 3 candidates and the voters have the option to fully rank them,
 but instead they all just choose to vote FPP-style thus:
 
  
 49: A
 48: B
 03: C
  
 Of course the only possible winner is A. Now say the election is held again 
 (with
 the same voters and candidates), and the B voters change to BC giving:
 
 49: A
 48: BC
 03: C
 
 Now to my mind this change adds strength to no candidate other than C, so 
 the winner 
 should either stay the same or change to C. Does anyone disagree?
 
 The change of 48 vote fragments from C=A to CA adds strength to C and 
 adds weakness to A. Condorcet methods often concentrate on the strength of 
 losses to other candidates.
 
  
 So how do you (Robert or whoever the cap fits) justify to the A voters (and 
 any fair-minded
 person not infatuated with the Margins pairwise algorithm) that the new 
 Margins winner is B??
 
 Candidate A now loses to one candidate in a pairwise comparison instead of 
 winning all others, so A might not win this time.
 
  
 The pairwise comparisons: BC 48-3,  CA 51-49,  AB 49-48.
 Ranked Pairs(Margins) gives the order BCA. 
 
 I am happy with either A or C winning, but a win for C might look odd to 
 people accustomed
 to FPP and/or IRV.
  
 *If* we insist on a Condorcet method that  uses only information contained 
 in the pairwise
 matrix (and so ignoring all positional or approval information) then 
 *maybe* Losing Votes
 is the best way to weigh the pairwise results. (So the strongest pairwise 
 results are those where
 the loser has the fewest votes and, put the other way, the weakest results 
 are those where the
 loser gets the most votes).
 
 With sincre votes the implications of the result in real life after the 
 election (strongest defeat / strength of opposition against the winner in 
 this case) is one good approach to determining which method is the most 
 sensible one. In the example all candidates lose to one other candidate (= 
 the candidate that is the strongest opponent in opposition).
 
 - Margins measure the strength of opposition as how many more supporters 
 does the opposition have (when compared to the number of supporters of the 
 winner)
 
 - Proportions measure the strength of opposition as how many times more 
 supporters does the opposition have (when compared to the number of 
 supporters of the winner)
 
 - Losing Votes measure the strength of opposition as how many people would 
 defend the winner (assuming that opposition has more supporters, but not 
 putting any weight on how many)
 
 - Winning Votes measure the strength of opposition as how many people would 
 oppose the winner (assuming that oppostion has more supporters, but not 
 putting any weight on how many defenders there are)
 
 All these make at least some sense in real life. But losing and winning votes 
 are somewhat limited in the sense that the number of (respectively) winning 
 or losing votes has no impact on the strength/weakness of the winner.
 
 My first concern with the nature of sincere margins as a way to measure the 
 quality of the winner as ability to defend against oppostion is if 
 proportions make more sense than margins or not. Margins are simpler. 
 Proportions say that 49-48 defeat is weaker than 48-47 defeat.
 
 (One additional interesting question is what all the ties mean. If we use the 
 pairwise matrix only and assume sincerity, maybe the default interpretation 
 is that all the ties are intentional (not e.g. a result of voters being too 
 tired to mark all their sincere opinions in the ballot).)
 
 Juho
 
 
  
 In the example Losing Votes elects A. Winning Votes elects C which I'm fine 
 with, but I don't
 like Winning Votes for other reasons.
 
 Chris Benham
  
  
  
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-10-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 6.10.2012, at 0.03, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 10/05/2012 12:12 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 And even in the three-categories classification, it's hard to find
 any objectively best method.
 
 
 The third category was quality of the outcome under honesty. For
 this category only, finding the best method is straight forward in
 the sense that one can freely decide what the criterion of the best
 candidate is in each election.
 
 The third category is both easy and hard. It's easy in that if you know what 
 society wants, the answer presents itself readily (unless the desideratum is 
 very indirect or statistical). It's hard in that you have to know what's 
 best. Is an utilitarian approach best? Sum-of-utilities? Mean-utilities? Is 
 equality and fairness valued in itself, thus possibly leading to a preference 
 for candidates everybody thinks is good enough in favor of those some love 
 and some hate? Or is utility hidden or incommensurable to begin with? Perhaps 
 the best one can do is make a hindsight prediction based on foresight data, 
 like in the OD_Ranking link I gave. In any event, there's no out of nothing 
 way to find the correct metric, I think.

Yes, one always has to understand the needs and make the decision based on 
those needs. There are for example the two classical categories, 
ranked/majority and rated/utility based categories. And then, wide support vs. 
first preference support etc.

Maybe third category definitions may include already some well established 
strategic concerns in the sense that even though one would think that some 
utility/ratings based function would be ideal, one uses a majority based 
function because one thinks that majority is the way to rule competitive 
societies anyway (since opposition that has majority would be too difficult or 
too unfair to suppress). But I guess this is still a sincere definition of who 
should win with sincere votes.

 
 The second category was resistance to noise and strategy. It is
 difficult to estimate how much protection there should be against
 each threat scenario. It is easier to find the correct answers after
 the method has been in use for a while (in the given environment).
 
 If you (the election method implementer) only get one shot, that makes it 
 more difficult still, because it would generally be advantageous to err on 
 the side of caution so that arguments similar to those against IRV don't get 
 used against your method, or so that the method doesn't perpetuate two-party 
 rule (which you won't know until the method is actually used); but assuming 
 you're on the Pareto front, each hardening within this category will lead to 
 a weakening of the other two.
 
 The first ctegory was consistency with itself. Maybe this can be
 measured somehow, although opinions on what is good may be
 subjective.
 
 Yes. Say you have to decide between margins and wv for the Ranked Pairs rule. 
 Let's disregard strategy susceptibility for now for the sake of illustrating 
 the point. Then the wv version passes Plurality while the margins version 
 passes symmetric completion. Which do you want? I can't see pure reasoning 
 finding the answer to that. Rather, it would appear to be a matter of 
 societal preference. (IMHO, Plurality seems to be more serious than 
 symmetric completion, but then I do prefer wv.)

In this category we are really talking about personal preferences. There are 
many criteria that can be used to point out paradoxes (that may also violate 
the chosen third category rule). All methods have some paradoxes and therefore 
it may be just a question of good positive and negative marketing which method 
gets the most negative points from the audience in the first category. Both 
plurality and symmetric completion could be used. I guess one could also reject 
all Condorcet methods since the possibility of cyclic opinions in the results 
is unpleasant to many. (Woodall says that all methods should meet Plurality but 
I don't see Plurality as a requirement, not even for majority methods.)

If we first decide what third category rule to use and what second category 
adjustments are needed to make the method work well, then what do the remaining 
first category decisions look like? Do they work against the chosen third and 
second category approaches? Do they make the method better? Or do they make the 
method better in the eyes of the audience? Maybe we could choose which one of 
the otherwise equally good methods we would use. Or maybe first category would 
tell us which methods are politically possible (not too much confusion or 
opposition).

 
 Summing up all three properties to determine which system is best
 could be done in theory, but is of course quite complex.
 
 Hence my reference to Pareto fronts. It's conservative - retaining lots of 
 methods that could be excluded if we knew how to compare the category 
 elements - but seems to be the best we can do without actually knowing how to 
 compare.
 
 I

Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-05 Thread Juho Laatu
On 5.10.2012, at 6.45, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 On Thu, Oct 4, 2012 at 6:51 PM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 On 4.10.2012, at 23.53, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 
 I think you recommended Symmetrical ICT for informational polling. I guess 
 you like and trust it within that framework.
 
 I like and trust Symmetrical ICT within every framework.
 
 In official public elections, I like and trust Symmetrical ICT.
 
 What I don't trust, in official public elections is the people who own
 and operate the machines that do the machine balloting, and the
 computerized counting. That's the trust reason why I don't propose
 any rank-balloting method for official public elections.
 
 We went through this already once.
 
 Yes.
 
 My opinion was that machine balloting can be avoided if needed. Computerized 
 counting is not a problem if the (securely recorded) ballots are public, or 
 if many parties can double-check the results.
 
 As you said, we've already covered that topic.  I refer you to my
 postings in the earlier discussion. So you want 150 million ballots to
 be public.

Yes, or alternatively available to few neutral parties. In many Condorcet 
methods this could also mean availability of the pairwise preference matrices 
of each polling station / vote recording station.

 What, you mean copies of the electronic recording are
 made public?

Yes, electronic versions.

 You have great faith in the honesty of the recording.

Not necessarily (you tell me, since I guess you assume your home country here), 
but I think that recording of rankings or ratings is not much more dishonest 
than recording bullet votes or approvals.

 ...the process between the voting and this 150 million-ballot record.
 
 As I said before, an Approval count can be publicly watched. Not just
 the making of an allegedly-honest electronic recording of rankings,
 but the actual final approval tallies in an Approval election, with
 marking-pen on paper. When the actual result can be arrived at, via
 simple tallying, in public, in the open, in front of observers from
 the various parties, and recorded and televised by cameras belonging
 to each party, Approval is incomparably, qualitatively, more
 fraud-secure than any Condorcet method could be.

I wonder where the difference is. Simple bullet votes are easy in the sense 
that one could collect them into piles for each candidate and then count the 
number of ballots in each pile. In Approval the process could be to tick the 
marked candidates of each ballot on a computer screen. In Condorcet the process 
could be to tick the marked candidates of each ballot on a computer screen, in 
the given order. The results could be double-checked by another counter and 
continuously monitored by others, physically and electronically.

Juho


 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.10.2012, at 7.49, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 You said:
 
 , maybe the question if you recommend the voters to rank sincerely or
 if you recommend them to sometimes use the top ties (although the
 candidates are not equally good).
 
 [endquote]
 
 Good question. In a public election, I'd emphasize that their best
 strategy in a u/a election is to equal top rank all of the
 acceptables, and to not rank any accceptables.

Ok, this is maybe where our thouhts differ. My target level with ranked methods 
is to be able to tell the voters that there indeed are some strategic 
possibilities, at least theoretical ones, but for them it is safe enough and 
their best general strategy to rank the candidates sincerely. I don't like the 
idea of recommending voters not to give their opinion about the candidates. Not 
giving one's sincere opinions may infroduce more problems than it solves. And 
it certainly makes the outcome of the election worse in the case that there was 
after all no need to vote strategically.

Maybe you don't worry about recommending voters to turn strategic in Condorcet 
elections since you dont like (or trust) Condorcet methods very much anyway. I 
think that a considerable part of the benefits of ranked methods would be lost 
if people would have to resort to strategic voting, and not indicate sincerely 
which candidates are good.

Maybe your answer is that Condorcet methods are so vulnerable to strategies 
that the voters must either vote strategically or fall prey to the strategists. 
I guess we'll just have to wait and see. There are many TTR and IRV elections 
where people generally vote sincerely, but one never knows. Of course this 
depends to some extent also on the society in question.

 in the unimproved Condorcet versions, you'd never really
 know what to do. You'd have to try to judge whether some acceptables
 are much more winnable than others, so that refusing to top-rank Y (an
 acceptable) is justified because Y isnt likely to win anyway, and
 top-ranking hir could make X (another acceptable) lose.
 
 That's a problem that you'd never have to worry about in Symmetrical
 ICT. It's the old lesser-evil dilemma of FBC-failing methods.

As I said, to me the most interesting strategic thinking related question in 
Condorcet is if one can honestly recommend sincere voting as the best general 
strategy to the voters. In Symmetrical ICT, with your advice to the voters, 
voters would have to worry whether to tell that their favourite is better than 
the compromise or if they should vote for a tie (and not support their 
favourite over the compromise).

 You might say that Symmetrical ICT's u/a strategy sounds a lot like
 Approval. Yes, and the fact that the best that you can get, in u/a
 strategy, in rank methods, is simply Approval strategy  is another
 good reason to propose Approval (or maybe Score) instead of any rank
 method.

Maybe you promote Symmetrical ICT because that helps you promoting Approval 
over the Condorcet methods, i.e. that there is a need to flatten your 
preferences to the level of Approval anyway. :-)

More seriously, my point is still that the best promise of Condorcet methods is 
that people might be able to give full sincere rankings in competitive 
elections. And that (e.g.) FBC properties of some traditional Condorcet methods 
may be good enough to allow voters to vote sincerely. Maybe you think the same 
way, except that for you the line of defence is at the level of Approval.

 You asked me how I'd instruct a voter. But you know that I don't
 propose any rank method for official public elecions.

Yes, I already commented that above. :-)

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.10.2012, at 16.18, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 You said:
 
 Maybe you don't worry about recommending voters to turn strategic in
 Condorcet elections since you don't like (or trust) Condorcet methods
 very much anyway.
 
 [endquote]
 
 That isn't true. Symmetrical iCT is a Condorcet method, and I like and
 trust Symmetrical ICT.

I think you recommended Symmetrical ICT for informational polling. I guess you 
like and trust it within that framework.

 You said:
 
 I think that a considerable part of the benefits of ranked methods
 would be lost if people would have to resort to strategic voting, and
 not indicate sincerely which candidates are good.
 
 [endquote]
 
 Good point. So then, you're therefore changing your proposal from
 margins to Approval, right?

Probably not, unless you manage to arrange some Condorcet elections and spread 
the message of strategic voting well enough. Hopefuly also Approval elections 
and good propaganda in the reverse direction. :-)

 You said:
 
 I guess we'll just have to wait and see. There are many TTR and IRV
 elections where people generally vote sincerely, but one never knows.
 
 [endquote]
 
 One can listen to what voters say. Where IRV is used for official
 public elections, voters say that they favorite-bury, so as to not
 waste their vote.

References?

 We've already made a pact: I won't tell you the strategy-inclinations
 of voters where you reside, and you won't tell me the
 strategy-inclinations in the U.S.

What was that?

 More seriously, my point is still that the best promise of Condorcet methods 
 is that people might be able to give full sincere rankings in competitive 
 elections.
 
 Yes, the promise of Symmetrical ICT is that it encourages sincere
 ranking, unlike unimproved Condorcet.

I believe you recommended voters to be sincere in one (not so competitive) 
election. In the previous mail you said I'd emphasize that their best strategy 
in a u/a election is to equal top rank all of the acceptables, and to not rank 
any accceptables. Maybe you think that this is the best level of sincerity 
that Condorcet methods can achieve.

 We've agreed to disagree
 about which one of us has more familiarity with and contact with
 American voters.

I disagree. :-)

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-10-04 Thread Juho Laatu
 And even in the three-categories classification, it's hard to find any 
 objectively best method.


The third category was quality of the outcome under honesty. For this 
category only, finding the best method is straight forward in the sense that 
one can freely decide what the criterion of the best candidate is in each 
election.

The second category was resistance to noise and strategy. It is difficult to 
estimate how much protection there should be against each threat scenario. It 
is easier to find the correct answers after the method has been in use for a 
while (in the given environment).

The first ctegory was consistency with itself. Maybe this can be measured 
somehow, although opinions on what is good may be subjective.

Summing up all three properties to determine which system is best could be done 
in theory, but is of course quite complex.

Condorcet comparison methods are relevant in all three categories. Maybe the 
ability to separate comparison methods from the rest of the method makes 
discussion one step easeir / more structured.

I guess the most discussed topic around comparison methods has been strategy 
resistance (category two). Many of the comparison methods are so simple that 
category one doesn't cause major problems. In category three there might be 
something more to discuss. Also soft / heuristic approaches could be valid (in 
addition to the traditional simple and hard ones (that may be easier to define 
and agree)).

Juho


On 4.10.2012, at 22.44, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 10/02/2012 12:50 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 I just note that there are many approaches to making the pairwise
 comparisons.
 
 - One could use proportions instead of margins =  A/B isntead of
 A-B.
 
 - If one measures the number of poeple who took position, one would
 have to know which ones voted for a tie intentionally, and which ones
 voted for a tie because they thought those candidates were already
 irrelevat, or because they didn't know the candidates, or were just
 too lazy to mark all the details in the ballot. An wlternative would
 be to assume that any tie is interpreted as an intentionally marked
 tie. A candidate taht is not known by many voters probably will not
 be ranked high anyway, so there may be no need for adjustments.
 
 - Winning votes counts the amount of opposition, but doesn't care
 about the amount of support.
 
 - Also other more fine-tuned approaches to making the pairwise
 comparisons could be developed. Or maybe rough and simple rules are
 easier to justify.
 
 - Truncation as a way to make the results of the truncated candidates
 worse is not a nice option because it may lead to people not ranking
 the candidates, which is contrary to the targets of ranked voting (=
 collect all preference opinions). The worst case would be bullet
 voting.
 
 My earlier voting software has a number of ways of doing Condorcet 
 comparisons, although most are pretty obscure. These are:
 
 - wv: winning votes, number of voters on the victorious side, 0 if losing
 - lv: losing votes, number of voters in total minus number of voters on the 
 losing side, or 0 if this is the losing side
 - margins: maximum of AB - BA and 0.
 - lmargins: AB - BA, so negative numbers are permitted.
 - pairwise opposition: number of voters on this side (even if this is the 
 losing side).
 - wtv: same as wv, but ties also count (on both sides).
 - tourn_wv: 1 if this is the winning side, otherwise 0.
 - tourn_sym: 1 if this is the winning side, 0 for a tie, otherwise -1.
 - fractional_wv: (AB) / (AB + BA) if on the winning side, otherwise 0.
 - relative_margins: (AB - BA) / (AB + B/A)
 - keener_margins: h((AB + 1) / (AB + BA + 2)) where h(x) = 0.5 + 0.5 
 sign(x - 0.5) * sqrt(|2x - 1), as per 
 meyer.math.ncsu.edu/Meyer/Talks/OD_RankingCharleston.pdf .
 
 It's not that hard to find different ways to compare Condorcet. I think 
 someone on the list had an idea of using a statistical comparison, i.e. to 
 say AB if A beats B with a certain level of confidence (as one would reason 
 with polls), BA if B beats a within the same level, and unknown otherwise.
 
 Perhaps the important part is not really what kind of interpretation one uses 
 as how well it goes with the three categories I have talked about earlier. 
 Well, both might be important. Say you had an interpretation that gave second 
 place votes much more weight (e.g. AB plus two times A votes in second 
 place) than others. Even if this interpretation had some criterion-failure 
 avoiding properties, it could easily lead to people doubting the legitimacy 
 of the method with such a seemingly arbitrary component to it.
 
 And even in the three-categories classification, it's hard to find any 
 objectively best method. You can find Pareto-dominating and 
 Pareto-dominated methods. For instance, unless the societal value under 
 sincerity of Black (Condorcet/Borda) is better than, say, Ranked Pairs, 
 Ranked Pairs would Pareto-dominate Black and so we

Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.10.2012, at 23.53, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 I think you recommended Symmetrical ICT for informational polling. I guess 
 you like and trust it within that framework.
 
 I like and trust Symmetrical ICT within every framework.
 
 In official public elections, I like and trust Symmetrical ICT.
 
 What I don't trust, in official public elections is the people who own
 and operate the machines that do the machine balloting, and the
 computerized counting. That's the trust reason why I don't propose
 any rank-balloting method for official public elections.

We went through this already once. My opinion was that machine balloting can be 
avoided if needed. Computerized counting is not a problem if the (securely 
recorded) ballots are public, or if many parties can double-check the results.

 We've agreed to disagree
 about which one of us has more familiarity with and contact with
 American voters.
 
 I disagree. :-)
 
 Do you mean that you disagree, in keeping with our agreement to
 disagree, or do you mean that you don't agree that you agreed to
 disagree.

Wasn't it an agreement that we disagree? If it wasn't then I must disagree now. 
:-)

 
 If it is the latter, then do you disagree that you agree to disagree
 because you agree?

You are deviating to the actual content. I'm certain I'd disagree also without 
this disagreement. :-)

 
 If so, then you agree with me about which one of us has more
 familiarity and contact with American voters.

I think we already quite certainly agree to disagree. And that's an agreement 
that we can agree. :-)

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-10-03 Thread Juho Laatu
On 3.10.2012, at 3.35, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 On Tue, Oct 2, 2012 at 12:55 AM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 On 2.10.2012, at 4.37, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 
 A) What is it that is gained by using traditional (unimproved)
 Condorcet instead of Symmetrical Improved Condorcet?
 
 The downsides of unimproved are:
 
 .1. FBC failure (though unimproved-Condorcet advocates speculate
 that people won't mind)
 
 The traditional interpretation of ranked votes may well support FBC well 
 enough in the classical Condorcet methods.
 
 Yes, that's what I meant by speculation.

It is well known that it is impossible to meet all ciriteria at the same time. 
Typical election methods can't  be made fully strategy free. Therefore the best 
approach must be to meet some criteria not 100% but well enough.

 
 And note that that speculation is coming from someone who likewise
 accepts Margins' failure of the Plurality Criterion. How often Margins
 fails Plurality isn't the issue. The examples in which it does will be
 widely shared with the public, by the opponents of any enactment
 proposal for any method that violates that criterion (or any other
 embarrassment-criterion).
 
 
 Speculation that voters won't be affected by a strategy-incentive is
 one form that unimproved Condorcet rationalization and self-deception
 can take.
 
 But my purpose, at this stage of the procedure isn't to argue about
 the criteria and properties, so much as to establish what unimproved
 Condorcet advocates think make unimproved Condorcet so good as to
 outweigh the disadvantages that I listed.
 
 By the way, of course it's better to call a method by the name used by
 its advocates. We have a term for the more EM-popular (unimproved)
 Condorcet versions: Strong Condorcet. That's the term that I'll
 start using. It refers to Beatpath, Ranked-Pairs, River, Goldfish,
 Kemeny, and VoteFair. Maybe other similar methods too. Sometimes I'll
 abbreviate Strong Condorcet to Strong.

I'd recommend to make the separation by using your new term improved 
Condorcet (or maybe some more descriptive name) and leave the traditional 
Condorcet approach as it is and how people usually refer to it, i.e. without 
any additional name when one refers to the basic rankings. Or maybe use generic 
words like traditional or regular when needed. I think you may be about to 
break your own good rule of using names that the advocates of the named object 
use.

 
 
 .2. Interpretation of equal-top and equal-bottom ranking is
 contrary to the voter's preferences, intent and wishes.
 
 I guess by default the meaning of equal-top and equal-bottom ranking is to 
 rank the candidates equal.
 
 Wrong.
 
 Ranking X and Y in 1st place, or ranking W and Z in last place
 additionally means that that voter prefers that the winner be X or Y,
 or that the voter would rather that the winner be someone else other
 than W or Z.

That's true already without any additions.

Juho


 
 And, you see, that's where unimproved Condorcet --excuse me, I meant
 Strong Condorcet--parts ways with what the voter prefers.
 
 I've explained this before, here at EM. I'll explain it again if requested.
 
 The voter may have interest to cast a stronger vote where the equal-top and 
 equal-bottom rankings have some additional strength
 
 ...such as being interpreted and counted in keeping with that voter's
 preferences, intent and wishes? Yes.
 
 , but that's another story
 
 Indeed,  in Strong, that is indeed another story. Strong has its own
 story, and it isn't about what the voter actually prefers.
 
 
 , and not the default interpretation of ranked votes.
 
 You mean _your_ default interpretation of ranked votes. From what you
 said, your default interpretation of equal top ranking disregards
 the voter's preference for the top-ranked candidates over the other
 candidates. Indeed, that is a different story.
 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-03 Thread Juho Laatu
You explanation sounds like a pretty regular ranked ballot approach. If I rank 
U and V second, I want them to lose to the firsts and win the rest.

Juho


On 3.10.2012, at 6.06, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Juho:
 
 In improved Condorcet, the voter who equal top ranks X and Y, or who
 equal bottom ranks W and Z, doesn't have any more power to vote one
 over the other, or to not do so, than any otther voter has to vote one
 candidate over the other or no do so.
 
 Nor does a vote for X over Y, or for Y over X, counted for the ballot
 of a voter top ranking X and Y, have any more power or effect as a
 pairwise vote cast by any voter between any two candidates.
 Likewise for the equal bottom ranking voter who ranks W and Z at
 bottom. (at bottom means not voted over anyone).
 
 So then, what makes Improved Condorcet different from unimproved
 Condorcet?  How is it more favorable to the equal top or equal bottom
 ranking voter, without giving undue power to that voter?:
 
 With respect to X and Y, hir ballot is counted in hir beat interest,
 in keeping with hir preferences, intent and wishes.
 
 As for what that means, I'll say it again:
 
 If you rank X and Y both in 1st place, that means that you'd rather
 elect one of them (either one of them) than anyone whom you don't rank
 in 1st place.
 
 If you rank W and Z at bottom, that means that you'd rather elect
 anyone whom you rank above bottom, instead of W or Z.
 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-03 Thread Juho Laatu
Yes, it seems that the interpretation of the ballots and sincere wishes of the 
voters are the same in both traditional ranked ballots and your improved 
approach. And the interpretation is the same for all ranks, except that the 
first and last ranks do not have any candidates above or below.

Juho


On 3.10.2012, at 13.53, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 3:25 AM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 You explanation sounds like a pretty regular ranked ballot approach. If I 
 rank U and V second, I want them to lose to the firsts and win the rest.
 
 Quite so.
 
 And (regarding your 2nd-ranked candidates), it's because you want
 someone else (your 1st ranked) to win more than you want your 2nd
 ranked to win, and because you also want your 2nd ranked to win more
 than you want your 3rd ranked to win--That's what makes the top and
 bottom rank positions different from all of the other rank positions.
 
 Your top-ranked candidates: You'd prefer that they win instead of anyone else.
 
 Your bottom-ranked candidates. You'd prefer that anyone but them wins.
 
 Neither of those things can be said for any other rank position, other
 than top or bottom rank position. For the reason that you stated in
 your above-quoted text.
 
 That's why, in keeping with what the voter would prefer and wishes
 with hir equal top and equal bottom rankings, Symmetrical ICT
 interprets equal top and bottom ranking as it does. That's why no
 other rank positions are treated in that way--because the voter intent
 and preference that I refer to at top and bottom rank position doesn't
 apply at any other rank position.
 
 Because, when ranking X and Y in 1st place, you'd prefer that the
 winner be from {X,Y}, then you don't want either to pairwise-beat the
 other, which could change the winner from someone in {X,Y} to someone
 else, like your last choice. So Symmetrical ICT lets you have your
 ballot counted as automatically voting between X and Y in such a way
 as to keep either from beating the other.
 
 It's your vote. It's your ballot, and it's your pairwise vote between
 X and Y. It should be counted in your best interest, in keeping with
 what you prefer and intend, when ranking X and Y equal top, or when
 ranking W and Z equal bottom.
 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 
 
 
 Juho
 
 
 On 3.10.2012, at 6.06, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 
 Juho:
 
 In improved Condorcet, the voter who equal top ranks X and Y, or who
 equal bottom ranks W and Z, doesn't have any more power to vote one
 over the other, or to not do so, than any otther voter has to vote one
 candidate over the other or no do so.
 
 Nor does a vote for X over Y, or for Y over X, counted for the ballot
 of a voter top ranking X and Y, have any more power or effect as a
 pairwise vote cast by any voter between any two candidates.
 Likewise for the equal bottom ranking voter who ranks W and Z at
 bottom. (at bottom means not voted over anyone).
 
 So then, what makes Improved Condorcet different from unimproved
 Condorcet?  How is it more favorable to the equal top or equal bottom
 ranking voter, without giving undue power to that voter?:
 
 With respect to X and Y, hir ballot is counted in hir beat interest,
 in keeping with hir preferences, intent and wishes.
 
 As for what that means, I'll say it again:
 
 If you rank X and Y both in 1st place, that means that you'd rather
 elect one of them (either one of them) than anyone whom you don't rank
 in 1st place.
 
 If you rank W and Z at bottom, that means that you'd rather elect
 anyone whom you rank above bottom, instead of W or Z.
 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-03 Thread Juho Laatu
Do you assume that the voters will know that the method will treat tied first 
and tied last in a different way than tied middle? If they know, then you could 
say that the interpretation and sincere wishes of the voters are different for 
the middle preferences. (In that case, probably you should include that 
difference also in the definition of what the ballots mean.)

Juho


On 3.10.2012, at 14.56, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 7:24 AM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 
 Yes, it seems that the interpretation of the ballots and sincere wishes of 
 the voters are the same in both traditional ranked ballots and your improved 
 approach.
 
 First of all, it isn't _my_ improved approach. It's Kevin Venzke's
 improved approach.
 
 (My innovation was to do it at bottom as well as at top. In fact, I'd
 proposed it at bottom long ago. At that time I called it power
 truncation).
 
 Yes, the wishes of the voters don't change, just because one count
 rule respects their wishes and another doesn't. You're right about
 that.
 
 But no, the interpretation of ballots is not the same in Improved
 Condorcet and unimproved Condorcet. Improved Condorcet respects the
 preferences, intent and wishes of equal top and equal bottom ranking
 voters. Unimproved Condorcet doesn't respect their intent and wishes.
 
 Let me again state the definition of Symmetrical ICT, to show how it
 differs from the versions of unimproved Condorcet:
 
 Symmetrical ICT:
 
 (XY) means the number of people ranking X over Y.
 (YX) means the number of peoiple ranking Y over X.
 (X=Y)T means the number of people ranking X and Y at top.
 (X=Y)B means the number of people ranking X and Y at bottom.
 
 X beats Y iff (XY) + (X=Y)B  (YX) + (X=Y)T.
 
 [end of Symmetrical ICT definition]
 
 So no, Improved Condorcet and unimproved Condorcet do not interpret
 ballots in the same way.
 
 And the interpretation is the same for all ranks, except that the first and 
 last ranks do not have any candidates above or below.
 
 Yes, and that's why Symmetrical ICT treats equal top and equal bottom
 ranking differently, in keeping with (as I said) the preferences,
 intent and wishes of the equal top and equal bottom ranking voters.
 
 Some here don't like to hear this: The emperor (unimproved Condorcet)
 doesn't have any clothes.
 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 
 
 
 
 
 Juho
 
 
 On 3.10.2012, at 13.53, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 
 On Wed, Oct 3, 2012 at 3:25 AM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 You explanation sounds like a pretty regular ranked ballot approach. If I 
 rank U and V second, I want them to lose to the firsts and win the rest.
 
 Quite so.
 
 And (regarding your 2nd-ranked candidates), it's because you want
 someone else (your 1st ranked) to win more than you want your 2nd
 ranked to win, and because you also want your 2nd ranked to win more
 than you want your 3rd ranked to win--That's what makes the top and
 bottom rank positions different from all of the other rank positions.
 
 Your top-ranked candidates: You'd prefer that they win instead of anyone 
 else.
 
 Your bottom-ranked candidates. You'd prefer that anyone but them wins.
 
 Neither of those things can be said for any other rank position, other
 than top or bottom rank position. For the reason that you stated in
 your above-quoted text.
 
 That's why, in keeping with what the voter would prefer and wishes
 with hir equal top and equal bottom rankings, Symmetrical ICT
 interprets equal top and bottom ranking as it does. That's why no
 other rank positions are treated in that way--because the voter intent
 and preference that I refer to at top and bottom rank position doesn't
 apply at any other rank position.
 
 Because, when ranking X and Y in 1st place, you'd prefer that the
 winner be from {X,Y}, then you don't want either to pairwise-beat the
 other, which could change the winner from someone in {X,Y} to someone
 else, like your last choice. So Symmetrical ICT lets you have your
 ballot counted as automatically voting between X and Y in such a way
 as to keep either from beating the other.
 
 It's your vote. It's your ballot, and it's your pairwise vote between
 X and Y. It should be counted in your best interest, in keeping with
 what you prefer and intend, when ranking X and Y equal top, or when
 ranking W and Z equal bottom.
 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 
 
 
 Juho
 
 
 On 3.10.2012, at 6.06, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 
 Juho:
 
 In improved Condorcet, the voter who equal top ranks X and Y, or who
 equal bottom ranks W and Z, doesn't have any more power to vote one
 over the other, or to not do so, than any otther voter has to vote one
 candidate over the other or no do so.
 
 Nor does a vote for X over Y, or for Y over X, counted for the ballot
 of a voter top ranking X and Y, have any more power or effect as a
 pairwise vote cast by any voter between any two candidates.
 Likewise for the equal bottom ranking voter who ranks W and Z at
 bottom. (at bottom means not voted over

Re: [EM] Let's clear up some confusion

2012-10-03 Thread Juho Laatu
On 3.10.2012, at 20.37, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 (In that case, probably you should include that difference also in the 
 definition of what the ballots mean.)
 
 Wrong. My definition of Symmetrical ICT fully specifies the method and
 its count rule.

No doubt about that. I was interested in if you expect regular voters to know 
that there are special rules on how the top and bottom ties are handled. If 
there is anything interesting left, maybe the question if you recommend the 
voters to rank sincerely or if you recommend them to sometimes use the top ties 
(although the candidates are not equally good).

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-10-01 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.10.2012, at 17.31, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Everyone here agrees that natural (sincere) circular ties would be
 rare.

Quite rare in typical political elections.

 Also, the choice is a lot less clear when there isn't a circular
 tie.

More difficult to think, but can be as clear.

 For those reasons, it matters much less what a rank method does
 when there isn't a CW.

Only because cycles are rare. But if we exclude that viewpoint, then quite as 
important.

 
 I read that Condorcet(margins) fails the Plurality Criterion. Did you
 know that, Juho?

Not one of my favourite criteria (if any are as on/off criteria, since I like 
many criteria but do not require them to be met 100% if there are also other 
important targets to meet).

 
 The Plurality Criterion is one of those embarrassment criteria. It
 could be important because it could be used to easily defeat an
 enactment proposal.

I don't know how well that idea could be sold as negative marketing. There are 
many criteria that sound (or whose name sounds ;-) ) intuitive but that deserve 
a second look.

 That was why I ceased advocating MMPO.   ...along
 with burial strategy.
 
 That's another thing about Margins: It has much more problem with
 burial and truncation to defeat a sincere CW, as compared with wv.

Margins are more vulnerable to some strategies than winning votes, but in some 
other strategies the balance is the other way around. What counts is 
vulnerability in real elections. Margins are quite good.

 And
 wv has a burial problem that its advocates are in denial about too.
 
 By the way, speaking of denial, people at EM are in denial about the
 feasibility problems of rank-methods in general. I've discussed them
 enough that it isn't necessary to explain what I mean about that.

The best test would be to arrange competitive real life Condorcet elections. 
IRV seems to work fine, at least if we ignore the complaints about the 
sensibility of the elimination process. I think I may be in denial although I 
don't know yet what the key problem is that I deny :-).

Juho


 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-10-01 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.10.2012, at 19.16, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 10/01/2012 12:13 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 30.9.2012, at 15.41, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 
 As far as intrinsically Condorcet methods go, Ranked Pairs feels
 simple to me. The only tricky part is the indirect nature of the
 unless it contradicts what you already affirmed step.
 
 To me the biggest problem of path based methods is that there is no very
 good real life explanation to why chains of pairwise victories are so
 important. In real life the idea of not electiong a candidate that would
 lose to someone who would lose to someone etc. doesn't sound like an
 important criterion (since it doesn't talk about what the candidate is
 like or how strong the opposition would be, but about what the set of
 candidates and its network of relations looks like). Probably there will
 never be a long chain of changes from one winner to another in real life.
 
 I don't think you need to go into path logic for Ranked Pairs. Rather, how 
 about this?

Ranked Pairs is based on setting up a complete ranking where the result of one 
candidate may depend on pairwise comparisons of some distant candidates. If 
therere is a large top loop, changes in opinions between A and B may change the 
winner from C to D. In this sense some distant opinons along the paths 
somewhere may influence the goodness of a candidate.

 
 Because of the existence of cycles, it's obvious we need to discard some of 
 the data. So, what data do we discard?

I wouldn't say that we have to discard some data but that we may violate some 
pairwise preference opinions in the sense that the winner may lose some 
pairwise comparisons.

The reason why I don't like word discard is actually related to the fact that 
this makes us too easily think of the end result as a complete ordeing of the 
candidates, where some facts had to be discarded because they did not fit in 
the picture. And here the problem is that group opinions may indeed be cyclic, 
and there is no need to correct them to a transitive order. The used words 
are not that important. But whatever the words, I do stick to the claim that 
group opinions are graphs, not linear orders, and we must decide who the winner 
is, in the presence of cyclic opinions (not by eliminating them, at least not 
in all methods).

(Same comments about terms like breaking cycles.)

 If we have to discard a one-on-one victory, lets discard those that are as 
 narrow, or involve as few voters, as possible.

Yes, it is in most cases better to violate some narrow victories rather than 
strong ones. (We can assume full rankings and skip the few voters criterion 
since it is not essential here and it would introduce new open questions.)

 Hence, we should go down the list of one-on-one contests and add the data 
 they give to our order unless it would produce a cycle. That way, all the 
 decisive contests get counted first and if we have to throw some away, it's 
 the weaker ones.

I can see two approaches here. One is to measure the preference relations of 
each candidate seprately, e.g. how much and to which other candidates someone 
loses and how this influences this candidate's goodness. The other approach 
is that also the pairwise preferences of other unrelated candidates may 
influence the goodness of this candidate. One special case of this second 
approach is to say that the best winner should be picked so that the group 
oinion is first forced into a linear opinion using some criteria, and then the 
first candidate of that order is the winner. Minmax is an example in the first 
category where only the personal properties of each candidate do count.

 
 It's a little IRVish (justifying the method by the way it works rather than 
 the outcome), but still...

I think the part that was method oriented was the formation of the linear 
ordering. The way Ranked Pairs arranges the candidates is however quite 
intuitive and natural (not as heuristic and procedural as IRV). But as 
already said, the intermediate result of a linear order of the candidates is 
not necessary, but just a method specfic trick.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-10-01 Thread Juho Laatu
I just note that there are many approaches to making the pairwise comparisons.

- One could use proportions instead of margins = A/B isntead of A-B.

- If one measures the number of poeple who took position, one would have to 
know which ones voted for a tie intentionally, and which ones voted for a tie 
because they thought those candidates were already irrelevat, or because they 
didn't know the candidates, or were just too lazy to mark all the details in 
the ballot. An wlternative would be to assume that any tie is interpreted as an 
intentionally marked tie. A candidate taht is not known by many voters probably 
will not be ranked high anyway, so there may be no need for adjustments.

- Winning votes counts the amount of opposition, but doesn't care about the 
amount of support.

- Also other more fine-tuned approaches to making the pairwise comparisons 
could be developed. Or maybe rough and simple rules are easier to justify.

- Truncation as a way to make the results of the truncated candidates worse is 
not a nice option because it may lead to people not ranking the candidates, 
which is contrary to the targets of ranked voting (= collect all preference 
opinions). The worst case would be bullet voting.

Juho


On 1.10.2012, at 23.52, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 10/01/2012 08:50 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:
 
 the reason i like margins over winning votes is that the margin, in vote
 count, is the product of the margin as a percent (that would be a
 measure of the decisiveness of the electorate) times the total number of
 votes (which is a measure of how important the election is). so the
 margin in votes is the product of salience of the race times how
 decisive the decision is.
 
 Similarly, one might say that wv is more about the degree of contention about 
 something than the margin of victory. If most people have no opinion about A 
 vs B, but 10 people vote A ahead of B, then that, according to wv, is less 
 important than if, out of a million, ten more people vote A ahead of B than B 
 ahead of A. In the latter case, the contest draws significant attention; in 
 the former, it doesn't.
 
 It's a bit like polling. Say you poll a thousand voters and 990 of them 
 decline to answer. Then that ten answer in favor of A isn't going to carry 
 much weight in favor of A; but if all thousand answer and 510 are in favor of 
 A, that's quite a bit more important.
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-10-01 Thread Juho Laatu
On 2.10.2012, at 4.37, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 A) What is it that is gained by using traditional (unimproved)
 Condorcet instead of Symmetrical Improved Condorcet?
 
 The downsides of unimproved are:
 
 .1. FBC failure (though unimproved-Condorcet advocates speculate
 that people won't mind)

The traditional interpretation of ranked votes may well support FBC well 
enough in the classical Condorcet methods.

 .2. Interpretation of equal-top and equal-bottom ranking is
 contrary to the voter's preferences, intent and wishes.

I guess by default the meaning of equal-top and equal-bottom ranking is to rank 
the candidates equal. The voter may have interest to cast a stronger vote where 
the equal-top and equal-bottom rankings have some additional strength, but 
that's another story, and not the default interpretation of ranked votes.

 Those are two drawbacks. If you advocate unimproved Condorcet, then it
 must offer some advantages--important enough advantages to outweigh
 the two disadvantages listed above.

Simplicity. Lack of interest to truncate one's vote (and lose preference 
information) at the top and at the bottom.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Strong methods (was Re: 3 or more choices - Condorcet)

2012-09-30 Thread Juho Laatu
On 30.9.2012, at 11.56, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 09/29/2012 10:49 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 What is a strong Condorcet method?
 
 Basically, one that gives good results while being resistant to tinkering by 
 the parties (who have greater capacity to coordinate strategy than do the 
 voters, and more to lose under the new regime), and not giving weird results 
 or having weird result dynamics that could be used to discredit the method.

That's a prestty good definition of good. I'd say good results (there may be 
different definitions) with sincere votes, and (if needed) good behaviour in 
the presence of strategists too.

 
 In practice, that means: is cloneproof, passes independence of as much as 
 possible (independence of Smith-dominated alternatives, say), and is monotone.

These criteria could be one set of definitions of a good (sincere) winner. I 
usually do not assume the first two ones since there may be good (sincere) 
winners also outside those criteria. Monotonicity is maybe more natural in the 
Condorcet category.

 
 River would be even better than Ranked Pairs, since River passes independence 
 of Pareto-dominated alternatives and RP doesn't, but River is even less known 
 than Ranked Pairs.
 
 I've put strong in quote marks because I know others may disagree with my 
 priorities. FairVote obviously doesn't consider the having weird result 
 dynamics part important as long as the strangeness can't be exploited by 
 deliberate strategy.

If one looks positively at their criteria, maybe they put strong emphasis on 
the marketability of the method. That marketability may include some tendency 
to favour the large parties.

 
 To digress a bit, I think you could say strong methods go further in 
 satisfying three categories than do not-as-strong methods.
 
 The first is consistency with itself. Nonmonotone methods do badly here. The 
 intuitive idea is that if a method is not monotone (say), then that means 
 that its concept of what is better is lacking - it's like someone who says 
 I'm closer to the city after traveling in the wrong direction. It's 
 important to make clear that whether or not these inconsistencies can be 
 exploited through strategy is not really important. The danger is that a 
 perfectly innocent election will find itself on the wrong side of an 
 inconsistency and so the result will be either inferior (as a result) or less 
 legitimate (because people will say WTF is going on here?).
 Of course, there are some such inconsistencies we have to accept if we want 
 Condorcet.

Yes, it is good if the winner is someone who can be said to be the best 
according to some definitions, and people agree with the sensibility of those 
definitions. This means picking the best winner (with sincere votes), not a 
random winner.

 
 The second is resistance to noise and strategy. Independence of clones fit 
 here, as well as independence of X (Smith-dominated alternatives, 
 Pareto-dominated alternatives, weak IIA). The resistance may protect against 
 strategy - cloneproof methods keep parties from running an army of identical 
 candidates - or improve the outcome when there is no strategy - e.g. by not 
 being affected by the liberal parties' vote-splitting in a replay of the 1988 
 South Korean presidential election.

(I just note that independence of clones can be an interesting topic both when 
discussing behaviour with sincere votes and strategies.)

 
 The third is quality of the outcome under honesty, according to some metric 
 or desired logic. It's hard to say which metric one should pick, 
 unfortunately, and for Ranked Pairs (and Schulze), there's probably no simple 
 metric that the method optimizes. Furthermore, the logic one uses for rated 
 methods probably wouldn't directly fit onto rank methods (because utilities 
 are either unknown or not applicable).

It seems that I assumed above that this category and the first category are 
related. Maybe this category implies also the first category. I.e. there is no 
such good logic of what we desire that would break against the first caregory. 
(Or maybe, if we step outside the Condorcet domain and think about IRV, then 
maybe the idea of kicking the weakest candidate out at every round makes sense 
in some setup??)

 
 I'm not sure where Condorcet compliance fits into the categories above, 
 either. Perhaps it's the third, in a sort of deontological logic that says 
 do whatever you want, but if there's a candidate that would win every 
 runoff, elect him. Perhaps it's a consistency criterion, where the people 
 expect X to win outright if he can win every runoff. Or maybe it's doing 
 without strategy what the voters could do with enough coordination in other 
 methods, easing the burden on those voters - or a way to have the method 
 resist single-group repeal efforts, where electing the CW ensures that if the 
 supporters of a loser tries to repeal or complain, there will always be a 
 greater group of supporters

Re: [EM] Strong methods (was Re: 3 or more choices - Condorcet)

2012-09-30 Thread Juho Laatu
On 30.9.2012, at 16.06, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 09/30/2012 11:47 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 30.9.2012, at 11.56, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 
 In practice, that means: is cloneproof, passes independence of as
 much as possible (independence of Smith-dominated alternatives,
 say), and is monotone.
 
 These criteria could be one set of definitions of a good (sincere)
 winner. I usually do not assume the first two ones since there may be
 good (sincere) winners also outside those criteria. Monotonicity is
 maybe more natural in the Condorcet category.
 
 There might be, but then again, there may also be better outcomes when the 
 method does not get confused by vote-splitting problems (e.g. the Korean 
 election).

Bad clone related problems must be corrected, but different criteria may 
conflict, and one may get similar votes and matrices with or without real 
clones (= politically similar candidates). Therefore one may also meet the 
clone related criteria well enough in order to respect better some other 
requirements.

 In my opinion, even if that works, it won't have the desired effect. 
 Australia shows this.

Maybe Austratlia shows that things could fail. But one could be also lucky, and 
Australia is a quite specific case. One must try and hope that things will work 
out. I believe most countries have some problems in their voting system, and 
usually they could be corrected, but they are not since there is not enough 
political will.

 So the difference between the third and first category is, I think, that the 
 third is about what's good for society in general, while the first is about 
 what makes the voters (and candidates) accept the outcome. The more democracy 
 is about having the losers accept that they've lost, the more important the 
 first category becomes with respect to the third, for instance.

Maybe one more first category related explanation behind promoting IRV is that 
the serial elimination rule looks like a fair fight (where the weakest fighters 
are fairly kicked out of the fight) to many voters :-).

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-09-30 Thread Juho Laatu
On 30.9.2012, at 15.41, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 09/30/2012 12:51 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 i still think that a cycle with a Smith set bigger than
 3 is s unlikely since i still believe that cycles themselves will be
 rare in practice.

...

 Currently, single-winner elections very rarely have cycles and large Smith 
 sets are even more rare.

In typical political environments where people know the candidates or at least 
the parties well, and where there often are also strong established orders like 
teh left-right axis, cycles are indeed quite rare, and cycles bigger than 3 are 
even more rare.

There can be however environments where cycles are somewhat more common. I mean 
environments where all the candidates look quite similar, there are many of 
them, and where there is no strong eastablished political structure that would 
help voters in making decisions. In such an environment there could be random 
loops among the very similar candidates. For example in the 2008 Wikimedia 
borad elections there was a large loop, but not at the top 
(http://meta.wikimedia.org/wiki/Board_elections/2008/Results/en).

But in typical political elections top cycles of 4 should be very rare.

 As far as intrinsically Condorcet methods go, Ranked Pairs feels simple to 
 me. The only tricky part is the indirect nature of the unless it contradicts 
 what you already affirmed step.

To me the biggest problem of path based methods is that there is no very good 
real life explanation to why chains of pairwise victories are so important. In 
real life the idea of not electiong a candidate that would lose to someone who 
would lose to someone etc. doesn't sound like an important criterion (since it 
doesn't talk about what the candidate is like or how strong the opposition 
would be, but about what the set of candidates and its network of relations 
looks like). Probably there will never be a long chain of changes from one 
winner to another in real life.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-09-30 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.10.2012, at 5.05, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 But in typical political elections top cycles of 4 should be very rare.
 
 and my understanding is that Schulze, RP, and Minmax all elect the same 
 candidate for case of a simple 3-choice cycle and, of course, they all elect 
 the same candidate when there is no cycle.

Yes, with three candidates the choice depends only on the used comparison 
method, i.e. margins, winning votes etc.

If there is a fourth candidate outside the 3-choice top cycle, Minmax can elect 
also the fourth candidate if the worst losses of all the cycled candidates are 
worse than that of the fourth candidate. This is also a very rare case. The 
justification behind that choice is that the level of opposition against the 
chosen winner (in favour of any single one of the competitiors) will be lowest 
this way. In Minmax(margins) the fourth candidate would also need the least 
amount of additional votes to become a Condorcet winner.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-09-29 Thread Juho Laatu
What is a strong Condorcet method?

Juho


On 29.9.2012, at 23.11, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 09/28/2012 10:11 PM, dn...@aol.com wrote:
 A  B
 
 Choice C comes along.
 
 C may - head to head ---
 
 1. Beat both
 C  A
 C  B
 2. Lose to both
 A  C
 B  C
 3. Beat A  BUT lose to B
 C  A  B  C
 
 Thus, obviously, a tiebreaker is needed in case 3.
 Obviously perhaps Approval.
 
 i.e. BOTH number votes and YES/NO Approval votes.
 
 Obviously much more complex with 4 or more choices.
 ---
 ANY election reform method in the U.S.A. has to get past the math
 challeged appointed folks in SCOTUS.
 
 i.e. ANY reform must be REALLY SIMPLE.
 
 Condorcet applies for legislative bodies and single or multiple
 executive/judicial offices.
 
 I think Ranked Pairs is the simplest strong Condorcet method. You sort the 
 pairwise victories so that the strongest comes first, then you go down the 
 list, adding that victory to the final order unless it would contradict 
 something you added earlier.
 
 So say you have
 
 100 voters prefer A to B
 80 voters prefer B to C
 85 voters prefer C to A
 
 which would give you:
 
 First the result must place A higher than B. (Okay.)
 Second, the result must place C higher than A. (Okay.)
 Third, the result must place B higher than C... but that's impossible because 
 C is higher than A is higher than B. So skip it.
 
 And the winner is thus C. A comes second, and B third.
 
 -
 
 On the other hand, Schulze is being used more widely, so it's a question of 
 what will be more persuasive: saying this thing is simple, or this thing 
 is used lots of places.
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Juho: I agree to disagree

2012-09-28 Thread Juho Laatu
Ok, thanks for the effort, trying to convince me.

Juho


On 28.9.2012, at 4.47, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 It's time to agree to disagree.
 
 But thank you for demonstrating (as if it needed more demonstrating on
 EM) the impossibility of ever adopting or enacting a rank-method, due
 to the innumerable different methods advocated by rank-method
 advocates, who will never be able to agree on one; and due to the
 innumerable criteria by which they justify their favorite methods.
 
 Mike Ossipoff
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MJ for use on wikipedia?

2012-09-28 Thread Juho Laatu
Since Wikipedia says in http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wikipedia:VOTE that 
voting is used maily to help in building consesus. The polls are thus not 
expected to be competitive. The final decisions are not made based on the poll 
results but in a discussion that the polls should help.

Because of this approach to voting and Wikipedia work in general, the main 
target of the polling seems to be to provide good information on the opinions 
and thereby help the process. It seems to me that one shold focus more on the 
results with sincere votes than on trying to make it impossible for the voters 
to use strategies to falsify the results. If someone will falsify the results 
and people will note that, it is not a problem since the outcome of the poll is 
not a binding one. The srategists would be told that the basic idea of 
Wikipedia is to co-operate, and they are supposed to give sincere answers in 
the polls. People who try to cheat and mislead others probably will not stay in 
the Wikipedia community for very long.

Since the method should be informative and not make strict decisions, there is 
no need to even declare the winner. One could just collect rankings from the 
voters and then collect and publish various informative results based on those 
polls. If there is a Condorcet winner opinion, that would of course be 
mentioned. But one could have multiple criteria on which candidate is best, and 
the result could well say that according to criterion 1 candidate 1 is best, 
but according to criteron 2 candidate 2 is best. The discussion would continue 
from these facts, and could eventually lead to deciding which one of the 
candidates is best and which criteria are most valid in this case.

One could collect also ratings in addition to rankings, if that adds some 
useful information. Often also ratings might add something interesting. One 
could also include additional pesudo-candidates in the candidate list, or other 
additional information in the ballot. For example if one wants to decide which 
elements should be included in some article, one could have a pseudo-candidate 
acceptability limit. It would be useful to know not only which candidates are 
better than others but also which candidates are generally considered 
acceptable.

My point here is thus that for the purposes of Wikipedia consensus building, 
the polling system could simply collect as much useful information from the 
voters/workers as it can. People are not supposed to fight on which candidate 
wins but to discuss on the properties of all the candidates.

There may be also need for more competitive polls, e.g. when the community 
wants to decide what tool to use for some purpose. Then there is a need to 
choose one single solution on the spot. But when following the discussion 
based consensus approach, the main target could be to just collect 
information. Taking into account the non-competitive nature of the Wikipedia 
community, also the strict (competitive, not discussion and consensus based) 
elections probably need not be very strategy resistance oriented.

In summary, the non-competitive, discussion and consensus oriented nature of 
Wikipedia may have impact on how and what polling / voting methods are used.

Juho


On 28.9.2012, at 15.59, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 I've written a wikipedia essay on how Majority Judgment would be a good 
 option for resolving certain disputes, in the extremely rare (but real) case 
 when it does come down to a vote. This essay has garnered a positive mention 
 in a pending Wikipedia RFC (Request For Comment).
 
 Jameson
 
 ps. This should go without saying, but please don't use my real name if you 
 respond to this essay on Wikipedia itself or repost anything about this 
 elsewhere.
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MJ for use on wikipedia?

2012-09-28 Thread Juho Laatu
On 28.9.2012, at 22.33, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 
 
 2012/9/28 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 Since Wikipedia says in http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wikipedia:VOTE that 
 voting is used maily to help in building consesus. The polls are thus not 
 expected to be competitive. The final decisions are not made based on the 
 poll results but in a discussion that the polls should help.
 
 Please actually read the essay I linked earlier. It begins by acknowledging 
 that consensus discussion is the norm on wikipedia, as you say. MJ is 
 proposed specifically for those rare cases when that does not work and some 
 decision is necessary (such as the choice of software tool example you 
 give).

I read it and I tried to cover both competitive and non-competitive approaches, 
but I admit that I got too much lost on the non-competitive side while your 
text focused on the competitive part.

I understood that as long as we are talking about the !voting system we are 
talking about the discussion and consensus driven approach.

I didn't study the history of the Ireland and abortion activism cases. I wonder 
if they were cases where people decided to vote on the Wikipedia content, or 
maybe on something else like used tools.

 
 ...Taking into account the non-competitive nature of the Wikipedia community, 
 also the strict (competitive, not discussion and consensus based) elections 
 probably need not be very strategy resistance oriented.
 
 I disagree. The cases when consensus discussion fails to resolve the issue 
 are precisely those cases when strategy is salient.

I can see at least three levels. The first one is the discussion and consensus 
based track where we probably need not make any voting decisions, but polling 
style information is enough (to be used for making decisions).

Then there is voting in a friendly environment. There I assume that the 
Wikipedia community is a characteristically non-competitive society where one 
can expect all (or almost all) voters to be sincere (that could mean e.g. use 
of Range to decide which tool is best, without strategy concerns).

The third level could be used when there obviously is a fight going on, and 
people think that the correct way to solve the problem is by voting, and voters 
indeed want to beat each others and do not trust the sincerity of each others 
when they vote. I guess there are also fights that are this strong in the 
Wikipedia community. Sometimes they could be solved by voting, but hopefully 
more often by letting the fighters cool down and find a solution that can be 
accepted by all. Maybe one typical (Wikipedia content related) situation could 
be to decide if some part of a controversial Wikipedia article is acceptable or 
not. But also in that case, maybe the controversial nature and fights on some 
parts of the text would be a sufficient reason to not include those parts in 
the Wikipedia article. (I'm not fully familiar with the current Wikipedia 
working practices, but I'd expect something like that.)

My point is that since Wikipedia aims at discussion and consensus on its work 
(probably also on other matters than Wikipedia content), the used methods could 
reflect this principle (first level: polling, second level non-competitive 
methods, third level: competitive strategy resistant methods). Probably 
competitive voting should never be the recommended way of working, but only the 
last resort. A voting procedure that can be used in competitive conflicts could 
be agreed, but if possible, never or seldom used. When used, that means giving 
temporarily up the principle of polling is not a substitute for discussion.

Maybe a decision on whether some part of text is acceptable or not could be 
made by elders using the second level voting, or better yet, using the first 
level process. Often also a timeout (and temporary removal of possible 
controversial content) may be a better approach (and the default approcah) than 
deciding something in a competitive election. Same with technical decisions on 
tools. I don't believe there would ve very often cases where the decision has 
to be made right away, bypassing the consensus approach.

I wonder if this makes sense to you. My text above may still not be a very good 
match with your article, but maybe you can tell how you see the need of those 
three levels of polling/voting based decision making in the Wikipedia community.

Juho


 
 Jameson


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MJ for use on wikipedia?

2012-09-28 Thread Juho Laatu
Article titles can indeed be problematic since every article must have some 
title. There is no way of having articles without a title in the case that 
there is no consensus. Old titles can however be used for some time (maybe with 
a note pointing out the ongoing debate) while seeking consensus.

Wikipedia should of course have very clear policies on what kind of titles to 
use when there are different opinions. In the case of Ireland it seems to me 
that use of the formally correct names must be the correct answer. If the 
formal name of the country is Republic of Ireland, then let's use that. The 
(island) addition would depend on if Wikipedia recommends clarifications in 
this format or clarifications in the text right after the title (as it is now). 
I read some of the Wikipedia naming policies, and they already seem to cover 
typical problem cases quite extensively. I hope they will be kept up to date so 
that next time when a similar problem emerges, the solution will be obvious and 
there is no need to vote.

I think also levels one and two could be used in this kind of naming conflicts. 
I'm not sure if the voters want to use strategies, although the discussion is 
heated. Also I don't know how quickly the issue must be solved, and if the 
title shall be decided as the voting result says or just based on the 
voting/polling results. But I wasn't there so I cant tell if discussion and 
consensus simply could not be used any more. In any case it is good that 
Wikipedia aims at making the working practices as discussion and consensus and 
agreed policy oriented as possible.

Juho


On 29.9.2012, at 1.16, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 
 
 2012/9/28 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 On 28.9.2012, at 22.33, Jameson Quinn wrote:
 
 
 
 2012/9/28 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 Since Wikipedia says in http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wikipedia:VOTE that 
 voting is used maily to help in building consesus. The polls are thus not 
 expected to be competitive. The final decisions are not made based on the 
 poll results but in a discussion that the polls should help.
 
 Please actually read the essay I linked earlier. It begins by acknowledging 
 that consensus discussion is the norm on wikipedia, as you say. MJ is 
 proposed specifically for those rare cases when that does not work and some 
 decision is necessary (such as the choice of software tool example you 
 give).
 
 I read it and I tried to cover both competitive and non-competitive 
 approaches, but I admit that I got too much lost on the non-competitive side 
 while your text focused on the competitive part.
 
 I understood that as long as we are talking about the !voting system we are 
 talking about the discussion and consensus driven approach.
 
 I didn't study the history of the Ireland and abortion activism cases. I 
 wonder if they were cases where people decided to vote on the Wikipedia 
 content, or maybe on something else like used tools.
 
 
 Both of them are debates centering on article titles. An article can have 
 only one title, and a title can refer to only one article. Redirects and 
 disambiguation pages can help reduce the tensions this creates, but there are 
 cases where the dispute goes too deep, and eventually a vote is called.
 
 So these would fit in the third level of your classification, and the 
 technical issues around titles keep some of the normal mechanisms of 
 compromise (ie, do both) from working.
 
 Jameson


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Juho: Different answers to your questions. You're right...

2012-09-27 Thread Juho Laatu
On 27.9.2012, at 9.21, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 ...about some things.
 
 But first, regarding some of the other things:
 
 1. You seem to imply that you think that there is a single, objective,
 right ideal sincere winner. Of course you'll deny that, but you've
 repeatedly fallaciously based on argument on that assumption.

I deny that I'd think that there is one definition of right ideal sincere 
winner (since I think different elections, societies and individuals are free 
to define themselves who is the best, and different elections may well have 
different requirements). But in each election, with a set of votes (that do not 
contain exactly similarly or exactly equally well ranked candidates), one (each 
opinion holder separately) should at least in theory be able to tell which one 
of the candidates is the best and should be elected if the votes are sincere. 
There is thus always some understanding of what kind of candidate should be 
elected, and this philosophy could in principle be defined and presented as a 
best sincere winner definition / criterion.

 
 Sometimes something is a matter of subjective, individual choice,
 without a single objective right answer.

Yes.

 
 How do you think that you might go about proving that one particular
 winner is the ideal right sincere winner? Proofs and conclusions have
 to be based on some objective premise.

Free choice.

 
 You're giving us an unsupported assumption.
 
 2. You seem to assume that, if there is a single, objective, right
 ideal sincere winner, then it must be found from rank-balloting.

I assumed that the best sincere winner definition will be given together with 
some assumption of the type of ballots. It would be ok to define the best 
sincere winner in terms of ratings, although one would choose a ranking based 
method for use in the elections. There might be various reasons for not using 
ratings directly in the actual method. Obviously one would pick such a rankings 
based method that elects as good winners as possible (according to the best 
sincere winner criterion), and has other good properties like sufficient 
strategy resistance. The resulting method would not always elect the best 
winner even if the votes were fully sincere, but it is now a good compromise 
between different needs (election of good winners, startegy resistance, 
simplicity etc.).

 
 Again, that's just your unsupported assumption.
 
 3. You seem to think that, for any two desirable method-attributes,
 one of them can only be achieved by something that spoils the other.
 In other words, you think that any pair of desirable method-attributes
 must be mutually incompatible.

In some sense yes. I have mentioned the assumption that methods that have 
modified to be strategy resistant, usually do not implement any sincere best 
winner definition that has been determined for sincere votes.

 
 ...a pair of desirable attributes such as freedom from the worst
 strategy needs, and choice of the unique, objective, right ideal
 sincere winner...or maybe any desirable sincere winner.

Yes.

 
 In fact, it doesn't occur to you that free-ness from the worst
 strategy needs can result from a result that would be desirable as the
 sincere winner...or the best ideal sincere winner, if there is such a
 thing.

Different needs could sometimes lead to the same answer. It is possible that 
the sincere winner definition naturally points in a direction that also is 
strategy resistant (maybe to some extent even typical). I only believe that if 
the method is tweaked or modified just to be strategy resistant, then one would 
with high probability deviate from the path of electing the best winner with 
sincere votes. Tweaking means here making decisions that aim at defending 
against some identified weaknesses of the method (strategic vulnerabilities or 
other other problems that are not related to pickng the best sincere winner).

My point thus is that if you first think about sincere votes and who should be 
elected, and then find a method that implements exactly that definition, and 
then you abserve some stratgy problems and modify the method so that it can 
better answer those chanllenges, then the method (by definition) is not any 
more the method that elected the best winners with sincere votes.

 
 I've told you why that, in fact is so (but without the assumption
 about there being a single best ideal sincere winner).
 
 Now: Something that you're right about:
 
 It made sense to ask me if I prefer any sincere winners or ways of
 choosing them. Yes I do.
 
 For Official Public Elections:
 
 Approval. (maybe Score too).

I guess Approval means the candidate that is most approved among the voters 
(not necessarily the one that gets the highest number of approvals from voters 
that give approvals to candidates using their best strategy to optimize the 
result from their point of view). That is, sincre Approval. Same with points in 
Score.

 
 I've discussed Approval's unique 

Re: [EM] SITC vs [what?]

2012-09-25 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.9.2012, at 7.56, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 You said:
 
 Minmax(margins) can elect outside the top cycle if such a candidate is
 closest to being a CW (measured in number of required additional
 votes)
 
 [endquote]
 
 Now,  you see, that's exactly what I was talking about. Now you're
 back to Dodgson again, aren't you.

I think I'm still at Minmax(margins). But you are right that the difference is 
not important.

 ..quite aside from the fact that I've told you why SITC does well when
 people rank sincerely.

I still have not heard you claim that SITC could be used as a definition of the 
best sincere winner. Is it an ideal definition of an ideal winner, or is it a 
practical method that performs almost ideally also when voters use strategies?

 With Approval, Score, or SITC, the voters will decide
 that for themselves.

Note that in multi-party countries representative bodies are typically elected 
using a multi-winner proportional method, not using a single-winner method in 
singe-member districts. The latter approach tends to maintain a strong role of 
the largest parties. When I talked about the possiility of keeping a two-party 
system, I thought that the latter approach would mean 50% interest to maintain 
a two-party (or few-party) system. In typical multi-party systems presidential 
and parliamentary election methods are normally very different (single-winner 
vs. multi-winner).

 I see the sincere winner criterion and strategic concerns as two separate 
 topics.
 
 What is the sincere winner criterion? The methods that I advocate are
 the most likely to encourage sincere voting, or relatively sincere
 voting, in comparison with other methods.

Throughout this mail stream I have tried to talk about two separate topics: 
who would be the ideal sincere winner and what method to use in practice. 
Strategic concerns may infuence the selection of the latter, but not the 
definition of the former. If your methods define sincere voting then they are 
sincere winner criteria themselves. If they encourage sincere voting by some 
additional tricks like properties that disourage strategic voting, then those 
modifications/tricks probably cause a deviation that means that the ideal 
winner will not be always elected with sincere votes (since the method differs 
from the ideal sincere winner definition).

 And that _is_ a strategic topic. That's because certain strategy-needs
 are what can and does distort sincere voting--the only thing that can
 distort and prevent sincere voting.

This sounds like certain strategy defence means are in place, and the method 
has therefore not been designed based on the ideal sincere winner criterion 
only, and therefore it does not always elect the ideal winner with sincere 
votes. The alternative explanation would be that the actual method and the 
ideal sincere winner criterion happen to coincide (which sounds unlikely). It 
may well be that the method elects more often or more ideal winners than a 
method that would implement exactly the ideal sincere winner definition 
(because of the strategic votes or increased number of sincere votes).

 You think that strategy-freeness and good sincere results are
 mutually incompatible.

No, I say that a method whose behaviour has been tweaked so that it performs 
well in strategic environments, normally does not always elect the ideal winner 
(in whatever way one defines that) with sincere votes.

 If there will be defection in situations like the chicken
 dilemma examples, then can you still advocate Beatpath,
 MinMax(margins) or Dodgson over SITC, by saying they will get sincere
 rankings?
 
 You have to pick the method so that strategic concerns will be properly 
 addressed. I don't want to take position if one of those is absolutely 
 better than others (since that is not relevant to my claim).
 
 I don't know what that means.

Nothing important, just restating the oblious fact that practical methods must 
be selected based on practical requirements, and that my intention was not to 
estimate the level of chicken dilemma problems in various methods but just to 
discuss the relation and differences between ideal sincere winner definitions 
and practical methods.

 1. What makes you think that MinMax(margins), Dodgson, or Beatpath
 won't have a chicken dilemma?
 
 I already said that I do believe that basic Condorcet methods are not very 
 prone to this problem. I know that you disagree. Maybe you'll find one day a 
 proof that will convince me.
 
 I'm going to repeat this all over again for you:

I'll comment this winning votes example together with the margins bease example 
in the other chicken dilemma mail.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-25 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.9.2012, at 9.31, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Juho:
 
 Here's the MinMax(margins) chicken dilemma example that I promised, in
 which defection by B voters is successful and rewarded::
 
 Sincere preferences:
 
 75: ABC
 51: BAC
 100: C(A=B)
 
 Voted rankings:
 
 75: AB
 51: B
 100: C
 
 Try MinMax(margins) with that example.
 
 Note that it's a Dodgson example too.
 
 Note also that the B faction is small in comparison to the other factions.
 
 Condorcet(wv) reliably rewards defection.
 
 SITC reliably thwarts and penalizes defection.
 
 Though MinMax(margins) and Dodgson don't reward defection quite as
 reliably as does wv, (though the example shows that they easily do
 so), they certainly don't reliably thwart and penalize it either.

I think I'll skip the Dodgson part since I have not claimed anything about that 
method (and that's quite irrelevant too in this context). You may forget 
Dodgson. I'll comment mainly margins since I prefer margins versions of 
Condorcet methods to winning votes versions. But I'll address also the winning 
votes related problems shortly.

 
 An additional problem of MinMax(margins) and Dodgson:
 
 It is well established and well-discussed on EM that MinMax(margins)
 has particularly great problem with strategic truncation and offensive
 burial.

And you probably already guessed that I would say that those theoretical 
vulnerabilities may not be that bad in real elections.

 
 Those things, even offensive burial, aren't a problem with SITC,
 because the only candidate who can benefit from it is the most
 top-ranked candidate among the unbeaten candidates--or just the most
 top-ranked candidate if there are no unbeaten candidates.

I'm not sure if it is wise to expand this discussion also to SITC. It might 
however be of interest to me (based of what I have written) to point out that 
sometimes SITC and electing the ideal sincere winner (your definition) do not 
coincide.

 
 Offensive burial can't make anyone else win.


Now to Minmax(margins). I assume that this is a regular public election.

Some reasons why the chicken dilemma might not be a major problem in the given 
example:

- With these numbers all B supporters will have to implement the strategy to 
guarantee that B wins. This is very unlikely in real life.

- It is very unlikely that all B supporters use the strategy but none of the A 
supporters do. A is more popular than B, and therefore A supporters might 
truncate B with higher probability (due to thinking that B is a weak 
candidate). If two of the A supporters bullet vote (when all B voters are 
strategic), C is already tied with B, and according to the given preferences, B 
supporters would be very unhappy with that. For this reason B supporters should 
concentrate on making C not win instead of trying to beat A with this very 
risky strategy.

- The anticipated opinions are likely to change before the election day. If one 
of the B supporters becomes an A supporter, all candidates are tied. Maybe that 
single voter didn't like the idea that B supporters would try to steal the 
victory. This is again one reason why B should try to be friends with A and not 
try to cheat and steal the victory.

- Opinions are not usually as clean as in this example. There are often also 
other parties and always some voters whose preferences differ from those three 
main categories (e.g. ACB). This means that it is more difficult to guess how 
people will vote, to take into account the strategic interests of all voter 
groups, and to estimate the outcome. There is also always a group of voters who 
want to vote sincerely. If we assume e.g. +/-5% change of all preference 
orders, strategic voting gets much more difficult than it is on paper. On paper 
we can define ourselves how each voter will vote and allow certain interest 
group to stratgeize with 100% control of the similar minded voters. In real 
life, if there is one strategy, there may be also other strategies.

Already based on the first bullet point, this strategy seems to be a highly 
irrational strategy in Minmax(margins). And the other bullet points do not make 
the life of the strategists any easier. I'd say that you can sleep peacefully 
and not worry abut the chicken dilemma, at least with this threat scenario. Do 
you agree?

The winning votes variants are however much more vulnerable to this strategy. 
There are also strategies where margins are more vulnerble. But I prefer 
margins based versions of the Codorcet methods, because I find their sincere 
winner philosophy and also strategic properties better. But I'll try to say 
some words in favour of the wv versions too in your chicken dilemma scenario.

In your wv example (27: ABC, 24: BAC, 49: C) three strategically 
truncating B supporters can change the result. That is already a low number 
that could be well achieved. But there are still many problems on the way of 
the strategists.

- Also in this scenario it is not probable that only B supporters 

Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-24 Thread Juho Laatu
I will not comment the Dodgson and changing vs. adding votes related 
misunderstandings. I hope that misunderstanding is now solved. My example best 
sincere winner criterion was meant to refer to the Minmax(margins) philosophy.

On 24.9.2012, at 16.33, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 If you think that
 MinMax(margins) or Dodgson is better than Symmetrical ICT, under
 sincere voting, you have yet to tell why.

My comments applied to any definition of best sincere winner. I didn't comment 
on which one is best. (Instead I said that different elections and different 
people may have different targets.) I noted at some point that SITC has some 
strategy defence related properties that may make it an unlikely choice as a 
best sincere winner criterion.

 Do you really think that would help hir
 status against opposition in office better than being the most
 favorite candidate in the top cycle?

I don't know what most favorite means here. Minmax(margins) can elect outside 
the top cycle if such a candidate is closest to being a CW (measured in number 
of required additional votes). I don't claim that this criterion would be the 
best one for all elections, but it is one that sounds usable for some needs.

 So you're saying that different voting systems should be used for
 different elections. But, as each new election comes near, who decides
 which method will be used for that particular election?

I'd expect one series of elections to stick to one method (and be based on one 
stable understanding on what kind of a candidate is the best sincere winner).

 Should we use different voting systems for presidential and
 Congressional elections? If so, then which one would be better (by
 ideal sincere winner) for the presidency,and which would be better for
 Congress?

Those two elecions are very different by nature, and therefore they could well 
have different targets / understanding of whom to elect with sincere votes. The 
question on which method and which sincere winner criterion to choose is very 
difficlt since changes to the current system may mean changes to the very basic 
concepts of the system. There are multiple options. One interesting question is 
if the president shoud be from a large party of if he/she could be a compromise 
candidate that has no major party behind him/her. In the Congress one has to 
decide e.g. if one wants to keep the two-party approach or not. The end result 
might be two very different election methods.

 Of course, judging by how well they choose the ideal sincere winner
 assumes that you still think that there won't be a chicken dilemma,
 and can tell why.

I see the sincere winner criterion and strategic concerns as two separate 
topics. The method that will be eventually used may deviate from what the 
sincere winner criterion points to if there are strategic concerns that must be 
addressed by selecting a method that has the required strategy related 
properties.

 If there will be defection in situations like the chicken
 dilemma examples, then can you still advocate Beatpath,
 MinMax(margins) or Dodgson over SITC, by saying they will get sincere
 rankings?

You have to pick the method so that strategic concerns will be properly 
adressed. I don't want to take position if one of those is absolutely better 
than others (since that is not relevant to my claim).

 I tried to cover all the questions in your mail. You may point out the 
 unanswered ones, so I can check what I can do with them.

I don't think the following four questions that you gave as a response are ones 
that I left unanswered, but new questions or new formulations. I'l check them 
anyway.

 1. What makes you think that MinMax(margins), Dodgson, or Beatpath
 won't have a chicken dilemma?

I already said that I do believe that basic Condorcet methods are not very 
prone to this problem. I know that you disagree. Maybe you'll find one day a 
proof that will convince me.

 Must I do that, to show you their
 chicken dilemma? Request it and I will.

No need since I don't expect that to change my opinions. It could be a wasted 
effort. I'm interested if there is something really convincing, but maybe 
better leave this topic this time, with the assumption that I would not believe 
it anyway.

 2. What makes you so sure that the United States won't have a
 significant amount of favorite-burial, when unimproved Condorcet, such
 as Dodgson, MinMax(margins) or Beatpath, is used?

I'm not sure but my best guess is that basic Condorcet methods would work 
well enough. My confidence is based on theoretical studies, experiences with 
Condorcet in non-political elections and experiences with IRV in political 
elections (also in the U.S.). Many Condorcet startegies are difficult to 
identify, to use, to coordinate, and often they may also backfire. The details 
have been debated numerous times in the history on the EM list.

 Sometimes you seem to say that you're just speaking in general, about
 most societies, or many 

Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-23 Thread Juho Laatu
On 23.9.2012, at 8.01, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 On Sat, Sep 22, 2012 at 6:11 PM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 On 22.9.2012, at 22.06, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 
 2. Your statement above implies that Symmetrical ICT doesn't choose as
 well as [...what?] when
 people rank sincerely. That statement requires specification of what
 method(s) choose(s) better than SITC under sincere voting, and why
 that is so.
 
 Give me a description of who would be the best winner with sincere votes in 
 the election that we talk about.
 
 You're the one who wants to use the notion of the best winner with
 sincere votes. Odd that you need to ask me to describe your ideal
 sincere winner. If you want to object that ICT and SITC don't choose
 the ideal sincere winnner well enough, then you're the one who needs
 to say what you mean by the best winner with sincere votes.

Note that my opinion is that different elections may have different criteria. I 
mentioned one possible criterion of the best winner as an example, but that 
need not be your target (or not in all elctions). You could also in principle 
declare the operative definition of ICT or SITC as the definition of an ideal 
winner (with sincere ballots), but I'd have some doubts on the genuity of that 
claim since I believe that those methods have some strategy defence flavour 
embedded in them, and it doesn't sound probable that the strategy defence 
algoritms and ideal winner definition would coincide. If you pick some other 
definition of ideal winner, then it is obvious that ICT and SITC sometimes 
deviate from that ideal.

 
 But, with all sincere ballots, many like the idea of electing the CW:
 The candidate who pair-beats each of the others, when such a candidate
 exists. When CW is legitimately defined, when equal top and equal
 bottom ranking are interpreted consistent with the preferences, intent
 and wishes of people voting in that way, then SITC elects the CW.
 Beatpath, VoteFair, and all unimproved Condorcet methods fail to elect
 the legitimately-defined CW.
 
 So, there is a popular ideal sincere winner: the CW.

CW could indeed be part of the definiton. All Condorcet methods would be 
partially ideal (i.e. when there is a sincere CW).

 
 You said:
 
 Then one can tell what the best method with sincere votes is (or at
 least give some directions). I don't know what the philosophy of ICT
 and the other mentioned related methods is if we assume sincere votes.
 
 [endquote]
 
 A sincere-voting property of SITC is that it elects the
 legitimately-defined CW. It's the method that does that.
 
 You see, what you're missing is that the same disregard for voters
 preference, wishes and intent tha makes unimproved Condorcet fail FBC,
 also makes it fail the legitmately-defined Condorcet Criterion, and
 fail to elect the legimately-defined CW.
 
 So, meeting FBC doesn't require some sort of violation of the choice
 of ideal sincere winner. On the contrary, it comes with the election
 of the ideal sincere winner, because both gains come from respecting
 the voters' intent and preference.

Do you mean that the voter should help e.g. by falsifying her sincere 
preferences by voting some candidates tied at top? :-)

 
 You said:
 
 My understanding is that they have been designed to resist certain
 strategies, not only to pick the best winner with sincere votes.
 
 [endquote]
 
 As explained above, Symmetrical ICT avoids favorite-burial need
 precisely _because_ it respects voter wishes. And if the CW and the
 Condorcet Criterion are defined according to voter wishes, then
 Symmetrical ICT is the method that elects the CW when there is one,
 and meets the Condorcet Criterion.
 
 You said:
 
 Therefore there must be another method that elects the best winner
 (based on the definition that you gave) more often than they do.
 
 [endquote]
 
 So that's your best argument: That, because SITC meets FBC, there must
 be a method (unspecified by you) that does better under sincere
 voting.
 
 The reason why you don't specify a method that does better than SITC
 under sincere voting is because you don't even know what a method
 should do under sincere voting. You ask me to describe the ideal
 sincere winner, because you don't have any idea what the ideal sincere
 winner should be.

True in some sense. But if you allow me to define the sincere winner for you, 
and for your election, you could take my example definition and compare it to 
SITC. That could be valid for some needs. There is a difference between those 
two definitions.

 
 But I gave you a suggestion: The legimately-defined CW.
 
 Do you see the irony here? Someone who doesn't know what the ideal
 sincere winner is, wants say that surely there's some method that
 chooses it better than Symmetrical ICT. He just doesn't know what that
 method is, because he doesn't have a suggestion for what the ideal
 sincere winner would be.
 
 This
 means that one should deviate from the method that picks the best winner

Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-22 Thread Juho Laatu
 if you rank hir over no one.
 
 Definition of beats that isn't consistent with preferences and
 intent of equal-top or equal-bottom ranking voter:
 
 X beats Y iff (XY)  (YX)
 
 Definition of beats that is consistent with preferences and intent
 of equal-top ranking voter:
 
 X beats Y iff (XY)  (YX) + (X = Y)T
 
 Definition of beats that is consistent with preferences and intent
 of equal-top ranking voter and equal-bottom ranking voter:
 
 X beats Y iff (XY) + (X=Y)B  (YX) + (X=Y)T
 
 Of course the reason why Symmetrical ICT meets the Condorcet Criterion
 wherein beats is defined consistent with the preferences and intent
 of the equal-top ranking voter and the equal-bottom ranking voter is
 because Symmetrical ICT's definition uses that meaning for beats.
 
 But note that it is not a matter of re-defining CC so that SITC will
 pass. It's a matter of defining CC consistent with interpreting a
 voter's ballot consistent with hir preferences, intent and wishes.
 
 B. Later-No-Harm (LNHa):
 
 Condorcet methods, Approval, and Score fail LNHa.
 
 But ICT and Symmetrical ICT don't fail it nearly as badly as does
 unimproved Condorcet. In fact, I'll venture to say that ICT and SITC
 don't importantly fail LNHa. Note that I'm not speculating about how
 often they'll pass or fail. I'm saying that their failures aren't
 important.That's because there isn't a chicken dilemma. Chicken
 dilemma is the worst kind of LNHa failure.
 
 C. Later-No-Help (LNHe):
 
 Approval, Score, and Symmetrical ICT pass LNHe. Unimproved Condorcet
 and ICT fail LNHe.
 
 LNHe greatly simplifies u/a strategy. SITC's u/a strategy is as simple
 as that of Approval and Score. In unimproved Condorcet, you won't know
 what to do, even in a u/a election. I've recently told you why.
 
 In ICT and unimproved Condorcet, u/a strategy calls for ranking the
 unacceptable candidates in reverse order of winnability. That
 incentive or need doesn't exist in Symmetrical ICT. In SITC, the u/a
 strategy for unacceptables is to simply not rank them.
 
 In (so far as I'm aware of) all rank methods that allow equal top
 ranking, in a u/a election, there is a need to equal top rank the
 acceptables. So, in ICT and SITC that is the u/a strategy. That need
 exists in unimproved Condorcet too, but the problem is that moving
 some particular acceptable to top can change the winner from an
 acceptable to an unacceptable. That's why I say that, in unimproved
 Condorcet, you won't know what to do, even in a u/a election.
 
 D. FBC:
 
 Approval, Score, ICT and SITC pass. Unimproved Condorcet fails.
 
 E. Defection resistance:
 
 ...is had by ICT and Symmetrical ICT, but not by Approval, Score, or
 unimproved Condorcet.
 
 As I said, not a problem for Approval and Score (and probably not for
 unimproved Condorcet either, for the same reason--though dealing with
 it could be more complicated). But, as I also said, chicken dilemma is
 the nearest thing to a problem that Approval has, and therefore you
 don't significantly improve on Approval without getting rid of chicken
 dilemma.
 
 I'd said:
 
 The Chicken Dilemma is the nearest thing to a problem that
 Approval has (though it's so well dealt with in Approval that it isn't
 really a problem).
 
 You replied:
 
 I'm afraid it might be.
 
 [endquote]
 
 ...except for the long list of reasons why it wouldn't be a problem,
 the list that I've frequently posted during the past several weeks.
 
 One of the defenses on that list was something that Forest suggested,
 and which I call Strategic Fractional Ratings. You of course must have
 missed my posting of that.
 
 I've posted so much and so recently about the reasons why chicken
 dilemma won't be a problem in Approval, and, posted specifically,
 about SFR, that I don't think that I should repeat it again this soon.
 
 On Fri, Sep 21, 2012 at 7:43 PM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 We are about to dive into the details of some methods. I'm not sure if there 
 are still some unanswered questions that I should cover, or my own claims 
 that I did not clarify yet. I'll comment some random points below.
 
 On 22.9.2012, at 1.48, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 
 Maybe you meant to compare unimproved Condorcet to Approval (because
 you didn't want to compare it to ICT and Symmetrical ICT).
 
 Ok. You mentioned the Chicken Dilemma. It exists in Approval and
 Condorcet. Unimproved Condorcet doesn't get rid of the Chicken
 Dilemma. It's basically the same in both methods.
 
 Approval meets FBC. Unimproved Condorcet fails FBC.
 
 Exactly how is unimproved Condorcet better than Approval?
 
 Condorcet's Criterion?
 
 Condorcet's Criterion compliance is meaningless when people are
 favorite-burying.
 
 Then there's the matter of the highly computation-intensive count that
 every rank method has, including the Condorcet methods.
 
 Computation-intensive, labor-intensive count = big count-fraud opportunity.
 
 It should be enough if you can record (digitally) the content of the ballots

Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-22 Thread Juho Laatu
On 22.9.2012, at 22.06, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 2. Your statement above implies that Symmetrical ICT doesn't choose as
 well as [...what?] when
 people rank sincerely. That statement requires specification of what
 method(s) choose(s) better than SITC under sincere voting, and why
 that is so.

Give me a description of who would be the best winner with sincere votes in the 
election that we talk about. Then one can tell what the best method with 
sincere votes is (or at least give some directions). I don't know what the 
philosophy of ICT and the other mentioned related methods is if we assume 
sincere votes. My understanding is that they have been designed to resist 
certan strategies, not only to pick the best winner with sincere votes. 
Therefore there must be another method that elects the best winner (based on 
the definition that you gave) more often than they do.

 Some properties of methods that I don't like very much are: 1) truncation
 based approval, since that encourages voters not to take position on which
 one of the non-approved candidates should be elected (works against the
 basic idea of ranked methods of collecting the sincere preferences),
 
 Sure, you're expressing the ideal goal of rank-balloting. But surely
 you know that that goal is unattainable.

There are many ranked methods that do not have this property. (Same with point 
2.)

 But remember that my question was: Ok, then what method chooses better
 than SITC under completely sincere ranking? And why do you say that it
 does?

See above.

 Doctors have similar problems. Many medicines are far from harmless. Doctors
 have to compare the risks of the disease and risks of the medicine. If the
 medicine is likely to make more harm than help, it should not be used. This
 means that one should deviate from the method that picks the best winner
 with sincere votes...
 
 ...which is _what_ method?

There are different best methods for different needs.

(In my text above I asked you to provide a definition of the best candidate. A 
simple Condorcet oriented definition could be e.g. the candidate that requires 
least additional support/votes to beat any of the other candidates in a 
pairwise comparison/battle should be elected. This target could be selected 
because it gives one rational argument why the winner could be able to rule 
well (= only little bit of additional support needed (if any) to gain majority 
support for his proposals while in office).)

 ...only if one is certain that otherwise the method would
 give even worse results because of strategic voting.
 
 ..even worse than what??

A method that has been modified to cope with strategies does not elect the 
ideal sincere winner always. But the corresponding sincere method could be even 
worse if strategic voting is rampant.

 You haven't said what are the bad results of
 SITC and ITC that we need to avoid.

See my first comments above. Their deviation from the ideal should become 
visible after one defines the ideal sincere winner.

 Obviously you believe
 that basic [unimproved] Condorcet methods would attract certain strategies 
 to the extent
 that those methods must be fixed. And I believe that in most societies it is
 more likely that strategic voting will be marginal.

 Because I don't know what method you're referring to, of course
 there's no way to answer your expression of belief.

I referred to basic Condorcet methods. (Ranked Pairs, MInmax,...)

 ...aside from the fact that I make no claim to know what's true about
 more than 1/2 of all societies.

With most I wanted to say that I don't expect many societies to converge 
towards widespread strategic voting. I start from that assumption and I want 
evidence before deviating from that assumption.

 I think I already said that the computations (from digitized ballot content
 to results) could be checked either by anyone or by some nominated entities
 (if ballot content is not published to protect privacy).
 
 Sure, but how would you guarantee the accuracy and honesty of the
 digitization? ...The process that occurs between the time that the
 voter casts hir ballot, and the time when we have that digitized
 record of which you speak.

This is a very traditional process. Nothing new in it. I'll give an approximate 
description of the process in Finland. In the polling station there are many 
representatives from many parties, monitoring the process. The votes are 
counted (information collected) right after the election ends, again together 
on one table by multiple people from multiple parties. After that the votes are 
sealed and sent for storage. I don't recall any serious problems or complaints. 
With complex votes the process would take more time, and there could be a need 
to double check, but the principles would probably stay the same.

 Did the voter hirself make out a paper ballot? Or
 was it made electronically by a voting machine (presumably, but not
 necessarily based on the voter's voting)?

Use of 

Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-21 Thread Juho Laatu
On 21.9.2012, at 4.05, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 When you say can't be elected, you need to examine what you mean by
 that. Do you mean can't be elected under combination of a selective
 media blackout, and Plurality voting? Or do you mean can't be
 elected because the public prefer the policies of the Republocrats?

Just in practice. Some more weight on Duverger's law, some less on media 
(would happen also without media).

 It is hard to find methods that have no weaknesses. Luckily we can often use 
 methods whose weaknesses are weak enough.
 
 We can do better. We can avoid certain strategy needs. For instance
 there are now a wide variety of FBC-complying methods. They have
 absolutely no favorite-burial incentive.

I think it makes often sense to trade one full compatibility to numerous well 
enough compatibilities. As in security, the system is as strong as its weakest 
link. One should thus focus on making the weakest points stronger, not on 
making strong points even stronger.

 All those three methods may meet that target in some elections.
 
 ...may...?

Depends on targets and environment. There are varoius needs and various best 
methods.

 I suggest to you that maybe actual conversations with actual
 people, here, tells a different story than your tv network sources.

I've had some.

 Have you ever noticed how perfectly the public psychology works with
 the sheep-herder's efforts? It's as if the sheep and the herders were
 made for eachother. It's as if those two sets of people were _born_
 for their roles with regard to eachother. It's as if we have specially
 bred sheep, to work with the sheep-herders. We do. It's just like
 Huxley's _Brave New World_ ...except that, of course, it's anything
 but new. It's the result of long evolution, over human and pre-human
 history. That's where the actual situation differs from _Brave New
 World_. It isn't done by drugging. It's done, instead, by natural
 evolution.

In politics, as in elsewhere, there are often multiple interest groups that try 
to optimize the game from their point of view. Achieved symbiotic balance 
states may well seem like made for each other.

Humans are good at learning new methods. They have learned e.g many tricks to 
make people buy something that they want them to buy. Politics is not very far 
from that.

 The opinion of other people does influence on what people do. Some methods 
 might even reinforce this behaviour. I believe, in most methods the method 
 specific bad group behaviour reinforcing factor is not very strong.
 
 [endquote]
 
 Again, you're speculating about a country (U.S.) about which your only
 information comes from such as CNN and Fox tv.

I try to avoid commenting on what the U.S. system is like or what the U.S. 
people shoud do. I may comment your comments on the U.S. system, but when I 
can, I prefer taking about election methods at a general level, not about the 
specifics of individual countries. In the sentence above I commented methods in 
general, not anything U.S. specific. (I also don't watch CNN nor Fox.)

 You continue:
 
 We also need good electorate, which could mean continuous education
 and encouragement (by media, country and fellow citizens).
 
 [endquote]
 
 In other words, you're saying that we need for the educational system
 and the media to act contrary to the best financial interest of those
 who have controlling interest in them. Why should they do that?

Media has also some interest to serve their customers. And customers may 
sometimes appreciate good information. Different countries have quite different 
traditions here. There are also media that are not tightly controlled by those 
who have controlling interest. I have received a lot of useful information 
from the media, but I'd like to receive even more.

 You've just shown that you _are_ making
 claims about the U.S. Must I retract the apology that I've just made?

Sorry, but you keep talking about the U.S. situation, so it is hard to avoid 
that topic totally :-). Because of the numerous misunderstandings I propose 
that you assume that my comments refer to election methods in general unless I 
mention U.S..

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-21 Thread Juho Laatu
On 21.9.2012, at 22.52, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Just in practice. Some more weight on Duverger's law, some less on media 
 (would happen also without media).
 
 So you keep repeating. But, in this country, the 1-party monopoly
 _wouldn't_ happen without the media fraud that I've discussed.
 
 You're quite vague and vacillatory about whether you're speaking of
 the U.S. or whether you're speaking in general.

As already said, U.S. meant when U.S. mentioned. That should give you the 
correct context with about 95% probability. You can correct me if I make 
mistakes.

 You said would happen
 also without media. Where would it happen also without media?

I meant that parties + plurality + single member distritcs + representative 
body has always a tendency to elect from two strong parties. (It is possible 
that different districts have different two parties, or the parties may change 
slowly in time.)

 It is hard to find methods that have no weaknesses. Luckily we can often 
 use methods whose weaknesses are weak enough.
 
 We can do better. We can avoid certain strategy needs. For instance
 there are now a wide variety of FBC-complying methods. They have
 absolutely no favorite-burial incentive.
 
 I think it makes often sense to trade one full compatibility to numerous 
 well enough compatibilities. As in security, the system is as strong as 
 its weakest link. One should thus focus on making the weakest points 
 stronger, not on making strong points even stronger.
 
 Your fallacy is your implication that there are other necessary
 properties, lacking in Approval , Score, and Symmetrical ICT, but
 possessed by unimproved Condorcet  ...if unimproved Condorcet is what
 you're suggesting. And if unimproved Condorcet isn't what you're
 suggesting,then what is it that you're suggesting?

I was talking about general rules concerning all methods. No intention to refer 
to any particular methods.

If you want my opinion on Condorcet methods in general, I think they are 
remarkably well balanced methods, for compromise seeking, competitive, majority 
style elections. They thus have quite well balanced well enoughs / 
vulnerabilities.

 If there's something that they don't do well enough, and that
 unimproved Condorcet does well enough then you forgot to tell what it
 is.

What kind of comparisons would you like me to make? If we are talking about the 
well enougs of other than Condorcet methods, then we should focus on the most 
probable vulnerabilities of each one of them (in the given environment). You 
already addressed the chicken dilemma in Approval. I think we agree that in 
real life that may well be the most problematic one. Same with Score.

 You keep making authoritatively-worded
 statements to the effect that unimproved Condorcet would work fine in
 the U.S. Sometimes you insist that you're only speaking in general,
 but then you go back to specifically making that statement about the
 U.S.

I'm trying to avoid anything U.S. specific, except when answering to U.S. 
specific points that you want to present to me.

Concerning Condorcet in the U.S., I believe the strong two-party and plurality 
tradition would cause some problems in transition, but I do believe that 
eventually people would vote pretty much the same way as in other countries (no 
panic burials etc.).

The only U.S. specific proof I have is that in the Burlington IRV elections I 
didn't notice any burial like or other strategic activity that could be harmful 
in Condorcet. The votes seemed in general quite sincere to me, and I don't 
recall any reports on strategic voting. I made some ballot content analysis 
myself, but I couldn't find any meaningful traces of strategies. I'd expect 
voters to behave pretty much the same way also with other ranking based methods.

I don't expect e.g. Australian style party guided voting to appear in the U.S. 
since people have a strong tendency to make their own independent decisions my 
way (probably not in Australia either unless their strangest IRV rules would 
be copied to Condorcet too).

 You said:
 
 I may comment your comments on the U.S. system, but when I can, I
 prefer taking about election methods at a general level, not about the
 specifics of individual countries.
 
 [endquote]
 
 ...then you often violate your own preference  :-)

The alternative would be to leave your questions / comments unanswered :-).

 I'm merely pointing out that your claims about how Americans would
 vote are lacking in authority.

None of my comments are based on complete understanding of what I'm talking 
about :-).

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-21 Thread Juho Laatu
On 22.9.2012, at 1.17, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Do you claim that unimproved Condorcet can be
 defended in a comparison with Symmetrical ICT, or ordinary ICT?

I don't know if I have anything important to say. You are probably a better 
expert on the properties of those methods. Also definitions of the methods 
needed in addition to their technical properties. I don't exacly know what you 
mean with unimproved Condorcet.

 The Chicken Dilemma is the nearest thing to a problem that
 Approval has (though it's so well dealt with in Approval that it isn't
 really a problem).

I'm afraid it might be.

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-21 Thread Juho Laatu
We are about to dive into the details of some methods. I'm not sure if there 
are still some unanswered questions that I should cover, or my own claims that 
I did not clarify yet. I'll comment some random points below.

On 22.9.2012, at 1.48, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Maybe you meant to compare unimproved Condorcet to Approval (because
 you didn't want to compare it to ICT and Symmetrical ICT).
 
 Ok. You mentioned the Chicken Dilemma. It exists in Approval and
 Condorcet. Unimproved Condorcet doesn't get rid of the Chicken
 Dilemma. It's basically the same in both methods.
 
 Approval meets FBC. Unimproved Condorcet fails FBC.
 
 Exactly how is unimproved Condorcet better than Approval?
 
 Condorcet's Criterion?
 
 Condorcet's Critrerion compliance is meaningless when people are
 favorite-burying.
 
 Then there's the matter of the highly computation-intensive count that
 every rank method has, including the Condorcet methods.
 
 Computation-intensive, labor-intensive count = big count-fraud opportunity.

It should be enough if you can record (digitally) the content of the ballots in 
a reliable way. Computations should not lead to fraud since they can be easily 
double checked. If the content of the ballots is mabe public, checking is 
really easy. If the content of the ballots is secret for privacy reasons, then 
we need to agree who can check the calculations.

 
 ...and it also means machine balloting and computerized count. That
 means an even more greatly-enhanced count-fraud opportunity.

Machine balloting is a risk in all methods (if votes are only bits, and there 
is no paper copy). Also complex ballots like ranked and rated ballots can be 
implemented on paper quite well (= without too bad limitations). Computerized 
count is not a problem if reliable source data is available for checks.

 
 Even if you could find a significant advantage of unimproved Condorcet
 over Approval, that advantage wouldn't obtain when count-fraud is
 being done.
 
 If you want my opinion on Condorcet methods in general, I think they are 
 remarkably well balanced methods, for compromise seeking, competitive, 
 majority style elections.
 
 Unimproved Condorcet gives incentive /or need for favorite-burial,
 unlike Approval or ICT or Symmetrical ICT.
 
 Yes, you could find voters who wouldn't be susceptible to that
 incentive. I can show you millions who would be. It's better to just
 not cause it at all. Because that is so easily achieved, there's no
 need for favorite-burial incentive.
 
 When favorite-burial happens, it distorts preferences so as to make a
 joke of the election.
 
 Unimproved Condorcet, unlike ICT and Symmetrical ICT, has the Chicken Dilemma.
 
 Unimproved Condorcet, unlike Approval, Score, and Symmetrical ICT,
 fails Later-No-Help.
 
 
 You said:
 
 They thus have quite well balanced well enoughs / vulnerabilities.
 
 [endquote]
 
 Is that what you call the above-described attributes?

I stick to my comment on Condorcet methods (see above). Maybe someone should 
arrange a real-life political Condorcet election so we could see how extensive 
favourite burial there will be and how much that will influence the results. 
Otherwise it seems to be just your guess against mine. I don't believe that the 
existence of a (theoretical) FBC vulnerability would automatically lead to 
widespread favourite betrayal. Again I refer to Burlington IRV elections as an 
argument why this probably would not happen even in the U.S. (The last sentence 
is about the U.S. The others are generic.)

Juho


 
 Mike Ossipoff


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-20 Thread Juho Laatu
On 20.9.2012, at 8.20, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 You said:
 
 The idea that there are third candidates but that are never elected,
 and that can act as spoilers  does not fly very well.
 
 [endquote]
 
 In what sense doesn't it fly well? What does that mean?

I just meant that it is a waste of effort and energy to have fake candidates 
that appear as they could be elected, but they can't, or whose presence may 
make the natural winner not win.

 Let me try to translate what you said:
 
 The idea that there are non-Republocrat candidates that have never
 been elected to the presidency, and that an act as spoilers is either
 unsatisfactory to Juho, or disbelieved by Juho.
 
 Is that what you meant?

Approximately so.

 1. We don't want nonwinning candidates to be spoilers. That's why we
 don't want Plurality, IRV, or unimproved Condorcet.

It is hard to find methods that have no weaknesses. Luckily we can often use 
methods whose weaknesses are weak enough. All those three methods may meet that 
target in some elections.

 2. It's unsatisfactory (to the public) that only Democrats and
 Republicans ever win, because the public regard the (Democrat and
 Republican) politicians as sharing the same moral level as a
 schoolground drug-dealer.

Depends on if they want that only Democrats and Republicans ever win.

 But I'm not sure that I've interpreted you correctly. Maybe you meant
 that what doesn't fly is the belief that the winner must be a
 Democrat or a Republican. Yes indeed, that doesn't fly.

I meant that using a method that appears to elect any of the candidates but in 
reality can elect only certain candidates does not look natural.

 So, you see, we are in complete agreement.

Pretty much so. But I didn't want to take position on two-party systems vs. 
multi-party systems.

 You said:
 
 If we want to have a two-party system...
 
 [endquote]
 
 Whoa. Who is this we who want to have a 2-party system. Are you
 saying that you want Finland to have a 2-party system? Or that you
 want the U.S. to have a 2-party system, and that I also do?

That was passive. So we could be anybody who wants that.

 But it isn't for me to say how many parties we have, or how many
 parties should sometimes win. That's for the voters to decide.

In a representative democracy perople elect representatives who will then 
decide. In this case the representatives of the two main parties will decide. 
This is a general problem of political systems (not only a problem of two-party 
systems) and also other organizations. Those that are in power have tendency to 
maintain their own strong position.

 To say that there should be some particular number of parties (like
 two) would be undemocratic.

Unless the voters or their representatives say so. (Or maybe someone just uses 
his freedom of speech and freedom of opinion.)

 So I'm not denying that some _do_ want a 2-party system. For instance,
 I'll venture a guess that the Democrats and Republicans like there to
 be a two party system.

That may well be true.

 In fact, I'll go farther than that, and suggest that maybe the wealthy
 types who own and bribe the Republocrat politicians also like there to
 be a two party system, in which the people owned by them are perceived
 as the two choices.

Yes, there may be also such people. But maybe not very many. Maybe there are 
also many people that make use of the situation but that don't have any 
philosophical thoughts on what political system would be good. They are just 
opportunistic, with not much interest in politics nor in theories on two-party 
systems, Duverger's law etc.

 But seriously, the number of parties should be as many as people want.

I note that also multi-party systems have similar problems. They may have e.g. 
cutoffs that give no seats to parties below 5% support. Or the size of 
districts may set some limits (from this point of view a one-member distric is 
an extreme case). A more general form of the question could be e.g. if in a N 
member representative body a party with M/N of the votes should get M seats.

 You said:
 
 , there are also better election methods for that purpose than plain 
 plurality.
 
 [endquote]
 
 
 Apparently, then, you disagree with Riker. I'll take Riker's side on
 that question: Plurality is perfect for making, maintaining,
 preserving a two-party system.

Maybe he should have said one good instead of perfect. Or maybe word 
perfect means that he is very happy with having fake candidates that can 
collect the protest votes without making any harm.

What I meant with better was that some methods could allow new parties to 
rise and replace one of the old two parties, or that would allow those two 
parties to be internally more responsive to voter opinions than they (maybe) 
are today.

 Oh don't get me wrong. I'm not saying
 that Plurality can do it alone. No, it needs a little help. It needs
 the help of a mass media system that continually hammers home the
 message about the two 

Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-19 Thread Juho Laatu
On 18.9.2012, at 18.03, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 09/16/2012 02:35 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 16.9.2012, at 9.57, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 
 
 
 (More precisely, the relative scores (number of plumpers required)
 become terms of type score_x - score_(x+1), which, along with SUM
 x=1..n score_x (just the number of voters), can be used to solve
 for the unknowns score_1...score_n. These scores are then
 normalized on 0..1.)
 
 It seems to work, but I'm not using it outside of the fitness
 function because I have no assurance that, say, even for a monotone
 method, raising A won't decrease A's score relative to the others.
 It might be the case that A's score will decrease even if A's rank
 doesn't change. Obviously, it won't work for methods that fail
 mono-add-plump.
 
 What should candidate's score indicate in single-winner methods? In
 single-winner methods the ranking of other candidates than the winner
 is voluntary. You could in principle pick any measure that you want
 (distance to victory or quality of the candidate or something
 else). But of course most methods do provide also a ranking as a
 byproduct (in addition to naming the winner). That ranking tends to
 follow the same philosophy as the philosophy in selecting the winner.
 As already noted, the mono-add-plump philosophy is close to the
 minmax(margins) philosophy, also with respect to ranking the other
 candidates.
 
 What should candidate's score indicate? Inasfar as the method's winner is 
 the one the method considers best according to the input given, and the 
 social ordering is a list of alternatives in order of suitability (according 
 to the logic of the method), a score should be a finer graduation of the 
 social ordering. That is, the winner tells you what candidate is the best 
 choice, the social ordering tells you which candidates are closer to being 
 winners, and the rating or score tells you by how much.

Here suitability is close to what I called quality of the candidate.

I note that we must have a suitable interpreation for social ordering because 
of the well known paradoxes of social ordering. Maybe we talk about scoring 
the candidates (transitively, numerically). That would make it social scoring 
or someting like that.

I also note that if we talk about list of alternatives in the sense that we 
want to know who should be elected in case the first winner can not be elected, 
then there may be different interpretations. We may want to know e.g. who 
should be elected if the winner would not have participated in the election, or 
in the case that the winner participates but can not be elected (= the 
question is, do we measure losses to the winner).

One more note. Term closer to being winners does refer to being close in 
quality / scores. It does not refer to being close to winning e.g. in number of 
voters that could change the results. (I used earlier term distance to 
victory.)

 
 If the method aims to satisfy certain criteria while finding good winners, it 
 should do so with respect to finding the winner, and also with respect to the 
 ranking and the score. A method that is monotone should have scores that 
 respond monotonically to the raising of candidates, too.
 
 I note that some methods like Kemeny seem to produce the winner as a
 byproduct of finding the optimal ranking. Also expression breaking a
 loop refers to an interest to make the potentially cyclic socielty
 preferences linear by force. In principle that is of course
 unnecessary. The opinions are cyclic, and could be left as they are.
 That does not however rule out the option of giving the candidates
 scores that indicate some order of preference (that may not be the
 preference order of the society).
 
 I think most methods can be made to produce a social ranking. Some methods do 
 this on its own, like Kemeny. For others, you just extend the logic by which 
 the method in question determines the winner. For instance, disregarding 
 ties, in Schulze, the winner is the candidate whom nobody indirectly beats. 
 The second place finisher would then be the candidate only indirectly beaten 
 by the winner, and so on.

I guess in Schulze we can have the two options that I mentioned above. We can 
consider the ballots/matrix with or without the first winner, when determining 
the second winner.

In real life these cases could be compared e.g. to the situation where the 
winnig candidate has died or has just decided to be in opposition instead of 
becoming elected. The ideal winner may be different depending on what kind of 
opposition he/she will have. This difference is obvious e.g. in the case of a 
loop of three vs. majority decision between two candidates.

 
 
 Turning rankings into ratings the proper way highly depends on
 the method in question, and can get very complex. Just look at this
 variant of Schulze: http://arxiv.org/abs/0912.2190 .
 
 They seem to aim at respecting multiple criteria. Many such criteria
 could maybe

Re: [EM] Scoring (was Re: OpenSTV 2.1.0 released)

2012-09-19 Thread Juho Laatu
On 19.9.2012, at 20.26, Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Juho--
 
 This thread is demonstrating something that I spoke of earlier: There
 are an unlimited number of things that different people can ask for
 from voting systems, just as there are infinitely-many ways to count
 rank ballots.
 
 It couldn't be any more obvious, could it, that there's just no way
 that agreement can ever be achieved, in such discussions, regarding
 which method to support as an actual proposal.

Well, maybe the experts are unable to agree, but practical people that seek 
practical methods for practical problems might be more sensible :-).

 
 But that's ok. EM's discussion needn't be toward the goal of practical
 agreement for support of an actual proposal. EM's goal needn't have
 anything to do with actual social improvement.
 
 Discussion of social choice methods can be (and usually is) entirely
 divorced from any social practicality, use, or value.

EM discussions may cover also theoretical (= not practical) topics. But I agree 
that discussions that try to find widely agreed conclusions on practical 
real-life situations are often surprisingly difficult.

 
 There's no law that says that you have to care about such things.
 
 I just want you to know that I'm not criticizing you about that.
 
 You said:
 
 For example FBC is an important criterion, but I can accept methods that do
 not meet it, but that are good enough in the sense that they allow voters to
 rank their favourite always first, as a safe enough rule of thumb. I don't
 like methods that fail FBC in the sense that voters often have to betray
 their favourite, or if voters have to decide whether to betray or not based
 on some complex analysis. In the same way many other criteria can be met
 well enough.
 
 That's what I used to say. There are a few problems with that.
 
 You can certainly be forgiven for not knowing what's important to
 voters in this country. No doubt each country is different in that
 regard.
 
 But understand that that means that what you say might not be
 applicable to this country. And, from what I've heard, some other
 Plurality countries have a very similar habit of lesser-evil voting.
 
 So, in fact, could it be that what you're saying is applicable only to
 countries that don't use Plurality for their main political elections?

When I wrote that I was thinking about single-winner elections that genuinely 
elect from multiple candidates. But I think it covers also plurality and 
two-party systems. The idea that there are third candidates but that are never 
elected, and that can act as spoilers does not fly very well. If we want to 
have a two-party system, there are also better election methods for that 
purpose than plain plurality. Or one approach could be also to have only two 
parties and two candidates (= meets FBC).

 
 As I said, I used to say what you said above. That was before I
 observed a progressive lesser-evil Democrat-voter voting in a
 Condorcet Internet poll, for a presidential election. Yes, I've
 mentioned this before.
 
 She's a progressive, and preferred the policies of Nader to those of
 the Democrats. But she felt that Nader couldn't win, and that, because
 only a Democrat can beat the Republicans, the one and only goal is to
 maximize the probability of a Democrat winning instead of a
 Republican. We've been over this.
 
 So she ranked all of the Democrats over Nader. I couldn't tell her
 that she needn't do that, because it was optimal strategy, given her
 assumptions and her goal.
 
 You see, that's what you're missing. It's what you were missing before, too.

But wasn't that more a problem of the voter than a problem of the method? She 
betrayed her favourite although there was maybe no need to do so. She just 
didn't believe that sincere ranking was a safe enough rule of thumb, or at 
least a better strategy than the one that she used.

 
 If you believe that the winner must necessarily be a Democrat or a
 Republican, if you believe that only a Democrat can beat the
 Republicans, then you also believe that maximizing your expectation
 and optimizing the outcome must mean maximizing the win-probability of
 a Democrat.
 
 In an election with a progressive (whose policies you prefer best), a
 Democrat, and some Republicans, your optimal strategy, in unimproved
 Condorcet, is to rank the Democrat _alone_ in 1st place.
 
 When we discussed this before, I told why that is. The reason hasn't
 changed since then.

I'm not quite convinced.

 
 So it isn't a matter of How likely is it that this method will show
 its FBC failure?. Instead, it's a matter of Does (can) this method
 fail FBC?

Maybe the question is if (rational) voters converge towards voting sincerely or 
towards (some opinion groups) burying their favourite.

 
 Maybe unimproved Condorcet won't often show its FBC failure.
 Irrelevant. By the beliefs, assumptions, and goal that I spoke of
 earlier--the beliefs, assumptions and goal of the fully-devoted
 

Re: [EM] OpenSTV 2.1.0 released and new OpaVote features

2012-09-17 Thread Juho Laatu
On 17.9.2012, at 21.08, Richard Fobes wrote:

 On 9/15/2012 3:02 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 On 09/15/2012 09:55 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 15.9.2012, at 6.05, Jeffrey O'Neill wrote:
 You can also now save Condorcet results in HTML format but still
 working on the best graphics to visualize Condorcet results.
 One solution is to support minmax(margins). With that method you can
 simply draw a histogram that indicates how many new (first preference)
 votes each candidate would need to win (or tie) with the winner /
 current leader.
 
 Here is the URL to a results page at VoteFair.org that shows another way to 
 graphically display pairwise-comparison results:
 
 http://www.votefair.org/cgi-bin/votefairrank.cgi/votingid=41541-56251-09157

Some observations.

The results contain two histogram style visualizations (= numeric value for 
each candidate), VoteFair ranking score and Traditional vote count / 
plurality. I discussed earlier about histograms that could show distance to 
victory or quality of the candidate (from the used method point of view). 
The presented histograms do not fall in these categories but offer additional 
information, I guess mainly to allow people to compare the reasults to some 
other ways to measure the candidates.

When reading the results I noted that the top two candidates were tied but all 
the other results were transitive. That means that the top two candidates had 
10 pairwise victories each (+ one tie). The number of victories of the 
ramaining candiates were 9, 8, 7, 6, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1 and 0. These values would 
give us one additional histogram that would show the number of pairwise 
victories. Those values would tell quickly, at least to an experienced 
observer, that other than the two top canididates are ordered transitively. 
That piece of information would be valid information for most Condorcet 
methods, but only partial, since it only indicates the order of the candidates 
unambigiously if there are no pairwise cycles or ties. (Well, there is no 
requirement of single-winner methods or Condorcet methods to give a ranking, 
but the intended order is often obvious anyway.)

That's all. Just some observations on the presented extar histogram style 
information. It is not very easy to generate distance to victory or quality 
of the candidate measures for all Condorcet methods.

Juho

 
 Note that the pairwise comparisons are sorted according to popularity.
 
 The length of each bar indicates how many voters support that choice compared 
 to the other choice in the pair.
 
 The summary section uses bar lengths that basically sum up the pairwise 
 counts.  This means that the length of a bar for a higher-ranked choice is 
 not necessarily always longer than the length of a bar for the 
 next-lower-ranked choice (but such cases become rare as the number of votes 
 increases).
 
 Richard Fobes
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] OpenSTV 2.1.0 released and new OpaVote features

2012-09-15 Thread Juho Laatu
On 15.9.2012, at 6.05, Jeffrey O'Neill wrote:
 You can also now save Condorcet results in HTML format but still working on 
 the best graphics to visualize Condorcet results.
One solution is to support minmax(margins). With that method you can simply 
draw a histogram that indicates how many new (first preference) votes each 
candidate would need to win (or tie) with the winner / current leader.

- This visualization method could be useful additional information also in 
other methods, but it would not be as accurate.
- For detailed analyis the pairwise matrix will be important in any case. But 
for quick visualization histograms (= n numeric values) are something that 
people can generally understand based on a quick look.
- I have seen 2D graphs that show all parwise wins, e.g. in Debian. They are 
however quite difficult to draw automatically, and the positioning of 
candidates in the drawing space (e.g. higher, lower) may not be neutral (unless 
they are in one row or circle).

Juho



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] OpenSTV 2.1.0 released and new OpaVote features

2012-09-15 Thread Juho Laatu
On 15.9.2012, at 13.02, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 On 09/15/2012 09:55 AM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 15.9.2012, at 6.05, Jeffrey O'Neill wrote:
 You can also now save Condorcet results in HTML format but still
 working on the best graphics to visualize Condorcet results.
 One solution is to support minmax(margins). With that method you can
 simply draw a histogram that indicates how many new (first preference)
 votes each candidate would need to win (or tie) with the winner /
 current leader.
 
 That also works with minmax(wv), and similar approaches can work for least 
 reversal methods and those that use sums of victories rather than 
 minimum/maximum ones. However, those visualization methods are still linked 
 to specific voting methods, and thus don't provide a general visualization of 
 the pairwise results.

For minmax(margins) the number of required additional votes to beat (or at 
least tie with) all other candidates is an exact definition of the method, and 
gives one number per candidate that can be used in the histogram. All methods 
that can do the same thing, i.e. give one numeric value that both indicates the 
winner and indicates a natural measure of distance of each candidate to winning 
the election, can use histogram level visualization effectively. One would need 
also an easy to understand verbal description of what the histogram values 
mean. I wonder which other Condorcet methods have such intuitive function 
available. Do you have such functions for some of the methods that you proposed 
as candidates?

The histogram results of minmax(margins) do not give all the information that 
is present in the pairwise comparison matrix. The histogram indicates only the 
distance to the worst competitor, which is always the current leader. Pairwise 
comparison results to all others are lost. (Information on 49-50 vs. 48-49 
against the current leader could be included in the histogram if needed. 
Probably better to leave this to the matrix.) But on the other hand the 
difference of the hstogram values of any two candidates still indicates exactly 
how much closer to victory the better one of those candidates is. For complete 
analysis full matrix is needed, but for practical information to regular 
voters, especially during the counting process, the histogram may well be all 
that is needed. (All pairwise comparisons could be presented to allow 
speculation on what if there had been only these two candidates.)

 
 I suppose one could use something similar with Kemeny as well: use integer 
 programming to find the pairwise sum of scores for the best transitive 
 ordering that puts X first. That is X's score. Then do it for Y and Z. 
 Assuming X wins, all other scores will be lower than X's. The relationship 
 between additional votes and Kemeny scores might not be obvious to the end 
 user, though.
 
 - I have seen 2D graphs that show all parwise wins, e.g. in Debian. They
 are however quite difficult to draw automatically, and the positioning
 of candidates in the drawing space (e.g. higher, lower) may not be
 neutral (unless they are in one row or circle).
 
 These can be decluttered by showing graphs where candidate X has an arrow 
 to candidate Y iff X beats Y pairwise, otherwise there is no arrow. Then 
 graph visualization programs can be used to arrange the candidates in a way 
 so that candidates with more pairwise victories (or stronger ones, or 
 whatnot) are closer to the top, or so that Smith set members always appear 
 above non-Smith set members.

Drawing Smith set members above non-Smith set members takes in a way position 
on if Smith set members are all better than all other candidates. That may make 
sense in methods that elect always from the Smith set since at least the winner 
will be drawn close to the top. But also in those (Smith set based) methods 
some members of the Smith set may be further from winning the election than 
some candidates outside the Smit set. I.e. the graph does not indicate how 
close different candidates are to winning the ongoing counting process.

 
 If one wants to visualize Ranked Pairs, it'd be easy to simply color the path 
 throughout the graph to correspond with the pairwise relations/defeats picked 
 by Ranked Pairs.
 

Yes, that approach could work for path based methods.

Ranked Pairs and methods that break all loops or make the opinions 
transitive could also show the candidaes ordered on a line. (But they would 
again lose the approximity to winning information.)

I can't draw any clear conclusions from this on how good Condorcet methods are 
in visualizing the results or an ongoing counting process. The measure of 
number of voters to change the result seems to be quite natural measure of 
distance to victory. Another approach to visualizing the results could be to 
try to point out how good winner each candidate would be. In minmax(margins) 
these measures coincide (measured as additional votes). In Smith set based 
methods I guess

Re: [EM] Conceiving a Democratic Electoral Process

2012-07-25 Thread Juho Laatu
On 25.7.2012, at 19.35, Fred Gohlke wrote:

 Good Morning, Juho
 
 re: In the quoted text I assumed that your question What would
 you think of letting interest groups (or parties) select
 their most effective advocates to compete with other
 candidates for public office? referred to candidates that
 are not set by the electors (starting from the most local
 level) but by the parties. In that case I felt that there
 maybe was a need to allow the regular voters to decide
 instead of letting the party nominated candidates make the
 decisions. But maybe that was not your intended scenario.
 
 Thanks, Juho.  I didn't realize you were speaking of nominees set by the 
 parties.  Now, after thinking about it in the way you intended, I still favor 
 the idea of having the nominees compete with each other to decide which ones 
 will be actual candidates for public office.

Ok, two phases then. One to elect the party candidates (by voters, by party 
members, or by nominees?) and then the final election.

The proportions may be manageable if there are e.g. 1,000,000 voters, 10 
parties, 1000 nominees per party, that elect 10 candidates per party. I wonder 
if you want some proportionality (e.g. betwee two wings of a party) or not. 
That would influence also the first phase.

 
 I'm not speaking of vacuous televised debates where, in a couple of hours, 
 fawning interrogators toss softball questions with inadequate follow-up, and 
 where nominees try to outdo each other by making phony promises in an appeal 
 for public favor.  I'm talking about a real competition conducted in open 
 sessions spanning several weeks, where the various party nominees can be 
 challenged, not only by each other, but by the public and the media; where 
 nominees are pressed when they give misleading or obfuscating responses, and 
 where the election occurs on the day after the nominees make their final 
 choice of candidates.
 
 In a competition like this, each nominee must try to persuade the other 
 nominees to select him or her as the most able candidate.  If they want to be 
 chosen, 'Party nominated candidates' will have to commit themselves to put 
 the public interest above their party's interest in instances where those 
 interests clash, while the competing party nominees will miss no opportunity 
 to show how their partisan bias is a disservice to the public.
 
 This is not the best solution to the political problems we face, but it would 
 be an improvement.  At the very least, it would reduce the deceit and 
 obfuscation that characterize political campaigns.  In terms of goals for a 
 democratic electoral method, it does not address goals 4, 6 or 7.  It meets 
 goals 2, 3, 5, 8 and 9, and although it does not meet goal 1, it improves on 
 present practice.
 
 1) Parties must not be allowed to control the nomination of
   candidates for public office.
 
 2) The electoral method must not require that candidates spend
   vast sums of money to achieve public office.

If the second phase is a traditional election, traditional financing practices 
may apply.

Juho


 
 3) The electoral method must give the people a way to address
   and resolve contemporary issues.
 
 4) The electoral method must allow every member of the electorate
   to become a candidate and participate in the electoral process
   to the full extent of each individual's desire and ability.
 
 5) The electoral method must ensure that all candidates for
   public office are carefully examined to determine their
   integrity and suitability to serve as advocates for the
   people.
 
 6) The electoral method must be repeated frequently (preferably
   annually).
 
 7) The electoral method must include a means for the electorate
   to recall an elected official.
 
 8) The electoral method must ensure that candidates for public
   office are examined, face-to-face, by people with a vital
   interest in ascertaining their character, and the examiners
   must have enough time to investigate their subject thoroughly.
 
 9) The electoral method must accommodate the fact that parties,
   interest groups, factions and enclaves are a vital part of
   society.
 
 Fred
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Conceiving a Democratic Electoral Process

2012-07-22 Thread Juho Laatu
On 23.7.2012, at 0.22, Fred Gohlke wrote:

 re: If we start from low/local level and parties set the
 candidates, I might try giving the decision power on who
 will go to the next levels to the regular voters, and not to
 the candidates that may already be professional politicians.
 
 That is certainly a possibility, although I think it unwise for several 
 reasons:
 
 * as described in an earlier post, those at the lower levels can
  influence those at the higher levels.  Each candidate achieves
  selection by a known list of electors, so communication between
  the electors and the candidate is straightforward.  That
  capability is more important than voting; it lets the electors
  influence, not only the choice of candidates, but the public
  issues on which the candidates will be legislating.

In the quoted text I assumed that your question What would you think of 
letting interest groups (or parties) select their most effective advocates to 
compete with other candidates for public office? referred to candidates that 
are not set by the electors (starting from the most local level) but by the 
parties. In that case I felt that there maybe was a need to allow the regular 
voters to decide instead of letting the party nominated candidates make the 
decisions. But maybe that was not your intended scenario.

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


  1   2   3   4   5   >