RE: Contraceptives and gender discrimination

2012-02-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Isn't there a difference here between (1) accepting specific 
subsidies (federal funds) that the government insists be used for behavior 
that furthers specific government goals, and (2) operat[ing] in the public 
sphere by running hospitals and universities?  By way of analogy, consider the 
Free Speech Clause.  Rust v. Sullivan  says that the government may insist that 
certain funds be used to promote prenatal care and not abortion; and though the 
holding is controversial as to that particular fact pattern, I assume it would 
be uncontroversial as to most other funding programs.  But it hardly follows, I 
take it, that anyone running a hospital could be ordered not to speak out in 
favor of abortion, or even some medical procedure that is not constitutionally 
protected.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steve Sanders
Sent: Monday, February 13, 2012 12:51 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Contraceptives and gender discrimination

What if a hospital is run by a religious group that believes doctrinally and 
sincerely in not using advanced technology or extraordinary interventions to 
prolong human life.  In response, the government says, no, if you want to 
receive federal funds, you'll employ conventional medical standards and 
treatments.  This burdens the institution's religious liberty by requiring it 
to use resources in a way that violates its religious principles, doesn't it?   
Yet in this case, it's highly doubtful that there would be any hew and cry 
about the sect's religious liberty.

Obama's opponents and the Catholic hierarchy have done an effective job 
painting this as an assult on religious liberty.  But let's be honest, this is 
really about controversial (i.e., those that remain part of the culture wars) 
v. non-controversial government mandates.  If a religious group chooses to 
operate in the public sphere by running hospitals and universities, it gives up 
some of its claim to be free of generally applicable government policies and 
regulation.  I had thought that principle was reasonably well settled.  Some 
might say, well yes, if the religious group is running a McDonald's franchise, 
that's different.  But why should profit or tax status be the relevant 
consideration?

Steve Sanders



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Monday, February 13, 2012 10:27 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Contraceptives and gender discrimination
I have to admit that as long as we are talking about private resources, I have 
a hard time understanding the argument that there is no burden on religious 
institutions here. The private resources of religious institutions are 
dedicated to conduct obligated by or at least consistent with religious beliefs 
and doctrine. How can it not be a burden on the institution's religious liberty 
for the state to require those resources to be used in a way that violates the 
religious principles to which the institution is committed.

As for the analogy to taxes, I have always though there was a burden here 
-although it is attenuated, difficult to mitigate, and probably overridden by 
important state interests. But wouldn't a tax imposed on a class including 
religious institutions that was earmarked for a specific purpose -such as 
providing contraceptive services-raise a more difficult question?

Alan Brownstein

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Monday, February 13, 2012 5:50 AM
To: Marc DeGirolami
Cc: Zietlow, Rebecca E.; Walsh, Kevin; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; 
Con Law Prof list
Subject: Re: Contraceptives and gender discrimination

On the burden question -- Religious entities may limit hiring to 
co-religionists, and then make their best efforts to enforce religious norms 
against employees.  Doesn't that option make the burden of the HHS policy far 
less substantial?

I think a common reaction to the religious liberty claim being advanced here is 
its leveraging effect on employees who are not of the faith.  So even if some 
faiths have a religious mission to serve others, do they similarly have a 
religious mission to employ others?  Or is it their religious mission to impede 
access to contraception by all, whether or not of the faith?  If it's the 
latter, I don't know why their position is any different from or stronger than 
taxpayers who don't want to to support what they see as immoral activity by 
their government.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

RE: Contraceptives and gender discrimination

2012-02-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Marty:  I had always thought that substantial burden meant, in 
relevant part, a requirement that I/we do something that I/we believe to be 
religiously wrong.  If this is so, then isn't the only substantial burden 
question whether this particular taxpayer or organization holds such a view, 
and what religions traditionally have done isn't that helpful except insofar 
as it tells us whether this taxpayer or organization has such a view.  Again, 
as Alan pointed out, and as United States v. Lee held, tax-paying requirements 
will almost always pass strict scrutiny; but they might well impose a 
substantial burden.

Now perhaps what's doing the work in the analysis below is 
serious moral injunction; maybe the theory is that if a religious group has 
made its peace with living in America, where tax money goes to all sorts of 
purposes, then the group can't think that paying taxes that go to war, 
abortion, etc. violates a serious moral injunction.  After all, they aren't 
emigrating or going to prison in order to avoid paying the taxes.

But has the substantial burden requirement ever been that 
strong?  I would think that if a group thinks that some compelled behavior - 
whether paying taxes or something else - is sinful, it can still somehow makes 
its peace with going along with the compulsion if forced to, and yet still ask 
for exemptions when possible, no?  Or am I misunderstanding what the rule is?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, February 14, 2012 4:30 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Contraceptives and gender discrimination

Well, if Alan is right that there is a substantial burden every time tax 
dollars are used by the state on something proscribed by someone's religion, 
then the substantial burden component of RFRA is simply an empty vessel -- 
or, in any event, it will be satisfied regularly in countless ordinary 
instances of all states' (and the federal government's) spending programs.

I don't think that can be right.  The question, instead, is whether the 
compelled taxation itself substantially burdens the exercise of one's religion. 
 I assume the answer to that is generally no, because religions traditionally 
have not treated such civil obligations of payment as implicating serious moral 
injunctions imposed upon the religious taxpayers, seeing as how the decision to 
apply the money to the activity in question is always mediated, often several 
times over, by the choices of others (e.g., legislators, government 
bureaucrats, private parties who are given the option of using the funds for 
various forms of health care, etc.).

OK, but then Alan asks:  What about if the tax itself is earmarked 
specifically for expenditure on the proscribed purpose?  Good question -- I 
wonder how many religions would see that as raising a materially different 
problem of complicity by the feepayer or taxpayer than in the case of the 
general tax.  Not many, I suspect, but perhaps I'm wrong.  (I'd greatly welcome 
Catholic and other religious perspectives on this question -- it's relevant to 
something I'm working on.)  But thankfully, we don't have to resolve that 
question here, since the cost to the employer of sponsoring a health insurance 
plan is not earmarked for contraception -- anything but.  The total 
collective expenditure by the insurance company on employees' contraceptives 
will be a drop in the proverbial ocean, since contraceptives are but one, 
woefully insignificant and relatively inexpensive, covered service among 
countless others, many of which are very, very expensive.  Indeed, I'd be 
surprised if the inclusion of contraceptive coverage affects the cost of 
sponsoring the insurance plan (the employer's share of the premium, which I 
don't believe would be compelled by federal law, in any event) at all -- not 
worth the dime, so to speak.
On Mon, Feb 13, 2012 at 1:26 PM, Alan Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:
I have to admit that as long as we are talking about private resources, I have 
a hard time understanding the argument that there is no burden on religious 
institutions here. The private resources of religious institutions are 
dedicated to conduct obligated by or at least consistent with religious beliefs 
and doctrine. How can it not be a burden on the institution's religious liberty 
for the state to require those resources to be used in a way that violates the 
religious principles to which the institution is committed.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can 

Post length

2012-02-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Folks:  The list software is configured to block posts that are longer than 40 
Kbytes, and I prefer to keep that block, since it helps avoid overflowing 
users' mailboxes.  Almost always, the long posts are ones that just 
automatically quote lots of earlier posts in the thread.  If you get a message 
saying that your post is too long, just please edit the post to get rid of most 
of the quoted posts, and resubmit it; that should fix the problem.  Thanks,

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

2012-02-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm with Jim in what I see as his skepticism as to the 
suggestion that exceptions from a law make it not of general applicability 
for Free Exercise Clause purposes.  (I realize that some post-Smith cases take 
this view, but I think they are mistaken.)  A vast range of laws, probably most 
laws, have some exceptions.  Killing people is murder, except in self-defense 
or defense of others or in executing a lawful order or in fighting lawfully in 
war or (in some jurisdictions) under duress or if you're adequately provoked 
(in the latter case it's still a crime but not murder).  Title VII's ban on sex 
discrimination has exemptions for small employers and for BFOQs.  The duty to 
testify has exceptions galore.  So does copyright law.  So does contract law.  
Statutory rape law in many states has exceptions for a minor's spouse, or 
people close in age to the minor.  Trespass law has exceptions for necessity, 
for easements by prescription, for permissible government action, and more.

Are all these laws therefore not covered by Smith?  (What 
really is left then for Smith?)  What's more, if the exceptions make the law 
not of general applicability, and thus trigger strict scrutiny, wouldn't they 
also make the law underinclusive, and thus make it fail strict scrutiny - so 
that religious objectors would get exemptions from murder law, trespass law, 
copyright law, contract law, statutory rape law, trespass law, the duty to 
testify, and so on?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of James Edward Maule
Sent: Monday, February 13, 2012 10:55 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The contraception mandate under Empoyment Division v Smith

I have a question about laws of general applicability. More than a few posts 
ago, someone - I apologize for not remembering who - gave the speed limit law 
as an example of a law of general applicability. I recall the point was that 
even if a person or religious organization had a religious reason for violating 
the speed limit, the claim would fail.

Thus, I wonder about the argument being made by the Becket Fund. The speed 
limit set by the speed limit law (a) does not apply to everyone (e.g., 
emergency vehicles), (b) [can't think of an analogy], and (c) provides for a 
system of individualized exemptions in the form of permits issued to allow 
violation of the minimum speed requirement for transporting certain large 
objects (and I think there are some instances where permits can be obtained to 
exceed the stated maximum).

Thus, I wonder, are these the tests for finding a law not to be of general 
applicability?

Jim Maule

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Will Esser
Sent: Monday, February 13, 2012 1:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The contraception mandate under Empoyment Division v Smith

Brad,

In the complaint filed by Belmont Abbey College challenging the contraception 
mandate, the Becket Fund argues that the contraception mandate is not a law of 
general applicability because among other things (a) it does not apply to all 
employers (for instance it does not apply to employers with fewer than 50 
employees); (b) it does not apply to certain grandfathered insurance plans; 
and (c) it provides for a system of individualized exemptions by allowing HHS 
the ability to grant waivers in response to individualized requests.  You can 
access the complaint here:

 
http://www.becketfund.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/11/HHS-Complaint-Final11.10.11.pdf)

Maybe the question to be asked is which law must be of general applicability? 
 In Smith, it strikes me that the peyote statute was a stand alone criminal 
law.  In this instance, I understood that the contraception mandate was just 
one component of the overall  federal healthcare reform act.  So it seems to me 
that in interpreting whether the law is one of general applicability, a court 
would be required to look at the entire healthcare reform act and determine 
what waivers and exemptions were included in it, rather than just narrowly 
focusing on the contraception mandate itself.

Thoughts?

Will


Will Esser --- Ad Majorem Dei Gloriam
Charlotte, North Carolina


We can easily forgive a child who is afraid of the dark;
the real tragedy is when men are afraid of the light.
(Attributed to Plato, 428-345 B.C.)


--- On Sat, 2/11/12, Brad Pardee 
bp51...@windstream.netmailto:bp51...@windstream.net wrote:

From: Brad Pardee bp51...@windstream.netmailto:bp51...@windstream.net
Subject: The contraception mandate under Empoyment Division v Smith
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Date: Saturday, February 11, 2012, 12:31 AM

I've been following the coverage of the mandate that religious 

RE: FW: RFRA substantial burden analysis

2012-02-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Whoops, sorry for the jarring shift from the second person to 
the third person in the third paragraph 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, February 14, 2012 9:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: FW: RFRA substantial burden analysis

Marty:  Doesn't this all depend on what you mean by facially plausible in 
whether the objector has at least articulated a facially plausible explanation 
of why being compelled to engage in the conduct in question would impose a 
materially different and more severe burden on religious exercise than the 
conduct in which the person or organization regularly engages without any 
notion that it results in 'proximate material cooperation with evil'?

I would think that it's obviously facially plausible to say that, once an 
employee has gotten a paycheck, the church is no longer responsible for what 
the employee does with it, but when a church is buying an insurance policy, it 
is responsible for the items that the insurance policy covers.  Indeed, this 
seems to be much like the line drawn by four Justices in Zelman:  Once the 
government gives someone money (a salary, welfare payments, unemployment 
compensation, etc.), the government is not responsible for the recipient's use 
of the money for religious purposes, but when the government is handing out 
education vouchers, it is responsible.  And if you object that the program in 
Zelman mostly involved religious beneficiaries (of course, a highly contested 
question that turns on what denominator you use), consider the Washington 
Supreme Court's decision in Witters - or for that matter, the Washington state 
rule in Locke v. Davey - that applied the same distinction to a program whose 
beneficiaries were indubitably overwhelmingly secular.  Naturally, one involves 
felt complicity in sin and the other felt subsidization of religious doctrine, 
but the underlying point for purposes of the proximate material cooperation 
line is the same.

But it sounds like Marty requires more than just this level of facially 
plausible.  And if we get past that level (or even to this level), then we're 
getting into the very sort of inquiry into the reasonableness of religious 
beliefs that the Court has rightly rejected.  Say that an orthodox Jew insists 
that he needs a diet that doesn't mix chicken and milk.  Will we start 
demanding a facially plausible explanation - in the sense of one that persuades 
us of its reasonableness - for why the bar on seething a kid in its other milk 
should extend to chicken but not to fish?  Or how about an orthodox Jew who 
does some things on the Sabbath but not others.  Will we start demanding a 
facially plausible explanation of why he can enter this kind of elevator but 
not that kind of elevator?  Religious rules are often based on distinctions 
that are facially implausible to outsiders.

It seems to me that the Court's view has consistently been that requiring 
someone to do something that he sincerely feels is religiously forbidden is a 
substantial burden, with no requirement of proof of plausibility - see, e.g., 
Thomas.  And this strikes me as quite right both in general, and in this case 
in particular.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, February 14, 2012 9:12 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: FW: RFRA substantial burden analysis

I don't think anyone on this list would advocate a full-fledged trial on 
Catholic moral theology.  I certainly wouldn't.  What I have been suggesting, 
instead, is that courts might look to the objector's own conduct to see if it 
is reflective of a religious commitment that would be substantially burdened if 
an exemption were denied.  Moreover, the government might ask whether the 
objector has at least articulated a facially plausible explanation of why being 
compelled to engage in the conduct in question would impose a materially 
different and more severe burden on religious exercise than the conduct in 
which the person or organization regularly engages without any notion that it 
results in proximate material cooperation with evil.  The objector doesn't 
have to persuade the court (or in this case HHS) of the correctness of its 
religious view and of the viability of such distinctions.  But it can't really 
be enough (can it?) for the court to accept Eugene's view that it must assume a 
substantial burden based on the objector's mere say-so, in a case where its 
dollars or resources are used, down the line and pursuant to intervening 
genuine and independent private choice (Zelman, Agostini), for activity that 
the employer finds morally objectionable, and where the employer regularly 
allows its resources to be used for those same foreseeable ends in other 
contexts.

Quite honestly, my

RE: FW: RFRA substantial burden analysis

2012-02-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Marty:  Doesn't this all depend on what you mean by facially plausible in 
whether the objector has at least articulated a facially plausible explanation 
of why being compelled to engage in the conduct in question would impose a 
materially different and more severe burden on religious exercise than the 
conduct in which the person or organization regularly engages without any 
notion that it results in 'proximate material cooperation with evil'?

I would think that it's obviously facially plausible to say that, once an 
employee has gotten a paycheck, the church is no longer responsible for what 
the employee does with it, but when a church is buying an insurance policy, it 
is responsible for the items that the insurance policy covers.  Indeed, this 
seems to be much like the line drawn by four Justices in Zelman:  Once the 
government gives someone money (a salary, welfare payments, unemployment 
compensation, etc.), the government is not responsible for the recipient's use 
of the money for religious purposes, but when the government is handing out 
education vouchers, it is responsible.  And if you object that the program in 
Zelman mostly involved religious beneficiaries (of course, a highly contested 
question that turns on what denominator you use), consider the Washington 
Supreme Court's decision in Witters - or for that matter, the Washington state 
rule in Locke v. Davey - that applied the same distinction to a program whose 
beneficiaries were indubitably overwhelmingly secular.  Naturally, one involves 
felt complicity in sin and the other felt subsidization of religious doctrine, 
but the underlying point for purposes of the proximate material cooperation 
line is the same.

But it sounds like Marty requires more than just this level of facially 
plausible.  And if we get past that level (or even to this level), then we're 
getting into the very sort of inquiry into the reasonableness of religious 
beliefs that the Court has rightly rejected.  Say that an orthodox Jew insists 
that he needs a diet that doesn't mix chicken and milk.  Will we start 
demanding a facially plausible explanation - in the sense of one that persuades 
us of its reasonableness - for why the bar on seething a kid in its other milk 
should extend to chicken but not to fish?  Or how about an orthodox Jew who 
does some things on the Sabbath but not others.  Will we start demanding a 
facially plausible explanation of why he can enter this kind of elevator but 
not that kind of elevator?  Religious rules are often based on distinctions 
that are facially implausible to outsiders.

It seems to me that the Court's view has consistently been that requiring 
someone to do something that he sincerely feels is religiously forbidden is a 
substantial burden, with no requirement of proof of plausibility - see, e.g., 
Thomas.  And this strikes me as quite right both in general, and in this case 
in particular.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, February 14, 2012 9:12 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: FW: RFRA substantial burden analysis

I don't think anyone on this list would advocate a full-fledged trial on 
Catholic moral theology.  I certainly wouldn't.  What I have been suggesting, 
instead, is that courts might look to the objector's own conduct to see if it 
is reflective of a religious commitment that would be substantially burdened if 
an exemption were denied.  Moreover, the government might ask whether the 
objector has at least articulated a facially plausible explanation of why being 
compelled to engage in the conduct in question would impose a materially 
different and more severe burden on religious exercise than the conduct in 
which the person or organization regularly engages without any notion that it 
results in proximate material cooperation with evil.  The objector doesn't 
have to persuade the court (or in this case HHS) of the correctness of its 
religious view and of the viability of such distinctions.  But it can't really 
be enough (can it?) for the court to accept Eugene's view that it must assume a 
substantial burden based on the objector's mere say-so, in a case where its 
dollars or resources are used, down the line and pursuant to intervening 
genuine and independent private choice (Zelman, Agostini), for activity that 
the employer finds morally objectionable, and where the employer regularly 
allows its resources to be used for those same foreseeable ends in other 
contexts.

Quite honestly, my principal objective here is not to resolve the RFRA 
question, but instead to ask, at an earlier point in the process, why the state 
should grant the requested permissive accommodation in the first instance and, 
perhaps more importantly, to prompt thoughtful people within the Catholic 
tradition to give further consideration to whether this would, in fact, be a 
case 

Apropos Sherbert v. Verner

2012-02-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
A question:  Say that an employee believes that God wants him to move across 
country to be near his family, which needs his help.  He quits his job, moves, 
but can't find a job where his family lives.  Should he be seen as 
constitutionally entitled to unemployment compensation?

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: contraceptives and RFRA

2012-02-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree with Chip that some burdens aren't treated as 
substantial, see Lyng and Bowen (both of which I think were correctly decided). 
 But Lyng and Bowen involved situations where the restriction did not require a 
claimant to do something that the claimant believed to be religiously wrong.  
My understanding of the caselaw is that any requirement that one do something 
one believes to be religiously wrong is a substantial burden - and I don't 
really see a plausible alternative.

I agree that this means that similar claims could be raised not 
just by religiously affiliated institutions, but also by institutions whose 
owners have those beliefs.  But why should that go to the substantial burden 
question, rather than to the application of strict scrutiny?  That, as I 
understand it, is exactly how the Court decided Lee and Bob Jones; why 
shouldn't it use a similar approach here (whatever the result might be)?

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 12:28 PM
To: conlawp...@lists.ucla.edu; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: contraceptives and RFRA

Having processed this rich conversation, I find myself convinced that a) the 
objecting religious institutions see themselves as burdened by these rules, and 
that government should not second-guess that determination, but b) the question 
of substantiality has to be for the government under some sort of objective 
standards (character of conflict? degree of conflict? cost of defiance?  ease 
of avoidability?).  If any and every objector gets to self-determine both 
substantiality and burden, then every case of enforcement of federal law can 
become a RFRA case, with the government always having to satisfy strict 
scrutiny or allowing opt-out.  That CAN'T be right.  (And it wasn't the law 
under Free Exercise, pre-Smith.  See Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery 
Protective Ass'n; Bowen v. Roy.)

But let's assume that the complainants in the filed RFRA cases (a college, a 
university, a religious media network) can satisfy the substantial burden 
test.  If they can, so can every entity, non-profit or profit, controlled by 
those with similar religious beliefs.  Moreover, this can't possibly be limited 
to objections to contraception and arguably abortifacient drugs. Other 
employers may assert religious objection to the provision of highly intrusive 
(and very expensive) end-of-life treatments, on the grounds that they are 
sinful and immoral attempts to defy divine will about when someone's time has 
come.  Others may object on religious grounds to any use of conventional 
medical care.

Are we not thus in a place quite like U.S. v. Lee, where the Supreme Court 
rejects an opt-out claim by the Amish from the obligation of employers to pay 
contributions, and withhold employee contributions, under the Federal Insurance 
Contribution Act (FICA), because the Court perceives that a scheme of social 
insurance (in that case, Social Security) depends on universal participation?  
Allowing some to opt out of an expensive obligation on religious grounds will 
invite fraudulent claims, be administratively very difficult, and will 
eventually gut the system.  Isn't the ACA system similarly one of universal 
social/medical insurance, albeit one with more of a role for private providers? 
 And if so, wouldn't the result be the same in the filed ACA cases as in Lee?  
(Of course, HHS (or Congress) could create a more limited exemption, as HHS has 
already done.  But the scope of that permissive accommodation would be for 
political decision, not judicial decision under RFRA.  And that political 
decision (for better and worse) does not depend on principled, consistent 
standards of which burdens are substantial.  It depends on clout.

--
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053tel:%28202%29994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

2012-02-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Mark:  A few hypotheticals:  (1)  Say that a state provides 
that adequate provocation makes killing manslaughter rather than murder, and 
that a particular set of behaviors - having sex with the defendant's spouse, 
having just beaten a defendant (but in a situation where the peril is over and 
no self-defense is allowed), and some other things - qualify as adequate 
provocation.  And say that this defense is indeed used in dozens of cases a 
year.  Someone kills someone for what he perceives is blasphemy, and argues 
that his religious sense of provocation should be treated the same as the 
provocation in the adultery, assault, etc. examples, so that he would be guilty 
only of manslaughter rather than murder.  He argues that this presumptively 
entitles him to an exemption, and that it indeed the presumption can't be 
rebutted under strict scrutiny because murder law is underinclusive.
(2)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to testify 
against his children or parents, or against coreligionists, or in other 
contexts.  He points to all the privileges recognized as defenses to the duty 
to testify, and argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle him to an 
exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under strict 
scrutiny because the duty to testify is underinclusive.

(3)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to hire women to 
work together with men, or not to hire women with small children at home.  He 
points to the BFOQ exemption and to the exemption for small employers, both of 
which would exclude many more employees from Title VII's protection than would 
his proposed exemption.  He argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle 
him to an exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under 
strict scrutiny because antidiscrimination law is underinclusive.

(4)  Someone feels a religious obligation to spread the word of 
God for free; that word happens to be in a book whose copyright is owned by 
others.  His claim isn't just to a right to do this in church, but to a right 
to do this everywhere.  He points to the many exceptions from copyright law, 
from 17 USC 107 to 17 USC 122 (each of the sixteen sections contains at least 
one exemption).  He argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle him to 
an exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under strict 
scrutiny because copyright law is underinclusive.

Is it really the case that all these laws should be subject to 
strict scrutiny - especially given that the underinclusiveness prong of strict 
scrutiny might well make the laws invalid under such a test?

My thinking is that the answer is no.  Most laws involve the 
reconciliation of competing interests, including competing private interests 
that the government is trying to protect; and I don't think that the fact that 
someone has a religious motivation to do something constitutionally entitles 
him to the best treatment available to others.  That my rights as a copyright 
owner are limited in some ways to serve rival concerns doesn't mean that 
there's a constitutional obligation on the government's part to limit them 
further in order to serve some people's view of what God demands - a view that 
is not my view, and to which my rights should not, I think, bend.  But whatever 
one might think of this as a matter of first principles, it seems to me that 
this most favored nations approach likely yields results, in cases such as 
the ones I described above, that are rightly seen as improper.

Eugene



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 9:16 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Paul rightly asks us to consider more than just formalism. History is 
important, and I think the concern about freedom of the church goes back at 
least to Pope Gregory (?) in the 11th (?) Century. Cf. Antigone.

I've suggested elsewhere that a historical approach to what constitutes free 
exercise might help us understand it. But here is some more somewhat 
formalistic analysis:

I have always understood the general applicability test to involve a kind of 
most favored nations concern. Are other exceptions allowed to undercut the 
basis purpose of a law to roughly the same degree that a religious exception 
would undercut it? If so, the law is not of general applicability. For example, 
if a prohibition law permitted sale and consumption of beer it would need to 
permit sale and consumption of wine for communion or for Shabbat or Passover 
dinners. If there is a copyright law exception for fair use of music in 
schools, then an exception must be made for church services. 

RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

2012-02-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
No, I think it's mistaken, and likewise with the more recent 
steel wheels case, Mitchell County v. Zimmerman (Iowa Feb. 3, 2012), 
http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=9939422895334605795 .  The 
conclusion that a public employer's provision of medical exemptions should 
likewise require the employer to recognize religious exemptions strikes me as 
quite unsound.  Consider some examples:

Many public employers would often give months-long leaves to people who are, 
for instance, battling cancer; does it follow that they are constitutionally 
obligated to give similar leaves to people who feel a religious obligation to 
go on a months-long religious pilgrimage?

A public employer whose employee has a peanut allergy (or perhaps even a less 
deadly allergy) might order its cafeteria not to cook with peanuts or peanut 
oil; does it follow that it is constitutionally obligated to order its 
cafeteria to cook only with kosher meats, and eschew pork or shrimp or mixed 
meat and milk, in order to make the cafeteria usable by a kosher-keeping 
employee?

A public university might excuse people with post-traumatic stress disorder 
from certain assignments that might trigger a bad reaction - e.g., a rape 
victim might be excused from an assignment that involves a rape case.  Does it 
follow that the university must excuse religious objectors from all assignments 
that they feel to be religiously objectionable, e.g., because they involve what 
the objector perceives as blasphemy?

The list could go on; but the basic point, it seems to me, remains - that we 
sometimes cut slack for those who are sick, and sacrifice the interests of 
taxpayers and of other employees in order to help the sick, doesn't mean that 
we have to sacrifice such interests in order to help those who feel a religious 
command that the taxpayers and other employees do not share.  (Of course, some 
people might support the result in Fraternal Order of Police v. Newark on the 
grounds that the government interests in that case were negligible; I'm not 
sure that's right, and I'm not sure that courts should make such decisions in 
such cases - but, even if they do, that would be reason for adopting some sort 
of weak intermediate scrutiny in such cases, not for adopting strict scrutiny.)

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 11:32 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Eugene,

I will try to respond to your hypos later today, but here is a non-hypothetical 
question: Do you think Fraternal Order of Police v. Newark was correctly 
decided?

Best,
Mark

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 9:44 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Mark:  A few hypotheticals:  (1)  Say that a state provides 
that adequate provocation makes killing manslaughter rather than murder, and 
that a particular set of behaviors - having sex with the defendant's spouse, 
having just beaten a defendant (but in a situation where the peril is over and 
no self-defense is allowed), and some other things - qualify as adequate 
provocation.  And say that this defense is indeed used in dozens of cases a 
year.  Someone kills someone for what he perceives is blasphemy, and argues 
that his religious sense of provocation should be treated the same as the 
provocation in the adultery, assault, etc. examples, so that he would be guilty 
only of manslaughter rather than murder.  He argues that this presumptively 
entitles him to an exemption, and that it indeed the presumption can't be 
rebutted under strict scrutiny because murder law is underinclusive.

(2)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to testify 
against his children or parents, or against coreligionists, or in other 
contexts.  He points to all the privileges recognized as defenses to the duty 
to testify, and argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle him to an 
exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under strict 
scrutiny because the duty to testify is underinclusive.

(3)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to hire women to 
work together with men, or not to hire women with small children at home.  He 
points to the BFOQ exemption and to the exemption for small employers, both of 
which would exclude many more employees from Title VII's protection than would 
his proposed exemption.  He argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle 
him to an exemption, and that indeed

RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

2012-02-18 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Setting aside Smith's exception for Sherbert, and setting aside 
the argument that South Carolina law's protection of Sunday observers 
discriminated against Saturday observers, I would agree with the dissent in 
Sherbert.  That unemployment compensation law has a good cause exemption, 
under which some secular causes are treated as sufficient but many as 
insufficient, doesn't mean that religious causes should be treated as well as 
the favored secular causes.

By analogy, as I mentioned, murder law has an exception for adequate 
provocation (which reduces the charge to manslaughter).  Copyright law has an 
exception for fair use.  The duty to testify has an exemption for those 
privileges that courts create in light of experience and reason, as well as the 
Rule 403 free-form admissibility balancing.  Title VII has an exception for 
bona fide occupational qualifications.  In many states, many criminal laws 
have a free-form lesser evil defense.  Trespass law has a private necessity 
defense.  Nuisance law in many jurisdictions involves pretty free-form 
balancing, as does negligence law.  It doesn't follow, I think, that claims for 
religious exemptions - entitlement to a manslaughter defense when the 
provocation is blasphemy, entitlement to use others' copyrighted works for any 
religious reasons, the right to refuse to testify when one thinks testimony 
would be religiously wrong, the right not to hire women when one's religion so 
calls, the right to escape criminal liability or trespass tort liability 
because of religious necessity, the right to interfere with others' enjoyment 
of their property when one has religious justification, or the right to have 
one's actions that injure another's property be declared reasonable because 
of one's religious motivations - should be treated as favorably as the most 
favorably treated secular motivations.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 11:55 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Similar question: Eugene, how would you today decide Sherbert v. Verner, with 
its good cause requirement?

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 2:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Eugene,

I will try to respond to your hypos later today, but here is a non-hypothetical 
question: Do you think Fraternal Order of Police v. Newark was correctly 
decided?

Best,
Mark

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 9:44 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Mark:  A few hypotheticals:  (1)  Say that a state provides 
that adequate provocation makes killing manslaughter rather than murder, and 
that a particular set of behaviors - having sex with the defendant's spouse, 
having just beaten a defendant (but in a situation where the peril is over and 
no self-defense is allowed), and some other things - qualify as adequate 
provocation.  And say that this defense is indeed used in dozens of cases a 
year.  Someone kills someone for what he perceives is blasphemy, and argues 
that his religious sense of provocation should be treated the same as the 
provocation in the adultery, assault, etc. examples, so that he would be guilty 
only of manslaughter rather than murder.  He argues that this presumptively 
entitles him to an exemption, and that it indeed the presumption can't be 
rebutted under strict scrutiny because murder law is underinclusive.

(2)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to testify 
against his children or parents, or against coreligionists, or in other 
contexts.  He points to all the privileges recognized as defenses to the duty 
to testify, and argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle him to an 
exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under strict 
scrutiny because the duty to testify is underinclusive.

(3)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to hire women to 
work together with men, or not to hire women with small children at home.  He 
points to the BFOQ exemption and to the exemption for small employers, both of 
which would exclude many more employees from Title VII's protection than would 
his proposed exemption.  He argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle 
him to an exemption

FW: Answering Eugene's hypos

2012-03-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
 (or for not practicing someone else's).

In addition, the traditional mitigating factors are retail in nature:  if I 
sleep with someone's wife, he may become enraged and kill me on the spot, but I 
won't be in danger from thousands of people who want to kill me for doing that 
(unless I'm Don Juan or Benjamin Franklin). Ditto if I beat someone up; he or 
she might become enraged and kill me, but it would only be one person who would 
be out for my blood. Or if I kill someone then one family or perhaps one family 
member might seek revenge. (My name is Inigo Montoya. You killed my father. 
Prepare to die. But in our world, Inigo would not be able to claim that his 
killing of Count Rugen was manslaughter, would he?) By contrast, there could be 
thousands of people who would want to kill me for committing blasphemy; it's 
more of a wholesale matter. That's certainly true historically, and, 
unfortunately it is once again becoming true. Consider Salman Rushdie and the 
cartoonists and publishers of the Mohammed cartoons. Consider all the people 
who died in riots over those cartoons. Consider the members of religious 
minorities who are killed by mobs because of rumors of blasphemy.

There are other distinctions that could be drawn, but I think this analysis 
makes my point. The purposes of our laws would  be very seriously undercut if a 
religious blasphemy motivation were sufficient to turn murder into 
manslaughter. The damage to the law's purposes would substantially exceed the 
damage caused by the traditional mitigating factors that differentiate 
manslaughter from murder. Under Justice (then Judge) Alito's analysis in 
Fraternal Order of Police, I think this is not even close.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law




From: Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 11:32 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Eugene,

I will try to respond to your hypos later today, but here is a non-hypothetical 
question: Do you think Fraternal Order of Police v. Newark was correctly 
decided?

Best,
Mark

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 9:44 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Mark:  A few hypotheticals:  (1)  Say that a state provides 
that adequate provocation makes killing manslaughter rather than murder, and 
that a particular set of behaviors - having sex with the defendant's spouse, 
having just beaten a defendant (but in a situation where the peril is over and 
no self-defense is allowed), and some other things - qualify as adequate 
provocation.  And say that this defense is indeed used in dozens of cases a 
year.  Someone kills someone for what he perceives is blasphemy, and argues 
that his religious sense of provocation should be treated the same as the 
provocation in the adultery, assault, etc. examples, so that he would be guilty 
only of manslaughter rather than murder.  He argues that this presumptively 
entitles him to an exemption, and that it indeed the presumption can't be 
rebutted under strict scrutiny because murder law is underinclusive.

(2)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to testify 
against his children or parents, or against coreligionists, or in other 
contexts.  He points to all the privileges recognized as defenses to the duty 
to testify, and argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle him to an 
exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under strict 
scrutiny because the duty to testify is underinclusive.

(3)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to hire women to 
work together with men, or not to hire women with small children at home.  He 
points to the BFOQ exemption and to the exemption for small employers, both of 
which would exclude many more employees from Title VII's protection than would 
his proposed exemption.  He argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle 
him to an exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under 
strict scrutiny because antidiscrimination law is underinclusive.

(4)  Someone feels a religious obligation to spread the word of 
God for free; that word happens to be in a book whose copyright is owned by 
others.  His claim isn't just to a right to do this in church, but to a right 
to do this everywhere.  He points to the many exceptions from copyright law, 
from 17 USC 107 to 17 USC 122 (each of the sixteen sections contains at least 
one exemption).  He argues that these exceptions presumptively

RE: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

2012-03-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The trouble with “common sense” is that it often points in 
different directions.  Common sense tells us there is real value to following 
rules with no exceptions, so that one doesn’t have to later deal with questions 
of “you accommodated them, why don’t you accommodate” us (even when the future 
request for accommodation might be different from the current one), and also to 
having a schedule that is predictable, especially given that team members and 
others related to the team may often plan their schedules around the 
preannounced playing schedule.  Common sense also tells us that there is real 
value to being flexible, especially for what could be a once-in-a-lifetime 
event for the kids in whose interest the league is supposed to be operating.

Likewise, respect for others sometimes includes changing your plans for others 
– and sometimes not insisting that others change their plans for you.  On 
balance, I’m pleased with TAPPS’ ultimate decision to accommodate the Jewish 
team, but I’m not sure that “common sense” and “respect” by themselves resolve 
this question.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Finkelman, Paul 
paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
Sent: Saturday, March 03, 2012 12:32 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

The common sense is what is often lacking and with a sense of fairness and 
toleration.  Apparently for the leaders of the TAPP common sense means 
everyone is a Christian and all people have a Sunday sabbath.  The lawyers 
serve as educator to teach common sense and respect for other religions.

Connected by DROID on Verizon Wireless


-Original message-
From: Alan Armstrong alanarmstrong@verizon.net
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sat, Mar 3, 2012 19:56:56 GMT+00:00
Subject: Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath
My understanding is that Jewish and 7th day adventists consider sabbath as 
going from sundown on Friday to sundown on Saturday. I do not know of any 
christian denominations that use sundown Saturday to sundown on Sunday as the 
Lord's day.Therefore a Saturday night game should be acceptable to all.

A little thought and common sense and we would need fewer lawyers.

Alan

Law Office of Alan Leigh Armstrong
Office 18652 Florida St., Suite 225
Huntington Beach CA 92648-6006
Mail 16835 Algonquin St., Suite 454
Huntington Beach CA 92649-3810
714 375 1147 fax 714 782 6007
a...@alanarmstrong.commailto:a...@alanarmstrong.com
Serving the family and small business since 1984
NOTICE:
 Any tax advice in this e-mail, including attachments, can not be used to
avoid penalties or for the promotion of a tax related matter.








On Mar 2, 2012, at 11:48 AM, Douglas Laycock wrote:


Some of you may have seen the story in the Times the other day about the Beren 
Hebrew Academy in Houston, whose basketball team has reached the state 
semi-finals of the Texas Association of Private and Parochial Schools 
tournament. The semifinal game was scheduled for tonight; the Academy is 
Orthodox and observant, and could not play.  The other school was willing to 
reschedule, but the TAPPS Board voted 8-0 not to allow that. Most TAPPS members 
are church affiliated, and as a matter of policy, it never schedules games on 
Sunday.

Beren parents and students filed a lawsuit this morning in the Northern 
District of Texas, alleging unconstitutional religious discrimination, Texas 
RFRA, and breach of contract (based on a provision in the TAPPS bylaws). The 
complaint’s state action theory was that the game was scheduled to be played in 
a public school gym, which is surely not enough. The contract claim looked 
stronger, judging only by the complaint.

Richard Friedman at Michigan tells me that TAPPS caved as soon as the complaint 
was filed, and that the game will begin imminently and will be completed before 
sunset.  If your position is utterly untenable as a matter of public relations, 
it may not matter that the other side’s state action theory is very weak. But 
they had to file the lawsuit before common sense could prevail.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
= div=
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

2012-03-04 Thread Volokh, Eugene
How would travel concerns affect this?  Since Orthodox Jews 
can't drive on the Sabbath, I assume they would often have to drive out during 
the day Friday and stay over the Sabbath.  Would that be an acceptable burden 
on the students?  Or would this itself be seen as a sufficient burden that it 
should justify rescheduling the game for some other day, when the team won't 
need to have the 24 hours of down time?  These aren't rhetorical questions - I 
don't know the answer to them - but they seem relevant in figuring out how easy 
or difficult such accommodations will tend to be.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Armstrong
Sent: Saturday, March 03, 2012 11:55 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

My understanding is that Jewish and 7th day adventists consider sabbath as 
going from sundown on Friday to sundown on Saturday. I do not know of any 
christian denominations that use sundown Saturday to sundown on Sunday as the 
Lord's day.Therefore a Saturday night game should be acceptable to all.

A little thought and common sense and we would need fewer lawyers.

Alan

Law Office of Alan Leigh Armstrong
Office 18652 Florida St., Suite 225
Huntington Beach CA 92648-6006
Mail 16835 Algonquin St., Suite 454
Huntington Beach CA 92649-3810
714 375 1147 fax 714 782 6007
a...@alanarmstrong.commailto:a...@alanarmstrong.com
Serving the family and small business since 1984
NOTICE:
 Any tax advice in this e-mail, including attachments, can not be used to
avoid penalties or for the promotion of a tax related matter.








On Mar 2, 2012, at 11:48 AM, Douglas Laycock wrote:


Some of you may have seen the story in the Times the other day about the Beren 
Hebrew Academy in Houston, whose basketball team has reached the state 
semi-finals of the Texas Association of Private and Parochial Schools 
tournament. The semifinal game was scheduled for tonight; the Academy is 
Orthodox and observant, and could not play.  The other school was willing to 
reschedule, but the TAPPS Board voted 8-0 not to allow that. Most TAPPS members 
are church affiliated, and as a matter of policy, it never schedules games on 
Sunday.

Beren parents and students filed a lawsuit this morning in the Northern 
District of Texas, alleging unconstitutional religious discrimination, Texas 
RFRA, and breach of contract (based on a provision in the TAPPS bylaws). The 
complaint's state action theory was that the game was scheduled to be played in 
a public school gym, which is surely not enough. The contract claim looked 
stronger, judging only by the complaint.

Richard Friedman at Michigan tells me that TAPPS caved as soon as the complaint 
was filed, and that the game will begin imminently and will be completed before 
sunset.  If your position is utterly untenable as a matter of public relations, 
it may not matter that the other side's state action theory is very weak. But 
they had to file the lawsuit before common sense could prevail.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

2012-03-04 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I wonder whether religious liberty is exactly the right term here, where 
we're talking about access to a privately provided program, and one that is 
hardly essential for life or livelihood.  The question isn't just whether 
Orthodox Jews are free to live as good Orthodox Jews, or even are free to get 
broadly available benefits of the welfare state that are important to survival 
(such as unemployment compensation).  Rather, the question is whether other 
private parties should adapt their behavior -- their exercise of their own 
liberty -- to accommodate Orthodox Jews' felt religious obligations.  That's an 
interesting question, and the answer might well be that they should so adapt 
their behavior, if it's a low-cost adaptation, out of hospitality or kindness 
or application of the Golden Rule or some such.  But I think that talk of 
liberty here is not very helpful.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein [aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu]
Sent: Sunday, March 04, 2012 12:33 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath


I don't view these issues as absolute Yes or No questions. I think 
tournament organizers should take the religious beliefs of participants into 
account, but there will be situations where the cost to others of particular 
accommodations will be too high for the requested accommodation to be granted.



Some accommodations are relatively low cost. If two semi-final games are going 
to be played Saturday afternoon and evening, why shouldn't the organizers 
accommodate the needs of a religious school's team that observes Saturday as 
the Sabbath and schedule their game for the evening rather the afternoon? Some 
rejections of accommodations create unnecessary burdens for religious schools. 
In the Oregon litigation I referenced earlier, the tournament organizers 
refused to allow the Adventist School's team to play in any tournament games 
unless they would commit to playing every game scheduled even if it fell on the 
Sabbath.



Other harder cases may involve higher costs. Even here, however, sometimes 
there may be creative solutions that mitigate burdens or spread costs. If we 
value religious liberty and are concerned about the exclusion and isolation of 
religious minorities, we should take accommodation problems seriously -- 
although that does not mean that the accommodation will always be granted.



Alan Brownstein
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree with Paul's point, and realize that I should make my statement more 
precise.  Common sense tells us there is real value to following rules with a 
minimum number of exceptions, and especially exceptions that are limited to 
truly extraordinary situations.  Indeed, if a tornado knocks out the arena 
where a game is to be played, you can't very well play the game that day.  
Likewise, if one of the tournament teams' buses crashes the day before, and 
most of the team is killed, it makes sense that all the other teams might 
postpone their games out of grief and respect for the dead.

But common sense tells us that there is still value for reserving exceptions 
for such extraordinary cases.  Now, as I said, there is also value for allowing 
exceptions even outside extraordinary cases; it may well be that an exception 
ought to be made.  My point -- on which Paul and I agree -- is simply that 
common sense doesn't generally resolve this sort of tension.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz [phorw...@hotmail.com]
Sent: Saturday, March 03, 2012 7:42 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

I agree generally with Eugene's point--which I would generalize to just 
about every situation--that common sense, like many other such phrases 
(certainly including respect, or the rule of law) is too capacious a term 
to resolve most disputes. In this case, one would have to both understand and 
expand the context sufficiently to help one reach a reasonable resolution of 
the dispute, and even then there would be more than one such resolution. In 
this case, it seems to me that the road to a reasonable resolution of the 
problem lies in the fact that TAPPS opened itself to a situation in which it 
welcomed the possibility of sporting events involving others whose religious 
needs might require accommodation. If the league had remained solely devoted to 
Christian schools and, in effect, had valued Christian community over sports or 
all-state intramural play itself, then refusing to change its schedule would a) 
be reasonable and b) not be much of a problem, since the issue would be 
unlikely ever to arise. Once it took the step of opening play to 
non-Christians, however, including those with an equally thick set of religious 
commitments, then common sense, if not simply being a good host, would suggest 
that the league ought to anticipate and accommodate the religious needs of its 
guests. But certainly the work here is not done by invoking common sense 
alone.

I do, though, think it's worth taking slight issue with the view that common 
sense tells us that there is real value to following rules with no 
exceptions. I appreciate that this phrase leaves open room for ambiguity and 
charitable interpretation; not least, Eugene says real value, not absolute 
value. But I still think its worth emphasizing that I can think of few if any 
conditions in which a regime intended for application to human affairs would 
common-sensically lead to a belief in following rules with no exceptions -- 
except perhaps, in situations where the rules themselves are already drawn up 
in such a way that the exceptions are either implicit or explicit. Of course, 
it is indeed true of rules generally that they contain explicit or implicit 
exceptions. Even Smith, read common-sensically, is not a rule meant to be 
followed with no exceptions: it contains both implicit and explicit exceptions. 
Even the military, a realm in which more people would be likely to agree that 
rules should be followed with not exceptions, either tailors its rules 
carefully so that they already contain exceptions or, in some quite crucial 
cases, insists that there are situations where one must disobey a command.

I appreciate that it was just a minor point along the way to a broader 
conclusion that I generally share. Still, at least in an audience of lawyers, I 
think it is always worth emphasizing that no sound system of rules could 
possibly insist on complete obedience, and that any understanding of the rule 
of law that does not make allowance, either implicitly or explicitly, for 
ignoring, avoiding, disobeying, or violating rules resembles madness more 
closely than it does common sense.

Best to all,
Paul Horwitz
University of Alabama School of Law

On Mar 3, 2012, at 5:41 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

The trouble with “common sense” is that it often points in 
different directions.  Common sense tells us there is real value to following 
rules with no exceptions, so that one doesn’t have to later deal with questions 
of “you accommodated them, why don’t you accommodate” us (even when the future 
request for accommodation might be different from the current one), and also to 
having a schedule that is predictable

RE: Exemptions and accommodations

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I wonder whether this further shows the value of distinguishing 
not just exemptions and accommodations, but discriminatory action and 
nondiscriminatory action.  For instance, I expect that few people would view a 
bookstore owner's decision to close the store as censorship, or a private 
organization's decision not to host a debate as burdening freedom of speech.  
So it seems that it's worth distinguishing - for analytical purposes even if 
not always for legal purposes - at least three categories of action:

1.  Deliberate action that singles out speakers, religious 
practitioners, and others who exercise particular constitutional rights for 
exclusion.

2.  A generally applicable rule that applies to people who have 
religious objections to it (or perhaps have free-speech-based objections, as 
with nondiscrimination rules or membership-disclosure rules applied to private 
associations, or as in cases such as O'Brien), and from which objectors seek an 
exemption.

3.  A generally applicable rule that applies to people who have 
religious objections to it, and as to which objectors seek an accommodation 
that would require action by others.

Eugene

Alan writes:

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Monday, March 05, 2012 1:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Exemptions and accommodations

Doug's distinction between exemptions and accommodations is helpful, but the 
cause of the problem isn't limited to free exercise cases. If we are talking 
about freedom of speech, for example, many people would describe the decision 
of a bookstore to reject a request to carry particular books in its inventory 
as censorship, not a failure to accommodate the author and her readers.  The 
exclusion of less popular candidates from privately organized debates is 
similarly decried as burdening freedom of speech, not the failure to 
accommodate the excluded speaker.. When government provides police to maintain 
order at political events involving unpopular speakers we typically describe 
this conduct as protecting freedom of speech, not the accommodation of 
unpopular speakers. When government sets up restrictive rules limiting access 
to non-public forums, we describe its decision as burdening freedom of speech, 
not failing to accommodate speakers seeking access to public property.

Perhaps we should be much more careful about distinguishing between requests to 
be left alone and requests for affirmative action to facilitate the exercise of 
different freedoms and rights. The failure to do so, however, is fairly 
widespread.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Israeli Postal Workers Object to Delivering New Testaments

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene


From: Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Monday, March 05, 2012 11:32 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Israeli Postal Workers Object to Delivering New Testaments

There are, it seems to me, two significant differences between 
the postal worker refusal and the taxi driver refusal:

(1)  A postal worker is a government employee who is refusing 
to do what he is being paid to do.  The taxi driver is a private individual, 
and while he may have a government-provided partial monopoly (as do lawyers, 
doctors, and others), he is still deciding what to do on his own private time 
and within his own private car.

(2)  It shouldn’t be hard to set up a system by which cab 
drivers who want an exemption from the carry-everyone rule on this point must 
make their preferences clear, for instance with a prominently visible logo, or 
a statement from the dispatcher when they’re ordered by phone.  Such a system 
should minimize any surprising delays for passengers, while letting taxi 
drivers engage in their profession without violating their religious 
principles.  It may be harder to have any such system with postal workers, if 
they have fixed routes; even if some postal workers don’t object to delivering 
the Bibles, setting up extra visits from those non-objecting postal workers to 
fill the delivery gaps created by the objecting workers might be much more 
burdensome.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Monday, March 05, 2012 8:43 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Israeli Postal Workers Object to Delivering New Testaments

This is also related to Islamic taxi drivers that refuse to
transport passengers who have bottles of
alcohol, eg, cases of wine from their travels

On Mar 5, 2012, at 11:26 AM, Rick Duncan 
nebraskalawp...@yahoo.commailto:nebraskalawp...@yahoo.com wrote:
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Religious liberty in demands that others change their behavior to follow one's religious beliefs

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Alan:  You give examples of deliberate discrimination, but I thought we 
were generally speaking about decisions not to change one's own affirmative 
practices -- not just one's prohibitions (e.g., no-headgear rules) but also 
one's choices to, for instance, play on a particular day -- in order to 
accommodate others' religious demands.  Here, it's not clear to me that a 
private actor's decision not to accommodate is properly seen as a violation of 
religious liberty.

Let's consider an example:  Say that either a patron or an employee 
feels a religious objection to sexually suggestive materials -- or religiously 
blasphemous materials -- posted as part of a bar's décor, and demands that the 
bar remove the material in order to make the bar a place where they would feel 
comfortable eating or visiting.  (That's Lambert v. Condor Manufacturing, 
though in the context of a bar rather than a shop floor.)  I don't think that 
the bar owner can properly be faulted for denying the patron's or employee's 
religious liberty here; religious liberty is not the label, I think, for an 
entitlement to demand that others change their behavior to fit one's religious 
preferences.  

Even if a Title VII duty of reasonable accommodation would be triggered 
on such facts -- I think it shouldn't be, for Free Speech Clause reasons, but 
others might disagree with me on the constitutional question and also conclude 
that on the facts changing the doctor won't impose much of a financial burden 
on the bar owner -- I don't think the reason is the employee's religious 
liberty.   And the same is true, I think, when someone demands that a private 
association change its schedule to accommodate one's beliefs, or change the 
food served at its functions, or remove supposedly blasphemous iconography.

Eugene


Alan Brownstein writes:

 Eugene is correct that the more private the program, the less obligation 
 there is to
 accommodate others. But I wasn't focusing on the TAPPS program. I was trying 
 to
 respond to Marci's more general question. The tournament organizers in the
 Oregon case I referenced were state actors. In other cases, state 
 institutions may
 provide much of the funding for tournament events, provide access to public
 venues where games are played and generally facilitate and support the
 tournament. The greater the state involvement in the tournament, the more
 appropriate the basis for a religious liberty argument.
 
 Even in a private situation, say a commercial context, I think it is fair to 
 talk about
 religious liberty being burdened if employers refuse to hire members of a
 particular faith or motels will not rent them rooms etc. If the employer's 
 decision is
 grounded on his or her own religious beliefs, religious liberty may be on both
 sides. If religious practice and belief are not justifications for a refusal 
 to
 accommodate, but economic or administrative convenience concerns are the basis
 for denying an accommodation, I have no trouble talking about religious 
 liberty (or
 religious equality) being weighed against economic liberty or other private
 interests.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Can this possibly be the right analysis?

(1)  It seems to me that the law routinely distinguishes 
between X discriminating against Y based on Y’s race or Y’s religion, and X 
discriminating against Y based on X’s own religious beliefs that are 
independent of Y’s race or religion.  In many states, for instance, a lawyer 
can’t reject a client based on the client’s race, but I take it that a lawyer 
could refuse to represent banks on the grounds that the lawyer believes that 
charging interest is evil – or for that matter could refuse to represent liquor 
stores on the grounds that the lawyer believes that liquor is evil.  Likewise, 
under Title VII an employer can’t fire an employee based on the employee’s 
race, but it can fire an employee based on the employee’s adultery (assuming it 
applies this rule equally to men and women), even when the employer’s hostility 
to adultery stems from the employer’s religious beliefs.

There is the separate question, of course, of whether taxicab 
drivers should be required to take all comers, without regard to race, baggage, 
or anything else.  But this has nothing to do with the race discrimination 
analogy.  Rather, the issue is whether there ought to be a religious exemption 
to the take-all-comers rule, a very different question than whether there ought 
to be a religious exemption to various race discrimination bans.

(2)  How it could possibly be relevant, for purposes of 
religious accommodation law, that “a number of imams announced the cabbies were 
misreading the Koran”?  The question, given Thomas, is what the cabbies 
sincerely thought, not what “a number of” religious leaders think.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Tuesday, March 06, 2012 2:59 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

Why is anger at a publicly licensed cab picking and choosing passengers 
according to religious belief anything like anti-Muslim animus?   Cabbies can't 
reject passengers on race.   Why should they  be able to reject those with 
religious beliefs different from their own?  If they don't want to be in the 
company of nonbelievers, they should find another line of work.


Also-- a number of imams announced the cabbies were misreading the Koran.  
There was no requirement they not transport others' cases of wine.  No one was 
asking them to drink the wine


We have crossed the line from legitimate claims to accommodation into the 
territory where religious believers demand a right to exist in a culture that 
mirrors their views.That is called Balkanization


Marci
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Cabbies vs. lawyers

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
In a sense this may be obvious, but it might be worth 
restating:  One thing that is facing the cabbies is that for complex reasons 
cabbies are stripped of liberties that the rest of us take for granted.  If we 
disapprove of alcohol – whether because we’re Muslim or Methodist, or because a 
close family member is an alcoholic or was injured by a drunk driver – we are 
free to refuse to fix the plumbing in a bar, to give legal advice to Coors, or 
to refuse to let people carrying beer bottles onto our business property.  To 
be sure, our right to freedom of choice may have been limited in some ways by 
bans on race discrimination, sex discrimination, religious discrimination, and 
the like.  But whether right or wrong those bans still leave us mostly free to 
choose whom to do business with.

The cab drivers thus want only the same kind of liberty that 
the rest of us generally have.  Their argument isn’t a pure freedom of choice 
argument (which the law has rightly or wrongly denied to cabbies generally) but 
a freedom of choice argument coupled with a religious freedom argument; but 
that simply shows that this freedom of choice is even more important to them 
than it generally is to the rest of us.

This doesn’t mean that they should win.  Maybe there’s a really 
good reason for denying cabbies, including religious objectors, this freedom of 
choice when it comes to transporting alcohol.  But it does cast a different 
light on objections to people “choosing [clients] according to [the choosers’] 
religious belief,” or “demand[ing] a ‘right’ to exist in a culture that mirrors 
their views.”  No-one makes such objections when we as lawyers pick and choose 
our clients; no-one faults us for choosing them according to our religious 
beliefs (unless those beliefs require race or sex discrimination or such); 
no-one says that lawyers who refuse to work for alcohol distributors demand a 
right to exist in a culture that mirrors our views.  Likewise, I don’t think 
it’s fair to condemn cabbies for seeking, in this one area that is unusually 
important to them, the same freedom that lawyers have.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Tuesday, March 06, 2012 2:59 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

Why is anger at a publicly licensed cab picking and choosing passengers 
according to religious belief anything like anti-Muslim animus?   Cabbies can't 
reject passengers on race.   Why should they  be able to reject those with 
religious beliefs different from their own?  If they don't want to be in the 
company of nonbelievers, they should find another line of work.

Also-- a number of imams announced the cabbies were misreading the Koran.  
There was no requirement they not transport others' cases of wine.  No one was 
asking them to drink the wine

We have crossed the line from legitimate claims to accommodation into the 
territory where religious believers demand a right to exist in a culture that 
mirrors their views.That is called Balkanization

Marci


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious liberty in demands that others change their behavior to follow one's religious beliefs

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
It may well be that intentionally discriminatory actions by private 
athletic organizations are better labeled as threats to religious equality 
and not religious liberty; on the other hand, sometimes liberty rules 
themselves embody equality norms (see, e.g., the shape of free speech doctrine, 
which treats content-based restrictions as more violative of liberty than 
content-neutral ones).  In either case, such intentionally discriminatory 
actions rightly arouse condemnation (at least when they involve exclusion of 
some religious groups from mostly secular events or programs).



In any event, when this factor of intentional discrimination is 
absent, and so is any governmental restrictions on what people can do or even 
private action that dramatically interferes with people's lives and livelihood, 
I don't think that religious liberty is the right label for an organization's 
not wanting to change its behavior to make life easier for other religious 
groups.  Suppose the only restaurants in a town where very few Jews live don't 
serve kosher meat.  (I expect that this is a very reasonably supposition.)  Is 
this really properly label an interference - even if a justified interference, 
given the burden on restaurants to change their practices - with religious 
liberty?  I don't think so.



Perhaps a restaurant's enforcing its no-outside-food rule in a situation where 
a Jewish member of a mostly non-Jewish party wants to bring in kosher food, 
paper plates, and plastic utensils so that he can eat with his friends, who'll 
be ordering plenty of the restaurant's food, might qualify as a limit on 
liberty:  The Jewish member is simply asking to do what he is doing, not asking 
the restaurant to change its cooking plans.  I don't think there should be laws 
mandating restaurants to carve out exceptions from their generally applicable 
rules here, but I do think one can discuss this as a question of liberty.  
But when it comes to the patron's demanding that the restaurant actually change 
its ingredients, or its food preparation practices, I think that is much more 
than a demand that the restaurant respect the patron's liberty - rather, it's 
the patron's attempt to restrict the restaurant's liberty in the name of his 
religion.



I think the same is true of Alan's soccer league example.  The league isn't 
violating anyone's liberty through its rules.  It might not be accommodating 
Jewish players, and we can debate whether it should accommodate them further 
(though, as Doug points out, such an accommodation might impose excessive 
burdens on other players).  But I don't think a refusal to change its plans, 
not motivated by hostility to Jews, is rightly treated as interfering with 
Jewish players' liberty (though a creation of a schedule that deliberately 
burdens Jews might reasonably be treated as a morally wrongful, and perhaps 
legally wrongful, violation of religious equality).



Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein

 Sent: Sunday, March 04, 2012 5:20 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: RE: Religious liberty in demands that others change their behavior 
 to

 follow one's religious beliefs



 Eugene, I'm not sure I understand why the motive or purpose of the actor 
 controls

 whether the result of the actor's conduct should be viewed as a burden on

 religious liberty or not. I might assign much less weight to the 
 discriminating actor's

 interest and consider his conduct more morally reprehensible. But if I focus 
 on the

 impact of the decision, there would be an equivalent material burden on the 
 ability

 of the religious actor to practice his faith in both cases.



 Suppose the only Soccer League for children is in a town where very few Jews

 live. The League is private.

 Games and practices are scheduled for Tuesday, Thursday and Saturday

 afternoon. The League insists that players must agree to show up for all

 scheduled games or practices or they cannot participate in the League's 
 activities.

 Observant Jews ask for an accommodation. Without it, their children will not 
 be

 able to participate and they are too few in number to create their own league.



 In hypo 1, the League refuses the accommodation. It explains that it just 
 doesn't

 care enough about the needs and interests of the Jewish families to change the

 way they have traditionally done things in town. The Jewish families religious

 liberty is burdened by the League's decision because it requires them to give 
 up

 an opportunity they value in order to obey the dictates of their faith. It's 
 not a

 burden that deprives anyone of the necessities of life. But it's a burden.



 In hypo 2, the League refuses the accommodation and explains that in fact its

 members are delighted that their decision will have the result of preventing 
 

Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
My sense is that the system would work better than Steve 
thinks, since I suspect that it would be rare that six cabbies in a row will 
have this objection.  It's true that, at least according to 
http://www.startribune.com/462/story/709262.html, most cabbies in Minneapolis 
are Somalis, and many of them are Muslims (by which the story likely means 
observant Muslims).  But my guess is that no more than a third or so will 
likely have this objection, and that most will take whatever fares they want.  
This might be why the Minneapolis Metropolitan Airports Commission was indeed 
planning to institute a color-coded light scheme (see the story linked to 
above); it would be interesting to see if this was tried and what the results 
were.  I realize that it's speculation both ways, but, especially given that 
Minnesota courts take a Sherbert/Yoder view of the state religious freedom 
provision, I would think that the burden would be on the government to try 
something and show it fails.

On the other hand, I'm not sure how one can get to the 
conclusion that this is a tiny burden on the cabbies.  Apparently the cabbies 
believe their religion bars them from transporting alcohol; that may seem 
unreasonable to us, but our judgment about reasonableness shouldn't matter for 
substantial burden purposes.  And if the claim is that the burden is tiny 
because they can just get a different job, I just don't see how this can be 
so, especially given cases such as Sherbert:  For many unskilled immigrants, 
there are very well-paying jobs out there, especially in this economy.  Perhaps 
the burden might be justified, but how can we really say that it's tiny?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Tuesday, March 06, 2012 10:14 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Israeli Postal Workers Object to Delivering New Testaments

It is hard to set up such a system for cab drivers -- think of cabbies waiting 
at an airport where 6 in a row refuse passengers based on their possession of a 
bottle of wine.  It may be a longish wait or even a very long wait for the 
non-discriminating cabbie.  Or just hailing one on the street -- where would 
the sign be displayed?  When would the discussion take place?  How?
Tiny burden on those cabbies, it seems to me.  And if they can't abide by the 
rules, get a different job.
Public accommodations and public services just should not allow that sort of 
accommodation when the service is being denied to others -- it is burdening 
others based on difference of religion -- for the provision of a public service.

Many accommodations that might seem easy from the outside turn out not to be so 
easy.  Of course some accommodations are in fact quite easy and not as 
burdensome as some people (often employers) think they will be.

In practical areas one should not be quite confident in the ease of applying a 
seemingly principled disctinction.

Steve
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Religious objections vs. medical objections

2012-03-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
It may well be that there were specifically anti-Muslim 
statements made in the Target controversy that Greg describes.  But it seems to 
me that, in general, the analogy between religious objections and medical 
objections tends to be somewhat overstated.  (I thought the same of the Third 
Circuit Judge Alito opinion in Fraternal Order of Police v. City of Newark.)

For instance, I imagine that many an employer will gladly give employees 
extended leave for serious illness, perhaps even weeks’ worth of paid leave and 
months’ worth of unpaid leave.  Does it follow that it must give the same leave 
to people who want to go on a months-long religious pilgrimage?  Likewise, an 
employee might make many accommodations for employees whose medical conditions 
make it impossible for them to do a certain job, even when that involves a far 
greater than de minimis cost.  The employee might be required to do so by 
disability law, but might sometimes simply choose to do that in order to help 
someone who is sick or injured.  Does it follow that it must make similarly 
high-cost accommodations for religious employees?

I don’t think so.  It seems to me that an employer can reasonably conclude 
that, as a general matter, health-based objections are less likely to be 
broadly shared (there will be fewer cashiers with peanut allergies than Muslim 
cashiers, at least in areas with a high density of Muslim immigrants), and less 
likely to be perceived as slights even by unbiased customers.  No customer who 
notices that a cashier refuses to handle peanut products will take that as a 
personal slight; but even customers who aren’t hostile to Islam as such might 
perceive religious objection to the handling of pork or alcohol as a statement 
that the customer’s religious beliefs are (in the cashier’s view) wrong, or 
that the customer’s eating habits are “unclean” and drinking habits are 
unwholesome.

And beyond this, it seems to me quite permissible (though not the only 
permissible view) for an employer to conclude that undoubted, scientifically 
provable medical risk deserves more accommodation than subjective, individually 
felt religious belief.  Moreover, when it comes to legal compulsion, I would 
think (see TWA v. Hardison) that imposing the costs of one person’s religious 
practice on others raises objections that are more serious than just imposing 
the costs of one person’s disability on others would.

Or am I mistaken on these things, and employers who generously provide 
substantial accommodations for those who are sick, allergic, or disabled must 
provide equally substantial accommodations for those who have religious 
objections?

Eugene

Greg Sisk writes:

And given that this episode occurred at the same time that Muslim cashiers at 
Target asked not to be required to handle pork, it was fell into a context in 
which simple accommodations offered to others – such as allowing a cashier 
allergic to peanuts not to handle peanuts or peanut butter – became the subject 
of vehement public objection when Muslims were asking for the same kind of 
thing.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Once it took the step of opening play to non-Christians

2012-03-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I think I understand Paul's point, and the arguments in favor it, 
but I wonder whether it might get things backward.  TAPPS could likely have 
focused itself on Christian private schools with little difficulty for it.  (It 
might have benefited from including secular schools, but it likely could have 
survived just as well limited to Christian schools.)  On the other hand, my 
sense is that in such situations it's a great benefit to minority schools - 
both secular schools and especially Jewish schools - to be able to join such an 
association, since otherwise there might be very few schools for them to play 
against.  In many places, an all-Orthodox-Jewish league would have very few 
teams, and very long travel times to games.



So TAPPS generally did Jewish schools a good turn by letting them 
participate.  And if it hadn't let them participate, I suspect many would have 
faulted them for being unfairly exclusionary, with the argument being What's 
it to you that the school is Jewish?  But now TAPPS is being told that by 
being somewhat more open, it now incurs this extra obligation.  That strikes me 
as both creating perverse incentives, and being a poor reward for TAPPS' 
moderate ecumenicalism, because it demands that this moderate ecumenicalism 
lead to considerably more demanding ecumenicalism.



As to the guest/host analogy, I would think that this too cuts the 
opposite direction at least as much as in the direction suggested below (and 
perhaps more).  If I invite someone to my home, or into my private association, 
I surely would feel some impulse to accommodate him; if someone comes for 
dinner but says that he can't eat pork (and doesn't otherwise demand a kosher 
kitchen), I'll probably try to give him a non-pork option even if the main 
course is ham.  But I would hope that he would feel an even stronger impulse 
not to reward my hospitality with excessive demands, or with repeating his 
demands after I say no (even if I'm being not as hospitable as I might be in 
saying so) - and I would certainly hope that he wouldn't reward my hospitality 
with a lawsuit.



Eugene





Paul Horwitz writes:



In this case, it seems to me that the road to a reasonable resolution of the 
problem lies in the fact that TAPPS opened itself to a situation in which it 
welcomed the possibility of sporting events involving others whose religious 
needs might require accommodation. If the league had remained solely devoted to 
Christian schools and, in effect, had valued Christian community over sports or 
all-state intramural play itself, then refusing to change its schedule would a) 
be reasonable and b) not be much of a problem, since the issue would be 
unlikely ever to arise. Once it took the step of opening play to 
non-Christians, however, including those with an equally thick set of religious 
commitments, then common sense, if not simply being a good host, would suggest 
that the league ought to anticipate and accommodate the religious needs of its 
guests. But certainly the work here is not done by invoking common sense 
alone.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies' refusal to 
carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, it 
shouldn't be treated as religious discrimination.  What's more, I think the 
argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.

1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies' actions affected 
Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
alcohol.  Moreover, they didn't affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
irreligious, and anyone else who didn't carry alcohol.

2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn't be affected (just as, I 
suppose, Mormons or Methodists wouldn't be affected), because they generally 
wouldn't carry alcohol.  But that analysis strikes me as unsound, and here's 
why.

Imagine a case closely modeled on Rasmussen v. Glass (Minn. Ct. App. 1993) 
(review granted but appeal later dismissed), 
http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=648897692635049631.  A restaurant 
owner refuses to deliver food to a doctor who performs abortions, because the 
owner believes abortions are evil, and doesn't want to provide any help, even 
indirect, to such evil.  And say the restaurant owner's is irreligious, and his 
opposition to abortion is based on his own personal moral views (e.g., he 
follows Nat Hentoff, 
http://groups.csail.mit.edu/mac/users/rauch/nvp/consistent/indivisible.html).  
I take it that we would all agree that the restaurant owner is not 
discriminating based on religion.  To be sure, devout Catholics, and devout 
members of other anti-abortion religious groups, wouldn't perform abortions.  
But that doesn't mean the restaurant owner is discriminating based on the 
would-be customers' religions - he's discriminating based on their secular 
actions.

Now say that another restaurant owner acts precisely the same way, but his 
opposition to abortion is based on his religious views.  As I understand the 
argument below, he would be seen as discriminating based on religion, because 
the performing of abortion is a badge of a religion different from yours.  
And thus he would be presumptively required to deliver to the doctor's office, 
if state public accommodations law covers discrimination based on religion in 
restaurant delivery.  But this would mean that the law itself has become 
religiously discriminatory:  The secular anti-abortion restaurant owner is free 
to do something (here, refusing to deliver to an abortion provider), but the 
religious anti-abortion restaurant owner is barred from doing precisely the 
same thing.

3.  I think the same applies to the alcohol example.  A secular cab driver who 
opposes alcohol on secular grounds would presumably not be treated as 
discriminating based on religion.  But to treat the religious cab driver who 
opposes alcohol on religious grounds would be treated as discriminating based 
on religion, and would thus be potentially violating relevant public 
accommodations bans.  Yet such an approach would itself impermissibly 
discriminate (in violation of Lukumi Babalu) against the religious cab driver 
based on the religiosity of his motivation for his conduct.  Or am I missing 
something here?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Cabbies vs. lawyers

Of course it is a proxy -- just like a collar or burka or yarmulke -- a badge 
of a religion different from yours -- only in this case it is alcohol 
possession -- a badge of a religion different from yours.  The dodge of oh, 
I'm not against their religion, just against their conduct can't be allowed 
can it?  The person transporting the alcohol is the passenger, not the cab 
driver.  The fact of hidden vs. open possession of the bottle of wine gives it 
away, doesn't it -- it is not about the action, it is about the religious 
nature of the action -- the violation of the religious beliefs of the driver by 
the religious beliefs (ok to have and transport alcohol) by the passenger.

It is action based on a difference of religious belief.  That is discrimination 
no matter how one twists it.

Maybe we should allow this discrimination, just like maybe we should allow 
discrimination in allowing landlords to discriminate against gays based on the 
landlord's religious beliefs, but that is still religious-based discrimination.

You can't suddenly say that motivation doesn't matter just because the 
motivation is their own religious beliefs.

Steve
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

RE: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
But the Minnesota Constitution has been interpreted as 
following Sherbert and Yoder, so isn't the question indeed why the cab drivers 
aren't constitutionally entitled to an exemption?  As it happens, I oppose 
constitutional exemption regimes, at the state and federal levels, and support 
jurisdiction-by-jurisdiction RFRAs, which means the question becomes statutory, 
and trumpable by the state legislature.  But the Minnesota rule is one of 
constitutionally mandated exemptions, unless strict scrutiny is satisfied, no?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:22 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

For the record, I was in favor of the accommodation attempted for the Somali 
Muslim cab drivers in Minneapolis and am in favor of most accommodations of 
religion done by employers and public agencies and the government in general -- 
even quite odd ones like this particular interpretation of the Quran by this 
group of Somalis.

But that is quite different from positing that there is a right in the Somalis 
to engage in this sort of discrimination let alone a constitutional right to do 
so.

Doug is right -- sometimes hostility to religious accommodation is motivated by 
a universalist thrust that we should in fact all be treated equally -- the same 
sort of hostility one sees against affirmative action for Blacks.  And Doug is 
also right that sometimes the hostility is directed against a religion and 
members of that religion -- as JWs, Muslims, Jews, and in some settings and 
some times, Catholics and others have experienced (19th Century Baptist prayer 
-- God save us from the Unitarians who at the time had circuit riders and 
were quite evangelical, unlike today).

No doubt both of these played into this event -- especially hostility to Islam.

But the subtextual motivation of hostility to the religion cannot make what is 
otherwise lawful discrimination unlawful, or does it?  Is there a 
constitutionally meaningful distinction between -- I don't like your religion 
and therefor will not accommodate you  and I don't think you are entitled to 
an accommodation as a matter of constitutional right -- where there is in fact 
no constitutional right to accommodation, as here.

Steve
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
So let me make sure I understand your view correctly:

1.  A secular restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
abortion provider for secular reasons is not guilty of religious discrimination 
in violation of public accommodations laws.  (Assume such laws generally apply 
to discrimination based on religion in restaurant deliveries.)

2.  A religious restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
abortion provider for religious reasons is indeed guilty of religious 
discrimination in violation of public accommodations laws.  (Assume such laws 
generally apply to discrimination based on religion in restaurant deliveries.)

Is that so?  And, if so, doesn’t that make the law itself into 
an unconstitutional religious discrimination, given that it treats precisely 
the same conduct differently based on the religious motivation of the actor, in 
violation of the Lukumi Babalu principle?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 3:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their 
actions

I have to say that I find Steve's analysis more sound and based on common sense.


Marci

On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies’ refusal to 
carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, it 
shouldn’t be treated as religious discrimination.  What’s more, I think the 
argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.

1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies’ actions affected 
Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
alcohol.  Moreover, they didn’t affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
irreligious, and anyone else who didn’t carry alcohol.

2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn’t be affected (just as, I 
suppose, Mormons or Methodists wouldn’t be affected), because they generally 
wouldn’t carry alcohol.  But that analysis strikes me as unsound, and here’s 
why.

Imagine a case closely modeled on Rasmussen v. Glass (Minn. Ct. App. 1993) 
(review granted but appeal later dismissed), 
http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=648897692635049631.  A restaurant 
owner refuses to deliver food to a doctor who performs abortions, because the 
owner believes abortions are evil, and doesn’t want to provide any help, even 
indirect, to such evil.  And say the restaurant owner’s is irreligious, and his 
opposition to abortion is based on his own personal moral views (e.g., he 
follows Nat Hentoff, 
http://groups.csail.mit.edu/mac/users/rauch/nvp/consistent/indivisible.html).  
I take it that we would all agree that the restaurant owner is not 
discriminating based on religion.  To be sure, devout Catholics, and devout 
members of other anti-abortion religious groups, wouldn’t perform abortions.  
But that doesn’t mean the restaurant owner is discriminating based on the 
would-be customers’ religions – he’s discriminating based on their secular 
actions.

Now say that another restaurant owner acts precisely the same way, but his 
opposition to abortion is based on his religious views.  As I understand the 
argument below, he would be seen as discriminating based on religion, because 
the performing of abortion is “a badge of a religion different from yours.”  
And thus he would be presumptively required to deliver to the doctor’s office, 
if state public accommodations law covers discrimination based on religion in 
restaurant delivery.  But this would mean that the law itself has become 
religiously discriminatory:  The secular anti-abortion restaurant owner is free 
to do something (here, refusing to deliver to an abortion provider), but the 
religious anti-abortion restaurant owner is barred from doing precisely the 
same thing.

3.  I think the same applies to the alcohol example.  A secular cab driver who 
opposes alcohol on secular grounds would presumably not be treated as 
discriminating based on religion.  But to treat the religious cab driver who 
opposes alcohol on religious grounds would be treated as discriminating based 
on religion, and would thus be potentially violating relevant public 
accommodations bans.  Yet such an approach would itself impermissibly 
discriminate (in violation of Lukumi Babalu) against the religious cab driver 
based on the religiosity of his motivation for his conduct.  Or am I missing 
something here?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu

RE: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
So I’m not sure that I understand.  As I understand Steve’s 
post, his claim is that when X discriminates against Y based on X’s religious 
opposition to Y’s actions, even when they are secular actions such as 
transporting alcohol, that is religious discrimination and potentially 
actionable as such.  Marci, is that the analysis that you endorse as sound?

Whether the cabbies should get a religious exemption, under 
Hershberger,  not from a religious discrimination ban but from a common-carrier 
must-serve requirement strikes me as an entirely different question from the 
one I was debating with Steve.

Eugene

Marci Hamilton writes:

Eugene--I'm going to focus on the third, relevant issue.   The restaurant 
examples are not analogous because one can do the act and the other cannot do 
it.   In the cabbie situation neither can

 The cabbie who refuses to carry alcohol for secular reasons loses his job 
because he is refusing to do his job.  The cabbie who refuses for religious 
reasons is subject to the same rule.   The only question is whether there 
should be an exemption.   Under Smith and Hershberger even, I think the 
religious cabbie loses.  So then it is just a matter of public policy.I 
will leave that to the lawmakers 





On Mar 7, 2012, at 6:55 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
So let me make sure I understand your view correctly:

1.  A secular restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
abortion provider for secular reasons is not guilty of religious discrimination 
in violation of public accommodations laws.  (Assume such laws generally apply 
to discrimination based on religion in restaurant deliveries.)

2.  A religious restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
abortion provider for religious reasons is indeed guilty of religious 
discrimination in violation of public accommodations laws.  (Assume such laws 
generally apply to discrimination based on religion in restaurant deliveries.)

Is that so?  And, if so, doesn’t that make the law itself into 
an unconstitutional religious discrimination, given that it treats precisely 
the same conduct differently based on the religious motivation of the actor, in 
violation of the Lukumi Babalu principle?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 3:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their 
actions

I have to say that I find Steve's analysis more sound and based on common sense.


Marci

On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies’ refusal to 
carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, it 
shouldn’t be treated as religious discrimination.  What’s more, I think the 
argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.

1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies’ actions affected 
Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
alcohol.  Moreover, they didn’t affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
irreligious, and anyone else who didn’t carry alcohol.

2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn’t be affected (just as, I 
suppose, Mormons or Methodists wouldn’t be affected), because they generally 
wouldn’t carry alcohol.  But that analysis strikes me as unsound, and here’s 
why.

Imagine a case closely modeled on Rasmussen v. Glass (Minn. Ct. App. 1993) 
(review granted but appeal later dismissed), 
http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=648897692635049631.  A restaurant 
owner refuses to deliver food to a doctor who performs abortions, because the 
owner believes abortions are evil, and doesn’t want to provide any help, even 
indirect, to such evil.  And say the restaurant owner’s is irreligious, and his 
opposition to abortion is based on his own personal moral views (e.g., he 
follows Nat Hentoff, 
http://groups.csail.mit.edu/mac/users/rauch/nvp/consistent/indivisible.html).  
I take it that we would all agree that the restaurant owner is not 
discriminating based on religion.  To be sure, devout Catholics, and devout 
members of other anti-abortion religious groups, wouldn’t perform abortions.  
But that doesn’t mean the restaurant owner is discriminating based on the 
would-be customers’ religions – he’s discriminating based on their secular 
actions.

Now say that another restaurant owner acts precisely

RE: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Yes, State v. Hershberger, 462 N.W.2d 393 (Minn. 1990).

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 12:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

Eugene-- just a point of information--is there a lead MN Sup Court case that 
applying  strict scrutiny in cases involving neutral generally applicable laws 
and worship conduct that is illegal?


Thanks!

On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:11 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
But the Minnesota Constitution has been interpreted as 
following Sherbert and Yoder, so isn’t the question indeed why the cab drivers 
aren’t constitutionally entitled to an exemption?  As it happens, I oppose 
constitutional exemption regimes, at the state and federal levels, and support 
jurisdiction-by-jurisdiction RFRAs, which means the question becomes statutory, 
and trumpable by the state legislature.  But the Minnesota rule is one of 
constitutionally mandated exemptions, unless strict scrutiny is satisfied, no?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:22 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

For the record, I was in favor of the accommodation attempted for the Somali 
Muslim cab drivers in Minneapolis and am in favor of most accommodations of 
religion done by employers and public agencies and the government in general -- 
even quite odd ones like this particular interpretation of the Quran by this 
group of Somalis.

But that is quite different from positing that there is a right in the Somalis 
to engage in this sort of discrimination let alone a constitutional right to do 
so.

Doug is right -- sometimes hostility to religious accommodation is motivated by 
a universalist thrust that we should in fact all be treated equally -- the same 
sort of hostility one sees against affirmative action for Blacks.  And Doug is 
also right that sometimes the hostility is directed against a religion and 
members of that religion -- as JWs, Muslims, Jews, and in some settings and 
some times, Catholics and others have experienced (19th Century Baptist prayer 
-- God save us from the Unitarians who at the time had circuit riders and 
were quite evangelical, unlike today).

No doubt both of these played into this event -- especially hostility to Islam.

But the subtextual motivation of hostility to the religion cannot make what is 
otherwise lawful discrimination unlawful, or does it?  Is there a 
constitutionally meaningful distinction between -- I don't like your religion 
and therefor will not accommodate you  and I don't think you are entitled to 
an accommodation as a matter of constitutional right -- where there is in fact 
no constitutional right to accommodation, as here.

Steve
___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
(1)  Can you say a bit more about the circumstances of the 
hour-long delays, given that it seems that many cab drivers were happy to 
transport anyone who is willing to pay?  Were they at the airport, with 
dispatches cabs, or with cabs hailed on the street?

(2)  Can you also please say a bit more about the cabbies’ 
reactions to the imams’ statements – is it just that they all said “OK, no 
problem then”?  Or did some continue to insist on their own interpretation of 
the religious doctrine?  If a few did persist in their “it’s sinful for us to 
transport alcohol” view, then I would think their position would be 
constitutionally protected – and the fact that there were so few would cut in 
favor of an exemption, because it would reduce the likelihood of the hour-long 
delays that are being discussed, no?

Marci Hamilton writes:

Thanks Eugene for taking us back to the facts.  I received many emails and 
calls regarding the situation and there were people who had to wait an hour for 
a cab because of the objection.  None of them were anti-Muslim.   They did have 
the sense that the cabbies were discriminating against them because they did 
not share their religious affiliation.

   I raised earlier the fact that the imams had intervened saying there was no 
rule about transporting alcohol because that is why the issue died away and did 
not resurface.

Marci
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree with the statement in the first paragraph that, if a 
cab driver is treated as a common carrier, then he might have to transport 
people who are carrying alcohol (unless he is entitled to a religious exemption 
under a Sherbert/Yoder-model state constitutional regime, or a state RFRA 
regime).  And this is so regardless of whether he's discriminating based on a 
characteristic such as religion.

But the second paragraph goes on and says that a business owner 
who discriminates against a customer who is doing something that the owner 
thinks is religiously improper is engaging in discrimination based on 
religion.  The logic of that paragraph goes far beyond the common carrier 
situation (and indeed in the common carrier situation is irrelevant whether the 
common carrier is discriminating based on religion).

If the claim is that this discrimination based on the actor's 
religious beliefs is the sort of religious discrimination prohibited by public 
accommodation discrimination laws, that strikes me as mistaken.  As I mentioned 
in my earlier post, a secular restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
abortion provider because of the owner's secular opposition to abortion should 
be precisely on the same footing as a religious restaurant owner who refuses to 
deliver to an abortion provider because of the owner's religious opposition to 
abortion - neither is guilty of actionable religious discrimination.  Likewise, 
a secular cab driver who refuses to transport people carrying alcohol because 
of the driver's secular opposition to alcohol should be precisely on the same 
footing as a religious cab driver who refuses to transport people carrying 
alcohol because of the driver's religious opposition to alcohol.  Again, 
neither is guilty of actionable religious discrimination.  Perhaps both are 
guilty of violating some common carrier obligation; but that's another story.

In either case, the suggestion that there's something illegally 
religiously discriminatory about a business owner's acting based on his own 
religious beliefs and conduct strikes me as mistaken - indeed, unconstitutional 
given Lukumi Babalu.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 3:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their 
actions

Yes, Eugene, I think you are missing the essential point that common carriers 
are not the same as other employers and when it comes to choice as to serve or 
not serve, they are more limited in what they can and cannot do.  They are 
bound by more than non-discrimination laws.  Or that is how I always understood 
the law in this field, but I could be mistaken - I've not worked in it for over 
2 decades now.  So the baseline is different.  It is not the same as for 
ordinary businesses.

I get the distinction you are trying so to make. And I agree that it is not the 
same as excluding someone because of a particular affiliation with a sect.  But 
it still is discrimination based on religion whether it is based on the 
customer not conforming to the religious expectations and demands of the 
business or the business excluding because of a status of the customer -- in 
both instances it is because of the religious beliefs and conduct of the 
business, not the customer.

I am troubled by the blame-the-customer attitude evinced in the solicitude for 
the  person engaged in provision of a public service such as common carriers 
and public transportation.

As I have written some time ago now, I think we should indeed recognize the 
religious needs or constraints or beliefs of the employer -- but one should 
also recognize and support the interests of the others.

If a system can be worked out with minimal harm to all involved, that is best.  
But I would favor the weaker party to the stronger -- in this situation the one 
needing the cab is decidedly in the weaker position.

Steve



On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote:


I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies' refusal to 
carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, it 
shouldn't be treated as religious discrimination.  What's more, I think the 
argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.

1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies' actions affected 
Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
alcohol.  Moreover, they didn't affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
irreligious, and anyone else who didn't carry alcohol.

2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn't be affected

RE: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-11 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I would think that narrow tailoring requires a good deal more 
justification than that.  Can it really be that a ban on discrimination against 
passengers who carry alcohol – discrimination that, outside the context of 
taxicabs and a few similar common carriers, would be legal in nearly all 
contexts (employment, public accommodation, contracting, etc.) in nearly all 
jurisdictions – passes strict scrutiny simply because carving out an exemption 
might lead to some hypothetical slippery slope to allowing race discrimination? 
 If the interest in banning race discrimination is so compelling in various 
contexts, then that should justify applying race discrimination law uniformly 
in those contexts.  But I don’t see how that interest would justify applying 
laws banning other forms of discrimination, such as discrimination based on 
carrying alcohol.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marc Stern
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:01 PM
To: 'religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu'
Subject: Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their 
actions

Might I suggest another way of looking at this debate: race. Not the race of 
the drivers and that of their passengers. instead i take it as common ground 
that no one would tolerate taxi drivers turning down passengers on the basis of 
race. Does it follow that we should treat all prohibited grounds of 
discrimination with the same rigor, both as a matter of primary law-all 
forbidden categories are treated equal-or because once the prohibition on 
discrimination is weakened, even in good cause, the pressure for other 
exemptions will grow and will weaken the non discrimination norm in regard to 
race. The latter argument was raised after Boerne when the question was whether 
to include civil rights claims in a statute protecting religious liberty..
Marc


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-12 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Steve writes that religious motivation matters, for purposes 
of making an action taken with religious motivation illegal when the same 
action taken with secular motivation is legal.  I see no basis for that in 
antidiscrimination law, which generally bans discrimination against an 
individual because of such individual's ... religion, not because of the 
defendant's religion (and discrimination based on a person's transporting 
alcohol is not based on that person's consistency).  And I see a basis in 
forbidding any such statutory discrimination against the religiously motivated, 
in Smith and LukumiI.  [T]he 'exercise of religion' often involves not only 
belief and profession but the performance of (or abstention from) physical 
acts: assembling with others for a worship service, participating in 
sacramental use of bread and wine, proselytizing, abstaining from certain foods 
or certain modes of transportation. It would be true, we think ..., that a 
State would be 'prohibiting the free exercise [of religion]' if it sought to 
ban such acts or abstentions only when they are engaged in for religious 
reasons, or only because of the religious belief that they display.  At a 
minimum, the protections of the Free Exercise Clause pertain if the law at 
issue discriminates against some or all religious beliefs or regulates or 
prohibits conduct because it is undertaken for religious reasons.

But Steve and I have gone over this territory before, so I'm 
not sure it's productive for us just to speak to each other.  I'm curious, 
though:  Do others share Steve's view on this?  (It sounded like Marci might, 
but then it sounded like she didn't, so I'm not sure.)  What am I missing?  Is 
there really a basis for allowing this sort of discrimination against religious 
believers?

Eugene

Steve Jamar writes:

I hope it comes as no surprise to anyone on this list that there are 
irreconcilable doctrinal problems with religious liberty no matter how one 
looks at it.  Religious motivation matters.  Particular facts matter.  Details 
matter.  Eugene's hypothetical restaurant is not analogous to the cabbies in 
Minneapolis or in general.

I am not at all sure that Lukumi extends to private conduct and general 
anti-discrimination laws.  In that case the state singled out a particular 
religion by ordinance -- not the application of an anti-discrimination law.  
There is also a world of difference between actions by private parties that 
discriminate on the basis of religion and ordinances by states (or cities) that 
ban particular religious practices.

If the past decades of religious jurisprudence have taught us anything it 
should be to by chary of expanding any decision by the court much beyond its 
peculiar facts.  Witness the recent distinguishing of Smith.  Who knew?

I do not contend that these cases are easy or that they are or can be decided 
with great consistency -- indeed, I contend exactly the opposite.  Motivation 
matters and I cannot transmute a religious motivated action against someone 
into a neutral action without any religious motivation.

The response to the accommodation in Minneapolis shows a societal anti-Islam 
animus.  Who is surprised?

But the claim of a person who has been denied a ride on a common carrier for no 
reason other than doing something he has an absolutely legal right to do and is 
denied the ride because of a religious belief by the driver is sure going to 
feel like religious discrimination whatever niceties one might want to draw.  
And in fact IS religiously-motivated action excluding someone.  It is.  Should 
it be permitted?  Should it be accommodated?  Probably, in the absence of 
showing hardship to riders.  But if it s the last cab of the night?  No way.

I generally think we should accommodate religious exercise rights of employers 
and service providers and everyone to the extent practicable.  But that is a 
long way from finding a constitutional or statutory right to engage in such 
conduct when engaged in the provision of such public services.

There is no constitutional principle or statutory provision that would or 
should require that.  The situations are too nuanced for hard-edged application 
of generally applicable rules in this area.  Minneapolis Airport Authority 
approached it sensibly and if the solution had been implemented and if it had 
worked as planned (I have doubts, but maybe it would have), then that is what 
should be done.  We are not a secular universalist society -- not by a long 
shot.  Nor should we be -- it is not within our traditions and experience and 
our polyglot amalgam of people -- but nor should it be heavy-handed 
rights-based regime with what becomes a unit veto.

Steve






--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  

FW: Call for Papers: Religion and the Public Schools

2012-04-04 Thread Volokh, Eugene


From: mailman-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:mailman-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On 
Behalf Of McKnite, Jacob
Sent: Tuesday, April 03, 2012 9:11 PM
To: religionlaw-ow...@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Call for Papers: Religion and the Public Schools

Dear Professor Volokh,

I am devoting Volume 39, Issue 3, of the William Mitchell Law Review to the 
topic of religion and the public schools.  To solicit authors for this topic, I 
would like to post a Call for Papers on your law and religion listserv, if 
possible.  The text of this posting would read as follows:



Call for Papers - Religion and the Public Schools
William Mitchell Law Review, Vol. 39, Issue 3 (Spring 2013)

I am the Executive Editor for Volume 39, Issue 3, of the William Mitchell Law 
Review (Spring 2013).  I am proud to dedicate Issue 3 to the topic of religion 
and the public schools, and I invite you to submit an article.  Submissions may 
take the form of either shorter commentaries or longer law review articles.  
Final submissions will be due October 1, 2012.

My goal is to assemble manuscripts pertaining to such constitutional law issues 
as religion in the curriculum, school prayer, religious displays, and other 
religious speech in the public schools.  However, if you are interested in 
writing on another topic within this theme, please let me know, and I would be 
happy to work with you.

The William Mitchell Law Review is highly regarded both regionally and 
nationally.  The Law Review recently ranked twenty-second in citations by 
judges and fifty-seventh in citations by other law journals.  Over the years, 
the Law Review has featured the work of local scholars and practitioners such 
as former Vice President Walter Mondale and U.S. Senator Amy Klobuchar.  The 
Law Review has also been privileged to publish work by Supreme Court Justices 
Blackmun, O'Connor, and White.

If you are interested in writing an article, please let me know at 
jacob.mckn...@wmitchell.edu.  Additionally, if you know of others who may be 
interested in contributing, please send me their information, and I will 
contact them.

Thank you!

Sincerely,

Jacob E. McKnite
Executive Editor
William Mitchell Law Review, Vol. 39, Issue 3
J.D. Candidate, May 2014
jacob.mckn...@wmitchell.edu



Thank you very much.

Sincerely,

Jacob E. McKnite
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-12 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree entirely; I mention this partly because I occasionally 
hear pork bans as examples of quintessential violations of the Establishment 
Clause, though I don't think they would be.

To be sure, a general pork ban might have a different motivation than a prison 
decision not to serve pork.  But at the same time even a general pork ban could 
certainly be an attempt to accommodate a religious group by minimizing the risk 
that its members will accidentally ingest pork (or that its members might be 
put in a position where their employment would require the handling or even 
sampling of pork).  And just as the state of California is free to ban the sale 
of horsemeat for human consumption (as it did in 1998), so it should be free to 
ban the sale of pork - not that I'd ever endorse that as a policy matter!

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 11, 2012 4:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Is this outcome surprising in any way?  Does anyone on the list believe that 
the court got this wrong? (I certainly don't).

If Congress overrode HHS and eliminated pregnancy prevention services from 
mandatory coverage by employers under the Affordable Care Act, wouldn't the 
analysis be just the same (imposition of a uniform policy to avoid religious 
conflict, avoid any need to create controversial exceptions for religious 
entities, avoid piece-meal litigation, and ease administration of the overall 
scheme), even though the impetus for change derived from a demand by some for 
religious accommodation?
On Wed, Apr 11, 2012 at 6:48 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
River v. Mohr (N.D. Ohio Apr. 5, 2012), 
http://volokh.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/04/RiversvMohr.pdf .

Eugene

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.



--
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-12 Thread Volokh, Eugene
River v. Mohr (N.D. Ohio Apr. 5, 2012), 
http://volokh.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/04/RiversvMohr.pdf .

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Bans on sale of pork vs. bans on sale of horsemeat

2012-04-12 Thread Volokh, Eugene
 religious 
 conflict,
 avoid any need to create controversial exceptions for religious entities, 
 avoid
 piece-meal litigation, and ease administration of the overall scheme), even 
 though
 the impetus for change derived from a demand by some for religious
 accommodation?
 On Wed, Apr 11, 2012 at 6:48 PM, Volokh, Eugene
 vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 River v. Mohr (N.D. Ohio Apr. 5, 2012), http://volokh.com/wp-
 content/uploads/2012/04/RiversvMohr.pdf .
 
 Eugene
 
 ___
 To post, send message to
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.
 
 
 
 --
 Ira C. Lupu
 F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law George Washington University
 Law School
 2000 H St., NW
 Washington, DC 20052
 (202)994-7053tel:%28202%29994-7053
 My SSRN papers are here:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
 
 ___
 To post, send message to
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.
 
 
 
 --
 Ira C. Lupu
 F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law George Washington University
 Law School
 2000 H St., NW
 Washington, DC 20052
 (202)994-7053
 My SSRN papers are here:
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
 
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law University of Virginia Law 
 School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe,
 change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Accommodation

2012-04-13 Thread Volokh, Eugene
, but if the government willingly 
accommodates all of these folks in all of these circumstances, but refuses to 
accommodate some folks when the only reason for their particular 
difference/exception is religious, isn't that discrimination on the basis of 
religion banned by the Free Exercise Clause?

Now, you might argue that religious accommodations are different because 
individuals choose to be in those situations where they need an exception, 
but surely most religious people don't choose their situation any more than 
you chose to speed in order to get to the hospital faster.

Finally, don't you think it is a very good thing, ethically, if we have a 
government that is willing in lots of circumstances to say, you as a person 
matter to us more than our rule, and we are willing to see you as a person?  
There will, of course, be a point where the law becomes incoherent if the 
government looks at every individual case to see what the result should be, but 
where it is not disruptive to the system, why shouldn't we want the government 
to see us as persons and not as objects to which the law needs to be applied.


Marie A. Failinger

Professor of Law
Editor, Journal of Law and Religion
Hamline University School of Law
1536 Hewitt Avenue
Saint Paul, MN 55104 U.S.A.
651-523-2124 (work phone)
651-523-2236 (work fax)
mfailin...@hamline.edumailto:mfailin...@hamline.edu (email)
 West, Ellis ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu 4/12/2012 
 2:34 PM 
Although the District Court may be correct in saying that the primary purpose 
of the policy is not “to establish the religion of Islam” or to “promote the 
practice of Islam,” it does concede that the policy “makes accommodating a 
multitude of religious practices and beliefs easier and more economical.”  
Would someone explain to me how that purpose and/or effect is “secular” in 
nature?  Even though Prof. Lupu may be correct in saying that this particular 
policy is good way of accommodating religious beliefs/practices, his comment 
simply assumes that a policy of accommodating religious beliefs/practices is 
secular in nature.  How so?

Ellis M. West
Emeritus Professor of Political Science
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 11, 2012 7:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Is this outcome surprising in any way?  Does anyone on the list believe that 
the court got this wrong? (I certainly don't).

If Congress overrode HHS and eliminated pregnancy prevention services from 
mandatory coverage by employers under the Affordable Care Act, wouldn't the 
analysis be just the same (imposition of a uniform policy to avoid religious 
conflict, avoid any need to create controversial exceptions for religious 
entities, avoid piece-meal litigation, and ease administration of the overall 
scheme), even though the impetus for change derived from a demand by some for 
religious accommodation?
On Wed, Apr 11, 2012 at 6:48 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
River v. Mohr (N.D. Ohio Apr. 5, 2012), 
http://volokh.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/04/RiversvMohr.pdf .

Eugene

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.



--
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Accommodation

2012-04-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
My apology for bringing this up again, but I'd like to hear what people 
think about it, and I thought it might be a relevant analogy.

In 1998, California banned the sale of horsemeat for human consumption, 
based on nonrational aesthetic / moral judgments about the impropriety of 
eating horses.  Say that a state bans the sale of pork for human consumption, 
based on the desire to minimize the risk that people would accidentally eat it 
(and thus violate their nonrational religious objections to eating pork), or 
that people would be economically pressured by restaurants, food processing 
plants, and so on into serving it or even tasting it (as a chef often must when 
he's cooking a dish).  If the horsemeat ban is constitutional, why wouldn't the 
pork ban is constitutional?

Alternatively, say some other religion bans the eating of pigs not 
because they are seen as unclean, but because they are seen as especially good 
and close to humans -- much the same reason, I think, why some people oppose 
the eating of horses.  (I've heard it said that pigs are quite intelligent, for 
instance.)  And say that a jurisdiction bans the sale of pork for food 
purposes, because of the influence of that religion.  Again, if the hosemeat 
ban is constitutional, why wouldn't the pork ban be constitutional, too?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
 Sent: Friday, April 13, 2012 10:12 AM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Accommodation
 
 Ellis West and I have discussed our posts off list, and I may have been 
 attacking a
 bit of a straw man. He says he did not mean to suggest that religious 
 exemptions
 are generally suspect under the Establishment Clause; he was still writing in 
 the
 context of the no-pork policy for the prison menu, which he and I agree is 
 not really
 an exemption. I misread, or overread, his later post.
 
 I am inclined to think that the no-pork policy has a secular purpose for the 
 same
 reasons that exemptions have a secular purpose. What troubles me about the no-
 pork policy, especially if it were imposed outside the prison context, is 
 that it
 seems to force everyone to observe a religious practice. It would be like the
 Sunday closing laws, with the same sorts of arguments about whether it 
 imposes a
 religious observance or can somehow be understood as simply a secular rule.
 
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law University of Virginia Law 
 School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
 
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe,
 change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-16 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Maybe it would and maybe it wouldn't, but I don't think that 
makes the purpose religious, or makes the effect primarily the advancement of 
religion (whatever primary effect might mean); it just suggests that the 
policy might prove counterproductive relative to the secular government purpose.

As to RLUIPA being secular in purpose and effect, the Supreme 
Court unanimously said in Cutter that RLUIPA is constitutional.  Maybe one can 
imagine contrary arguments, but they didn't impress any of the Justices, even 
Stevens.

But even if RLUIPA didn't exist, the no-pork policy would be 
permissible for the reasons Doug mentions.  Likewise, a uniform vegetarian diet 
policy would also be constitutionally permissible.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 2:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

I should have added to the post below that the policy might create as much 
conflict as it eliminates, just as would a vegetarian diet.

Ellis M. West
Emeritus Professor of Political Science
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 5:21 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Sure avoiding litigation is a secular purpose, but only if one assumes that 
RFRA and RLUIPA, the basis of the litigation, are secular in purpose and 
effect, but that is precisely the issue.  Suppose these two laws did not exist. 
 Then would the prison policy in question be secular in nature?  The avoidance 
of conflict might also be a secular purpose, but it would justify all kinds of 
exemptions, not just religion-based exemptions, because persons object to all 
kinds of laws for all kinds of reasons.  For example, as Prof Levinson 
suggested in an earlier post, it would justify a uniform vegetarian diet for 
all prisoners.

Ellis M. West
Emeritus Professor of Political Science
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 4:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Avoiding litigation (and there are many, many RLUIPA and free exercise cases 
about prison diets) and other forms of conflict, and having the efficiencies of 
a uniform diet for all prisoners, sound like secular purposes to me.
On Thu, Apr 12, 2012 at 3:34 PM, West, Ellis 
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu wrote:
Although the District Court may be correct in saying that the primary purpose 
of the policy is not to establish the religion of Islam or to promote the 
practice of Islam, it does concede that the policy makes accommodating a 
multitude of religious practices and beliefs easier and more economical.  
Would someone explain to me how that purpose and/or effect is secular in 
nature?  Even though Prof. Lupu may be correct in saying that this particular 
policy is good way of accommodating religious beliefs/practices, his comment 
simply assumes that a policy of accommodating religious beliefs/practices is 
secular in nature.  How so?

Ellis M. West
Emeritus Professor of Political Science
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536tel:804-289-8536
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 11, 2012 7:32 PM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Is this outcome surprising in any way?  Does anyone on the list believe that 
the court got this wrong? (I certainly don't).

If Congress overrode HHS and eliminated pregnancy prevention services from 
mandatory coverage by employers under the Affordable Care Act, wouldn't the 
analysis be just the same (imposition of a uniform policy to avoid religious 
conflict, avoid any need to create controversial exceptions for religious 
entities, avoid piece-meal litigation, and ease administration of the overall 
scheme), even though the impetus for change derived from a demand by some for 
religious accommodation?
On Wed, Apr 11, 2012 at 6:48 PM, Volokh, Eugene

RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-16 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Well, Ellis was arguing that “the issue” was whether “RFRA and 
RLUIPA ... are secular in purpose and effect.”  I read Cutter as concluding 
that they are, though indeed particular accommodations implemented out of a 
desire to avoid RLUIPA litigation might not be.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Monday, April 16, 2012 1:33 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Cutter only addressed the facial Establishment  Clause attack on the prison 
provisions of RLUIPA.  It did not protect any particular program or exemption 
from attack

Marci

On Apr 12, 2012, at 7:19 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Maybe it would and maybe it wouldn’t, but I don’t think that 
makes the purpose religious, or makes the effect primarily the advancement of 
religion (whatever “primary effect” might mean); it just suggests that the 
policy might prove counterproductive relative to the secular government purpose.

As to RLUIPA being “secular in purpose and effect,” the Supreme 
Court unanimously said in Cutter that RLUIPA is constitutional.  Maybe one can 
imagine contrary arguments, but they didn’t impress any of the Justices, even 
Stevens.

But even if RLUIPA didn’t exist, the no-pork policy would be 
permissible for the reasons Doug mentions.  Likewise, a uniform vegetarian diet 
policy would also be constitutionally permissible.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 2:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

I should have added to the post below that the policy might create as much 
conflict as it eliminates, just as would a vegetarian diet.

Ellis M. West
Emeritus Professor of Political Science
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 5:21 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Sure avoiding litigation is a secular purpose, but only if one assumes that 
RFRA and RLUIPA, the basis of the litigation, are secular in purpose and 
effect, but that is precisely the issue.  Suppose these two laws did not exist. 
 Then would the prison policy in question be secular in nature?  The avoidance 
of conflict might also be a secular purpose, but it would justify all kinds of 
exemptions, not just religion-based exemptions, because persons object to all 
kinds of laws for all kinds of reasons.  For example, as Prof Levinson 
suggested in an earlier post, it would justify a uniform vegetarian diet for 
all prisoners.

Ellis M. West
Emeritus Professor of Political Science
University of Richmond, VA 23173
804-289-8536
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 4:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Avoiding litigation (and there are many, many RLUIPA and free exercise cases 
about prison diets) and other forms of conflict, and having the efficiencies of 
a uniform diet for all prisoners, sound like secular purposes to me.
On Thu, Apr 12, 2012 at 3:34 PM, West, Ellis 
ew...@richmond.edumailto:ew...@richmond.edu wrote:
Although the District Court may be correct in saying that the primary purpose 
of the policy is not “to establish the religion of Islam” or to “promote the 
practice of Islam,” it does concede that the policy “makes accommodating a 
multitude of religious practices and beliefs easier and more economical.”  
Would someone explain to me how that purpose and/or effect is “secular” in 
nature?  Even though Prof. Lupu may be correct in saying that this particular 
policy is good way of accommodating religious beliefs/practices, his comment 
simply assumes that a policy of accommodating religious beliefs/practices is 
secular in nature.  How so?

Ellis M. West
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo

RE: Mothers leaving ultra-religious groups, and religious upbringing as a factor in custody disputes

2012-04-21 Thread Volokh, Eugene

religions depending on the facts of the case.  The focus must be the child.



This sort of assumption that religious status quo is a social good is an

unconstitutional preference for religion.

This is a good example of when the application of a neutral generally applicable

principle can serve the greater good more directly than a religious preference.



Marci



Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

New York, NY 10003



On Apr 20, 2012, at 9:09 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:



 There's an interesting op-ed at 
 http://blog.nj.com/njv_guest_blog/2012/04/among_nj_orthodox_jewish_women.html

that faults the child custody law preference for stability of religious

upbringing:  When women leave arranged marriages in the ultra-Orthodox Jewish

community -- and leave ultra-Orthodoxy more general -- they may sometimes lose

custody of their children on the grounds that the person who remains within the

community is more able to provide stability of religious upbringing.



 I'm inclined to say that this rule (which of course could equally apply to

fathers who leave a religious community as well, though I don't know how

relatively frequent such departures are) is a sound one, for children who are

old enough to have some experience with the religion and thus some stake in

stability of religious upbringing.  To be sure, the rule does create some

pressure against departing the faith, since often someone who leaves the group

can no longer raise the children in the same religious environment even if she's

willing to, because the group might no longer accept her; but this seems in this

situation to be an acceptable and denominationally neutral rule (especially if

it is equally applied to a parent who moves into a ultra-religious community

which disrupts the stability of the children's nonreligious, or only mildly

religious, upbringing).  But I still thought I'd mention the op-ed, in case

people think it's a difficult and interesting question.



 Eugene



 ___

 To post, send message to 
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,

 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see

 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the

messages to others.

___

To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, 
unsubscribe,

change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the

messages to others.



___

To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see

http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the

messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Mothers leaving ultra-religious groups, and religious upbringing as a factor in custody disputes

2012-04-21 Thread Volokh, Eugene
There's an interesting op-ed at 
http://blog.nj.com/njv_guest_blog/2012/04/among_nj_orthodox_jewish_women.html 
that faults the child custody law preference for stability of religious 
upbringing:  When women leave arranged marriages in the ultra-Orthodox Jewish 
community -- and leave ultra-Orthodoxy more general -- they may sometimes lose 
custody of their children on the grounds that the person who remains within the 
community is more able to provide stability of religious upbringing.  

I'm inclined to say that this rule (which of course could equally apply to 
fathers who leave a religious community as well, though I don't know how 
relatively frequent such departures are) is a sound one, for children who are 
old enough to have some experience with the religion and thus some stake in 
stability of religious upbringing.  To be sure, the rule does create some 
pressure against departing the faith, since often someone who leaves the group 
can no longer raise the children in the same religious environment even if 
she's willing to, because the group might no longer accept her; but this seems 
in this situation to be an acceptable and denominationally neutral rule 
(especially if it is equally applied to a parent who moves into a 
ultra-religious community which disrupts the stability of the children's 
nonreligious, or only mildly religious, upbringing).  But I still thought I'd 
mention the op-ed, in case people think it's a difficult and interesting 
question.  

Eugene

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punishchildren by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels

2012-05-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm not sure why it should matter whether a minister is 
speaking in a church with a building, or to a small group of people; nor is it 
clear to me to what extent the law can take into account how much people fear 
their leaders on spiritual grounds, whether they be the leader of a small group 
or the Pope.  The Court's First Amendment jurisprudence has, quite rightly I 
think, never tried to draw a line between small charismatic religious groups 
and bigger, more established religious organizations.

As to teaching church members how to do something, I agree that 
if he were teaching little-known techniques for more effectively committing 
crimes, we might have a crime-facilitating speech question, which raises a 
different (and unresolved) set of issues.  But it sounds like teaching here 
is just another word for urging people to act in a particular way, in the 
same sense as we can talk about any church's teachings.  So that's why this 
strikes me as quite likely a Brandenburg case, though as I noted at the outset 
more specific counseling might make it a Williams solicitation case.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steve Sanders
Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 11:12 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punishchildren by 
hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels

Here is yet another story that sheds some more light and provides more facts 
that may affect the legal analysis.  
http://host.madison.com/wsj/news/local/crime_and_courts/trial-set-to-begin-for-pastor-who-allegedly-instructed-followers/article_31306240-6cac-11e1-b1cf-0019bb2963f4.html.
  This sounds less like a church (they had no building) than a small 
fundamentalist fringe group under the sway of a feared leader.  The story also 
says he was accused not just of advocating but of teaching church members how 
to discipline their young children by striking them with wood spoons or dowels 
on their bare bottoms.  The more you learn about the case, the less it seems 
like Brandenburg, don't you think?



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 8:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punishchildren by 
hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels

I think where you and I disagree, Eugene, is on the question of what it means 
to advocate illegal action at some indefinite future time. I think if the 
pre-condition on which the illegal action is to be based is known to the 
speaker and the audience to be certain and to occur in the near future, then 
Brandenburg and Hess  are satisfied. If a minister urges his congregants to 
smoke marijuana, without more, I view that as general advocacy. If the minister 
urges his congregants to give marijuana to any child they see when they take 
their own kids to school -- when it is clear to everyone that the congregants 
take their kids to school everyday and, necessarily, will see other children 
when they do so -- I view that as urging imminent unlawful conduct.



It's not just that the illegal conduct would occur on many occasions. It is 
that the condition which will trigger the illegal action is certain and that 
the first of those many occasions when the illegal conduct is to occur is going 
to be in the very near future.



Do you think a minister could be prosecuted consistent with the First Amendment 
under my hypothetical, Eugene?



Alan


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene 
[vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 7:56 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children 
by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels
Alan:  So if a minister preaches the propriety of the frequent 
use of marijuana (as I'm told the Rastafarians do), he could be prosecuted as 
well, on the theory that people are likely to act on it some time soon?  I 
would think that Hess v. Indiana's distinction between advocacy of imminent 
conduct and advocacy of illegal action at some indefinite future time would 
be helpful to both the pro-marijuana minister and the pro-beating-children 
minister.  Or is it really the case that advocating the general propriety of 
illegal conduct can be criminalized, so long as the illegal conduct would take 
place relatively often?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan

RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels

2012-05-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Alan:  You raise an interesting question, and it might be well 
be that intentionally urging someone illegal to do something tomorrow morning, 
when such urging is likely to lead to the illegality, is indeed incitement.  
But I saw nothing in the stories that suggested that the beatings were a daily 
affair.  To be sure, the minister's teachings contemplated that the beatings 
would take place at some point, and likely within months rather than years.  
But I assume that when a Rastafarian minister says that the use of marijuana is 
a sacrament, his teachings likewise contemplate that the criminal conduct would 
take place at some point, and likely soon - perhaps sooner than, because more 
often than, the beatings in this case.

So I suppose that the key question is whether imminence does 
extend beyond conduct that's likely to happen today or tomorrow, to conduct 
that's likely to happen at some unspecified time within the next several 
months.  I had thought that it doesn't so extend, and that this is part of why 
the Brandenburg exception has been seen as so narrow.  Am I mistaken on that?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 8:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children 
by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels


I think where you and I disagree, Eugene, is on the question of what it means 
to advocate illegal action at some indefinite future time. I think if the 
pre-condition on which the illegal action is to be based is known to the 
speaker and the audience to be certain and to occur in the near future, then 
Brandenburg and Hess  are satisfied. If a minister urges his congregants to 
smoke marijuana, without more, I view that as general advocacy. If the minister 
urges his congregants to give marijuana to any child they see when they take 
their own kids to school -- when it is clear to everyone that the congregants 
take their kids to school everyday and, necessarily, will see other children 
when they do so -- I view that as urging imminent unlawful conduct.



It's not just that the illegal conduct would occur on many occasions. It is 
that the condition which will trigger the illegal action is certain and that 
the first of those many occasions when the illegal conduct is to occur is going 
to be in the very near future.



Do you think a minister could be prosecuted consistent with the First Amendment 
under my hypothetical, Eugene?



Alan


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene 
[vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 7:56 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children 
by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels
Alan:  So if a minister preaches the propriety of the frequent 
use of marijuana (as I'm told the Rastafarians do), he could be prosecuted as 
well, on the theory that people are likely to act on it some time soon?  I 
would think that Hess v. Indiana's distinction between advocacy of imminent 
conduct and advocacy of illegal action at some indefinite future time would 
be helpful to both the pro-marijuana minister and the pro-beating-children 
minister.  Or is it really the case that advocating the general propriety of 
illegal conduct can be criminalized, so long as the illegal conduct would take 
place relatively often?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 4:53 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children 
by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels


The news story doesn't give us a lot of detail as to exactly what the pastor 
said in this case nor does it tell us much about his parishioners. But if the 
pastor's instructions to his parishioners are to do something unlawful if a 
certain pre-condition is satisfied and the pre-condition is sufficiently common 
that it will almost certainly occur in the very near future, I'm not sure I see 
the Brandenburg problem. Infants will cry and will fail to sit still. If a 
speaker instructs a group of parents with very young children to stick their 
children's hand in boiling water if they cry or fail to sit still, that seems 
pretty imminent to me.



If the parishioners follow his instructions and he ratifies their conduct and 
tells them to continue to do so, I think  that's more than abstract advocacy.






From: 
religionlaw-boun

Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels

2012-05-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I would think that such a conviction would likely be 
unconstitutional under the Free Speech Clause, given Brandenburg v. Ohio, even 
without regard to any special religious freedom claim (note that Wisconsin 
courts read the Wisconsin Constitution following Sherbert/Yoder).  It seems to 
me that teaching parishioners the propriety of such conduct - even illegal 
conduct - doesn't fit within the Brandenburg exception, because it isn't 
intended to yield imminent lawless conduct; and I don't think the general 
teachings would fit within the United States v. Williams solicitation 
exception, since no specific act is being discussed.  On the other hand, it's 
possible that pastoral counseling of a specific parent, telling the parent to 
engage in illegal child abuse (assuming the discipline is indeed illegal) might 
qualify as solicitation of crime and not just abstract advocacy.  Or is this 
analysis mistaken?

Relatedly, could ministers of churches that teach that 
marijuana is a sacrament be prosecuted for conspiracy to engage in criminal 
possession or receipt of marijuana?  Could imams who preach the propriety of 
jihad be prosecuted for conspiracy to engage in jihad, just based on the 
teaching alone?

Eugene



http://host.madison.com/wsj/news/local/crime_and_courts/motion-to-dismiss-charges-against-black-earth-pastor-denied/article_3c17db6a-9b01-11e1-967a-001a4bcf887a.html

A Dane County judge on Thursday denied a motion to dismiss charges against a 
Black Earth pastor convicted of conspiracy to commit child abuse for advocating 
the use of wooden rods to spank children as young as 2 months old.

Philip Caminiti, 55, pastor of the Aleitheia Bible Church, was convicted in 
March of eight counts of conspiracy to commit child abuse for instructing 
church members to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with 
wooden dowels to teach them to behave correctly, in keeping with the church's 
literal interpretation of the Bible.

The motion to dismiss the charges alleged Caminiti had been deprived of his 
constitutional right to religious freedom.

Circuit Judge Maryann Sumi found that Caminiti had a sincerely held religious 
belief as a Christian fundamentalist that requires using a rod to discipline 
children beginning at a young age. But Sumi said Caminiti failed to show the 
state's child abuse statute places a burden on his sincerely held religious 
belief.

Scripture doesn't specify how and when the rod should be used, Sumi said, 
adding that Caminiti also was willing to modify the church's practices to 
comply with the law
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Solicitation, Conspiracy and Caminiti (was: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels)

2012-05-19 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I think solicitation is indeed relevant; as my initial post 
noted, pastoral counseling of a specific parent, telling the parent to engage 
in illegal child abuse (assuming the discipline is indeed illegal) might 
qualify as solicitation of crime and not just abstract advocacy.  But I would 
think that general preaching of the propriety of disciplining children by 
hitting them in a particular way would be more on the Brandenburg / Hess v. 
Indiana general advocacy side of the line than on the Williams solicitation 
side of the line.

This having been said, I realize that the solicitation/advocacy 
line is not clearly defined.  Do you have any sense of how such a line could 
properly be drawn, including in light of Hess?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Thursday, May 17, 2012 8:03 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Solicitation, Conspiracy and Caminiti (was: Minister convicted for 
teaching parishioners to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks 
with wooden dowels)

Eugene:  While reading the government's brief in al-Bahlul,
www.lawfareblog.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/05/2012-05-16-Bahlul-Brief-Respondent.pdfhttp://www.lawfareblog.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/05/2012-05-16-Bahlul-Brief-Respondent.pdf,
 I noticed that the argument in the alternative at pp. 78-79 repeats the 
government's argument from the Lynne Stewart case that if the government simply 
denominates public advocacy of criminal conduct as solicitation, it 
apparently avoids the need to satisfy Brandenburg analysis.  (In the Stewart 
case, the CTA2 also appeared to rely in part on the fact that the intended 
audience was especially susceptible to the speaker's admonitions, analogizing 
to a crime boss's call to arms, 590 F3d at 115-16 -- certainly relevant to the 
minster and congregants case.).  I've previously raised concerns about this 
solicitation argument here:

http://balkin.blogspot.com/2011/07/begolly-indictment-and-first-amendment.html

But even if one thinks this move is inconsistent with Brandenburg, at a minimum 
one needs to deal with the recent case law supporting the solicitation theory 
in discussing the Caminiti case.

(I'd also note that the public accounts of the Caminiti case state that he was 
convicted of conspiracy, not solicitation.  Wholly apart from the First 
Amendment, is it really the case that he can be said to have agreed with the 
parents to engage in child abuse under Wisconsin law?)
On Mon, May 14, 2012 at 12:24 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
I'm not sure why it should matter whether a minister is 
speaking in a church with a building, or to a small group of people; nor is it 
clear to me to what extent the law can take into account how much people fear 
their leaders on spiritual grounds, whether they be the leader of a small group 
or the Pope.  The Court's First Amendment jurisprudence has, quite rightly I 
think, never tried to draw a line between small charismatic religious groups 
and bigger, more established religious organizations.

As to teaching church members how to do something, I agree that 
if he were teaching little-known techniques for more effectively committing 
crimes, we might have a crime-facilitating speech question, which raises a 
different (and unresolved) set of issues.  But it sounds like teaching here 
is just another word for urging people to act in a particular way, in the 
same sense as we can talk about any church's teachings.  So that's why this 
strikes me as quite likely a Brandenburg case, though as I noted at the outset 
more specific counseling might make it a Williams solicitation case.

Eugene
 ...
On May 13, 2012, at 7:10 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
I would think that such a conviction would likely be 
unconstitutional under the Free Speech Clause, given Brandenburg v. Ohio, even 
without regard to any special religious freedom claim (note that Wisconsin 
courts read the Wisconsin Constitution following Sherbert/Yoder).  It seems to 
me that teaching parishioners the propriety of such conduct - even illegal 
conduct - doesn't fit within the Brandenburg exception, because it isn't 
intended to yield imminent lawless conduct; and I don't think the general 
teachings would fit within the United States v. Williams solicitation 
exception, since no specific act is being discussed.  On the other hand, it's 
possible that pastoral counseling of a specific parent, telling the parent to 
engage in illegal child abuse (assuming the discipline is indeed illegal) might 
qualify as solicitation of crime and not just abstract advocacy.  Or is this 
analysis mistaken?

Relatedly, could ministers of churches that teach that 
marijuana

RE: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse

2012-06-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Actually, my criticism of Marci was not because she was a woman 
(surprise!), but because it seemed to me that for whatever reason her argument 
was framed in a way that was as unsubstantive and as lacking in concreteness as 
possible.  As I noted in the e-mail to which Marci responded, there is a 
plausible but contestable explanation for how enacting a RFRA might indeed 
indirectly increase the rate of child sexual abuse.  But that’s an argument 
that, it seems to me, is most helpfully offered by explaining its specifics, 
and in the process noting its limitations.

Instead, Marci’s first post on the subject framed the matter as 
“Most Americans when they understand that a RFRA opens the door to 
discrimination or child sex abuse or medical neglect quickly cool on the 
extremism of a RFRA.”  “[A] RFRA opens the door to ... child sex abuse”?  
That’s rhetoric, or hyperbole, or perhaps just careless wording.  “Opens the 
door” suggests that something that before wasn’t happening now would be 
happening, or at least (as in the “discrimination” and “medical neglect” items) 
something that before wasn’t legal now would be legal.  Of course, child sex 
abuse is a very serious crime with or without a RFRA; at most, what RFRA might 
do is diminish the incentives that one set of institutions has to maximally 
combat child sex abuse.

In another post, Marci writes, “RFRA, as we all know, does not mirror the First 
Amendment, and the North Dakota RFRA would have triggered strict scrutiny even 
without a showing that the burden was ‘substantial’ -- so we can be certain 
that it could be more problematic in child sex abuse and medical neglect 
cases.”  Can we really be so “certain,” given the rather modest difference in 
wording, the fact that court decisions providing protection to churches are 
generally entanglement cases, not RFRA cases, and the fact that most courts 
don’t accept either entanglement or free exercise/RFRA challenges?  (Or is the 
sentence saved by the fact that it only says “we can be certain that it could 
be more problematic,” in which case the claim is made accurate by being made 
basically empty?)

Most recently, Marci’s latest response offers one case citation: Gibson v 
Brewer.  But it might be worth noting that Gibson accepts a First Amendment 
defense to employer negligence claims on entanglement and endorsement grounds, 
with a dollop of Kedroff.  It didn’t rely on the Sherbert/Yoder/RFRA strict 
scrutiny model.  Again, instead of concrete analysis, what I’m seeing is 
one-liners and broad assertions.

I would not normally publicly criticize another list member’s work this way, 
but Marci’s implicit accusation of sexism requires me to explain just why her 
argument struck me as more “rhetoric” than substance, and would have regardless 
of her sex.

Eugene




From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 4:28 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse

I'm not sure why stating the facts in these cases is rhetoric   I sincerely 
hope it is not because a woman is pointing out the facts rather than a man.  
This last statement also is not rhetoric but an honest observation.

Eugene's analysis is correct to a point.   Even though slightly more than half 
of the states have rejected religious liberty as an absolute defense, the 
churches still raise religious liberty defenses in a myriad of situations in 
these cases i  those states  Examples: They balk at discovery on a routine 
basis and use the defense to try to get around SOLs.   Shifting from the 
constitutional standard to the RFRA formulation increases delay and cost in 
these cases.   That means it increases the suffering of the victims now and 
creates more dangers in the future.   These are the facts

The same is true for medical neglect.

Having said that -- the North Dakota RFRA also was more extreme than most 
because it did not require a substantial burden.  Just a burden.

RFRA is a misguided approach.  If legislators are foolish enough to adopt this 
formulation which disables laws they worked hard to pass, at the least they 
should exempt all cases involving child abuse and neglect.   Existing rfras 
should be amended accordingly and religious lobbyists should include the child 
safety exemption in every bill they push.

Still, the gay rights lobbies and women 's rights lobbies passionately oppose 
the RFRA formulation.   The tide has turned because they came to understand 
that the rfras are one means of oppressing them.  Again just a fact -- not 
rhetoric.

Marci





On Jun 14, 2012, at 12:13 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Folks:  I think that, if we soften the rhetoric and get more 
concrete, we could arrive at the following

RE: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse

2012-06-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Anecdotal evidence and surmise is all we have for most laws – 
it’s all we have for the proposition that, for instance, having RFRAs actually 
increases religious freedom; it’s not like we have social science or criminal 
statistics to support that.  And social science and criminal statistics are 
especially unlikely to be available for child sexual abuse by the clergy, which 
is for obvious reasons hard to measure accurately, and which is numerically 
rare enough that random variation can easily swamp any slight effects of a RFRA 
or employer tort liability.  To be sure, I think that social science evidence, 
when it’s available and when it’s properly gathered and analyzed, can be very 
helpful in making policy decisions.  But we often find ourselves having to make 
such decisions even without such evidence.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of lawyer2...@aol.com
Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 6:21 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse



Do we know of any social science or criminal statistics that supports a notion 
that jurisdictions with RFRA or upheld constitutional defenses to employer 
liability have a higher incidence of child sexual abuse (or, for that matter, 
that incidents of child sexual abuse are higher in religious settings than 
settings, such as public schools, where these legal arguments regarding 
employer liability are inapplicable)...or are we left with anecdotal evidence, 
if not surmise?

--Don Clark
  Nationwide Special Counsel
  United Church of Christ

In a message dated 6/13/2012 11:14:28 P.M. Central Daylight Time, 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu writes:
Folks:  I think that, if we soften the rhetoric and get more 
concrete, we could arrive at the following:

1.  There’s been a debate about whether religious freedom 
protections insulate churches from lawsuits for negligent hiring, negligent 
supervision, and negligent retention in child sex abuse cases (I’ll call this 
“employer negligence” for short, though some courts have treated the different 
theories differently).

2.  Many church lawyers, faced with a lawsuit trying to hold a 
church liable for crimes by some of its clergy, have indeed asserted such 
defenses.

3.  In some cases, those defenses have been successful, not 
because religious freedom is seen a defense to a sex abuse charge as such, but 
because it’s seen as a defense to an employer negligence claim.

4.  These defenses have generally been based on constitutional 
non-entanglement arguments, on the theory that secular courts shouldn’t be in 
the business of deciding whether a decision to hire or not hire a minister is 
“reasonable,” but they might in principle also be strengthened by a 
Sherbert/Yoder regime, such as that created by RFRAs or similar constitutional 
amendments.  This having been said, lots of courts in states with such 
Sherbert/Yoder regimes have indeed accepted liability for employer negligence 
notwithstanding those regimes, so it seems quite likely that implementing a 
RFRA would not thwart such negligence – but only quite likely, not certain.

5.  Liability for employer negligence may help encourage 
churches to more closely police their clergy, based on standard 
tort-law-as-deterrence theory.

6.  Conversely, disallowing such liability may, by comparison, 
diminish the incentive for churches to closely police their clergy, and may 
thus yield somewhat more sex abuse by clergy.

7.  Therefore, depending on the magnitude of the effects 
described in item 4 (RFRA strengthening the no-employer-negligence-liability 
position) and item 6 (absence of liability diminishing the incentive to police 
clergy, and absence of policing increasing abuse), enacting a RFRA might in 
some measure yield somewhat more sex abuse by clergy.

This of course doesn’t meaning that enacting a RFRA (even one 
without an exception for employer negligence) is necessarily bad.  I favor 
state RFRA statutes, though I also favor Smith as a constitutional model.  But 
it does suggest one possible cost of a RFRA.

Eugene
=

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, 

Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Thanks for the pointer.  Out of this list at the ndagainst3.com site, the only 
item that seems at all plausible is that people could break certain laws on 
non-discrimination, though almost certainly not employment discrimination 
laws.  The other claims would either be almost certainly rejected under strict 
scrutiny, or (in some circumstances) would prevail even without a RFRA, for 
instance if a church employer is firing an unmarried pregnant minister or 
teacher of religion.



A man could be allowed to marry girls, as young as 12, in the name of religion.1

An employer could fire an unmarried pregnant woman simply because of the 
employer's religious beliefs.2

A man could claim domestic violence laws don't apply to him because his 
religion teaches that a husband has the right to discipline his family, 
including his wife and children as he sees fit.3

A parent who believes in faith healing could to deny critical medical treatment 
to a seriously ill child.4

Simply put, people could break our laws in the name of religious freedom, 
including laws on non-discrimination, domestic violence and child abuse.5



Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach

 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 1:42 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND





 These appear to be some of the main arguments against passing the RFRA:



 http://ndagainst3.com/get-the-facts/



 As an example, this TV ad said that the RFRA would allow men to marry girls

 aged 12 and to beat their spouses:



 http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=14ngnqGR6e8



 There was also quite a bit of blog chatter about sharia law being enforced in

 North Dakota as a result of passing the RFRA.



 I did not see anything about Native Americans.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND


Eugene,



Just to follow up on your point that some discrimination in the name of 
religion would possibly be tolerated under Measure 3 such as . . .

 1.  A pharmacist refusing to dispense Plan B.
 2.  A taxi cab driver refusing to transport a person with the smell of alcohol 
on his breath.
 3.  A professional photographer refusing to photograph an LGBT civil ceremony.
 4.  A landlord refusing to rent to an atheist.

Seems to me this is precisely why Measure 3 was defeated and RFRAs should be 
repealed -- because equality is a core American value.



Bob Ritter

On June 14, 2012 at 7:29 PM Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

Thanks for the pointer.  Out of this list at the ndagainst3.com site, the only 
item that seems at all plausible is that “people could break” certain “laws on 
non-discrimination,” though almost certainly not employment discrimination 
laws.  The other claims would either be almost certainly rejected under strict 
scrutiny, or (in some circumstances) would prevail even without a RFRA, for 
instance if a church employer is firing an unmarried pregnant minister or 
teacher of religion.



A man could be allowed to marry girls, as young as 12, in the name of religion.1

An employer could fire an unmarried pregnant woman simply because of the 
employer’s religious beliefs.2

A man could claim domestic violence laws don’t apply to him because his 
religion teaches that a husband has the right to discipline his family, 
including his wife and children as he sees fit.3

A parent who believes in faith healing could to deny critical medical treatment 
to a seriously ill child.4

Simply put, people could break our laws in the name of religious freedom, 
including laws on non-discrimination, domestic violence and child abuse.5



Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric 
 Rassbach

 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 1:42 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND





 These appear to be some of the main arguments against passing the RFRA:



 http://ndagainst3.com/get-the-facts/



 As an example, this TV ad said that the RFRA would allow men to marry girls

 aged 12 and to beat their spouses:



 http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=14ngnqGR6e8



 There was also quite a bit of blog chatter about sharia law being enforced in

 North Dakota as a result of passing the RFRA.



 I did not see anything about Native Americans.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Thanks - I much appreciate the kind words!

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 8:07 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND


Very well stated, Eugene. My compliments.



Alan


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene 
[vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 7:24 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
Folks:  Again, perhaps it might be good to avoid the rhetoric 
and focus on the serious issues involved.  American law has long valued both 
equality and accommodation of religious beliefs.   For many decades, it has 
valued equality in treatment by many nongovernmental actors (and incidentally 
in requiring certain nongovernmental actors to accommodate religious beliefs, 
but that isn't involved here).  The ACLU has likewise long valued both equality 
and accommodation of religious beliefs.

The difficulty is that the two often conflict.  Sometimes the legal system 
deals with this conflict by categorically prioritizing liberty (from government 
intrusion) over equality of treatment by nongovernmental actors.  For instance, 
the government may not tell people not to discriminate in marriage, or, I take 
it, in choice of friends, and no state laws purport to do that.  The government 
may not bar parade organizers from discriminating against gay-themed floats, 
and (more controversially) may not bar the Boy Scouts from discriminating 
against gay scoutmasters.  The Ninth Circuit recently interpreted California 
fair housing law as leaving people free to discriminate in choice of roommates, 
in part because of constitutional concerns.

Likewise, statutes often don't regulate even behavior that they 
constitutionally may regulate.  The Civil Rights Act of 1964, for instance, 
left the vast majority of businesses and professionals free to choose whom to 
deal with as customers; it defined regulated places of public accommodation 
quite narrowly.  Many state laws, though, have provided far broader coverage 
for the equality mandate, thus diminishing the business owners' liberty (and, 
in the process, religious liberty).

Other times the legal system deals with this conflict by categorically 
prioritizing equality of treatment over liberty; for instance, to my knowledge 
courts have consistently rejected religious exemption claims from employment 
discrimination laws, outside the context of (1) ministerial positions and (2) 
statutory exemptions (for instance, exemptions for religious institutions from 
bans on discrimination based on religion, and in some states based on sexual 
orientation).

Still other times, though rarely, courts have carved out religious exemptions 
under RFRAs and similar state constitutional exemption regimes; to my 
knowledge, this has only happened with regard to housing discrimination based 
on marital status.

How to resolve this is not, I think, easily answered either with assertions 
that equality is a core American value or that religious freedom is a basic 
American value, or claims that the ACLU doesn't value[] religious liberty 
for conservative faiths.  My sense is that we need to talk more specifically 
and concretely about the arguments for and against respecting equality and 
liberty in each instance.  (For instance, the argument for letting taxi cab 
drivers discriminate based on passengers' consumption of alcohol - a right that 
most other businesses enjoy, since it doesn't involve discrimination based on 
the passenger's religion, race, etc. - is different from the argument for 
letting landlords refuse to rent to atheists or from the argument for letting 
photographers choose which kinds of expressive works to create.)

My sense is that it might also be helpful to talk about the level of law at 
which a religious exemption regime is enacted.  A state statutory RFRA leaves 
the state legislature free to decide that some laws (including 
antidiscrimination laws) should be exempted from the RFRA, and to effectively 
overturn the results of court decisions that grant exemptions.  A state 
constitutional RFRA doesn't do that.  A federal statutory RFRA that binds state 
governments, and a federal Sherbert/Yoder regime, make it even harder for 
legislatures who feel strongly about the need for an exemption-less equality 
rule to implement those views into law.

Eugene


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
OK, sorry, that wasn't meant for the whole list   D'oh!

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 8:11 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND

Thanks - I much appreciate the kind words!

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 8:07 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND


Very well stated, Eugene. My compliments.



Alan


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene 
[vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 7:24 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
Folks:  Again, perhaps it might be good to avoid the rhetoric 
and focus on the serious issues involved.  American law has long valued both 
equality and accommodation of religious beliefs.   For many decades, it has 
valued equality in treatment by many nongovernmental actors (and incidentally 
in requiring certain nongovernmental actors to accommodate religious beliefs, 
but that isn't involved here).  The ACLU has likewise long valued both equality 
and accommodation of religious beliefs.

The difficulty is that the two often conflict.  Sometimes the legal system 
deals with this conflict by categorically prioritizing liberty (from government 
intrusion) over equality of treatment by nongovernmental actors.  For instance, 
the government may not tell people not to discriminate in marriage, or, I take 
it, in choice of friends, and no state laws purport to do that.  The government 
may not bar parade organizers from discriminating against gay-themed floats, 
and (more controversially) may not bar the Boy Scouts from discriminating 
against gay scoutmasters.  The Ninth Circuit recently interpreted California 
fair housing law as leaving people free to discriminate in choice of roommates, 
in part because of constitutional concerns.

Likewise, statutes often don't regulate even behavior that they 
constitutionally may regulate.  The Civil Rights Act of 1964, for instance, 
left the vast majority of businesses and professionals free to choose whom to 
deal with as customers; it defined regulated places of public accommodation 
quite narrowly.  Many state laws, though, have provided far broader coverage 
for the equality mandate, thus diminishing the business owners' liberty (and, 
in the process, religious liberty).

Other times the legal system deals with this conflict by categorically 
prioritizing equality of treatment over liberty; for instance, to my knowledge 
courts have consistently rejected religious exemption claims from employment 
discrimination laws, outside the context of (1) ministerial positions and (2) 
statutory exemptions (for instance, exemptions for religious institutions from 
bans on discrimination based on religion, and in some states based on sexual 
orientation).

Still other times, though rarely, courts have carved out religious exemptions 
under RFRAs and similar state constitutional exemption regimes; to my 
knowledge, this has only happened with regard to housing discrimination based 
on marital status.

How to resolve this is not, I think, easily answered either with assertions 
that equality is a core American value or that religious freedom is a basic 
American value, or claims that the ACLU doesn't value[] religious liberty 
for conservative faiths.  My sense is that we need to talk more specifically 
and concretely about the arguments for and against respecting equality and 
liberty in each instance.  (For instance, the argument for letting taxi cab 
drivers discriminate based on passengers' consumption of alcohol - a right that 
most other businesses enjoy, since it doesn't involve discrimination based on 
the passenger's religion, race, etc. - is different from the argument for 
letting landlords refuse to rent to atheists or from the argument for letting 
photographers choose which kinds of expressive works to create.)

My sense is that it might also be helpful to talk about the level of law at 
which a religious exemption regime is enacted.  A state statutory RFRA leaves 
the state legislature free to decide that some laws (including 
antidiscrimination laws) should be exempted from the RFRA, and to effectively 
overturn the results of court decisions that grant exemptions.  A state 
constitutional RFRA doesn't do that.  A federal statutory RFRA that binds state 
governments, and a federal Sherbert/Yoder regime, make it even harder for 
legislatures who feel strongly about the need for an exemption-less equality 
rule to implement those views

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Marc:  It seems to me that state RFRAs are aimed at protecting 
religious observers and religious institutions more than at least many other 
social interests.  Conversely, as I understand the church liability cases, 
plaintiffs usually aim to simply apply normal negligent 
hiring/supervision/retention law to churches, just as it would apply to (say) 
secular private schools, secular youth organizations, secular day care centers, 
and so on.  To be sure, as Doug pointed out, state and local governments often 
are treated better than all these private institutions, under 
sovereign-immunity-ish principles.  But whether that better treatment or not is 
right, it is justified by the sense that taxpayer money needs to be specially 
protected.  Why should religious institutions be given more protection against 
liability than other private organizations?

Eugene

Marc Stern writes:

Allowing religious liberty defenses(which have so far been mostly unsuccessful) 
no more endangers children than does placing the burden of proof on the 
plaintiff in civil cases and the state(beyond a reasonable doubt) in criminal 
cases,rules against hearsay or requiring actual confrontation with accusers and 
so on. What is so troubling about Marci's message is not so much the bottom 
line result as the suggestion that interests of religious institutions-who 
after all are not themselves molesting children whatever their culpability for 
not acting more vigorously to protect children-are somehow systematically less 
worthy of protection than other social interests.
While I accept Eugene's rebuke about rhetoric,and his observation about both 
equality and religious liberty being protected,it seems to me fair to observe 
that while there often ways to maximize both interests, there is an increasing 
tendency-readily visible in positions on conscientious objection by pharmacists 
to eschew such balancing tests in favor of sweeping assertions of the 
overarching importance of equality.
The same trend is evident in the debates over religious exemptions in the 
context of same sex marriage.
Marc

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Excellent points, both in the first paragraph and in the third.

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Graber, Mark
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 6:46 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND

May I suggest this is too strong.  A great many constitutional rights increase 
to some degree the possibility that child abuse will occur, not be detected and 
not be adequately punished.  Consider in this respect the Fourth and Fifth 
Amendments, at least as presently interpreted (and I suspect most of us would 
not agree with an interpretive rule that said government does not violate the 
Fourth and Fifth Amendment whenever doing so might increase to any degree the 
possibility that a crime will not be committed, not be detected, and not be 
punished.  So we might assume that a) protections for religious freedom will 
have some negative consequences, including some severe negative consequences 
but b) that this is true for pretty much all constitutional rights.

So the issue is how much do we risk because we value religious freedom 
(remembering that a strategy of risk nothing will have other severe bad 
consequences.

In this vein, may I suggest that the present alternatives are not helpful.  
SMITH seems to suggest a rational basis test that would allow government to 
severely burden religious practice whenever doing so has any appreciable 
tendency to prevent, detect, or punish crime.  Many RFRAs suggest a compelling 
interest test that probably puts too high a burden on government to do a 
variety of acts (not just in the area of criminal justice-so even if you think, 
as I do, that preventing child abuse is obviously a compelling government 
interest, you might still think the compelling interest standard too strong in 
other cases).

Strikes me that one thing we might discuss is what that in-between standard 
looks like.

Mark A. Graber
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
No, actually I think the quote was an unnecessarily pugnacious 
attempt to capture an important point.  Some religious groups have apparently 
failed to reasonably investigate and monitor people whom they put in positions 
of influence over children, and some of those people have used that influence 
to molest children.  It's at least plausible that holding religious groups 
liable for negligent hiring, retention, and supervision would provide an extra 
incentive for such monitoring and investigation in the future.  Conversely, 
it's at least plausible that immunizing those groups from such employer 
liability would make it easy for them to endanger children -- not through 
deliberate attempts to harm children, of course, but through failure to protect 
the children.



As I've mentioned, I'm skeptical that RFRAs will provide such 
immunity.  But some states have indeed interpreted the First Amendment as 
providing such immunity - and even if that is nonetheless the correct result, 
for non-entanglement reasons or other reasons - it does seem to facilitate 
religious groups' failure to take proper care to protect children.  As I said, 
I think both sides of the discussion have at times put things more pugnaciously 
than is helpful.  But the basic point of the cost of immunity from tort law is 
one that should be taken seriously.



Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of lawyer2...@aol.com

 Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 3:42 AM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND



 Giving religious groups more power to endanger children



 Wow



 To be charitable, I will chalk that one up to the lateness of the hour in 
 which it

 was written.



 -Don Clark

   Nationwide Special Counsel

   United Church of Christ

 Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry



 -Original Message-

 From: Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

 Sender: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu

 Date: Fri, 15 Jun 2012 03:08:48

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law 
 Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law 
 Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND



 ___

 To post, send message to 
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,

 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlawhttp://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people

 can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward

 the messages to others.

 ___

 To post, send message to 
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,

 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlawhttp://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people

 can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward

 the messages to others.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene


From: Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 10:44 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

I disagree on very much with Marci, and I’m not sure that the 
Sherbert/Yoder test would have been inapplicable to the things that NARAL and 
CHILD fears.

But Marci’s more general point strikes me as quite correct:  At least if read 
literally, RFRA enacts an across-the-board strict scrutiny test, which the 
Court in the Sherbert/Yoder era never did.  For instance, when the government 
was acting as prison administrator or as commander of military personnel, the 
religious exemption test--like the Free Speech Clause test--was close to the 
rational basis framework. Lower courts adopted a similarly deferential test for 
probation conditions that incidentally interfered with religious practices.  
When the government was acting as employer, some lower courts likewise adopted 
fairly (but not entirely) deferential tests borrowed from the Pickering test 
applied in government employee free speech cases. There was no agreed-on test 
for the government acting as educator in kindergarten through high school, but 
courts at least had the option of concluding that the free exercise test--like 
the free speech test--should be relatively deferential in these cases, too.

When the government was acting as sovereign, the test was usually strict 
scrutiny, but not always.  For claimants requesting exemptions from generally 
applicable speech restrictions, the free exercise test was the same as the free 
speech test, which might differ from strict scrutiny.  Content-neutral 
restrictions on the time, place, or manner of speech, for instance, are only 
subject to a form of intermediate scrutiny under the Free Speech Clause, and 
Heffron v. ISKCON held that this same quasi-intermediate scrutiny was 
applicable to requests for religious exemptions from such restrictions.   
Similarly, some lower court cases suggested that zoning restrictions were 
subject to a lower standard of scrutiny.

Now perhaps the same results could be reached by applying strict scrutiny with 
an eye towards the special circumstances present in those cases – but that, 
even more than the Court’s “feeble in fact” version of strict scrutiny applied 
in cases such as Lee, Bob Jones, and the like, would in practice be a way of 
avoiding strict scrutiny rather than a way of honestly applying it.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 12:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND

The Sherbert/Yoder test was never treated by the
Supreme Court as a test available across the
board.   So NARAL's concerns and CHILD 's
Issues would not have been controlled by it

The concern is not over enforcement but rather enforcement
Giving religious groups more power to endanger children is
not a good idea.

Marci
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
But as I understand it, some states – though a minority – do 
indeed protect churches from negligent supervision/retention/hiring liability; 
and since generally speaking respondeat superior is usually unavailable in such 
cases, the effect is indeed an immunity of churches from liability for this 
particular sort of abuse.  (I agree that this is hard to lay at the door of 
RFRAs, since the immunity has generally been recognized under the 
non-entanglement doctrine.)

In any case, it seems to me that these concrete discussions of 
what the law does and does not authorize, and which law does so, are more 
helpful than snippy one-liners from either side.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of lawyer2...@aol.com
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 10:57 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND

Agreed.

But in order for there to be a cost of immunity from tort law there first has 
to be immunity from tort law and, particular to this discussion, immunity 
from tort law in child sex abuse cases.

This discussion started with the assertion that RFRA's open the door to child 
sex abuse, lessen deterrence of it, and that RFRA arguments to this end were 
being made by churches and their lawyers all the time

When that was questioned, the limitless assertions devolved to RFRA's adding a 
layer of argument during the course of litigation

--Don Clark
  Nationwide Special Counsel
  United Church of Christ



In a message dated 6/15/2012 12:40:08 P.M. Central Daylight Time, 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu writes:

No, actually I think the quote was an unnecessarily pugnacious 
attempt to capture an important point.  Some religious groups have apparently 
failed to reasonably investigate and monitor people whom they put in positions 
of influence over children, and some of those people have used that influence 
to molest children.  It's at least plausible that holding religious groups 
liable for negligent hiring, retention, and supervision would provide an extra 
incentive for such monitoring and investigation in the future.  Conversely, 
it's at least plausible that immunizing those groups from such employer 
liability would make it easy for them to endanger children -- not through 
deliberate attempts to harm children, of course, but through failure to protect 
the children.



As I've mentioned, I'm skeptical that RFRAs will provide such 
immunity.  But some states have indeed interpreted the First Amendment as 
providing such immunity – and even if that is nonetheless the correct result, 
for non-entanglement reasons or other reasons – it does seem to facilitate 
religious groups’ failure to take proper care to protect children.  As I said, 
I think both sides of the discussion have at times put things more pugnaciously 
than is helpful.  But the basic point of the cost of immunity from tort law is 
one that should be taken seriously.



Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
 lawyer2...@aol.commailto:lawyer2...@aol.com

 Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 3:42 AM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND



 Giving religious groups more power to endanger children



 Wow



 To be charitable, I will chalk that one up to the lateness of the hour in 
 which it

 was written.



 -Don Clark

   Nationwide Special Counsel

   United Church of Christ

 Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry



 -Original Message-

 From: Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

 Sender: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu

 Date: Fri, 15 Jun 2012 03:08:48

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law 
 Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law 
 Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND



 ___

 To post, send message to 
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,

 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlawhttp://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people

 can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward

 the messages to 

Religious exemptions and discrimination

2012-06-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I think this is combining under the rubric of “discrimination” 
many different things.  First, item 2 doesn’t involve discrimination based on 
the passenger’s race, religion, sex, and so on which is why businesses 
generally are free to discriminate against patrons with wine, or employees who 
drink wine.  The relevant law here is a sort of “common carrier” rule that 
imposes on a few businesses (and only a few) the obligation to do business with 
pretty much everyone, an obligation that is much broader than that imposed by 
antidiscrimination law.  Relatedly, item 1 doesn’t involve discrimination in 
the antidiscrimination law sense (except insofar as one can argue that such a 
refusal is sex discrimination because only women take Plan B, which I doubt 
will succeed).  Indeed, I take it that all of us would agree that a supermarket 
could choose to refuse to stock condoms (male or female) or over-the-counter 
contraceptives.  Rather, the relevant law is a professional obligation imposed 
on pharmacies to stock either all in-demand pharmaceuticals, or at least to 
stock this particular pharmaceutical.

Second, even true discrimination rules have historically been 
applied more narrowly in some areas than in others, and this reflects (in 
addition to federalism concerns) real differences in the way discrimination 
affects people.  Title II of the Civil Rights Act, for instance, does not 
constrain pharmacies, cab drivers, or professional photographers; indeed, it 
applies to only a narrow range of places of public accommodation.  It does, 
however, affect all businesses with more than a threshold number of employees.  
And this makes sense, because as to many places of public accommodation, the 
chief harm with discrimination is only dignitary:  If Elaine Huguenin refuses 
to photograph a same-sex commitment ceremony, the couple might be annoyed by 
the refusal, but they can probably find another photographer at little cost, at 
least in most places.  (Indeed, the couple may prefer to hire a photographer 
who they feel will see their ceremony as beautiful, and thus be inspired to 
photograph it that way, rather than a photographer who is being forced by law 
to photograph something she disapproves of.)  On the other hand, employment 
discrimination can dramatically affect people’s livelihoods, especially since 
employment is often much less fungible than most commercially available 
services.

Third, different sorts of discrimination rules relate 
differently to other constitutional rights, and liberty rights more generally.  
Requiring a photographer to photograph something she doesn’t want to photograph 
affects her  First Amendment right not to create expressive works that she 
disapproves of.  (Even those who think wedding photography isn’t expressive 
enough to qualify for that purposes might, I think, agree that a commercial 
press release writer should have the right to refuse to write press releases 
for Scientology – though that’s discriminating based on religion – or to write 
a glowing account of a same-sex ceremony.)  Likewise, constraining a landlord’s 
choice about who lives in the other half of a duplex in which she lives may 
burden her privacy rights, constitutional or otherwise.  Not so for a landlord 
who owns a large apartment building.  This doesn’t directly affect the 
religious exemption claim, of course, but it does highlight why the wedding 
photographer example may need to be treated differently.

Given these differences, it seems to me quite unsurprising that 
the caselaw rejecting religious exemptions to employment discrimination claims 
wouldn’t necessarily fully extend to claims of housing  discrimination based on 
marital status (to give an example of a religious exemption claim that some 
courts have accepted), and wouldn’t be particularly helpful as to claimed 
exemptions from common carrier obligations or professional regulations.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 12:19 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND


Chris,



While you would be willing to grant a child safety exception to appease Marci, 
I presume that in your view (and correct me if I'm wrong) that burden type 
RFRAs (like the North Dakota proposal) would permit the following examples of 
discrimination?

 1.  A pharmacist refusing to dispense Plan B.
 2.  A Muslim taxi cab driver refusing to transport a person with a bottle of 
wine in a grocery bag.
 3.  A professional photographer refusing to photograph an LGBT civil ceremony.
 4.  A landlord refusing to rent to an atheist.

If yes, are these acts of discrimination less a compelling governmental 
interest than anti-discrimination provisions of the Civil Rights Act?



Bob Ritter

On June 15, 2012 at 10:31 AM 

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-18 Thread Volokh, Eugene
But I suspect the Texas Statutes includes many more than 400 statutes!  
Moreover, my sense is that many states that provide for initiative 
constitutional amendments also provide for initiative statutes, which are 
easier to put on the ballot than the amendments; that's certainly true in 
California.  And if a legislature thinks a court decision interpreting a RFRA 
statute is wrong, it can correct it by just enacting a statute.  If it thinks a 
court decision interpreting a state constitutional amendment is wrong, it needs 
to put a proposed amendment on the ballot, which (I believe) generally requires 
a greater majority of the vote in the legislature coupled with (in all states 
but Delaware) a vote of the people.  And while constitutional amendments can be 
put on the ballot by initiative in many states (about half, if I recall 
correctly), that usually takes a good deal of money, something that often might 
not be available.

So it seems to me that it is indeed generally a good deal easier to 
change a court decision handed down under a state statute than one handed down 
under a state constitutional amendment.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
 Sent: Monday, June 18, 2012 1:24 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 
 
 Should we really assume that it is harder to get something through a
 legislature than to get a ballot measure passed? I can't speak to how easy it 
 is
 to get a ballot measure together in North Dakota, but in several states and on
 some issues it is arguably easier to change the constitution than to get a 
 bill
 through the legislature. The Texas Constitution has over 400 amendments, I
 believe.
 
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edu]
 Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 11:03 AM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 That is true.
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 10:49 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 Chris Lund writes:
 
 It's also important to keep in mind that the protection of state RFRAs can
 always be legislatively narrowed-and that has happened.  Concerned with a
 pending suit by a Muslim to claim a drivers' license without having to take 
 off
 her headscarf, Florida statutorily (and retroactively) removed such claims
 from the protection of Florida's RFRA.  Judging by Florida's reaction to it, 
 that
 apparently is the most threatening state RFRA claim that has ever been
 brought.  I leave it to the listserv to evaluate how bad it really is, but it 
 is
 certainly less scary than what Measure 3 opponents feared.
 
 
   I think the opportunity for legislative narrowing is a critical 
 argument
 in favor of state RFRAs - but wouldn't that have at least been somewhat
 harder with Measure 3, which would have been a state constitutional
 amendment and not a state statute?
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,
 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people
 can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward
 the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


FW: 2012 Elon Law Review Symposium

2012-06-18 Thread Volokh, Eugene


From: mailman-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:mailman-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On 
Behalf Of Ryan Morrison
Sent: Monday, June 18, 2012 6:48 PM
To: religionlaw-ow...@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: 2012 Elon Law Review Symposium

Good evening,

My name is Ryan Morrison, and I am a Symposium Editor for the Elon Law Review.  
I was hoping your LISTSERV would include a blurb about our call for articles, 
essays and requests to present for our 2012 Symposium: Emerging Issues in 
First Amendment Jurisprudence: Interpreting the Relationship Between Religion 
and the State in the Modern Age.  It will be held on October 26, 2012, and 
proposals are due by July 15, 2012.

Website: http://www.elon.edu/e-web/law/law_review/symposium2012.xhtml
Call for Authors: 
http://www.elon.edu/docs/e-web/law/law_review/Elon_Law_Review_2012_Symposium_Call_for_Authors.pdf

Please let me know if you need me to provide any additional information in 
order to be included in your LISTSERV.  Thanks in advance!

Best,
Ryan Morrison
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-20 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Well, I suppose sometimes it might be so.  But I think that on balance 
ordinary legislation is easier to pass than a constitutional amendment.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
 Sent: Monday, June 18, 2012 3:52 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 
 Would you agree that for political reasons it is sometimes easier to get a
 ballot initiative (even a constitutional one) passed than to get legislation 
 with
 the same provisions passed?  I think it is likely that the relative ease of 
 passing
 legislation vs. passing a ballot measure will differ significantly from state 
 to
 state, in particular between states that allow constitutional amendment by
 ballot initiative and those that do not, and between states that tend to be
 dominated by one party or the other and those that are not. And it is probably
 a lot easier to get 4% of the voters in North Dakota to sign on to a ballot
 initiative than it is to get 4% of the voters in California.  In short, I 
 don't think it
 makes sense to generalize here, and I understand your proposition below to be
 a generalization.
 
 Also, for what it's worth, I imagine it might take a good deal of money to 
 get
 a particular law through a state legislature; the money flow is just less
 obvious.
 
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
 [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
 Sent: Monday, June 18, 2012 4:47 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 But I suspect the Texas Statutes includes many more than 400 statutes!
 Moreover, my sense is that many states that provide for initiative
 constitutional amendments also provide for initiative statutes, which are
 easier to put on the ballot than the amendments; that's certainly true in
 California.  And if a legislature thinks a court decision interpreting a RFRA
 statute is wrong, it can correct it by just enacting a statute.  If it thinks 
 a court
 decision interpreting a state constitutional amendment is wrong, it needs to
 put a proposed amendment on the ballot, which (I believe) generally requires
 a greater majority of the vote in the legislature coupled with (in all states 
 but
 Delaware) a vote of the people.  And while constitutional amendments can be
 put on the ballot by initiative in many states (about half, if I recall 
 correctly),
 that usually takes a good deal of money, something that often might not be
 available.
 
 So it seems to me that it is indeed generally a good deal easier to 
 change
 a court decision handed down under a state statute than one handed down
 under a state constitutional amendment.
 
 Eugene
 
  -Original Message-
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
  Sent: Monday, June 18, 2012 1:24 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 
 
  Should we really assume that it is harder to get something through a
  legislature than to get a ballot measure passed? I can't speak to how
  easy it is to get a ballot measure together in North Dakota, but in
  several states and on some issues it is arguably easier to change the
  constitution than to get a bill through the legislature. The Texas
  Constitution has over 400 amendments, I believe.
 
 
  
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-
  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edu]
  Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 11:03 AM
  To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
  Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
  That is true.
 
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
  Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 10:49 AM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
  Chris Lund writes:
 
  It's also important to keep in mind that the protection of state RFRAs
  can always be legislatively narrowed-and that has happened.  Concerned
  with a pending suit by a Muslim to claim a drivers' license without
  having to take off her headscarf, Florida statutorily (and
  retroactively) removed such claims from the protection of Florida's
  RFRA.  Judging by Florida's reaction to it, that apparently is the
  most threatening state RFRA claim that has ever been brought.  I leave
  it to the listserv to evaluate how bad it really is, but it is certainly 
  less scary
 than what Measure 3 opponents feared.
 
 
I think the opportunity for legislative narrowing is a
  critical argument in favor of state RFRAs - but wouldn't that have at
  least been somewhat harder

RE: Providing public school credits for release-time religious classes

2012-06-30 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I share some list members’ discomfort with Zorach, and with the 
South Carolina law that gives favored treatment to religious studies classes, 
rather than just releasing students to take a class at any other accredited 
school or at any unaccredited school if the class is certified by an accredited 
school.  I’m sure I’m “hostile to separation” in Marci’s view, and though I’m 
entirely irreligious myself I am indeed hostile to the separation that Marci 
advocates.  Yet I do think that this sort of discrimination in favor of 
religion ought to be seen as constitutionally suspect, and I regret that Zorach 
took a different view.

But the argument below seems to me to go too far, because of 
the transfer student point raised by Rick and by the Fourth Circuit opinion.  
Say that someone transfers to a public school in the 11th grade, and to be 
entitled to so transfer he has to show some number of semester-hours of 
schoolwork at his prior school; and say that the prior school had a pervasively 
religious curriculum, so that many classes have a religious component.  Is it 
really the case that the public school is constitutionally barred from 
accepting those semester-hours?  I would think not, though I’d be happy to hear 
Marci’s view on the subject.

Now perhaps there is some constitutional distinction between 
pure theology classes and mixed religious/nonreligious classes – but when it 
comes to funding programs, the Souter/Stevens/Brennan/Marshall wing has 
generally insisted that there is no such distinction.  So it seems to me that 
the constitutional objection can’t be to schools accepting credit for religious 
instruction from other schools; the objection must be to schools doing so under 
programs that favor religious instruction.

Eugene

Marci Hamilton writes:

On the merits, I don't see why or how the public schools can take frankly 
ecclesiastical courses from frankly religious schools for credit under existing 
doctrine.

Now, if the argument is that the Court should and may abandon the Establishment 
Clause, let's be honest about that.   It is well known that those hostile to 
separation are hoping this new Court will cut back on the Est Cl

Under existing doctrine, these credits are a violation of the separation of 
church and state and the Memorial and Remonstrance.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: German circumcision decision

2012-07-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Any chance we could have some helpful analysis of the decision, 
rather than one-liners?  The question of the degree to which parents should be 
able to permanently alter their children's bodies - for religious reasons or 
otherwise - is not, it seems to me, one that has a completely obvious answer 
one way or the other.  There may indeed be one correct answer that can be 
demonstrated, but such demonstration requires argument rather than assertion.

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Male circumcision, female circumcision, and ear-piercing

2012-07-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
An analogy between male circumcision and ear-piercing is no 
more dispositive than an analogy between male circumcision and female 
circumcision, it seems to me.  There’s a spectrum here:  Normal ear-piercing 
has virtually no effects on bodily function, since there seem to be no really 
significant nerve endings or other really significant tissue removed in the 
process.  Normal male circumcision might well have some effects on sexual 
sensation, given the removal of an area of skin that does seem to have 
considerable sexual sensation.  Many forms of female circumcision pretty 
clearly have very substantial effects on sexual sensation (as well as having 
other harmful effects).

What makes this a hard question is precisely that we don’t know 
much about where to draw the line on this spectrum – a spectrum that of course 
involves people’s altering other people’s bodies (even if those other people 
are their children) and not their own.  Incidentally, it’s far from clear to me 
that a ban on tattooing under-18-year-olds in prominent places (which could 
have marked effects on their children’s future social lives as adults) would be 
unconstitutional or improper even if parents wanted to tattoo the children, 
especially in an era when tattoos were hard to remove.

Eugene

Paul Finkelman writes:

Are they also banning parents from piercing the ears of children? In many 
cultures it is common to see infant girls with pierced ears.   Does the ban 
extend to pierced ears before age 18?  And then there is body piercing before 
age 18.  Is that being banned?  Has the Court banned tattoos for people under 
18?
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: German circumcision decision

2012-07-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Marty:  Everything you say is sensible, and I agree that the 
case is difficult.  This is precisely why a one-line statement about German 
history is inadequate to advance the ball much on this.  As a general matter, 
it seems to me that a country's 70-year-old crimes tell much about what that 
country should do today; as a specific matter, I don't think that a country's 
killing Jews in the past tells us much about whether it's wrong for the country 
to try to protect children - indeed, often Jewish (or Muslim) children - from 
what a reasonable person could perceive as irreversible imposition of a harm 
that the children can't consent to and might indeed eventually regret.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Sunday, July 01, 2012 9:21 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: German circumcision decision

Actually, I don't think Paul's comment is a one-liner -- the fact that this 
decision comes from Germany is surely the most striking and disconcerting -- 
and important -- thing about it.

As far as analysis is concerned, well, how could there be a correct answer? 
 I think we can all agree that such a law imposes a very substantial burden on 
the religious exercise of most of those affected.  Is there a governmental 
interest sufficient to overcome this burden, as either a legal or a moral 
matter?  Well, that depends, of course, on how the society in question measures 
the harms to the infant boys -- harms to health, dignity, autonomy, etc.  And 
that in turn depends on ever-shifting evidence and evolving moral sensibilities.

If this were a case in which many or most of the boys in question later 
regretted the decisions of their parents, or where there were an undeniable, 
severe harm in terms of health or sexual well-being -- as is the case with 
respect to, e.g., female genital mutilation -- then the balancing would be 
fairly obvious.  But in this case, not only do most men not mind that their 
parents made that decision (I assume that's also true in Germany -- but perhaps 
not), but in addition, many or most of those men who prefer to be circumcised 
are actually grateful that the decision was made at birth, since the procedure 
is much riskier and more painful (or so I'm told!) when performed on an adult.  
Surely that unusual set of facts makes this case much different from, e.g., the 
FGM and denial-of-lifesaving-medical treatment cases.  On the other hand, the 
harm to the men (presumably a minority -- but again, perhaps things are 
different in Germany) who regret their parents' decision is irreversable.  
That's what makes the case so difficult.
On Sun, Jul 1, 2012 at 11:56 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Any chance we could have some helpful analysis of the decision, 
rather than one-liners?  The question of the degree to which parents should be 
able to permanently alter their children's bodies - for religious reasons or 
otherwise - is not, it seems to me, one that has a completely obvious answer 
one way or the other.  There may indeed be one correct answer that can be 
demonstrated, but such demonstration requires argument rather than assertion.

Eugene

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: German circumcision decision

2012-07-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I don't see why it's religio-cultural[ly] insensitiv[e] to 
say that a decision made for medical reasons is permissible but a decision made 
for religious reasons is not; or if it is religio-culturally insensitive, I 
would be proudly religio-culturally insensitive in many instances.  (This 
instance I do find hard, for many reasons, but not for the reasons described 
below.)  For instance, I don't see why we should treat (a) a parent's refusing 
necessary medical treatment to a child because there's a plausible argument 
that the treatment will do more harm than good the same as (b) a parent's 
refusing such treatment without any such explanation but simply because he 
concludes we should pray instead of performing the medical procedure, and God 
will take care of things.  Perhaps it's too hard to tease apart such 
rationales in some situations, but as a general matter I would think that 
courts might quite rightly reject rationale (b) even if they accept rationale 
(a).

Now of course here the situation is not identical - indeed, as 
I've argued before, male circumcision is not identical to pretty much any other 
procedure - and perhaps the situation should be different when we're not 
talking about refusal of necessary medical treatment but rather the performance 
of a medical procedure for which the practical effect (with regard to possible 
loss of sexual sensation) is unknown.  But the point is that the mere fact that 
a decision might permissibly be made for plausible medical reasons doesn't mean 
that it might permissibly be made for religious reasons (or other nonmedical 
reasons).

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Vance R. Koven
Sent: Sunday, July 01, 2012 9:38 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: German circumcision decision

Isn't there still a substantial body of medical opinion--perhaps not as 
prevalent as in decades past--that recommends circumcision as a preventive 
health measure? If the issue is the lack of consent from the subject of the 
operation, this certainly affects more than just religious observance, and more 
than just this particular operation. And if the decision hinges specifically on 
the fact that the motivation (if that can ever be clear) is primarily 
religious, that certainly smacks of religio-cultural insensitivity, to put it 
mildly.

Vance
On Sun, Jul 1, 2012 at 12:21 PM, Paul Finkelman 
paul.finkel...@yahoo.commailto:paul.finkel...@yahoo.com wrote:
Are they also banning parents from piercing the ears of children? In many 
cultures it is common to see infant girls with pierced ears.   Does the ban 
extend to pierced ears before age 18?  And then there is body piercing before 
age 18.  Is that being banned?  Has the Court banned tattoos for people under 
18?

And has this ban spread to Muslim male children, who are circumcised at age 7, 
10 or slightly later depending on the sect.

The fact is, given Germany's history of how it has dealt with Jews, is is not 
illegitimate to wonder what the Court is thinking.   Germany has one of the 
fastest growing Jewish populations in the world -- mostly through immigration.  
This decision, if enforced all over the country, would slow down or stop that 
population growth.  One might at least ponder why this case has come to the 
Germany court, and not one involving piercing, tattoos, or Muslim circumcision.


Paul Finkelman
President William McKinley Distinguished Professor of Law
Albany Law School
80 New Scotland Avenue
Albany, NY 12208
518-445-3386tel:518-445-3386 (p)
518-445-3363tel:518-445-3363 (f)

paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edumailto:paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu

www.paulfinkelman.comhttp://www.paulfinkelman.com

From: Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sunday, July 1, 2012 11:56 AM
Subject: RE: German circumcision decision

Any chance we could have some helpful analysis of the decision, 
rather than one-liners?  The question of the degree to which parents should be 
able to permanently alter their children's bodies - for religious reasons or 
otherwise - is not, it seems to me, one that has a completely obvious answer 
one way or the other.  There may indeed be one correct answer that can be 
demonstrated, but such demonstration requires argument rather than assertion.

Eugene

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted

Laws that impose semi-religious, ethical view[s]

2012-07-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
It seems to me that a vast range of laws - including laws that 
Paul and others would very much support - can equally be described as imposing 
semi-religious, ethical view[s] on others.  After all, at the bottom of many 
laws is an ethical judgment that can't be proven or disproven, and one can 
label it semi-religious in the sense that it is taken as an article of moral 
faith.  That's true, I imagine, of animal cruelty laws, antidiscrimination 
laws, child labor laws, endangered species laws, historical preservation laws, 
and many more.  (One can also make supposedly utilitarian arguments for some 
such laws, but at some point the utility calculus will require one to ascribe a 
particular weight to one or another value, and that judgment will be the same 
sort of unprovable ethical semi-religious judgment.)  One can even conclude 
that people who support those laws are unwilling to embrace diversity when it 
comes to people who have (and implement) diverse views on whether to 
discriminate in employment or public accommodation, whether to treat animals in 
particular ways, whether to hunt grizzly bears, whether to raze historical 
building that they own, and so on.

I don't see how laws implementing the principle that one person 
ought not alter another person's body without permission - even when the 
alterer is the altered person's parent - unless it's very clear that the 
alteration is likely to be almost entirely harmless (or unless the motivation 
is medical necessity, and the alterer can credibly say that he's acting as the 
altered person would likely prefer in this situation) are any more intolerant 
or impermissible than those other laws I mentioned.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Finkelman, Paul 
paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
Sent: Sunday, July 01, 2012 11:42 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: German circumcision decision

Alan's point raises another analytical issue.  If don't harm the body is a 
semi-religious, ethical view, then aren't the German court and the proponents 
of the SF measure simply imposing their religious values on those of others who 
have a different faith. I think it is not unreasonable to see the German 
decision as an attempt to force out Muslims (and Jews) in a nation that is very 
uncomfortable with foreigners, immigration, and diversity.  I have spent a fair 
amount of time in Germany over the last 20 years and I am always struck by how 
determined the Germans are not to allow Turks -- but this time 3rd and 4th 
generation German-born, German-speaking Turks -- to become German citizens.



*
Paul Finkelman, Ph.D.
President William McKinley Distinguished Professor of Law
Albany Law School
80 New Scotland Avenue
Albany, NY 12208

518-445-3386 (p)
518-445-3363 (f)

paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edumailto:paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
www.paulfinkelman.comhttp://www.paulfinkelman.com
*

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Alan Brownstein 
[aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu]
Sent: Sunday, July 01, 2012 2:31 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: German circumcision decision

I agree with almost of all of Marty's thoughtful post -- except that I do not 
see this as a difficult case. When an attempt was made to place this issue on 
the ballot in San Francisco, some people argued medical and health concerns 
(although as Marty and Paul point out, the evidence here is indeterminate and 
disputed.) But most of the people I spoke with who supported the ban did so for 
almost quasi religious reasons -- a kind of don't alter the natural body 
philosophy -- or on autonomy grounds.



While I think the autonomy argument isn't entirely frivolous, our legal system 
allows parents to make so many choices for their children that  substantially 
impact their physical and mental health, personality, and appearance (without 
being subject to challenge on the grounds that they have interfered with the 
child's autonomy) that I don't assign a lot of weight to this interest. The 
alternative, after all, to having parents make these decisions is for the state 
to do so in their place.



Finally, of course, there are the obvious consequences for such a ban on 
religious freedom. Laws that require devout religious individuals to violate 
core obligations of their faith at best are intrinsically exclusionary. Unless 
one envisions a world where moderately or seriously religious Jews (and 
Muslims) voluntarily cease to exist, a ban on circumcision prohibits those 
families from living in a community.



Alan









___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To 

What parents may or may not do with regard to their children

2012-07-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Alan:  But our legal system also bars parents from physically 
acting towards their children in various other ways.  Parents may not beat 
their children beyond a certain point.  Parents may not excise their girls' 
genitalia.  Parents may not consent to their children's having sex before a 
certain age (in some states, that age is 18), or participating in making 
pornography.  Parents may not consent to their children's working in various 
jobs that impose even modest risk to health until a certain age.  It's possible 
that if parents wanted to change their children's appearance in a permanent and 
material way, they wouldn't be allowed to do that (except in situations where 
the appearance change is likely to be seen by outside observers as an 
improvement).  If parents wanted to bind their daughter's feet, I expect that 
would be forbidden.  And while the alternative in all these cases if for the 
state to make the decision, that decision is generally do not allow the 
physical actions until the child is old enough to decide for himself or 
herself - a plausible conclusion, I think.

So the question, it seems to me, is whether male circumcision 
should be treated more like, say, ear-piercing or teaching children some 
philosophy or religion, ore more like all the other things I described above.

Eugene

Alan Brownstein writes:


While I think the autonomy argument isn't entirely frivolous, our legal system 
allows parents to make so many choices for their children that  substantially 
impact their physical and mental health, personality, and appearance (without 
being subject to challenge on the grounds that they have interfered with the 
child's autonomy) that I don't assign a lot of weight to this interest. The 
alternative, after all, to having parents make these decisions is for the state 
to do so in their place.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Harm to religious communities vs. the harm of unconsented-to surgical operations on those communities' children

2012-07-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm skeptical about Mark's historical argument (though I do 
agree that if foreskin regeneration were easy and reliable, we'd have much less 
of an argument for banning circumcision).  But as to the reprehensible 
ethics of the decision, the question is why we should weigh destroying or 
banishing one or more religious communities as ethically worse than allowing 
unconsented-to surgical operations that might well substantially harm the 
children and that often aren't made for any medical reason.  Again, I take it 
that we wouldn't be that upset that a ban on female circumcision might destroy 
or banish some religio-cultural communities (not all Muslims but presumably 
some subgroups), because we think that the protection of girls is more 
important than protection of the religious sensibilities of those who would 
mutilate the girls' genitals.  So it seems to me that while the effect on 
religious communities might have some weight, the weight should be quite 
limited.

I agree entirely that the case for allowing male circumcision 
might well be strong, for instance if there is strong evidence that it does 
indeed provide health benefits (as it well might) or that it doesn't materially 
affect sexual sensation (again, that might well be true as well, though of 
course it's hard to tell).  But it is these factors, which go to the well-being 
of children who are being operated on without their consent, that strike me as 
more important than the religious views of those who would do the 
unconsented-to operations.

Eugene

Mark Scarberry writes:

With regard to the US and our 1st Amendment:

I've been suggesting for some time informally that we should consider a 
historical (an historical?) approach to free exercise. Those religious 
practices that have been accepted for a long time in our society  settings (and 
modern analogues) should be seen as part of the religious exercise that is 
protected. Use of relatively small amounts of mildly intoxicating substances by 
adults or near-adults in controlled settings (e.g., communion wine) should be 
protected. That would cover not only communion wine but also the religious uses 
of hoasca tea and peyote. Use of large amounts of traditionally accepted 
intoxicants in a historically societally-accepted setting (drinking of 
substantial amounts wine in Jewish religious celebrations like the Passover 
Seder) could arguably be protected.

Circumcision not only has been a historically-accepted practice but also has 
historically been seen as necessary for the existence in our society of a 
minority religious community, the Jews. By analogy, similar practices that have 
only relatively benign and limited physical effects should  be protected, 
including Muslim circumcision (which I suppose but do not know to be very 
similar to Jewish circumcision). Branding children's faces or female genital 
mutilation would not be protected, though the details of how they would be 
distinguished would have to be worked out.

Note that circumcision has been widely practiced in the US by Christians as 
well as by Jews, and has been seen as a kind of familial choice. For Smith 
purposes, the combination of historically-rooted parental rights with the free 
exercise claim should be sufficient even under current law to protect 
circumcision.

All of this is apart from the ethics of this German decision, which is 
reprehensible in its foreseeable effect of destroying or banishing one or more 
religious communities.

Note also that circumcision is not necessarily irreversible. See 
http://intactnews.org/node/115/1314118161/pioneering-foreskin-regeneration-reverse-circumcision-interview-founder-foregen.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Laws that impose semi-religious, ethical view[s]

2012-07-04 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The post below seems to retreat entirely from the argument that 
somehow circumcision bans are impermissible because 'don't harm the body' is a 
semi-religious, ethical view - and rightly so, because most important laws, as 
I argued below, rest on such unproven and unprovable ethical views.  (That 
antidiscrimination laws can't apply to churches stems not from their being 
based on an ethical view, since antidiscrimination laws applied to ordinary 
businesses are likewise based on an ethical view, but rather from our judgment 
about the freedom of religious association.)

The question remains whether it's proper to restrict infant 
male circumcision - a long standing religious practice - based on such an 
ethical view.  I'm inclined to say that the longstanding nature of the practice 
shouldn't weigh much in the analysis, just as the longstanding nature of the 
practice of beating one's children (sometimes, based on the Biblical statement, 
spare the road, spoil the child) as discipline shouldn't.   I should say that 
I'm not sure that all corporal punishment is bad, just that restrictions on 
such punishment are not improper intrusions on religious freedom.

As I said before, I think that whether infant male circumcision 
bans should be permissible ought to turn on (1) the degree to which there's 
reason to think that male circumcision diminishes sexual sensation (that would 
distinguish it from ear-piercing), and (2) the degree to which it in any event 
has important health benefits (that would analogize it to various other medical 
procedures that parents can rightly choose).  But those questions, it seems to 
me, are the important ones - and labeling of don't harm the body as a 
semi-religious, ethical view should be entirely irrelevant.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Finkelman, Paul 
paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
Sent: Sunday, July 01, 2012 5:59 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws that impose semi-religious, ethical view[s]

The answer maybe that a one size fits all theory does not work; we may need 
some traditional balancing.  Some of that is clearly dictated by societal norms 
-- so we no longer accept binding of feet as acceptable (although that never 
had a religious basis).  Anti-discrimination laws, for example, cannot compel a 
church to accept non-members or even integrate. The do require people to 
forsake their religiously based discrimination in the outside world.  So, a 
person may have a religious belief in the inferiority of blacks or Jews, and 
thus not let them into his home or his church or private club; he may not 
refuse to serve them in his restaurant.  Thus I am not sure where Eugene is 
tying to go with this.  It strikes me that a law banning a long standing 
religious practice has a heavy burden to overcome, and it might be balanced by 
the harm it would cause the religious group.



*
Paul Finkelman, Ph.D.
President William McKinley Distinguished Professor of Law
Albany Law School
80 New Scotland Avenue
Albany, NY 12208

518-445-3386 (p)
518-445-3363 (f)

paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edumailto:paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
www.paulfinkelman.comhttp://www.paulfinkelman.com
*

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, July 01, 2012 5:34 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Laws that impose semi-religious, ethical view[s]
It seems to me that a vast range of laws - including laws that 
Paul and others would very much support - can equally be described as imposing 
semi-religious, ethical view[s] on others.  After all, at the bottom of many 
laws is an ethical judgment that can't be proven or disproven, and one can 
label it semi-religious in the sense that it is taken as an article of moral 
faith.  That's true, I imagine, of animal cruelty laws, antidiscrimination 
laws, child labor laws, endangered species laws, historical preservation laws, 
and many more.  (One can also make supposedly utilitarian arguments for some 
such laws, but at some point the utility calculus will require one to ascribe a 
particular weight to one or another value, and that judgment will be the same 
sort of unprovable ethical semi-religious judgment.)  One can even conclude 
that people who support those laws are unwilling to embrace diversity when it 
comes to people who have (and implement) diverse views on whether to 
discriminate in employment or public accommodation, whether to treat animals in 
particular ways, whether to hunt grizzly bears, whether to raze historical 
building that they own, and so on.

I don't see how laws implementing the principle that one

RE: What parents may or may not do with regard to their children

2012-07-04 Thread Volokh, Eugene
 consequence, I am unpersuaded that 
it harms the child.



If the state limits its intervention in parental decision-making to a 
considerable extent out of respect for parental autonomy, and the question of 
whether circumcision harms the child is unresolved, I think respect for 
religious freedom and parental autonomy make this a relatively easy decision 
for me.



Alan


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Volokh, Eugene 
[vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, July 01, 2012 2:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: What parents may or may not do with regard to their children
Alan:  But our legal system also bars parents from physically 
acting towards their children in various other ways.  Parents may not beat 
their children beyond a certain point.  Parents may not excise their girls' 
genitalia.  Parents may not consent to their children's having sex before a 
certain age (in some states, that age is 18), or participating in making 
pornography.  Parents may not consent to their children's working in various 
jobs that impose even modest risk to health until a certain age.  It's possible 
that if parents wanted to change their children's appearance in a permanent and 
material way, they wouldn't be allowed to do that (except in situations where 
the appearance change is likely to be seen by outside observers as an 
improvement).  If parents wanted to bind their daughter's feet, I expect that 
would be forbidden.  And while the alternative in all these cases if for the 
state to make the decision, that decision is generally do not allow the 
physical actions until the child is old enough to decide for himself or 
herself - a plausible conclusion, I think.

So the question, it seems to me, is whether male circumcision 
should be treated more like, say, ear-piercing or teaching children some 
philosophy or religion, ore more like all the other things I described above.

Eugene


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Medical reasons for action vs. religious reasons for action

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Here's an analogy from another area in which the normal rule - 
one person may not alter or injure another's body without permission - is 
relaxed: self-defense.

Say Vic is doing something that Don perceives as blasphemous, 
but that might also be dangerous to Don or Don's property.  (E.g., say Vic is 
burning a Koran and saying things that might reasonably lead Don - a Muslim - 
to think that Vic will imminently injure Don, or that the fire will spread to 
Don's property.)  Vic attacks Don using nondeadly force and injures him.

If Don reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure Don, 
and hit Don to prevent that, Don is not guilty of any crime, by reason of 
self-defense.  But say that the objective circumstances are the same, so that 
Don could have reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure him, but Don 
did not actually sincerely believe this.  Instead, he says that he attacked Vic 
because he thought God wanted him to attack Vic.  Then Don is guilty of 
assault; no self-defense defense is available (and I take it that we'd agree 
that no other defense should be available to him).  This rule does not treat 
religious reasons for hitting Vic worse than secular reasons generally.  But it 
does treat all reasons for hitting Vic worse than one favored secular reason - 
the perception that Vic poses an imminent danger to Don's person or property.

If I'm right on this, then I all think that there's no 
violation of the norm of equal treatment when we add another reason for 
allowing one person to alter or injure another's body: that the actor is the 
subject's parent and has a medical reason for ordering a surgery to the 
underage child.  That the parent has a right to alter the child's body for 
medical reasons doesn't mean he has a right to alter the child's body - even 
when the objective circumstances seem the same - for nonmedical reasons, 
including religious ones.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Vance R. Koven
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 7:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: German circumcision decision

OK, let's turn this around again. I don't follow Eugene's reasoning here. If I 
do for religious reasons what anyone else could do for secular reasons, why 
should this be penalized? Seems like a fundamental equal-treatment issue.

On the second paragraph, Eugene is correct that my point went to institutional 
competence and legitimacy. I have little faith in courts to divine a social or 
moral consensus that isn't heavily biased in favor of whatever the upper middle 
class (the category into which most judges fall) thinks it knows. In the 
absence of an affirmative policy decision by elected representatives, 
therefore, the rule of decision that imposes the least harm to the polity ought 
to be that tradition carries prima facie probative weight. This is especially 
true in criminal cases, where the standard of statutory interpretation requires 
that crimes be clearly specified--none of this do no harm generalizing!
On Wed, Jul 4, 2012 at 4:24 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Sorry for the delay responding - I was traveling Monday and 
Tuesday - but I'm not sure I grasp the argument in the first paragraph.  My 
view is generally this:

(1)  People should generally have the power to make medical 
decisions for themselves.
(2)  Infants and children can't make such decisions.
(3)  Yet some such medical decisions must be made quickly, 
before the child becomes mature enough to decide.
(4)  We therefore delegate this power to make medical decisions 
to the parents.

But this argument hinges on there being medical reasons for the 
decision - I don't see any reason for parents to have this power when they 
exercise it for nonmedical reasons.  We may defer to a parent's decision, even 
one we doubt, when it involves a tradeoff of one medical risk for another 
medical risk.  But I don't see why we should defer to such a decision when the 
parent doesn't even purport to be making a medical judgment, but is just 
deciding based on the judgment that God wants me to do this or I don't want 
to give more profits to Big Pharma.  That's not weighing religious motivation 
negatively because it's religious - that's weighing a nonmedical motivation 
negatively compared to a medical motivation because the only justification for 
letting me order someone to alter not my body but my son's body is the need for 
medical judgment.

This leaves two different arguments.  One is letting people do 
what they have always done, which strikes me as weak for the reasons I gave in 
part of my response to Paul Finkelman's post - especially give the longstanding 
tradition of allowing

Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
This raises a fascinating and practically very important 
question (because there are more than 10 times as many American parents who 
authorize circumcision for nonreligious reasons than for religious reasons):  
Do Meyer/Pierce rights extend to the right to raise one's child in the sense of 
selecting an education for the child, setting behavior rules for the child, 
choosing a place to live with the child, and so on, or do they also have the 
constitutional right (not just a common-law right) to physically alter the 
child's body, including for nonmedical reasons?  When I last checked the 
caselaw on the subject, the Supreme Court cases weren't clear on that.  Are 
there cases I'm missing on that?

To be sure, I agree that parents are generally allowed to let 
their children put themselves at risk in various ways, such as by playing 
tackle football and not wearing enough sunscreen.  But that doesn't tell us 
much about whether that's a constitutional right.  And indeed I don't think 
that laws banning child labor, for instance, have been judged as interfering 
with parental rights (imagine Prince without the religious motivation), even 
though many such laws (again, imagine Prince) are pretty clearly overbroad.  
Likewise, I would think that a ban on ear piercing, tattooing, etc. of minors, 
even when the parents order such actions, would be constitutional, though of 
course that's part of the dispute between us.

Is there dispositive caselaw I'm missing here?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 7:38 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: German circumcision decision

We are making this so much more complicated than it has to be.  I cannot speak 
to the particulars of the case in Germany, so I won't try.  But in the U.S, we 
have a longstanding tradition, initially at common law and ultimately in 
constitutional law (Pierce, Meyer, etc.) of parental control over the 
upbringing of their children.  The state can interfere with that control only 
for very good reason, and the state bears the burden of persuasion that it has 
such a reason.  Compulsory education, compulsory vaccination, and limiting 
child labor are the most obvious, specific policies that interfere with those 
rights of parental control.  (Perhaps I'm missing something on that list -- 
happy to learn of other such specific policies.)  Outside of such specific 
policies, parents (or other lawful guardians) presumptively control decisions 
about child well-being, unless the parents violate general norms about abuse or 
neglect.

Parents do all sorts of things that put their children's bodies at risk for 
permanent harm --  letting them play tackle football, go out in the sun all day 
without enough sunscreen, etc. Whether a particular practice of (more or less 
permanent) body-altering -- ear-piercing, nose-straightening, orthodonture -- 
is abusive depends on a social and medical judgment on the actuality of present 
harm, and in some cases the likelihood of future harm.

But two propositions control our approach to this -- 1) all parents/guardians 
have the same rights and face the same limits (religious motivation adds or 
subtracts nothing to parental rights); 2) the state has the burden of proof 
that a practice is abusive.  So, when reasonable people can and do differ about 
the social, medical, or hygienic benefits of a practice --as is obviously the 
case with infant male circumcision -- the state cannot meet its burden of 
showing the practice is abusive.  The presence or absence of religious 
motivation for the practice may explain parents' behavior, or a faith 
community's concerns, but -- when the rights of children are at stake - the 
state should be constitutionally indifferent to that motivation.  If the 
practice is abusive, the state should make its best efforts to put an end to 
it; if it cannot be shown to be abusive, everyone is free to engage in it.   
And liberty -- not religious liberty, but liberty generally -- resides in the 
initial allocation of power to parents/guardians, and the assignment of the 
burden of proof of abusiveness to the authorities.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate Howard's point, but the question is:  Why should 
some children who by definition do not share a religious belief drown - or 
otherwise be injured - for the sake of the beliefs of the adults who do have 
that belief (and even for the sake of those children who, later in life, will 
wish that they had been so baptized)?  I have great sympathy for people's 
rights to risk their own lives (in the baptism example) or alter their own 
bodies (in the circumcision example) for the sake of their religious beliefs, 
or for that matter for the sake of their secular beliefs.  But why does it 
follow that they should have the right to impose such risks on others, even 
others to whom they are genetically linked?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Friedman, Howard M.
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 8:52 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct


What has been absent from all of the discussion on this issue is the importance 
to Jewish belief of circumcision while the son is an infant. This ceremony at 
8-days of age (except where health precludes it that early) is the son's 
initiation into Jewish peoplehood. Waiting until adulthood is not the 
functional equivalent. Because the case in Germany involved a Muslim 
circumcision at a later age, the issue is muddled.  As I understand it, Islam 
has varying views on the proper age for circumcision, and even on how important 
it is. While centrality of religious belief has been a factor of declining 
importance in free exercise cases in recent years, here it perhaps should be 
revived. I think a better analogy for trying to come up with a rule is this:

Suppose there were a handful of cases in which infants drowned (or almost 
drowned) during full immersion baptism, and a court then ruled that because of 
the danger parents cannot baptize infants. They must wait until the child is an 
adult and then let him or her decide.  How would everyone come out on that case?

Howard Friedman


-Original Message-
From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thu 7/5/2012 10:57 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Parental rights and physical conduct

This raises a fascinating and practically very important 
question (because there are more than 10 times as many American parents who 
authorize circumcision for nonreligious reasons than for religious reasons):  
Do Meyer/Pierce rights extend to the right to raise one's child in the sense of 
selecting an education for the child, setting behavior rules for the child, 
choosing a place to live with the child, and so on, or do they also have the 
constitutional right (not just a common-law right) to physically alter the 
child's body, including for nonmedical reasons?  When I last checked the 
caselaw on the subject, the Supreme Court cases weren't clear on that.  Are 
there cases I'm missing on that?

To be sure, I agree that parents are generally allowed to let 
their children put themselves at risk in various ways, such as by playing 
tackle football and not wearing enough sunscreen.  But that doesn't tell us 
much about whether that's a constitutional right.  And indeed I don't think 
that laws banning child labor, for instance, have been judged as interfering 
with parental rights (imagine Prince without the religious motivation), even 
though many such laws (again, imagine Prince) are pretty clearly overbroad.  
Likewise, I would think that a ban on ear piercing, tattooing, etc. of minors, 
even when the parents order such actions, would be constitutional, though of 
course that's part of the dispute between us.

Is there dispositive caselaw I'm missing here?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 7:38 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: German circumcision decision

We are making this so much more complicated than it has to be.  I cannot speak 
to the particulars of the case in Germany, so I won't try.  But in the U.S, we 
have a longstanding tradition, initially at common law and ultimately in 
constitutional law (Pierce, Meyer, etc.) of parental control over the 
upbringing of their children.  The state can interfere with that control only 
for very good reason, and the state bears the burden of persuasion that it has 
such a reason.  Compulsory education, compulsory vaccination, and limiting 
child labor are the most obvious, specific policies that interfere with those 
rights of parental control.  (Perhaps I'm missing something on that list -- 
happy to learn of other such specific policies.)  Outside of such specific 
policies

RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The difficulty is that newborn males aren't Jewish in the sense 
of actually believing in the Jewish religion - they are, after all, newborns.  
When they are 18, they might be religious enough (or culturally identified 
enough) to appreciate being circumcised if they had been circumcised, and to 
resent not having been circumcised if they hadn't been.  Or they might be 
irreligious (or religious but non-Jewish) and appreciate not being circumcised 
if they hadn't been circumcised, and to resent having been circumcised if they 
had been.  Or of course they might be irreligious but not care much one way or 
another.

One possible answer to this is to try to estimate - how exactly 
would one do that? - which group is likely to be largest (those who would 
resent not having been circumcised or those who would resent having been 
circumcised), adjust the numbers to account for the greater difficulty of 
undoing a circumcision as an adult (very difficult, I understand, even now) vs. 
getting one as an adult (painful but less difficult), and adjust further to 
account for the relative importance of the matter to each group (if such a 
thing is possible).

Another possible answer is to say that parents are entitled to 
make the choice for their children.

A third answer is to say that it's not proper to substantially 
alter the bodies of some people without their consent (and absent medical 
need), at least if the alteration is likely to interfere in some measure with 
some valued function, even in order to advance the religious or cultural 
interests of other people.  My sense is that this latter view is the right 
view, because I agree that the important right is the right of the child, and 
the right to be free of surgery that one may later not want is more important 
than the right to have surgery that one may later want.

Eugene



Brian Landsberg writes:


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Brian Landsberg
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 11:35 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

Let me try again.  The discussion has focused on the rights of the parents and 
of the state.  The children have come into the discussion only as objects of 
control or protection by the parents or state; that is the context of the best 
interests of the child standard.  But isn't the state depriving most newborn 
Jewish males of a right when it bans circumcision of children?  Of course, the 
infant does not have capacity to exercise his right, so the law generally 
declares the parent rather than the state as a surrogate decision-maker.  At 
least at the policy level isn't that ordinarily the proper allocation of 
responsibility?

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Permissible protection of the religious individual's autonomy and identity

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Isn't the key problem precisely that the claimed religious 
liberty ... of the family here refers to the claimed religious liberty of one 
individual to alter the body of a different individual?  And I don't see why 
that is a normatively appealing liberty, given that it impinges on the 
autonomy of the child, and of the adult that the child will become.  One day, 
the infant will become a man, and that man might not accept Judaism (or Islam). 
 He might then ask of the rest of us, Why did you allow these people - my 
parents, to be sure, but still people other than me - to cut off part of my 
body, and a part that I think would have been quite valuable to me?  Just 
because they believed that God wanted this?  Well, I couldn't believe that 
then, and I don't believe it now.  Where was your concern for my autonomy then?

Eugene

Alan Brownstein writes:

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 11:21 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct


I thought we were long past the argument that the only basis for protecting 
religious liberty was that the state had a favorable perspective on the 
religious belief and practice at issue -- whether it is saving a child's soul 
through baptism or fulfilling the obligation to circumcise an 8 day old Jewish 
boy.



There are clear cases where the state can and should intervene to prevent child 
abuse or the imposition of unacceptable risks of harm on children -- whatever 
the parents motivation might be. No religious liberty exemption should be 
granted in such circumstances. Indeed, as Chip suggests, exemptions of this 
kind might well violate the Establishment Clause.



But there are many other cases where the state exercises considerable 
discretion in deciding whether it should intervene and limit parental 
authority. The constitutional interest of parents in controlling the education 
and upbringing of their children is poorly defined and reasonable people would 
disagree on its scope and application in particular cases. In those cases, if I 
understand Chip correctly (and I appologize if if I have misunderstood his 
point), the fact that that a religious obligation or practice is involved 
should be irrelevent in deciding whether the state should intervene.



If the burden of a religion specific accommodation for individuals does not 
violate the Establishment Clause, and clearly some religion specific 
accommodations that burden third parties satisfy that standard, we accept some 
such accommodations as permissible protection of the religious individuals 
autonomy and identity. Why isn't something like that analysis appropriate when 
we are discussing the autonomy and identity of religious families?



Obviously, we can disagree about whether any specific accommodation of 
religious parents and families should be provided -- but why should we insist 
that the religious liberty and identity of the family has no bearing on these 
issues?


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree that the danger to infants from full immersion baptism is very 
low and perhaps zero; the hypothetical was that it happened in a handful of 
cases, but I think that's just a hypothetical.  As to what burdens the 
government imposes to avoid a handful of deaths of infants, I think that 
varies from context to context.  My sense is that there are quite a few safety 
regulations -- though generally not total bans -- that are indeed justified by 
the desire to avoid just a handful of deaths. 

On the other hand, circumcision involves not a very low risk of death, 
but a certainty of loss of part of the body, which in turn involves an 
uncertain possible health benefit and an unknown (and likely very hard to 
quantify) possibility of loss of some sexual function.  That might well be a 
materially higher aggregate loss of utility, to borrow the economic term, than 
the loss of utility from playing football, even in Texas.  Or it might not; 
again, much depends on the facts.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
 Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 9:43 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct
 
 
 Eugene --
 
 I don't think this makes sense because it posits an impossible universe of
 zero-risk parenting. It is far riskier to drive your child on the freeway 
 (not to
 mention take him/her skiing, or letting him/her play soccer, or play football
 (esp. in Texas)) than it is to baptize him/her. All those risks are well 
 within the
 set of risks that parents take in the normal course of parenting. Indeed, for
 the state to interfere with the ability of parents to expose children to those
 risks would be a gross interference with parental rights. And I imagine that
 the danger to infants from either circumcision or full immersion baptism is 
 far
 lower than driving them around town, though I claim no actuarial expertise
 on the matter.
 
 Eric
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
 [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
 Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 12:31 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct
 
 I appreciate Howard's point, but the question is:  Why should 
 some
 children who by definition do not share a religious belief drown - or
 otherwise be injured - for the sake of the beliefs of the adults who do have
 that belief (and even for the sake of those children who, later in life, will 
 wish
 that they had been so baptized)?  I have great sympathy for people's rights
 to risk their own lives (in the baptism example) or alter their own bodies (in
 the circumcision example) for the sake of their religious beliefs, or for that
 matter for the sake of their secular beliefs.  But why does it follow that 
 they
 should have the right to impose such risks on others, even others to whom
 they are genetically linked?
 
 Eugene
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Friedman, Howard M.
 Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 8:52 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct
 
 
 What has been absent from all of the discussion on this issue is the
 importance to Jewish belief of circumcision while the son is an infant. This
 ceremony at 8-days of age (except where health precludes it that early) is
 the son's initiation into Jewish peoplehood. Waiting until adulthood is not 
 the
 functional equivalent. Because the case in Germany involved a Muslim
 circumcision at a later age, the issue is muddled.  As I understand it, Islam 
 has
 varying views on the proper age for circumcision, and even on how important
 it is. While centrality of religious belief has been a factor of declining
 importance in free exercise cases in recent years, here it perhaps should be
 revived. I think a better analogy for trying to come up with a rule is this:
 
 Suppose there were a handful of cases in which infants drowned (or almost
 drowned) during full immersion baptism, and a court then ruled that because
 of the danger parents cannot baptize infants. They must wait until the child 
 is
 an adult and then let him or her decide.  How would everyone come out on
 that case?
 
 Howard Friedman
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Thu 7/5/2012 10:57 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Parental rights and physical conduct
 
 This raises a fascinating and practically very important 
 question
 (because there are more than 10 times as many American parents who
 authorize circumcision for nonreligious reasons than

Medical reasons for action vs. religious reasons for action

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The question, I think, isn't whether there should be a crime of 
circumcision as such.  Rather, the question is whether the normal crime of 
mayhem, assault, battery, or child abuse - whatever label a particular 
jurisdiction would use for cutting off a part of an infant's body - should have 
as a defense (1) categorical parental prerogative, at least when it comes to 
circumcision (I'm the parent and I can cut off certain parts of the child's 
body for any reason I choose), (2) religious parental prerogative (I'm the 
parent and I can cut off certain parts of the child's body if I think God wants 
me to), or (3) medical parental decision (I'm the parent and I can make 
medical decisions for the child, within broad parameters, even if that includes 
cutting off certain parts of the child's body, based on my good-faith estimate 
of the costs and benefits of a procedure).

I'm inclined to think that defense 2 is improper (for some of the reasons Chip 
gives), that defense 1 is proper only for actions that are highly unlikely to 
affect future bodily function (which male circumcision might or might not 
qualify, and which ear piercing does qualify as), and defense 3 is proper for 
actions that are fairly likely to affect future bodily function.  And the 
analogy to self-defense helps explain why defense 3 is proper even though it 
treats medical reasons as better than all other reasons, including religious 
ones.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Vance R. Koven
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 11:05 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Medical reasons for action vs. religious reasons for action

I'm not sure who the we is in Eugene's hypothesis, but nobody is proposing to 
add anything to defenses, since it's the existence of the offense that is under 
discussion. Nobody contests that the crime of murder, or attempted murder, 
exists with a rather precise definition. There is as yet no crime of 
circumcision. Moreover, in looking at the two situations, it's obvious that the 
defense of self-defense (which derives from the same unalienable right to 
life to which the crime of murder speaks) contains a mental state within its 
definition, as does the crime of murder. If there were a similar mental state 
in the crime of circumcision (e.g. removing someone else's foreskin with the 
intent to do grievous bodily harm), then one might say that the normal 
circumcision would never violate the law, and if the perpetrator did have the 
requisite intent, claiming religious justification might well not suffice as a 
defense.

Of course, a legislature creating a crime of circumcision could decide to allow 
medical exemptions  but not to allow a religious one (RFRA arguments, anyone? 
Would Lukumi apply?), but I still think that would be merely a trap for the 
unwary defendant who fails to allege medical motives.
On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Here's an analogy from another area in which the normal rule - 
one person may not alter or injure another's body without permission - is 
relaxed: self-defense.

Say Vic is doing something that Don perceives as blasphemous, 
but that might also be dangerous to Don or Don's property.  (E.g., say Vic is 
burning a Koran and saying things that might reasonably lead Don - a Muslim - 
to think that Vic will imminently injure Don, or that the fire will spread to 
Don's property.)  Vic attacks Don using nondeadly force and injures him.

If Don reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure Don, 
and hit Don to prevent that, Don is not guilty of any crime, by reason of 
self-defense.  But say that the objective circumstances are the same, so that 
Don could have reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure him, but Don 
did not actually sincerely believe this.  Instead, he says that he attacked Vic 
because he thought God wanted him to attack Vic.  Then Don is guilty of 
assault; no self-defense defense is available (and I take it that we'd agree 
that no other defense should be available to him).  This rule does not treat 
religious reasons for hitting Vic worse than secular reasons generally.  But it 
does treat all reasons for hitting Vic worse than one favored secular reason - 
the perception that Vic poses an imminent danger to Don's person or property.

If I'm right on this, then I all think that there's no 
violation of the norm of equal treatment when we add another reason for 
allowing one person to alter or injure another's body: that the actor is the 
subject's parent and has a medical reason for ordering a surgery to the 
underage child.  That the parent has a right to alter the child's body for 
medical reasons doesn't mean he has a right to alter the child's body - even

Circumcision of 12-year-olds

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The quote from Boldt rather strikingly focuses on how forcing a 
12-year-old to be circumcised is bad for the 12-year-old because it could 
seriously affect the relationship between [him] and father.  Is that really 
all there is to it?  Might it not also be bad because a 12-year-old shouldn't 
be forced to lose a part of his body that he doesn't want to lose, at least 
absent some pretty significant medical reason?

More broadly, say that the issue arose not in a child custody case, but 
within an intact family.  Should the law allow parents to circumcise their 
12-year-old son against his expressed will -- as opposed to circumcising an 
infant who can't express a will?  Or should that be seen as child abuse, with 
possible criminal or civil liability for the parents or the mohel?

Eugene

Eric Rassbach writes:

 I would add to Chip's point that almost all of these cases would arise in 
 state
 court rather than federal court since they would for the most part deal with
 domestic relations issues or state law tort claims.
 
 See for example, In re Marriage of Boldt, 344 Or. 1, 176 P.3d 388 (Ore. 2008):
 
 
 Although the parties and amici have presented extensive material regarding
 circumcision, we do not need to *12 decide in this case **394 which side has
 presented a more persuasive case regarding the medical risks or benefits of
 male circumcision. We conclude that, although circumcision is an invasive
 medical procedure that results in permanent physical alteration of a body
 part and has attendant medical risks, the decision to have a male child
 circumcised for medical or religious reasons is one that is commonly and
 historically made by parents in the United States. We also conclude that the
 decision to circumcise a male child is one that generally falls within a 
 custodial
 parent's authority, unfettered by a noncustodial parent's concerns or
 beliefs-medical, religious or otherwise. Were mother's concerns or beliefs
 regarding circumcision all that were asserted in the affidavits in this case, 
 we
 would conclude that mother did not carry her initial statutory burden to
 demonstrate a sufficient change in circumstances demonstrating father's
 inability to properly care for M.
 
 However, in this case, mother has averred in her affidavit that M objects to
 the circumcision.FN8 In our view, at age 12, M's attitude regarding
 circumcision, though not conclusive of the custody issue presented here, is a
 fact necessary to the determination of whether mother has asserted a
 colorable claim of a change of circumstances sufficient to warrant a hearing
 concerning whether to change custody. That is so because forcing M at age
 12 to undergo the circumcision against his will could seriously affect the
 relationship between M and father, and could have a pronounced effect on
 father's capability to properly care for M. See Greisamer, 276 Or. at 400, 555
 P.2d 28 (illustrating proposition). Thus, if mother's assertions are verified 
 the
 trial court would be entitled to reconsider custody. As to that inquiry,
 however, we think that no decision should be made without some
 assessment of M's true state of mind. That conclusion dictates the outcome
 here.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree with Chris entirely when it comes to questions having 
to do with what to teach the child, whom to expose the child to, where to live 
with the child, and similar child-rearing questions:  There, in an intact 
family, a court may not intrude simply on the grounds that some other form of 
child-rearing - or some other set of child-rearers - would be more in the 
child's best interests, but must show parental unfitness.

But when it comes to physical injury to the child, or danger of 
physical injury, many rules restrain parents without a showing of parental 
unfitness.  I don't think that driving a child without a child safety seat is a 
mark of parental unfitness; the risk to the child is fairly low, and I don't 
think parents should lose custody of their children for this.  Yet the law may 
require parents to use child safety seats.  Likewise, having a child work 
before a certain age might not be a mark of parental unfitness, but it is 
forbidden.

Likewise, my sense is that many states, including my own 
California, outlaw the tattooing of minors (see, e.g., Cal. Penal Code sec. 
653), which interferes with parents' ability to get their children tattooed.  I 
don't think the rationale is that a parent who authorizes such a tattoo is an 
unfit parent - just that when it comes to sufficiently substantial 
alterations of a person's body, and absent a medical reason (there is a medical 
exemption to the California law, by the way), those alterations should only 
happen with that person's consent, which can only be meaningfully given if the 
person is an adult.

So I certainly don't think that the law generally mandates a 
best interests of the child standard, outside the child custody context.  But 
I also don't think that the law generally mandates an unfitness [or] child 
abuse or neglect standard, when it comes to decisions that involve physical 
injury or threat of injury (and I mean injury here to include physical 
alterations, such as tattoos).

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund
Sent: Friday, July 06, 2012 9:07 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

Yes, I'm feeling some of the same confusion as Paul.

I don't know much at all about family law.  But my understanding was that the 
best interest of the child standard was emphatically not the standard for 
judicial or legislative interference with parental decisions.  It is the 
standard for what happens to the child when custody is disputed among divorcing 
or divorced parents.   But I thought the standard for interfering with an 
intact family was much higher-a showing of unfitness, of child abuse or 
neglect.  Before this conversation, I assumed that unless circumcision 
constitutes abuse or neglect, parents have the right to do it to their 
children, with talk of best interests being irrelevant.  Another way of 
putting it is that the law presumes parents act in the best interests of the 
children, a presumption that only gets overridden in exceptional situations, a 
constitutional presumption under the Troxel line of cases.

So have I gotten this completely wrong?

Best,
Chris

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Friday, July 06, 2012 11:23 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct


This has been a very interesting discussion. I confess that at this point, I am 
quite confused about the meaning of best interests of the child. I understand 
it is a complex, context-driven, and multivalent test. But it would certainly 
help to understand the foundational values and defaults here and what interests 
are considered admissible or inadmissible. In some sense, the thinner the 
exposition of the test becomes, the more I wonder what thick assumptions 
underlie it. Take, for instance, the claim that [m]any would argue that it is 
in the best interest of the child to welcome him into a supportive, religious 
community with shared values and age-old historic traditions, and the response 
that [t]he question is what is in the interest of this child today. It's my 
own fault, I'm sure, but I'm having trouble figuring out exactly where this 
leaves us. Is it that it may be in the interest of the child today to welcome 
him into a supportive religious community but that it is not dispositive, or 
that the fact that the community is well-established and has shared values is 
not dispositive of the child's best interests? Is it that the possibility of a 
supportive religious community should never be relevant as between two possible 
custody dispositions? Is it an empirical question to be decided in each case? 
If it is potentially relevant but we 

RE: Relevance of Parham v JR To Circumcision Debate

2012-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I think that accurately captures the rule - and likely the 
right rule - with regard to decisions made for medical reasons, when the 
decisions are within the range of plausible medical decisions.  (As I've said 
all along, I think circumcision decisions may well fall in this category.)  But 
I don't think it disposes of a parent's decision made for nonmedical reasons, 
or if the decision (1) has substantial and possibly harmful permanent physical 
effects and (2) there comes to be a medical consensus that the decision is not 
medically justified.

An analogy:  Say that parents want prescription-only 
psychotropic drugs administered to their child, and they make clear that the 
reason is not a medical judgment but purely a religious one.  (The drug happens 
to be a sacrament to them, for instance.)  It seems to me that Parham doesn't 
dispose of this situation.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Friedman, Howard M.
Sent: Friday, July 06, 2012 9:35 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Relevance of Parham v JR To Circumcision Debate


I think some guidance on relative rights of parents and children to make a 
decision that could arguably either harm the child or be in the child's best 
interest are found in the Supreme Court's 1979 decision in Parham v. J.R. on 
parental commitment of a minor to a state mental hospital.  While there is 
language in Chief Justice Burger's opinion that may point more than one way in 
the circumcision example, I call your attention to these excerpts:

Simply because the decision of a parent is not agreeable to a child, or 
because it involves risks, does not automatically transfer the power to make 
that decision from the parents to some agency or officer of the state. The same 
characterizations can be made for a tonsillectomy, appendectomy, or other 
medical procedure. Most children, even in adolescence, simply are not able to 
make sound judgments concerning many decisions, including their need for 
medical care or treatment. Parents can and must make those judgments. Here, 
there is no finding by the District Court of even a single instance of bad 
faith by any parent of any member of appellees' class The fact that a child 
may balk at hospitalization or complain about a parental refusal to provide 
cosmetic surgery does not diminish the parents' authority to decide what is 
best for the child

... [W]e conclude that our precedents permit the parents to retain a 
substantial, if not the dominant, role in the decision, absent a finding of 
neglect or abuse, and that the traditional presumption that the parents act in 
the best interests of their child should apply. We also conclude, however, that 
the child's rights and the nature of the commitment decision are such that 
parents cannot always have absolute and unreviewable discretion to decide 
whether to have a child institutionalized. They, of course, retain plenary 
authority to seek such care for their children, subject to a physician's 
independent examination and medical judgment.

Howard Friedman

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: German circumcision decision

2012-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I don't think that such agnosticism is generally sound, or 
even possible.  Maybe God did command Jews to circumcise their children, or 
command Sikhs to wear turbans in a way that makes it impossible for them to 
wear motorcycle helmets, or command Rastafarians to smoke marijuana, or command 
white supremacist church members not to hire non-whites, or command Muslims to 
wage jihad; but our legal system, I think, must necessarily evaluate these 
things based on our judgments about what has impermissible secular effects, and 
I don't see how we can meaningful take into account the possibility that God 
has commanded the contrary.



But in any event, even if such agnosticism is proper when 
deciding whether to protect someone against his own decisions - a situation 
where one can reasonably conclude that we shouldn't impose our paternalistic 
cost-benefit balancing on that person, given that he might be considering 
benefits that we don't - I don't see it as proper when it comes to deciding 
whether to let A cut off a part of B's body rather than of A's own (even when A 
is B's parent).  After all, the child might well not believe in the religious 
command to circumcise when he grows up; and maybe he's right.  Or maybe he'll 
come to believe that God doesn't want people to alter their bodies without 
strong reason (perhaps an analogy to the Jewish prohibition on tattooing, see 
http://www.myjewishlearning.com/practices/Ethics/Our_Bodies/Adorning_the_Body/Tattoos.shtml,
 though applied to circumcision instead).



So if we choose not to decide, we still have made a choice, 
as some philosopher or other said - we have chosen to let someone, for 
religious reasons, alter the body of another person who by definition does not 
believe in that religion, and who might or might not grow up to believe in that 
religion.  However we resolve that question, I don't think this sort of 
agnosticism has any helpful role to play here.



Eugene



Eric Rassbach writes:



 I think the problem with your non-medical reasons paragraph below is that it

 misstates the proper attitude of the state towards religious freedom and

 religious reasons given by parents. The state is supposed to be neutral on

 claims of religious obligation, not merely tolerant of them. And true

 neutrality (or agnosticism, if you will) means that the state doesn't just say

 Let the Jews do what they want as long as they aren't hurting anybody. It

 means saying, Maybe the Jews are right -- that is, maybe God really did

 command them to do what they are doing. The state and its judges are of

 course incompetent to *decide* such questions. But the proper response to

 such incompetence is not to disregard the religious claim entirely but to back

 off from deciding it as much as possible, precisely because the state cannot

 exclude the possibility of its truth. Otherwise the state is deciding a 
 religious

 truth claim by resort to its own incompetence. Thus on a question where the

 medical interests are in equipoise, the tie has to go to the religious liberty

 interest, not to inactivity. That to me seems to be the case with respect to

 circumcision (though in my non-expert opinion the medical interests do not

 seem to be in equipoise).



 I understand that this runs counter to a mere tolerance understanding of

 where religious freedom rights come from, especially one heavily inflected

 by freedom of speech doctrine (cf. our sincerity discussion on this list a

 couple of years ago). But I don't think our system has adopted the mere

 tolerance philosophy, and in fact adopted an entirely different philosophy of

 rights during the Founding era. For evidence one need look only as far as the

 Declaration of Independence.



 Eric







 

 From: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene

 [vol...@law.ucla.edu]

 Sent: Wednesday, July 04, 2012 4:24 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: RE: German circumcision decision



 Sorry for the delay responding - I was traveling Monday and 
 Tuesday

 - but I'm not sure I grasp the argument in the first paragraph.  My view is

 generally this:



 (1)  People should generally have the power to make medical

 decisions for themselves.

 (2)  Infants and children can't make such decisions.

 (3)  Yet some such medical decisions must be made quickly, 
 before

 the child becomes mature enough to decide.

 (4)  We therefore delegate this power to make medical 
 decisions to

 the parents.



 But this argument hinges on there being medical reasons for 
 the

 decision - I don't see any reason for parents to have this power when they

 exercise it for nonmedical reasons.  We may

RE: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
And that “non-Jewish standard of ‘Jewishness’” – that newborn 
males aren’t Jewish – is, I think, precisely the standard that our government 
must adopt.  Our law cannot (with some excepts related to political 
distinctions, such as membership in an Indian tribe) accept a notion of rights 
or protections that turns on the ethnicity of a child’s forebears.

To be sure, to religious Jews an 8-day-old baby is Jewish, and bound by God’s 
law.  But the government must, I think, accept that child as someone who has no 
religious beliefs of his own, and who may one day become a Christian, an 
atheist, a religious Jew, or anything else.  Whatever rationale courts or 
legislatures may use in reaching whatever result they reach on the circumcision 
question, I think they cannot rely on the notion that somehow circumcising the 
baby protects the baby’s own religious interests as a Jew.  (That is a separate 
question as to whether they can rely on arguments about what the child is 
empirically likely to prefer when he becomes an adult.)

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of wlind...@verizon.net
Sent: Friday, July 06, 2012 11:02 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct


 But that is invoking a non-Jewish standard of Jewishness (and I speak as 
someone intensely exasperated by refusal to acknowledge any distinction between 
ethnic and religious Jewishness.*) Someone can say I spit on G_d, I spit 
on Torah, I spit on halakhah.; He can spend Sabbath behind a desk, and never 
have seen the inside of a synagogue. No one will say You aren't Jewish'. All 
that matters is who his mother was. And yes,  I am acutely aware of the 
cognitive dissonance in play when as soon as someone says I believe in Jesus, 
it suddenly ceases to matter who his mother  was (and the israeli courts will 
say so officially in applying the Law of Return.)

   (* not to mention the frustration of being Jewish enough for any real 
anti-Semites, but not for the Jews.)

On 07/05/12, Volokh, Eugenevol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu 
wrote:

The difficulty is that newborn males aren’t Jewish in the sense 
of actually believing in the Jewish religion – they are, after all, newborns.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

2012-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
From what I understand, think the health arguments for 
circumcision are substantial, and, as I've noted before, to the extent that 
parents are making a medical choice in favor of circumcision, I think it makes 
sense to defer to their judgment, just as it does for other medical choices.  
Likewise, I'm inclined to say that if there was reason to think (though also 
reason to doubt) that circumcision would enhance sexual function, parents could 
also reasonable choose that as a medical matter.



The interesting question, I think, is how we should resolve the 
matter if (1) the medical consensus comes to be that there was no medical 
benefit of circumcision and no sexual function benefits, but (2) there comes to 
be no consensus on whether there is a sexual function cost.  My inclination 
would be to say that the uncertainty should not be resolved in favor of 
parental choice, but rather resolved in favor of patient choice: the principle 
that - absent medical need - practically irreversible and potentially harmful 
surgery should not be undertaken without the actual consent of the adult 
subject of the surgery.



Eugene



Eric Rassbach writes:



 I am not sure that you can even rely on a claim that the sexual function was

 necessarily reduced; I know that some proponents of circumcision claim that

 circumcision actually enhances sexual function. Would you agree that if the

 evidence on that point is ambiguous or equivocal, then circumcision falls

 within the realm of things that parents can decide? That is reinforced by the

 fact that there are health reasons offered for circumcision; if those 
 rationales

 are true (or perhaps just plausible?) then it is less like having an ear cut 
 off

 and more like having an unsightly mole excised or an extra toe removed,

 both of which are easier at a younger age.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
As I mentioned, I think that statutory law on this is quite a 
mix.  The best way to characterize it, I think, is that
(1) there's a broad consensus that, for overdetermined reasons (practical to 
some, moral to others), most decisions about children are left to parents,
(2) there's a broad consensus that, when a medical decision is to be made, a 
minor patient's parents generally make it, within the range of what is seen by 
the medical profession as reasonable,
(3) constitutional precedents hold that parents have broad authority over 
educational decisions and similar childrearing decisions that likely don't have 
a physical effect on the child, but
(4) legislatures step in, in a wide range of cases, to restrict parents when 
there's a risk of physical injury, whether the issue is corporal punishment, 
safety belts, tattoos, permission to have sex, or a wide range of other things.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 8:07 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Parental rights and physical conduct

I don't know why we should be limited to the particulars of Supreme Court 
decisions when we think about this.  I suggest that the approach I outlined is 
deeply embedded in the statutory and judge-made law of all the states.  And, if 
I'm right about, then the relevant constitutional doctrines of substantive due 
process liberty would indeed give great weight to that long-standing and 
wide-spread legal tradition (Troxel v. Granville).
On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 10:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
This raises a fascinating and practically very important 
question (because there are more than 10 times as many American parents who 
authorize circumcision for nonreligious reasons than for religious reasons):  
Do Meyer/Pierce rights extend to the right to raise one's child in the sense of 
selecting an education for the child, setting behavior rules for the child, 
choosing a place to live with the child, and so on, or do they also have the 
constitutional right (not just a common-law right) to physically alter the 
child's body, including for nonmedical reasons?  When I last checked the 
caselaw on the subject, the Supreme Court cases weren't clear on that.  Are 
there cases I'm missing on that?

To be sure, I agree that parents are generally allowed to let 
their children put themselves at risk in various ways, such as by playing 
tackle football and not wearing enough sunscreen.  But that doesn't tell us 
much about whether that's a constitutional right.  And indeed I don't think 
that laws banning child labor, for instance, have been judged as interfering 
with parental rights (imagine Prince without the religious motivation), even 
though many such laws (again, imagine Prince) are pretty clearly overbroad.  
Likewise, I would think that a ban on ear piercing, tattooing, etc. of minors, 
even when the parents order such actions, would be constitutional, though of 
course that's part of the dispute between us.

Is there dispositive caselaw I'm missing here?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 7:38 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: German circumcision decision

We are making this so much more complicated than it has to be.  I cannot speak 
to the particulars of the case in Germany, so I won't try.  But in the U.S, we 
have a longstanding tradition, initially at common law and ultimately in 
constitutional law (Pierce, Meyer, etc.) of parental control over the 
upbringing of their children.  The state can interfere with that control only 
for very good reason, and the state bears the burden of persuasion that it has 
such a reason.  Compulsory education, compulsory vaccination, and limiting 
child labor are the most obvious, specific policies that interfere with those 
rights of parental control.  (Perhaps I'm missing something on that list -- 
happy to learn of other such specific policies.)  Outside of such specific 
policies, parents (or other lawful guardians) presumptively control decisions 
about child well-being, unless the parents violate general norms about abuse or 
neglect.

Parents do all sorts of things that put their children's bodies at risk for 
permanent harm --  letting them play tackle football, go out in the sun all day 
without enough sunscreen, etc. Whether a particular practice of (more or less 
permanent) body-altering -- ear-piercing, nose-straightening, orthodonture -- 
is abusive depends on a social and medical judgment on the actuality of present 
harm, and in some cases the likelihood of future harm.

But two propositions

RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

2012-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciated Marty's arguments in favor of considering how 
most circumcised adults view their parents' decision to circumcise them as 
babies, and perhaps there is something to them.  I have two reservations, 
though, about this (albeit ones that I might be persuaded out of).

First, while adult circumcision is much more painful than child circumcision 
(or at least the pain is more likely to be remembered), my sense is that it's 
still much easier to circumcise than to undo a circumcision (if undoing a 
circumcision, in the sense of replacing the tissue with comparably sensitive 
tissue, is possible).  If that's so, then the sizes of the groups - those who 
wish they hadn't been circumcised, those who are happy they were circumcised, 
those who wish they had been circumcised, and those who are happy they weren't 
circumcised - would need to be adjusted accordingly (though I don't know 
exactly how).

Second, and more fundamentally, I think there is a general moral principle that 
people usually have a right not to have their bodies altered without their 
permission, at least in a way that involves some substantial risk of 
substantial loss of function (thus setting aside the ear piercing example).  I 
think that principle can be trumped by parents' reasonable medical judgments, 
on the theory that someone has to make these medical choices, and the parents 
are the best people to make them.  But I don't think that principle can be 
trumped by parents' personal religious preferences, which might not match the 
religious preferences of the adult into whom the child grows.  (On that, I 
think Marty and I may agree.)  And, tentatively, I don't think that principle 
can be trumped by a desire to make life easier for other adults into whom other 
children will grow.  If John Doe asks, Why did the law let my parents cut off 
part of my body?, I don't think the answer that We thought most people whose 
parents ordered this would be happier with it removed, for religious reasons 
suffices, because that's not a sufficient reason to justify such surgery in the 
absence of the patient's own mature consent.  Does that make sense?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Friday, July 06, 2012 3:26 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

Eugene:  Without regard to what adult subjects generally think of the 
procedure having been done (or not done) to them?  Shouldn't we defer to 
parents at least until such time as there are many adults who are outraged that 
the state didn't step in?
On Fri, Jul 6, 2012 at 6:19 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

From what I understand, think the health arguments for 
circumcision are substantial, and, as I've noted before, to the extent that 
parents are making a medical choice in favor of circumcision, I think it makes 
sense to defer to their judgment, just as it does for other medical choices.  
Likewise, I'm inclined to say that if there was reason to think (though also 
reason to doubt) that circumcision would enhance sexual function, parents could 
also reasonable choose that as a medical matter.



The interesting question, I think, is how we should resolve the 
matter if (1) the medical consensus comes to be that there was no medical 
benefit of circumcision and no sexual function benefits, but (2) there comes to 
be no consensus on whether there is a sexual function cost.  My inclination 
would be to say that the uncertainty should not be resolved in favor of 
parental choice, but rather resolved in favor of patient choice: the principle 
that - absent medical need - practically irreversible and potentially harmful 
surgery should not be undertaken without the actual consent of the adult 
subject of the surgery.



Eugene



Eric Rassbach writes:



 I am not sure that you can even rely on a claim that the sexual function was

 necessarily reduced; I know that some proponents of circumcision claim that

 circumcision actually enhances sexual function. Would you agree that if the

 evidence on that point is ambiguous or equivocal, then circumcision falls

 within the realm of things that parents can decide? That is reinforced by the

 fact that there are health reasons offered for circumcision; if those 
 rationales

 are true (or perhaps just plausible?) then it is less like having an ear cut 
 off

 and more like having an unsightly mole excised or an extra toe removed,

 both of which are easier at a younger age.

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list

RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

2012-07-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Part of the reason, I think, is that irreversible decisions 
should, when possible, be left to the adult that the child will become; and 
while lack of circumcision is painful to reverse in adulthood, it's possible, 
while circumcision is at the very least much harder to reverse effectively.

Consider a few analogies.  It's not unreasonable for adults to 
tattoo themselves; it's not my choice, but a substantial minority of people do 
it.  Yet I think California law is right to bar all tattooing of minors, 
regardless of parental authorization - and it was even more correct when 
tattoos were very hard to reverse.  It's true that this is a decision by the 
state, but it's a decision that increases the decisionmaking authority of the 
adult that the child will become.

At the other extreme, it's not unreasonable for adults to get 
vasectomies or have their fallopian tubes tied - it's much rarer, especially in 
people who have no children at all, but it does happen.  Indeed, it may have 
some benefits, because it decreases the risk of pregnancy; and it can even 
provide some benefit to a teenage minor.  Plus if a child has especially 
serious genetic conditions, deciding on such a surgery may be especially 
plausible.  But I take it that parents would generally not be allowed to order 
such a surgery on their children (setting aside exceptional circumstances, such 
as when a child is mentally retarded, sexually active, and likely to get 
pregnant without such surgery), again because that is a decision that should be 
made by the adult that the child will become.

The same argument, I think, could be made about circumcision, 
depending on the evidence about medical costs and benefits (the case for 
allowing parents to decide becomes stronger when there are serious medical 
benefits) and on the evidence about whether circumcision indeed causes 
sufficient loss of sexual sensation.

Eugene

Brian Landsberg writes:

In the case of a newborn the possible decision makers are the parents and the 
state. Why should we trust the state's judgment more than the parents' on an 
issue as to which reasonable minds can differ?

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

2012-07-07 Thread Volokh, Eugene
(1)  I'm not sure why A's interest in B's religion should give 
A the right to alter B's body - even if A is B's parent.

(2)  As to the sons' own interest in conforming to their 
religion, I don't think it's their religion at age 8 days, at least under 
what should be the secular legal system's understanding of religion (the 
subject's own belief system).

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Brian Landsberg
Sent: Saturday, July 07, 2012 9:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

Why consider only medical costs and benefits and ignore the parents' interest 
in the religious upbringing of their sons and the sons' own interest in 
conforming to their religion?

As to harms, shouldn't the burden be on the proponent of banning the procedure?

Sent from my iPhone

On Jul 7, 2012, at 3:40 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Part of the reason, I think, is that irreversible decisions 
should, when possible, be left to the adult that the child will become; and 
while lack of circumcision is painful to reverse in adulthood, it's possible, 
while circumcision is at the very least much harder to reverse effectively.

Consider a few analogies.  It's not unreasonable for adults to 
tattoo themselves; it's not my choice, but a substantial minority of people do 
it.  Yet I think California law is right to bar all tattooing of minors, 
regardless of parental authorization - and it was even more correct when 
tattoos were very hard to reverse.  It's true that this is a decision by the 
state, but it's a decision that increases the decisionmaking authority of the 
adult that the child will become.

At the other extreme, it's not unreasonable for adults to get 
vasectomies or have their fallopian tubes tied - it's much rarer, especially in 
people who have no children at all, but it does happen.  Indeed, it may have 
some benefits, because it decreases the risk of pregnancy; and it can even 
provide some benefit to a teenage minor.  Plus if a child has especially 
serious genetic conditions, deciding on such a surgery may be especially 
plausible.  But I take it that parents would generally not be allowed to order 
such a surgery on their children (setting aside exceptional circumstances, such 
as when a child is mentally retarded, sexually active, and likely to get 
pregnant without such surgery), again because that is a decision that should be 
made by the adult that the child will become.

The same argument, I think, could be made about circumcision, 
depending on the evidence about medical costs and benefits (the case for 
allowing parents to decide becomes stronger when there are serious medical 
benefits) and on the evidence about whether circumcision indeed causes 
sufficient loss of sexual sensation.

Eugene

Brian Landsberg writes:

In the case of a newborn the possible decision makers are the parents and the 
state. Why should we trust the state's judgment more than the parents' on an 
issue as to which reasonable minds can differ?


___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

2012-07-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I should think that the law's treating people interests 
differently based on the ethnicity of their mothers would raise insuperable 
Equal Protection Clause problems, as an unconstitutional discrimination based 
on ethnicity.  It may well be that private religious organizations should be 
free to engage in such discrimination; but I don't think that the government 
can.  So to the extent that the legal considers people's interest in 
conforming to their religion, it has to base that on the people's actual 
religious beliefs, and not to religious identity imputed to them by others as a 
result of the people's ethnic background.

An interesting analogy here, I think, is the special treatment 
of children of American Indian tribe members in adoption cases, and the 
recognition of tribal interests with regard to those children even when the 
children are too young to themselves have any felt tribal identity.  But to the 
extent that is permissible, I think that this is only because of the special 
treatment of Indian-related classifications as being political - given the 
tribes' political identities - rather than racial or ethnic.  See Morton v. 
Mancari.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Friedman, Howard M.
Sent: Sunday, July 08, 2012 10:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose


It seems to me that your paragraph (2) focuses the issue.  Should the Free 
Exercise clause understand religion only as a belief system?  Traditional 
Judaism does not define it that way. Instead (for those who are born of a 
Jewish mother) it is an identity that precedes a belief system. Can the 1st 
Amendment be seen as protecting a concept of religion that is different from 
the Christian notion that belief (acceptance of Jesus) defines religion? It was 
the insistence on seeing religion as only a belief system that led to the 
controversial decision by the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom in 2009 that 
ruled Jewish schools using the Orthodox Jewish definition of who is a Jew 
were engaged in ethnic origin discrimination (which British law equates with 
racial discrimination).

Howard Friedman


-Original Message-
From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Sun 7/8/2012 12:29 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

(1)  I'm not sure why A's interest in B's religion should give 
A the right to alter B's body - even if A is B's parent.

(2)  As to the sons' own interest in conforming to their 
religion, I don't think it's their religion at age 8 days, at least under 
what should be the secular legal system's understanding of religion (the 
subject's own belief system).

Eugene

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

What religion is an 8-day-old?

2012-07-09 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The theoretical principle behind my claim that, As to 'the 
sons' own interest in conforming to their religion,' I don't think it's 'their 
religion' at age 8 days, at least under what should be the secular legal 
system's understanding of religion (the subject's own belief system), is 
simply that, under the First Amendment and under equal protection principles, 
any special treatment of people based on their religion must stem from their 
religious beliefs - their own understanding of God's commands - and not because 
of their bloodlines.

First, the justifications for religious freedom have generally stemmed from the 
burden that is imposed on people when they are ordered by secular law to do 
something and feel ordered by their religious beliefs to do the opposite.  And 
it is the individual's beliefs that are important, not to the beliefs of the 
group to which society says he belongs.  See, e.g., Thomas v.  Review Bd.  
Second, claims that we should treat some people's interests differently because 
of the ethnic group to which their mothers belonged conflicts with 
well-established equal protection principles, under which our secular rights 
and interests are not supposed to be affected by our ethnicity.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Monday, July 09, 2012 5:35 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

I am also curious about roughly the same point Howard raises. I always value 
the doctrine- and act-specific discussions I get on this list--I learn a great 
deal from them, and the theory I can more or less do on my own. But these 
discussions often seem to me to be just one step away from fairly major and 
consequential statements or assumptions about the underlying theory. So what is 
driving Eugene's paragaph (2), or some of the other statements (not just from 
Eugene) that have taken place in the course of this valuable discussion? Is it 
a moral intuition? A belief, as the paragraph below indicates, both that we 
have a secular legal system and about what that entails? A belief about the 
Constitution itself and what it requires? A belief in a wholly individualist 
and voluntarist conception of the self as a legal subject? A kind of 
implication that the Constitution enacts Mill's On Liberty or Joel Feinberg's 
work and not, say, Charles Taylor's work? A thin or thick conception of what 
harm means? A belief about the relevance or irrelevance of history, 
tradition, community, the sources of or proper occasions for thick commitments?

I appreciate that these are large questions. And in many particular fact-based 
cases what I loosely call my common-sense intuitions *might* comport with 
Eugene's views. But it seems to me, as I wrote earlier, that there are some 
fairly large theoretical commitments guiding those intuitions here and that 
they are reasonably subject to questioning.

Paul Horwitz
University of Alabama School of Law

Subject: RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose
Date: Sun, 8 Jul 2012 13:08:57 -0400
From: howard.fried...@utoledo.edumailto:howard.fried...@utoledo.edu
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

It seems to me that your paragraph (2) focuses the issue.  Should the Free 
Exercise clause understand religion only as a belief system?  Traditional 
Judaism does not define it that way. Instead (for those who are born of a 
Jewish mother) it is an identity that precedes a belief system. Can the 1st 
Amendment be seen as protecting a concept of religion that is different from 
the Christian notion that belief (acceptance of Jesus) defines religion? It was 
the insistence on seeing religion as only a belief system that led to the 
controversial decision by the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom in 2009 that 
ruled Jewish schools using the Orthodox Jewish definition of who is a Jew 
were engaged in ethnic origin discrimination (which British law equates with 
racial discrimination).

Howard Friedman


-Original Message-
From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Sun 7/8/2012 12:29 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Equivocal evidence, and the right to choose

(1)  I'm not sure why A's interest in B's religion should give 
A the right to alter B's body - even if A is B's parent.

(2)  As to the sons' own interest in conforming to their 
religion, I don't think it's their religion at age 8 days, at least under 
what should be the secular legal system's understanding of religion (the 
subject's own belief system).

Eugene


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get

RE: What religion is an 8-day-old?

2012-07-09 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate the force of this argument in many situations.  
But, as I argued before, it’s not clear to me that this approach should be 
followed when a parent’s choice to order surgery performed on the child will 
essentially be irrevocable for the child – I mentioned the hypotheticals about 
a parent’s tattooing the child (illegal in California and other states, I 
think), especially in a time before tattoos could easily be removed, or for 
that matter about a parent’s ordering that the child be sterilized.  Perhaps 
one can argue that such decisions are clearly against the child’s best 
interest, but I’m not sure; the better argument, I think, that such permanent 
decisions are decisions that children should make when they are old enough to 
think through the matter for themselves.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Brian Landsberg
Sent: Monday, July 09, 2012 8:38 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: What religion is an 8-day-old?

There is much we do not know about what the 8 day old boy will want or believe 
at age 18 or 50?  Yet decisions must be made for the child. Normally we trust 
the parent to act in the child's best interest. We turn the job over to the 
state only when there is clear evidence that the parents are not acting in the 
child's best interest. The evidence here seems in conflict.

Sent from my iPhone

On Jul 9, 2012, at 7:13 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
The theoretical principle behind my claim that, “As to ‘the 
sons' own interest in conforming to their religion,’ I don't think it's ‘their 
religion’ at age 8 days, at least under what should be the secular legal 
system's understanding of religion (the subject's own belief system),” is 
simply that, under the First Amendment and under equal protection principles, 
any special treatment of people based on their religion must stem from their 
religious beliefs – their own understanding of God’s commands – and not because 
of their bloodlines.

First, the justifications for religious freedom have generally stemmed from the 
burden that is imposed on people when they are ordered by secular law to do 
something and feel ordered by their religious beliefs to do the opposite.  And 
it is the individual’s beliefs that are important, not to the beliefs of the 
group to which society says he “belongs.”  See, e.g., Thomas v.  Review Bd.  
Second, claims that we should treat some people’s interests differently because 
of the ethnic group to which their mothers belonged conflicts with 
well-established equal protection principles, under which our secular rights 
and interests are not supposed to be affected by our ethnicity.

Eugene

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Circumcision

2012-07-11 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I would think that a distinction between physical alteration of 
a child's body and other actions would indeed be a sensible one (though not 
always a dispositive one), and one that is consistent with our general view 
that physical alteration of another's body is an especially serious intrusion 
on that person.  But let me ask Perry what he thinks of these hypotheticals:



(1)  California law, as best I can tell, categorically bans all 
tattooing of under-18-year-olds.  Let's go back to a time when tattoos were 
essentially permanent.  Would parents nonetheless have a constitutional right 
-- just as the exercise of their parental rights -- to tattoo a child, 
especially one too young to have a view on the subject?  Or could the state say 
that this is a decision that should be left to the person whose body this 
actually is, at a time when the person can make the decision?



(2)  Say that parents decide to sterilize their child, perhaps 
because they believe that either God or Gaea doesn't want more children to be 
born on the planet, or perhaps because they have some genetic condition that 
they do not want the child to risk spreading.  (Set aside the special case when 
the child is mentally retarded, unable or unwilling to use contraceptives, and 
unlikely to ever be able to make an informed decision about sterilization.)  Do 
parents have a constitutional right to do this, or should this be left for the 
child to decide when he or she becomes an adult?  I take it that whatever one 
might say of sterilization, one wouldn't say that it is necessarily an 
unquestionably grave harm, physical or psychological; quite a few sane adults 
choose to be sterilized.  Of course it may be an unquestionably grave harm when 
done without the subject's informed consent; but why wouldn't removal of a 
functioning and an apparently quite sexually sensitive part of the body 
likewise be seen as a sufficiently grave harm?  (Or is the point simply that it 
is questionabl[e] whether the removal really does affect sexual sensitivity?)



(3)  Say that parents have a doctor perform an artificial 
insemination of their 14-year-old daughter, with the daughter's agreement; 
assume the daughter is sufficiently sexually mature that the pregnancy poses no 
medical risk.  (There's also no sex involved, so it isn't a statutory rape 
question.)  Perhaps one of the parents is dying and wants the experience of 
being a grandparent as quickly as possible, or perhaps they take be fruitful 
and multiply to mean as soon as possible.  I take it having a baby, even at 
14, is not as such an unquestionably grave harm, physical or psychological; 
and I don't think the problem here is really that pregnancy is not 
developmentally appropriate as such.  Rather, it seems to me that it's 
reasonable for the state to say that the decision about whether and when (and 
with what sperm) to become a parent is a decision that should optimally be made 
by an adult, or at least by someone older than 14.  (While of course the 
14-year-old could get pregnant the old-fashioned way, assume the law also 
prohibits that, by making it statutory rape on the man's part, and by making 
any adults who facilitate or encourage such an action accessories to statutory 
rape.)



Eugene



 -Original Message-

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Perry Dane

 Sent: Wednesday, July 11, 2012 1:42 PM

 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 Subject: Circumcision



 Hi,



 Just a couple of general thoughts:



 1. Most everyone, including Eugene, admits that parents are empowered

 within broad limits to make all sorts of major decisions, inlcuding decisions

 with likely irreversible consequences, on behalf of their minor children.

 These include decisions about education, religious training (or lack of it), 
 form

 of community (e.g., living in a small rural town vs. living in Manhattan), 
 forms

 of cultural exposure or immersion, and etc., etc., etc.



 I therefore don't see why we should take seriously a bright line between

 physical interventions such as circumcision and all these other myriad ways

 that parents (often irreverisbily) influence their children's lives.  Indeed,

 even with respect to the narrow question of sexual gratification, circumcision

 is probably very low (even if it appears at all) on the list of deeply

 consequential parental interventions, conscious and unconscious.



 2. It also bears emphasis that most everyone, including the non-libertarians

 among us, admit that adult men should have the right to have themselves

 circumcised.  That is not merely because the adult has the capacity to

 consent.  There are all sorts of things that even consenting adults don't

 have the right to do.  Rather, it is because society doesn't understand

 circumcision -- and in particular circumcision for 

Corporate donations to religious groups

2012-08-16 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Folks:  I'm trying to make an argument using religious contributions as an 
analogy, and wanted to make sure I'm not missing something in the thing I'm 
analogizing to.



I wanted to say something about the protecting shareholders rationale for 
limiting corporate campaign-related speech, and consider an analogy to 
corporate contributions to religious organizations (whether those contributions 
would go entirely to religious uses, or would also partly promote the 
charitable function of the organization).  As I understand the protecting 
shareholders argument, it goes something like this:  Many people don't want to 
have their money used to support or oppose candidates or ballot measures, even 
when the use is indirect (i.e., when they have rights under a retirement fund, 
the retirement fund buys stock in a corporation, and then the corporation 
spends the money, based on its managers' judgment that spending the money would 
be good for business).  Moreover, it's not so easy for people to avoid this, 
since many people can't meaningfully control where their retirement money is 
being invested.  Therefore, there's a sufficiently compelling interest in 
preventing this imposition on such involuntary shareholders by banning 
corporations from spending money to support or oppose candidates or ballot 
measures.



My questions:  (1)  Has anyone similarly argued that states should bar 
corporate donations to religious organizations, on the theory that this 
protects shareholders from having their money used to support religious 
beliefs they disagree with?  (2)  Would such a prohibition be constitutionally 
permissible, or would it violate the Lukumi Babalu / McDaniel 
no-discrimination-against-religion principle?



My inclination is to say that it wouldn't be proper, and would likely even be 
unconstitutional, to bar such corporate donations, and that protecting 
shareholders isn't a sufficient reason for such a bar - and it likewise 
wouldn't be as to a bar on corporate expenditures on campaign-related speech.  
But I wanted to make sure that I hadn't missed some arguments, or some 
situations in which some such bar has indeed been imposed.



I'm not talking here about the perennial question of whether public money can 
be given to various religious organizations; I'm speaking of hypothetical laws 
that would bar corporate funds from being given to such organizations.  (Note 
also that I'm not talking about evenhanded application of the business judgment 
rule to foreclose contributions that can't reasonably be seen as furthering the 
corporate interest; assume the prohibition also extends to contributions that 
do further the corporate interest, for instance because they build goodwill.)



Thanks in advance for any feedback people might have,



Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: New circumcision policy statement from the AAP

2012-08-24 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I don't think it changes my analysis, since I've all along 
acknowledged that there are plausible medical arguments in favor of 
circumcision.  I'm hesitant to treat the AAP statement as materially changing 
that, since I take it that there's some disagreement among pediatric groups - 
especially internationally -- even now.  (The statement does make it even more 
unlikely that any U.S. jurisdiction would ban infant circumcision - and likely 
makes it morally and practically unjustifiable for the jurisdiction to make 
that decision - but any such ban was unlikely even before this statement.)



Given this situation, what is the right result?  As I mentioned in my July 4 
message, http://lists.ucla.edu/pipermail/religionlaw/2012-July/026058.html, my 
view is generally this:



(1)  People should generally have the power to make medical decisions for 
themselves.

(2)  Infants and children can't make such decisions.

(3)  Yet some such medical decisions must be made quickly, before the child 
becomes mature enough to decide.

(4)  We therefore delegate this power to make medical decisions to the parents. 
 (Indeed, Parham v. J.R. states, whether or not correctly, that this is a 
constitutional mandate.)



Circumcision was a reasonable medical decision before the AAP 
statement - precisely because the matter was uncertain - and it is a reasonable 
medical decision now; I think parents who make such a medical decision should 
indeed be free to do that.  The interesting question is what happens if the 
medical evidence eventually ends up being contrary, or if the parents make a 
decision for nonmedical reasons.



I will say that focusing on the views of pediatricians here is 
good, because it focuses on what I think is the right question: what is in the 
best interest of the child whose body is being pretty much irreversibly 
altered, and not what the parents prefer or on what is in the interest of 
religious communities.



Eugene





 -Original Message-

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach

 Sent: Friday, August 24, 2012 4:26 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: New circumcision policy statement from the AAP





 http://www.tabletmag.com/scroll/110165/leading-pediatric-group-endorses-http://www.tabletmag.com/scroll/110165/leading-pediatric-group-endorses-circumcision

 circumcisionhttp://www.tabletmag.com/scroll/110165/leading-pediatric-group-endorses-circumcision





 Eugene --



 Would this change your legal analysis with respect to this issue?



 Eric



 ___

 To post, send message to 
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, 
 unsubscribe,

 change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlawhttp://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the

 messages to others.




___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: New circumcision policy statement from the AAP

2012-08-24 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The question is why, in the first place, people should have 
rights to control not only their own bodies, but also other people's (their 
children's) bodies.  I think there are good prudential answers to this question 
- as someone put it, no government official will love my children like I will, 
and no government official will know them like I will, and that's true for the 
great bulk of parents.  But it is prudential factors such as this, and not some 
preexisting inherent moral right, that is doing the work here, it seems to me.  
And such questions must indeed be considered by us as a political community, in 
deciding  to what extent we should protect some of our fellow citizens 
(children) against other fellow citizens (their parents).

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Walsh, Kevin
Sent: Friday, August 24, 2012 5:35 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: New circumcision policy statement from the AAP

With appreciation to Eric and especially to Eugene for pushing us to think 
carefully about the right legal rule regarding circumcision, I wonder if 
focusing on even more fundamental considerations can clarify even more.

As I see it, we do not delegate the authority to parents to make decisions 
of this sort. Rather, we recognize as a political community that there is no 
general warrant for interfering with the decisions that parents make for their 
children regarding circumcision.

Even if the outcomes will be the same whether one views the issue through the 
first framing or the second, the two seem worth distinguishing.

On Aug 24, 2012, at 7:56 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

I don't think it changes my analysis, since I've all along 
acknowledged that there are plausible medical arguments in favor of 
circumcision.  I'm hesitant to treat the AAP statement as materially changing 
that, since I take it that there's some disagreement among pediatric groups - 
especially internationally -- even now.  (The statement does make it even more 
unlikely that any U.S. jurisdiction would ban infant circumcision - and likely 
makes it morally and practically unjustifiable for the jurisdiction to make 
that decision - but any such ban was unlikely even before this statement.)



Given this situation, what is the right result?  As I mentioned in my July 4 
message, http://lists.ucla.edu/pipermail/religionlaw/2012-July/026058.html, my 
view is generally this:



(1)  People should generally have the power to make medical decisions for 
themselves.

(2)  Infants and children can't make such decisions.

(3)  Yet some such medical decisions must be made quickly, before the child 
becomes mature enough to decide.

(4)  We therefore delegate this power to make medical decisions to the parents. 
 (Indeed, Parham v. J.R. states, whether or not correctly, that this is a 
constitutional mandate.)



Circumcision was a reasonable medical decision before the AAP 
statement - precisely because the matter was uncertain - and it is a reasonable 
medical decision now; I think parents who make such a medical decision should 
indeed be free to do that.  The interesting question is what happens if the 
medical evidence eventually ends up being contrary, or if the parents make a 
decision for nonmedical reasons.



I will say that focusing on the views of pediatricians here is 
good, because it focuses on what I think is the right question: what is in the 
best interest of the child whose body is being pretty much irreversibly 
altered, and not what the parents prefer or on what is in the interest of 
religious communities.



Eugene





 -Original Message-

 From: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-

 boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric 
 Rassbach

 Sent: Friday, August 24, 2012 4:26 PM

 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 Subject: New circumcision policy statement from the AAP





 http://www.tabletmag.com/scroll/110165/leading-pediatric-group-endorses-http://www.tabletmag.com/scroll/110165/leading-pediatric-group-endorses-circumcision

 circumcisionhttp://www.tabletmag.com/scroll/110165/leading-pediatric-group-endorses-circumcision





 Eugene --



 Would this change your legal analysis with respect to this issue?



 Eric



 ___

 To post, send message to 
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, 
 unsubscribe,

 change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlawhttp://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot

RE: New circumcision policy statement from the AAP

2012-09-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Sorry for the delay responding -- I was working on a cert petition all 
week, and just handed it off to my cite-checker.

As list readers might recall, my position was not that circumcision 
restriction would be justified.  Rather, I wrote, From what I understand, 
think the health arguments for circumcision are substantial, and, as I've noted 
before, to the extent that parents are making a medical choice in favor of 
circumcision, I think it makes sense to defer to their judgment, just as it 
does for other medical choices.  Likewise, I'm inclined to say that if there 
was reason to think (though also reason to doubt) that circumcision would 
enhance sexual function, parents could also reasonable choose that as a medical 
matter.

The interesting question, I think, is how we should resolve 
the matter if (1) the medical consensus comes to be that there was no medical 
benefit of circumcision and no sexual function benefits, but (2) there comes to 
be no consensus on whether there is a sexual function cost.  My inclination 
would be to say that the uncertainty should not be resolved in favor of 
parental choice, but rather resolved in favor of patient choice: the principle 
that - absent medical need - practically irreversible and potentially harmful 
surgery should not be undertaken without the actual consent of the adult 
subject of the surgery.

The AAP decision reinforces my understanding that the health arguments 
for circumcision are substantial, though we have to recognize, I think, that 
the matter is still up to debate, with different views being expressed by 
organizations in different countries.  Moreover, the medical understanding may 
well change with time, as there is more research into the connection with 
sexual function, more research into the connection with disease, and changes in 
other disease-related factors -- for instance, if a major medical plus of 
circumcision is greater protection against some diseases, then the develop of a 
new and effective immunization against the disease may reduce this marginal 
plus. 

As to the philosophy, more in a separate e-mail.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
 Sent: Monday, August 27, 2012 11:36 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: New circumcision policy statement from the AAP
 
 
 Eugene --
 
 I have to respectfully continue to disagree with your approach to this issue,
 as well as your assessment of the effect of the AAP decision on your
 argument:
 
 Previously I think you had offered both medical and philosophical/legal
 reasons for why you felt a circumcision-restrictive position would be 
 justified.
 
 At this point your proffered medical reasons no longer serve as support for
 your legal position. The AAP decision does not say that it is wrong for 
 parents
 to fail to circumcise their children, but the medical nod (including as to 
 issues
 of sexual sensation) now goes to circumcision as opposed to non-
 circumcision. You say that there is disagreement among doctors overseas,
 but I am not aware of any medical association overseas that has conducted a
 similar multi-year study to the AAP's and reached a contrary conclusion. And
 it is a commonplace that circumcision is medically indicated in many parts of
 the world (e.g. sub-Saharan Africa).
 
 There are of course advocates on both sides, including licensed doctors, but
 the great weight of international medical opinion seems to be on the side of
 circumcision in both developed and developing countries. And the AAP is I
 believe the largest (and perhaps the most respected) pediatric medical
 association in the world. As for future changes, it seems quite speculative 
 for
 you to say if the medical evidence eventually ends up being contrary when
 the AAP has moved closer to the circumcision-positive end of the debate
 after taking into account both the vigorous criticisms of circumcision and and
 making a multi-year study of the entire medical literature in the area. In
 short, at this point you bear the burden of overcoming medical opinion that
 favors circumcision. Thus your previously-offered medical reasons provide no
 support for your position and you now have a new medical hurdle to
 overcome.
 
 That leaves you with what I refer to as legal/philosophical reasons. Your
 second line of argument was couched in legal terms, but I think it is really a
 species of political philosophy. It goes directly to questions about whether
 individuals and associations of individuals and their
 rights/privileges/immunities precede the state or whether the state has
 some sort of defining role in the first instance that regulates all 
 interactions
 outside of monadic individuals, as indicated by your use of the word
 delegate. Here is where I pushed back on you in the original discussion and
 I am 

Liberty and parent-child relatiosn

2012-09-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Let me try to respond, relatively briefly, to Eric's long and 
interesting argument about the philosophical issues raised by the circumcision 
debate.



Here is my general thought -- I don't know whether most 
Americans, most Finns, most Germans, or most of anyone else will agree with me, 
but it still strikes me as sound.



(1)  There are powerful arguments for broad liberty to do 
things with one's own body and with the bodies of consenting adults, free of 
government restriction.  But those arguments do not apply the same way to an 
asserted liberty to do things with the bodies of others who are not consenting 
-- including others who happen to be your children.  This claim of a liberty 
to do things to unconsenting others is thus a very different creature than the 
normal claims of liberty we have.



(2)  Indeed, at this point the claim of liberty runs up against 
the liberty of the rest of us to try to defend our fellow people against 
aggression.  If I see a parent trying to kill his child, it seems to me I have 
the right to step in and stop that.  That too is not quite the same sort of 
liberty as the liberty just to do what I please with myself, because the parent 
is an unconsenting other for purposes of my formulation.  But it is, I think, a 
rightly recognized liberty, precisely because it is aimed at preventing 
unconsented-to violence to an innocent third party.  The same is true if I see 
a parent trying to rape his child, or -- what is not far off -- handing over 
his obviously unwilling daughter for an underage marriage (however religiously 
or culturally sanctioned that might be).  The same is true if I learn that 
parents are about to mutilate their daughter's genitals.  In these cases 
(though, as I'll note, not necessarily all other cases), my liberty to come to 
the defend of others applies just as much to defending children against their 
parents as it does to defending anyone else against anyone else.



(3)  State power to protect children against such abuse is, I 
think, largely derivative of the power of each of us to come to the defense of 
innocent others, including strangers.  It is of course more dangerous, because 
it can lead to more organized oppression if abused.  But it is also in many 
respects superior, both because it can lead to more reliable protection if 
properly used, and can be done in a more procedurally reliable way that 
diminishes the risk of error, as well as of a cycle of violent retaliation.



(4)  The hard questions, of course, arise not when we're 
talking about parents killing their children, raping them, or marrying them off 
at too early an age, but about less grave harms -- indeed, things that not 
everyone thinks are harms.  What if a parent is beating a child quite seriously 
by today's standards?  Spanking the child?  Taking the child back to a 
totalitarian country (e.g., Cuba or North Korea) from which the child might be 
unable to flee?  Tattooing the child?  Donating the child's kidney to a 
stranger?  Circumcising the child?



In such situations, it may well be that I should not have the 
liberty to come what I see as the defense of the child, and the state should 
not have such a power, either.  Or maybe I and the state should have such 
power.  And maybe views on that subject may change over time -- consider the 
serious beating situation, or some of the others.  But I don't think that these 
questions can be resolved just by referring to some preexisting liberty of 
parents over the bodies of third persons (even those whom they brought into the 
world), just as they can't be resolved just by referring to a preexisting 
liberty of third parties (which might be delegated to the state) to rescue such 
third persons from the parents.  Nor do I think that long tradition should 
carry much weight in this field; I think that the last few centuries have 
fortunately involved a rejection of many traditions related to the power of 
people over third parties (such as wives or children), even when they have been 
defended as being benevolently motivated.  It seems to me quite proper to 
reexamination such traditions as to circumcision as well as to other matters.



On balance, it appears to me that when it comes to parental 
physical actions related to children -- as opposed to parental teachings, which 
raise additional freedom of speech concerns -- are rightly resolved through the 
democratic process, with all of us deciding on the proper limitations on both 
our interests as parents wanting to do things to our children and our interests 
in being able to protect third parties from abuse.  One possible exception 
might be for substituted judgment as to medical decisions, see Parham v. J.R., 
though I'm not positive that this is the right approach.  (Note that, as I 
mentioned in my post earlier this morning, I have 

Stanford Religious Liberty Clinic: Staff Attorney Post

2012-09-20 Thread Volokh, Eugene
This might be a great opportunity for some of our former students, so I thought 
I'd pass it along:



Stanford Law School
Religious Liberty Clinic
Staff Attorney


The Mills Legal Clinic of Stanford Law School invites applicants for the staff 
attorney position with its Religious Liberty Clinic (RLC).  The staff 
attorney will join the thriving clinical community at Stanford Law School 
where, together with the clinical faculty and staff, he or she will represent 
clients and help train law students at one of the country's leading 
institutions for legal scholarship and education.

The RLC is the newest of the eleven clinics comprising the Mills Legal Clinic, 
and is the only one of its kind in the country.  The RLC was launched in August 
2012, and will be open to students in January 2013.  The Stanford clinical 
program is unique in that students participate in a clinic on a full-time 
basis; the clinic is the only course a student takes during the term of 
enrollment.  The Mills Legal Clinic occupies an entire floor in an 
award-winning central campus building opened earlier this year.

The RLC will focus on developing professional skills in a dynamic way.  
Specifically, students will be introduced to the real practice of law through 
their representation of a diverse group of clients in disputes arising from a 
wide range of religious beliefs, practices, and settings.  Projects might 
involve a prisoner facing obstacles to religious observance, a small church, 
synagogue, or mosque with zoning challenges, or a faith-based group seeking 
access to public facilities.  Students will learn and apply the laws affecting 
religious liberty, and will be expected to counsel individual or small 
institutional clients and litigate on their behalf with excellence, 
professionalism, and maturity.

As a litigation-focused clinic, the RLC will involve administrative, trial, and 
appellate work.  Most administrative and trial work will take place in 
California, while appellate work will be done nationally.  Because the RLC is a 
new and unique project, near-term clinic activities will also include 
marketing, outreach, and development efforts.

The staff attorney will participate in all activities of the RLC, including 
client development, student supervision, and client representation.  The 
attorney will also assist the RLC's director with curriculum design, teaching 
and evaluation matters, and clinic operations.  All Mills Legal Clinic 
attorneys are part of the intellectual community within the clinical program 
and the Law School and university at large.  For example, the staff attorney 
will be invited to attend weekly workshops at which scholars from Stanford and 
throughout the world present works in progress.  The clinic also provides 
resources for its lawyers to participate in continuing education and other 
professional development activities.

Applicants for the staff attorney position should have at least three years of 
litigation experience, preferably at the trial level, and be a member of the 
California bar (or be willing to take the next-offered California bar exam).  
Applicants must possess strong academic credentials, an interest in religious 
liberty, and organizational and team skills essential to helping run what is, 
in essence, a small law firm.  Successful teaching and/or student supervision 
experience or the demonstrated potential for such skills are desirable.

The salary is based on a formula that is competitive with similar positions.

Applicants should submit their resumes through http://jobs.stanford.edu, 
referencing job number 49499.  Applicants should also send the following 
materials electronically to Judy Gielniak, Mills Legal Clinic administrative 
manager, at jgieln...@law.stanford.edu:


 *   a statement no longer than one page describing the applicant's: (i) prior 
litigation or other relevant experience; (ii) interest in religious liberty; 
and (iii) interest and potential for clinical supervision and teaching;


 *   a resume


 *   a list of at least three references


 *   a complete law school transcript

Applications will be considered on a rolling basis until the position is filled.


*  *  *  *  *  *  *  *
inline: image001.jpg___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

<    4   5   6   7   8   9   10   11   12   >